Classics of modern science : (Copernicus to Pasteur)

By William S. Knickerbocker

The Project Gutenberg eBook of Classics of modern science
    
This ebook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and
most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions
whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms
of the Project Gutenberg License included with this ebook or online
at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United States,
you will have to check the laws of the country where you are located
before using this eBook.

Title: Classics of modern science
        (Copernicus to Pasteur)

Editor: William S. Knickerbocker

Release date: October 18, 2025 [eBook #77076]

Language: English

Original publication: New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1927

Credits: Tim Miller, Laura Natal and the Online Distributed Proofreading Team at https://www.pgdp.net (This file was produced from images generously made available by The Internet Archive)


*** START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK CLASSICS OF MODERN SCIENCE ***





                              CLASSICS OF
                            MODERN SCIENCE


 THERE is no grander nor more intellectually elevating spectacle than
 that of the utterances of the fundamental investigators in their
 gigantic power. Possessed as yet of no methods--for these were first
 created by their labors and are only rendered comprehensible to us by
 their performances--they grapple with and subjugate the object of their
 inquiry and imprint upon it the forms of conceptual thought.

                                                           --ERNST MACH




                               CLASSICS
                                  OF
                            MODERN SCIENCE

                        (COPERNICUS TO PASTEUR)




                               EDITED BY

                    WILLIAM S. KNICKERBOCKER, PH.D.

                PROFESSOR OF ENGLISH IN THE UNIVERSITY
                      OF THE SOUTH · EDITOR, THE
                            SEWANEE REVIEW




                     ALFRED · A · KNOPF · NEW YORK

                               MCMXXVII




              COPYRIGHT 1927, BY ALFRED · A · KNOPF, INC.


              SET UP, ELECTROTYPED, PRINTED AND BOUND BY
               THE VAIL-BALLOU PRESS, BINGHAMTON, N. Y.
              PAPER FURNISHED BY W. F. ETHERINGTON & CO.,
                               NEW YORK


                             MANUFACTURED
                    IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA




                TO MY FORMER ASSOCIATES OF THE FACULTY,
                   AND THE STUDENTS OF THE NEW YORK
                 STATE COLLEGE OF FORESTRY AT SYRACUSE
                              UNIVERSITY.




                                PREFACE


“The history of science,” wrote Du Bois-Reymond, “is the real history
of mankind.” Gradually we are coming to realize the significance of
that statement, and the sooner we realize it on a grand scale the more
shall we hasten the happiness of man.

Fortunately for education, science no longer has to fight for its
inclusion among the courses offered for study in colleges and
universities. As scientific knowledge increases and the technique
of teaching science improves, the exact knowledge of the few more
rapidly becomes the accepted knowledge of the many. More than that,
the scientific attitude of mind produces many of the virtues which in
old-fashioned courses in ethics were taught as objectively as a problem
in geometry. Patience, endurance, humility, teachableness, honesty,
accuracy--without these it is impossible for a scientist properly to
work. And the history of science is as inspiring in its human values as
are the legends of the saints. Contemplate the heroism of a Galileo,
the patience of a Darwin, the humility of a Pasteur; a modern eleventh
chapter of _Hebrews_ might be written listing the names of all
those men of faith who by quiet work, unremitting in their zeal, one by
one discovered facts which have made man’s lot easier and happier in
what was otherwise to him a hostile and unhappy universe.

Little by little, accretion upon accretion, man’s knowledge of
the physical forces of his universe has been increased, but his
progress has often been retarded by those who, with good intentions,
superstitiously feared the power of the gods who, as in the story of
Brunhilde, encircled their mysteries with a ring of fire. Periodically
superstition re-arises, but it does not permanently halt the advance
deploy of armed skirmishers, however much it may temporarily retard
the advancement of knowledge. Since the seventeenth century, however,
so remarkable has been the progress of science, so evident have been
its beneficent achievements, that regardless of the present assault
upon one phase of science, western civilization is committed to this
way of discovery. But it is no easy way! “The rapid increase of
natural knowledge,” wrote Thomas Henry Huxley, “which is the chief
characteristic of our age, is affected in various ways. The main army
of science moves to the conquest of the new worlds slowly and surely,
nor ever cedes an inch of the territory gained. But the advance is
covered and facilitated by the ceaseless activity of clouds of light
troops provided with a weapon--always efficient, if not always an
arm of precision--the scientific imagination. It is the business of
these _enfants perdus_ of science to make raids into the realms
of ignorance wherever they see, or think they see, a chance; and
cheerfully to accept defeat, or it may be annihilation, as the reward
of error. Unfortunately the public, which watches the progress of the
campaign, too often mistakes a dashing incursion ... for a forward
movement of the main body; fondly imagining that the strategic movement
to the rear, which occasionally follows, indicates a battle lost by
science.”

It is regrettable that Huxley was compelled to use the metaphor of
a battle in describing the general advance of scientific knowledge;
how much better it would have been if he could have used a scientific
word like _enzyme_ or _catalyst_ in referring to those courageous men
of the laboratory and the field who went forth alone with instruments
to discover things as they really are and changed fields of knowledge
through their discoveries. But if he had employed these scientific
terms, no one, apart from the select company of scientists themselves
who have had to evolve a special language of their own to express
new matters and new meanings, would understand him. People who use
strange tongues are always suspect to the populace. If science is to
be “understanded” by the people, the people’s language must be used.
Fortunately, for the sake of science, scientists themselves are now
keenly aware of the necessity of presenting their findings in language
which may be understood by the ordinary man. Huxley himself made the
_liaison_ in his age, an age in which battles were highly idealised.
His grandson, however, speaking to our age, rephrases the idea in a
mode more acceptable to us: “Each science or branch of science seems
roughly to go through three main phases in its development. There is
first a preliminary phase in which miscellaneous sporadic knowledge
is amassed and is dated; theories are pursued, often to be proved
valueless. There then comes a classic or heroic age, in which a general
principle of firmly interrelated principles is gradually laid down,
upon which in its turn a coherent architecture of theory can be built,
and finally this passes over into a period of maturity, in which the
position is consolidated, the scope of the principles widened, their
bases more finally tested, and their consequences worked out in fullest
detail. Naturally, each stage lasts for a considerable time, and in
many cases a science which thought itself securely embarked upon the
third phase is reminded by some fundamental discovery that it is still
only in the second.”[1]

These movements of science have produced a copious literature which
has not enjoyed the same attention and reading as imaginative books,
because, once the ideas are known and incorporated into the existing
body of scientific knowledge, these scientific writings tend to acquire
chiefly an historical interest. Yet they are monuments of the advance
of civilization, and deserve a better fate. Many of them are still
interesting to read as human documents because they illustrate how
painfully and slowly man’s exact knowledge of verifiable phenomena has
been accumulated. No one outside of the small company of highly trained
scientists can read all of them through, yet most of them have sections
which are as readable and as exciting as any modern novel. It is the
purpose of this book to present to the young college student and to the
general reader some of the more representative of these classics in the
literature of science, bringing together in this convenient form at
least some reminders of a vast field of reading where one may browse
for a lifetime with interest and profit. If it be used in conjunction
with a history of science it will readily supply a vivid sense of
the movement of the mind of western civilization, increasing in us a
respect for the effort of our ancestors, and inspire us to encourage
and to forward the work of contemporary scientists, and restrain us at
least from hindering them in their efforts.

Although the selections may be used as a textbook in courses like
Introduction to Modern Civilization, Philosophy, and The History of
Science now given in the more progressive colleges and universities,
it may also profitably be used as a text for freshman or sophomore
readings in English courses given in colleges predominantly technical
or scientific, like Engineering, Agricultural, and Forestry Colleges.
In those English courses where emphasis upon ideas is made to provide
the inspiration for writing, these selections will be found, as I
found them in my own work, to stir up considerable discussion and
to provide opportunities for reading modern scientific literature.
Moreover, the literary style of science at its best will be found to be
excellently illustrated in these straightforward, coherent sentences
written by some of the world’s clearest thinkers. They illustrate
concretely what Tyndall remarked in his closing words of the famous
_Belfast Address_: “It has been said that science divorces itself
from literature. The statement, like so many others, arises from
lack of knowledge. A glance at the less technical writings of its
leaders--of its Helmholtz, its Huxley, and its Du Bois-Reymond--would
show what breadth of literary culture they command. Where among
modern writers can you find their superiors in clearness and vigor
of literary style? Science desires no isolation, but freely combines
with every effort toward the bettering of man’s estate. Single-handed
and supported not with outward sympathy, but by inward force, it has
built at least one great wing of the many-mansioned home which man in
his totality demands.... The world embraces not only a Newton, but a
Shakespeare; not only a Boyle, but a Raphael; not only a Kant, but a
Beethoven; not only a Darwin, but a Carlyle. Not in each of these, but
in all, is human nature whole. They are not opposed, but supplementary;
not mutually exclusive, but reconcilable.”

                                               WILLIAM S. KNICKERBOCKER

UNIVERSITY OF THE SOUTH
SEWANEE, TENN.
_April 5, 1927_




FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 1: Julian Huxley, in _Harper’s Magazine_ for April,
1926.]




                               CONTENTS


 I  FRANCIS BACON (1561-1626)                                  1

 THE METHOD OF INDUCTIVE SCIENCE
 ON THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE, OR THE
 REIGN OF MAN

 II  NICOLAUS COPERNICUS (1473-1543)                          20

 THE NEW IDEA OF THE UNIVERSE

 III  JOHANN KEPLER (1671-1630)                               29

 ON THE PRINCIPLES OF ASTRONOMY

 IV  GALILEO GALILEI (1564-1642)                              36

 THE COPERNICAN VERSUS THE PTOLEMAIC ASTRONOMIES

 V  WILLIAM HARVEY (1578-1667)                                46

 THE CIRCULATION OF BLOOD IN ANIMALS

 VI  ROBERT BOYLE (1627-1691)                                 49

 THE DISCOVERY OF THE LAW OF THE COMPRESSIBILITY
 OF GASSES

 VII  CHRISTIAN HUYGHENS (1629-1695)                          52

 THE WAVE THEORY OF LIGHT

 VIII  ANTHONY VON LEEUWENHOECK (1632-1723)                   62

 OBSERVATIONS ON ANIMALCULÆ

 IX  SIR ISAAC NEWTON (1642-1727)                             67

 THE THEORY OF GRAVITATION

 X  BENJAMIN FRANKLIN (1706-1790)                             72

 THE IDENTITY OF LIGHTNING AND ELECTRICITY

 XI  LINNAEUS (1707-1778)                                     76

 THE SEX OF PLANTS

 XII  JOSEPH BLACK (1728-1799)                                89

 THE DISCOVERY OF CARBONIC ACID GAS

 XIII  JOSEPH PRIESTLEY (1733-1804)                           96

 THE DISCOVERY OF OXYGEN

 XIV  HENRY CAVENDISH (1731-1810)                            102

 THE COMBINATION OF HYDROGEN AND OXYGEN
 INTO WATER

 XV  SIR WILLIAM HERSCHEL (1738-1822)                        109

 THE DISCOVERY OF URANUS
 ON THE NAME OF THE NEW PLANET
 ON NEBULOUS STARS

 XVI  KARL WILHELM SCHEELE (1742-1786)                       122

 THE CONSTITUENTS OF AIR

 XVII  ANTOINE LAURENT LAVOISIER (1743-1794)                 129

 THE NATURE OF COMBUSTION

 XVIII  ALESSANDRO VOLTA (1745-1827)                         135

 NEW GALVANIC INSTRUMENT

 XIX  PIERRE SIMON LAPLACE (1749-1827)                       138

 THE NEBULAR HYPOTHESIS

 XX  EDWARD JENNER (1749-1823)                               148

 THE THEORY OF VACCINATION

 XXI  COUNT RUMFORD (1753-1814)                              157

 THE NATURE OF HEAT

 XXII  JOHN DALTON (1766-1844)                               166

 THE ATOMIC THEORY

 XXIII  MARIE FRANÇOIS XAVIER BICHAT (1771-1802)             168

 THE DOCTRINE OF TISSUES

 XXIV  AMADEO AVOGADRO (1776-1856)                           177

 THE MOLECULES IN GASES PROPORTIONAL TO
 THE VOLUMES

 XXV  SIR HUMPHREY DAVY (1778-1829)                          183

 ON SOME NEW PHENOMENA OF CHEMICAL
 CHANGES PRODUCED BY ELECTRICITY

 XXVI  MICHAEL FARADAY (1791-1867)                           190

 ON FLUID CHLORINE
 ELECTRICITY FROM MAGNETISM

 XXVII  JOSEPH HENRY (1797-1878)                             198

 ON THE PRODUCTION OF CURRENTS AND SPARKS
 OF ELECTRICITY FROM MAGNETISM

 XXVIII  SIR CHARLES LYELL (1797-1875)                       206

 UNIFORMITY IN THE SERIES OF PAST CHANGES
 IN THE ANIMATE AND INANIMATE WORLD

 XXIX  CHARLES DARWIN (1809-1882)                            226

 NATURAL SELECTION

 XXX  THEODOR SCHWANN (1810-1882)                            245

 CELL THEORY

 XXXI  HERMANN VON HELMHOLTZ (1821-1894)                     273

 THE CONSERVATION OF ENERGY

 XXXII  LOUIS PASTEUR (1822-1895)                            304

 INOCULATION FOR HYDROPHOBIA

 XXXIII  JAMES CLERK MAXWELL (1831-1879)                     320

 THE MAXWELL AND HERZ THEORY OF ELECTRICITY
 AND LIGHT

 XXXIV  AUGUST WEISMANN (1834-1914)                          334

 THE CONTINUITY OF THE GERM-PLASM AS THE
 FOUNDATION OF A THEORY OF HEREDITY

 XXXV  SIR NORMAN LOCKYER (1836-1920)                        360

 THE CHEMISTRY OF THE STARS

 XXXVI  ROBERT KOCH (1843-1910)                              374

 THEORY OF BACTERIA




                              CLASSICS OF
                            MODERN SCIENCE




                                   I

                             FRANCIS BACON

                               1561-1626


 _Francis Bacon, Lord Verulam, is distinguished in the history of
 science for his criticism of the methods of knowledge of his day.
 In his great writings, “The Advancement of Learning” (1605), “Novum
 Organum” (1620), and “De Augmentis Scientiarum” (1623), he cumulatively
 outlined a new method, named after him, whereby all knowledge was
 referred to experience and corrected by experiment. His inductive
 method was epoch-making in that it established the technique underlying
 all modern science._

 _He was born in London, January 22, 1561, the son of Sir Nicholas
 Bacon, Lord Keeper of the Seals. In 1573, at the age of twelve, he
 matriculated in Trinity College, Cambridge. After his father’s death,
 in 1579, he led a precarious life, accumulated many debts, and ended
 by accusing his intimate friend, Lord Essex, of treason. In 1607 King
 James appointed him Solicitor. In 1613 he became Attorney General,
 and in 1618 was made Lord Chancellor and knighted Baron Verulam. The
 following year he was impeached for bribery, and imprisoned four days
 for the offense. Thereafter, until his death on April 9, 1626, he gave
 himself wholly to the development of his new scientific method._


                  THE METHOD OF INDUCTIVE SCIENCE[2]

They who have presumed to dogmatize on nature, as on some well
investigated subject, either from self-conceit or arrogance, and in the
professorial style, have inflicted the greatest injury on philosophy
and learning. For they have tended to stifle and interrupt inquiry
exactly in proportion as they have prevailed in bringing others to
their opinion; and their own activity has not counterbalanced the
mischief they have occasioned by corrupting and destroying that of
others. They again who have entered upon a contrary course, and
asserted that nothing whatever can be known, whether they have fallen
into this opinion from their hatred of the ancient sophists, or from
the hesitation of their minds, or from an exuberance of learning, have
certainly adduced reasons for it which are by no means contemptible.
They have not, however, derived their opinion from true sources,
and, hurried on by their zeal and some affectation, have certainly
exceeded due moderation. But the more ancient Greeks (whose writings
have perished), held a more prudent mean, between the arrogance of
dogmatism, and the despair of scepticism; and though too frequently
intermingling complaints and indignation at the difficulty of inquiry,
and the obscurity of things, and champing, as it were, the bit, have
still persisted in pressing their point, and pursuing their intercourse
with nature; thinking, as it seems, that the better method was not to
dispute upon the very point of the possibility of anything being known,
but to put it to the test of experience. Yet they themselves, by only
employing the power of the understanding, have not adopted a fixed
rule, but have laid their whole stress upon intense meditation, and a
continual exercise and perpetual agitation of the mind.

Our method, though difficult in its operation, is easily explained.
It consists in determining the degrees of certainty, whilst we, as it
were, restore the senses to their former rank, but generally reject
that operation of the mind which follows close upon the senses, and
open and establish a new and certain course for the mind from the first
actual perceptions of the senses themselves. This, no doubt, was the
view taken by those who have assigned so much to logic; showing clearly
thereby that they sought some support for the mind, and suspected its
natural and spontaneous mode of action. But this is now employed too
late as a remedy, when all is clearly lost, and after the mind, by
the daily habit and intercourse of life, has come prepossessed with
corrupted doctrines, and filled with the vainest idols. The art of
logic, therefore, being (as we have mentioned) too late a precaution,
and in no way remedying the matter, has tended more to confirm errors,
than to disclose truth. Our only remaining hope and salvation is to
begin the whole labor of the mind again; not leaving it to itself,
but directing it perpetually from the very first, and attaining our
end as it were by mechanical aid. If men, for instance, had attempted
mechanical labors with their hands alone, and without the power and aid
of instruments, as they have not hesitated to carry on the labors of
their understanding with the unaided efforts of their mind, they would
have been able to move and overcome but little, though they had exerted
their utmost and united powers. And just to pause awhile on this
comparison, and look into it as a mirror; let us ask, if any obelisk of
a remarkable size were perchance required to be moved, for the purpose
of gracing a triumph or any similar pageant, and men were to attempt it
with their bare hands, would not any sober spectator avow it to be an
act of the greatest madness? And if they should increase the number of
workmen, and imagine that they could thus succeed, would he not think
so still more? But if they chose to make a selection, and to remove
the weak, and only employ the strong and vigorous, thinking by this
means, at any rate, to achieve their object, would he not say that they
were more fondly deranged? Nay, if not content with this, they were
to determine on consulting the athletic art, and were to give orders
for all to appear with their hands, arms, and muscles regularly oiled
and prepared, would he not exclaim that they were taking pains to rave
by method and design? Yet men are hurried on with the same senseless
energy and useless combination in intellectual matters, as long as
they expect great results either from the number and agreement, or the
excellence and acuteness of their wits; or even strengthen their minds
with logic, which may be considered as an athletic preparation, but yet
do not desist (if we rightly consider the matter) from applying their
own understandings merely with all this zeal and effort. Whilst nothing
is more clear, than that in every great work executed by the hand of
man without machines or implements, it is impossible for the strength
of individuals to be increased, or that of the multitude to combine.

Having premised so much, we lay down two points on which we would
admonish mankind lest they should fail to see or to observe them. The
first of these is, that it is our good fortune (as we consider it), for
the sake of extinguishing and removing contradiction and irritation of
mind, to leave the honor and reverence due to the ancients untouched
and undiminished, so that we can perform our intended work, and yet
enjoy the benefit of our respectful moderation. For if we profess
to offer something better than the ancients, and yet should pursue
the same course as they have done, we could never, by any artifice,
contrive to avoid the imputation of having engaged in a contest or
rivalry as to our respective wits, excellencies, or talents; which,
though neither inadmissible nor new (for why should we not blame and
point out anything that is imperfectly discovered or laid down by
them, of our own right, a right common to all), yet however just and
allowable, would perhaps be scarcely an equal match, on account of
the disproportion of our strength. But since our present plan leads
us to open an entirely different course to the understanding, and one
unattempted and unknown to them, the case is altered. There is an end
to party zeal, and we only take upon ourselves the character of a
guide, which requires a moderate share of authority and good fortune,
rather than talents and excellence. The first admonition relates to
persons, the next to things.

We make no attempt to disturb the system of philosophy that now
prevails, or any other which may or will exist, either more correct or
more complete. For we deny not that the received system of philosophy,
and others of a similar nature, encourage discussion, embellish
harangues, are employed, and are of service in the duties of the
professor, and the affairs of civil life. Nay, we openly express and
declare that the philosophy we offer will not be very useful in such
respects. It is not obvious, or to be understood in a cursory view,
nor does it flatter the mind in its preconceived notions, nor will
it descend to the level of the generality of mankind unless by its
advantages and effects.

Let there exist, then (and may it be of advantage to both), two
sources, and two distributions of learning, and in like manner
two tribes, and as it were kindred families of contemplators or
philosophers, without any hostility or alienation between them; but
rather allied and united by mutual assistance. Let there be, in short,
one method of cultivating the sciences, and another in discovering
them. And as for those who prefer and more readily receive the former,
on account of their haste or from motives arising from their ordinary
life, or because they are unable from weakness of mind to comprehend
and embrace the other (which must necessarily be the case with by
far the greater number), let us wish that they may prosper as they
desire in their undertaking, and attain what they pursue. But if any
individual desire, and is anxious not merely to adhere to, and make
use of present discoveries, but to penetrate still further, and not
to overcome his adversaries in disputes, but nature by labor, not in
short to give elegant and specious opinions, but to know to a certainty
and demonstration, let him, as a true son of science (if such be his
wish), join with us; that when he has left the antechambers of nature
trodden by the multitude, an entrance may at last be discovered to her
inner apartments. And in order to be better understood, and to render
our meaning more familiar by assigning determinate names, we have
accustomed ourselves to call the one method the anticipation of the
mind, and the other the interpretation of nature.

We have still one request left. We have at least reflected and taken
pains, in order to render our propositions not only true, but of easy
and familiar access to men’s minds, however wonderfully prepossessed
and limited. Yet it is but just that we should obtain this favor from
mankind (especially in so great a restoration of learning and the
sciences), that whosoever may be desirous of forming any determination
upon an opinion of this our work either from his own perceptions,
or the crowd of authorities, or the forms of demonstrations, he
will not expect to be able to do so in a cursory manner, and whilst
attending to other matters; but in order to have a thorough knowledge
of the subject, will himself, by degrees, attempt the course which we
describe and maintain; will be accustomed to the subtlety of things
which is manifested by experience; and will correct the depraved and
deeply-rooted habits of his mind by a seasonable, and, as it were, just
hesitation: and then, finally (if he will), use his judgment when he
has begun to be master of himself.


        ON THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE, OR THE REIGN OF MAN[3]

Man acts, then, upon natural bodies (besides merely bringing them
together or removing them) by seven principal methods: I. By the
exclusion of all that impedes and disturbs; II. by compression,
extension, agitation, and the like; III. by heat and cold; IV. by
detention in a suitable place; V. by checking or directing motion; VI.
by peculiar harmonies; VII. by a seasonable and proper alternation,
series, and succession of all these, or, at least, of some of them.

I. With regard to the first--common air, which is always at hand, and
forces its admission, as also the rays of the heavenly bodies, create
much disturbance. Whatever, therefore, tends to exclude them may
well be considered as generally useful. The substance and thickness
of vessels in which bodies are placed when prepared for operations
may be referred to this head. So also may the accurate methods of
closing vessels by consolidation, or the _lutum sapientiæ_ as
the chemists call it. The exclusion of air by means of liquids at
the extremity is also very useful, as when they pour oil on wine,
or the juices of herbs, which by spreading itself upon the top like
a cover, preserves them uninjured from the air. Powders, also, are
serviceable, for although they contain air mixed up in them, yet they
ward off the power of the mass of circumambient air, which is seen in
the preservation of grapes and other fruits in sand or flour. Wax,
honey, pitch, and other resinous bodies, are well used in order to
make the exclusion more perfect, and to remove the air and celestial
influence. We have sometimes made an experiment by placing a vessel or
other bodies in quicksilver, the most dense of all substances capable
of being poured round others. Grottoes and subterraneous caves are of
great use in keeping off the effects of the sun, and the predatory
action of air, and in the north of Germany are used for granaries.
The depositing of bodies at the bottom of water may be also mentioned
here; and I remember having heard of some bottles of wine being let
down into a deep well in order to cool them, but left there by chance,
carelessness, and forgetfulness, for several years, and then taken
out; by which means the wine not only escaped becoming flat or dead,
but was much more excellent in flavor, arising (as it appears) from
a more complete mixture of its parts. But if the case require that
bodies should be sunk to the bottom of water, as in rivers or the sea,
and yet should not touch the water, nor be enclosed in sealed vessels,
but surrounded only by air, it would be right to use that vessel which
has been sometimes employed under water above ships that have sunk, in
order to enable the divers to remain below and breathe occasionally
by turns. It was of the following nature:--A hollow tub of metal was
formed, and sunk so as to have its bottom parallel with the surface of
the water; it thus carried down with it to the bottom of the sea all
the air contained in the tub. It stood upon three feet (like a tripod),
being of rather less height than a man, so that, when the diver was
in want of breath, he could put his head into the hollow of the tub,
breathe, and then continue his work. We hear that some sort of boat or
vessel has now been invented, capable of carrying men some distance
under water. Any bodies, however, can easily be suspended under some
such vessel as we have mentioned, which has occasioned our remarks upon
the experiment.

Another advantage of the careful and hermetical closing of bodies is
this--not only the admission of external air is prevented (of which we
have treated), but the spirit of bodies also is prevented from making
its escape, which is an internal operation. For anyone operating on
natural bodies must be certain as to their quantity, and that nothing
has evaporated or escaped, since profound alterations take place in
bodies, when art prevents the loss or escape of any portion, whilst
nature prevents their annihilation. With regard to this circumstance,
a false idea has prevailed (which if true would make us despair of
preserving quantity without diminution), namely, that the spirit of
bodies, and air when rarefied by a great degree of heat, cannot be so
kept in by being enclosed in any vessel as not to escape by the small
pores. Men are led into this idea by the common experiments of a cup
inverted over water, with a candle or piece of lighted paper in it,
by which the water is drawn up, and of those cups which, when heated,
draw up the flesh. For they think that in each experiment the rarefied
air escapes, and that its quantity is therefore diminished, by which
means the water or flesh rises by the motion of connection. This is,
however, most incorrect. For the air is not diminished in quantity,
but contracted in dimensions, nor does this motion of the rising of
the water begin till the flame is extinguished, or the air cooled, so
that physicians place cold sponges, moistened with water, on the cups,
in order to increase their attraction. There is, therefore, no reason
why men should fear much from the ready escape of air: for although it
be true that the most solid bodies have their pores, yet neither air,
nor spirit, readily suffers itself to be rarefied to such an extreme
degree; just as water will not escape by a small chink.

II. With regard to the second of the seven above-mentioned methods, we
must especially observe, that compression and similar violence have a
most powerful effect either in producing locomotion, and other motions
of the same nature, as may be observed in engines and projectiles, or
in destroying the organic body, and those qualities, which consist
entirely in motion (for all life, and every description of flame and
ignition are destroyed by compression, which also injures and deranges
every machine); or in destroying those qualities which consist in
position and a coarse difference of parts, as in colors; for the color
of a flower when whole, differs from that it presents when bruised, and
the same may be observed of whole and powdered amber; or in tastes,
for the taste of a pear before it is ripe, and of the same pear when
bruised and softened, is different, since it becomes perceptibly
more sweet. But such violence is of little avail in the more noble
transformations and changes of homogeneous bodies, for they do not,
by such means, acquire any constantly and permanently new state, but
one that is transitory, and always struggling to return to its former
habit and freedom. It would not, however, be useless to make some more
diligent experiments with regard to this; whether, for instance, the
condensation of a perfectly homogeneous body (such as air, water, oil,
and the like) or their rarefaction, when effected by violence, can
become permanent, fixed, and, as it were, so changed, as to become
a nature. This might at first be tried by simple perseverance, and
then by means of helps and harmonies. It might readily have been
attempted (if we had but thought of it), when we condensed water (as
was mentioned above), by hammering and compression, until it burst out.
For we ought to have left the flattened globe untouched for some days,
and then to have drawn off the water, in order to try whether it would
have immediately occupied the same dimensions as it did before the
condensation. If it had not been done so, either immediately, or soon
afterwards, the condensation would have appeared to have been rendered
constant; if not, it would have appeared that a restitution took place,
and that the condensation had been transitory. Something of the same
kind might have been tried with the glass eggs; the egg should have
been sealed up suddenly and firmly, after a complete exhaustion of
the air, and should have been allowed to remain so for some days, and
it might then have been tried whether, on opening the aperture, the
air would be drawn in with a hissing noise, or whether as much water
would be drawn into it when immersed, as would have been drawn into it
at first, if it had not continued sealed. For it is probable (or, at
least, worth making the experiment) that this might have happened, or
might happen, because perseverance has a similar effect upon bodies
which are a little less homogeneous. A stick bent together for some
time does not rebound, which is not owing to any loss of quantity in
the wood during the time, for the same would occur (after a larger
time) in a plate of steel, which does not evaporate. If the experiment
of simple perseverance should fail, the matter should not be given up,
but other means should be employed. For it would be no small advantage,
if bodies could be endued with fixed and constant natures by violence.
Air could then be converted into water by condensation, with other
similar effects; for man is more the master of violent motions than of
any other means.

III. The third of our seven methods is referred to that great practical
engine of nature as well as of art, cold and heat. Here, man’s power
limps, as it were, with one leg. For we possess the heat of fire, which
is infinitely more powerful and intense than that of the sun (as it
reaches us), and that of animals. But we want cold, except such as we
can obtain in winter, in caverns, or by surrounding objects with snow
and ice, which, perhaps, may be compared in degree with the noontide
heat of the sun in tropical countries, increased by the reflection of
mountains and walls. For this degree of heat and cold can be borne
for a short period only by animals, yet it is nothing compared with
the heat of a burning furnace, or the corresponding degree of cold.
Everything with us has a tendency to become rarefied, dry, and wasted,
and nothing to become condensed or soft, except by mixtures, and,
as it were, spurious methods. Instances of cold, therefore, should
be searched for most diligently, such as may be found by exposing
bodies upon buildings in a hard frost, in subterraneous caverns, by
surrounding bodies with snow and ice in deep places excavated for
that purpose, by letting bodies down into wells, by burying bodies in
quicksilver and metals, by immersing them in streams which petrify
wood, by burying them in the earth (which the Chinese are reported to
do with their china, masses of which, made for that purpose, are said
to remain in the ground for forty or fifty years, and to be transmitted
to their heirs as a sort of artificial mine), and the like. The
condensations which take place in nature, by means of cold, should also
be investigated, that by learning their causes, they may be introduced
into the arts; such as are observed in the exudation of marble and
stones, in the dew upon the panes of glass in a room towards morning
after a frosty night, in the formation and the gathering of vapors
under the earth into water, whence spring fountains, and the like.

Besides the substances which are cold to the touch, there are others
which have also the effect of cold, and condense; they appear, however,
to act only upon the bodies of animals, and scarcely any further. Of
these we have many instances, in medicines and plasters. Some condense
the flesh and tangible parts, such as astringent and inspissating
medicines, others the spirits, such as soporifics. There are two modes
of condensing the spirits, by soporifics or provocatives to sleep;
the one by calming the motion, the other by expelling the spirit. The
violet, dried roses, lettuces, and other benign or mild remedies,
by their friendly and gently cooling vapors, invite the spirits to
unite, and restrain their violent and perturbed motion. Rosewater, for
instance, applied to the nostrils in fainting fits, causes the resolved
and relaxed spirits to recover themselves, and, as it were, cherishes
them. But opiates, and the like, banish the spirits by their malignant
and hostile quality. If they be applied, therefore, externally, the
spirits immediately quit the part and no longer readily flow into it;
but if they be taken internally, their vapor, mounting to the head,
expels, in all directions, the spirits contained in the ventricles of
the brain, and since these spirits retreat, but cannot escape, they
consequently meet and are condensed, and are sometimes completely
extinguished and suffocated; although the same opiates, when taken in
moderation, by a secondary accident (the condensation which succeeds
their union), strengthen the spirits, render them more robust, and
check their useless and inflammatory motion, by which means they
contribute not a little to the cure of diseases, and the prolongation
of life.

The preparations of bodies, also, for the reception of cold should not
be omitted, such as that water a little warmed is more easily frozen
than that which is quite cold, and the like.

Moreover, since nature supplies cold so sparingly, we must act like
the apothecaries, who, when they cannot obtain any simple ingredient,
take a succedaneum, or quid pro quo, as they term it, such as aloes for
xylobalsamum, cassia for cinnamon. In the same manner we should look
diligently about us, to ascertain whether there may be any substitutes
for cold, that is to say, in what other manner condensation can be
effected, which is the peculiar operation of cold. Such condensations
appear hitherto to be of four kinds only. 1. By simple compression,
which is of little avail towards permanent condensation, on account
of the elasticity of substances, but may still however be of some
assistance. 2. By the contraction of the coarser, after the escape
or departure of the finer parts of a given body; as is exemplified
in induration by fire, and the repeated heating and extinguishing of
metals, and the like. 3. By the cohesion of the most solid homogeneous
parts of a given body, which were previously separated, and mixed with
others less solid, as in the return of sublimated mercury to its simple
state, in which it occupies much less space than it did in powder, and
the same may be observed of the cleansing of all metals from their
dross. 4. By harmony or the application of substances which condense by
some latent power. These harmonies are as yet but rarely observed, at
which we cannot be surprised, since there is little to hope for from
their investigation, unless the discovery of forms and conformation
be attained. With regard to animal bodies, it is not to be questioned
that there are many internal and external medicines which condense
by harmony, as we have before observed, but this action is rare in
inanimate bodies. Written accounts, as well as report, have certainly
spoken of a tree in one of the Tercera or Canary Islands (for I do not
exactly recollect which) that drips perpetually, so as to supply the
inhabitants, in some degree, with water; and Paracelsus says that the
herb called _ros solis_ is filled with dew at noon, whilst the sun
gives out its greatest heat, and all other herbs around it are dry. We
treat both these accounts as fables; they would, however, if true, be
of the most important service, and most worthy of examination. As to
the honey-dew, resembling manna, which is found in May on the leaves
of the oak, we are of opinion that it is not condensed by any harmony
or peculiarity of the oak-leaf, but that whilst it falls equally upon
other leaves it is retained and continues on those of the oak, because
their texture is closer, and not so porous as that of most of the other
leaves.

With regard to heat, man possesses abundant means and power; but his
observation and inquiry are defective in some respects, and those of
the greatest importance, notwithstanding the boasting of quacks. For
the effects of intense heat are examined and observed, whilst those of
a more gentle degree of heat, being of the most frequent occurrence
in the paths of nature, are, on that very account, least known. We
see, therefore, the furnaces, which are most esteemed, employed in
increasing the spirits of bodies to a great extent, as in the strong
acids, and some chemical oils; whilst the tangible parts are hardened,
and, when the volatile part has escaped, become sometimes fixed; the
homogeneous parts are separated, and the heterogeneous incorporated and
agglomerated in a coarse lump; and (what is chiefly worthy of remark)
the junction of compound bodies, and the more delicate conformations
are destroyed and confounded. But the operation of a less violent heat
should be tried and investigated, by which more delicate mixtures, and
regular conformations may be produced and elicited, according to the
example of nature, and in imitation of the effect of the sun, which we
have alluded to in the aphorism on the instances of alliance. For the
works of nature are carried on in much smaller portions, and in more
delicate and varied positions than those of fire, as we now employ
it. But man will then appear to have really augmented his power, when
the works of nature can be imitated in species, perfected in power,
and varied in quantity; to which should be added the acceleration in
point of time. Rust, for instance, is the result of a long process,
but _crocus martis_ is obtained immediately; and the same may be
observed of natural verdigris and ceruse. Crystal is formed slowly,
whilst glass is blown immediately: stones increase slowly, whilst
bricks are baked immediately, etc. In the mean time (with regard to
our present subject) every different species of heat should, with its
peculiar effects, be diligently collected and inquired into; that
of the heavenly bodies, whether their rays be direct, reflected, or
refracted, or condensed by a burning-glass; that of lightning, flame,
and ignited charcoal; that of fire of different materials, either open
or confined, straitened or overflowing, qualified by the different
forms of the furnaces, excited by the bellows, or quiescent, removed to
a greater or less distance, or passing through different media; moist
heats, such as the _balneum Mariæ_, and the dunghill; the external
and internal heat of animals; dry heats, such as the heat of ashes,
lime, warm sand; in short, the nature of every kind of heat, and its
degrees.

We should, however, particularly attend to the investigation and
discovery of the effects and operations of heat, when made to approach
and retire by degrees, regularly, periodically, and by proper intervals
of space and time. For this systematical inequality is in truth the
daughter of heaven and mother of generation, nor can any great result
be expected from a vehement, precipitate, or desultory heat. For this
is not only most evident in vegetables, but in the wombs of animals
also there arises a great inequality of heat, from the motion, sleep,
food, and passions of the female. The same inequality prevails in
those subterraneous beds where metals and fossils are perpetually
forming, which renders yet more remarkable the ignorance of some of the
reformed alchemists, who imagined they could attain their object by the
equable heat of lamps, or the like, burning uniformly. Let this suffice
concerning the operation and effects of heat; nor is it time for us
to investigate them thoroughly before the forms and conformations
of bodies have been further examined and brought to light. When we
have determined upon our models, we may seek, apply, and arrange our
instruments.

IV. The fourth mode of action is by continuance, the very steward and
almoner, as it were, of nature. We apply the term continuance to the
abandonment of a body to itself for an observable time, guarded and
protected in the mean while from all external force. For the internal
motion then commences to betray and exert itself when the external and
adventitious is removed. The effects of time, however, are far more
delicate than those of fire. Wine, for instance, cannot be clarified
by fire as it is by continuance. Nor are the ashes produced by
combustion so fine as the particles dissolved or wasted by the lapse
of ages. The incorporations and mixtures, which are hurried by fire,
are very inferior to those obtained by continuance; and the various
conformations assumed by bodies left to themselves, such as mouldiness,
etc., are put a stop to by fire or a strong heat. It is not, in the
mean time, unimportant to remark that there is a certain degree of
violence in the motion of bodies entirely confined; for the confinement
impedes the proper motion of the body. Continuance in an open vessel,
therefore, is useful for separations, and in one hermetically sealed
for mixtures, that in a vessel partly closed, but admitting the
air, for putrefaction. But instances of the operation and effect of
continuance must be collected diligently from every quarter.

V. The direction of motion (which is the fifth method of action) is
of no small use. We adopt this term, when speaking of a body which,
meeting with another, either arrests, repels, allows, or directs
its original motion. This is the case principally in the figure and
position of vessels. An upright cone, for instance, promotes the
condensation of vapor in alembics, but when reversed, as in inverted
vessels, it assists the refining of sugar. Sometimes a curved form,
or one alternately contracted and dilated, is required. Strainers may
be ranged under this head, where the opposed body opens a way for
one portion of another substance and impedes the rest. Nor is this
process or any other direction of motion carried on externally only,
but sometimes by one body within another. Thus, pebbles are thrown
into water to collect the muddy particles, and syrups are refined by
the white of an egg, which glues the grosser particles together so as
to facilitate their removal. Telesius, indeed, rashly and ignorantly
enough attributes the formation of animals to this cause, by means of
the channels and folds of the womb. He ought to have observed a similar
formation of the young in eggs which have no wrinkles or inequalities.
One may observe a real result of this direction of motion in casting
and modelling.

VI. The effects produced by harmony and aversion (which is the
sixth method) are frequently buried in obscurity; for these occult
and specific properties (as they are termed), the sympathies and
antipathies, are for the most part but a corruption of philosophy. Nor
can we form any great expectation of the discovery of the harmony which
exists between natural objects, before that of their forms and simple
conformations, for it is nothing more than the symmetry between these
forms and conformations.

The greater and more universal species of harmony are not, however,
so wholly obscure, and with them, therefore, we must commence. The
first and principal distinction between them is this; that some bodies
differ considerably in the abundance and rarity of their substance, but
correspond in their conformation; others, on the contrary, correspond
in the former and differ in the latter. Thus the chemists have well
observed, that in their trial of first principles sulphur and mercury,
as it were, pervade the universe; their reasoning about salt, however,
is absurd, and merely introduced to compromise earthy dry fixed bodies.
In the other two, indeed, one of the most universal species of natural
harmony manifests itself. Thus there is a correspondence between
sulphur, oil, greasy exhalations, flame, and, perhaps, the substance of
the stars. On the other hand, there is a like correspondence between
mercury, water, aqueous vapor, air, and perhaps pure inter-sidereal
ether. Yet do these two quarternions, or great natural tribes (each
within its own limits), differ immensely in quantity and density of
substance, whilst they generally agree in conformation, as is manifest
in many instances. On the other hand, the metals agree in such quantity
and density (especially when compared with vegetables, etc.), but
differ in many respects in conformation. Animals and vegetables, in
like manner, vary in their almost infinite modes of conformation, but
range within very limited degrees of quantity and density of substance.

The next most general correspondence is that between individual bodies
and those which supply them by way of menstruum or support. Inquiry,
therefore, must be made as to the climate, soil, and depth at which
each metal is generated, and the same of gems, whether produced in
rocks or mines, also as to the soil in which particular trees, shrubs,
and herbs, mostly grow and, as it were, delight; and as to the best
species of manure, whether dung, chalk, sea sand, or ashes, etc., and
their different propriety and advantage according to the variety of
soils. So also the grafting and setting of trees and plants (as regards
the readiness of grafting one particular species on another) depends
very much upon harmony, and it would be amusing to try an experiment
I have lately heard of, in grafting forest trees (garden trees alone
having hitherto been adopted), by which means the leaves and fruit
are enlarged, and the trees produce more shade. The specific food of
animals again should be observed, as well as that which cannot be used.
Thus the carnivorous cannot be fed on herbs, for which reason the order
of _feuilletans_, the experiment having been made, has nearly
vanished; human nature being incapable of supporting their regimen,
although the human will has more power over the bodily frame than
that of other animals. The different kinds of putrefaction from which
animals are generated should be noted.

The harmony of principal bodies with those subordinate to them (such
indeed may be deemed those we have alluded to above) are sufficiently
manifest, to which may be added those that exist between different
bodies and their objects, and, since these latter are more apparent,
they may throw great light when well observed and diligently examined
upon those which are more latent.

The more internal harmony and aversion, or friendship and enmity
(for superstition and folly have rendered the terms of sympathy and
antipathy almost disgusting) have been either falsely assigned, or
mixed with fable, or most rarely discovered from neglect. For if
one were to allege that there is an enmity between the vine and the
cabbage, because they will not come up well sown together, there is
a sufficient reason for it in the succulent and absorbent nature of
each plant, so that the one defrauds the other. Again, if one were
to say that there is a harmony and friendship between the corn and
the corn-flower, or the wild poppy, because the latter seldom grow
anywhere but in cultivated soils, he ought rather to say, there is an
enmity between them, for the poppy and the corn-flower are produced and
created by those juices which the corn has left and rejected, so that
the sowing of the corn prepares the ground for their production. And
there are a vast number of similar false assertions. As for fables,
they must be totally exterminated. There remains, then, but a scanty
supply of such species of harmony as has borne the test of experiment,
such as that between the magnet and iron, gold and quicksilver, and
the like. In chemical experiments on metals, however, there are some
others worthy of notice, but the greatest abundance (where the whole
are so few in numbers) is discovered in certain medicines, which,
from their occult and specific qualities (as they are termed), affect
particular limbs, humors, diseases, or constitutions. Nor should we
omit the harmony between the motion and phenomena of the moon, and
their effects on lower bodies, which may be brought together by an
accurate and honest selection from the experiments of agriculture,
navigation, and medicine, or of other sciences. By as much as these
general instances, however, of more latent harmony, are rare, with
so much the more diligence are they to be inquired after, through
tradition, and faithful and honest reports, but without rashness and
credulity, with an anxious and, as it were, hesitating degree of
reliance. There remains one species of harmony which, though simple
in its mode of action, is yet most valuable in its use, and must
by no means be omitted, but rather diligently investigated. It is
the ready or difficult coition or union of bodies in composition, or
simple juxtaposition. For some bodies readily and willingly mix, and
are incorporated, others tardily and perversely; thus powders mix best
with water, chalk, and ashes with oils, and the like. Nor are these
instances of readiness and aversion to mixture to be alone collected,
but others, also, of the collocation, distribution, and digestion of
the parts when mingled, and the predominance after the mixture is
complete.

VII. Lastly, there remains the seventh, and last of the seven, modes
of action; namely that by the alternation and interchange of the
other six; but of this, it will not be the right time to offer any
examples, until some deeper investigation shall have taken place of
each of the others. The series, or chain of this alternation, in its
mode of application to separate effects, is no less powerful in its
operation, than difficult to be traced. But men are possessed with the
most extreme impatience, both of such inquiries, and their practical
application, although it be the clue of the labyrinth in all greater
works.


But it must be noted, that in this our organ, we treat of logic, and
not of philosophy. Seeing, however, that our logic instructs and
informs the understanding, in order that it may not, with the small
hooks, as it were, of the mind, catch at, and grasp mere abstractions,
but rather actually penetrate nature, and discover the properties and
effects of bodies, and the determinate laws of their substance (so that
this science of ours springs from the nature of things, as well as
from that of the mind); it is not to be wondered at, if it have been
continually interspersed and illustrated with natural observations and
experiments, as instances of our method. The prerogative instances are,
as appears from what has preceded, twenty-seven in number, and are
termed: solitary instances, migrating instances, conspicuous instances,
clandestine instances, constitutive, instances, similar instances,
singular instances, deviating instances, bordering instances,
instances of power, accompanying and hostile instances, subjunctive
instances, instances of alliance, instances of the cross, instances
of divorce, instances of the gate, citing instances, instances of the
road, supplementary instances, lancing instances, instances of the
rod, instances of the course, doses of nature, wrestling instances,
suggesting instances, generally useful instances, and magical
instances. The advantage, by which these instances excel the more
ordinary, regards specifically either theory or practice, or both. With
regard to theory, they assist either the senses or the understanding;
the senses, as in the five instances of the lamp; the understanding,
either by expediting the exclusive mode of arriving at the form, as in
solitary instances, or by confining, and more immediately indicating
the affirmative, as in the migrating, conspicuous, accompanying, and
subjunctive instances; or by elevating the understanding, and leading
it to general and common natures, and that either immediately, as in
the clandestine and singular instances, and those of alliance; or very
nearly so, as in the constitutive; or still less so, as in the similar
instances; or by correcting the understanding of its habits, as in
the deviating instances; or by leading to the grand form or fabric of
the universe, as in the bordering instances; or by guarding it from
false forms and causes, as in those of the cross and of divorce. With
regard to practice, they either point it out, or measure, or elevate
it. They point it out, either by showing where we must commence in
order not to repeat the labors of others, as in the instances of power;
or by inducing us to aspire to that which may be possible, as in the
suggesting instances; the four mathematical instances measure it. The
generally useful and the magical elevate it.

Again, out of these twenty-seven instances, some must be collected
immediately, without waiting for a particular investigation of
properties. Such are the similar, singular, deviating, and bordering
instances, those of power, and of the gate, and suggesting, generally
useful, and magical instances; for these either assist and cure
the understanding and senses, or furnish our general practice. The
remainder are to be collected when we furnish our synoptical tables
for the work of the interpreter, upon any particular nature; for these
instances, honored and gifted with such prerogatives, are like the
soul amid the vulgar crowd of instances, and (as we from the first
observed) a few of them are worth a multitude of the others. When,
therefore, we are forming our tables they must be searched out with the
greatest zeal, and placed in the table. And, since mention must be made
of them in what follows, a treatise upon their nature has necessarily
been prefixed. We must next, however, proceed to the supports and
corrections of induction, and thence to concretes, the latent process,
and latent conformations, and the other matters, which we have
enumerated in their order in the twenty-first aphorism, in order that,
like good and faithful guardians, we may yield up their fortune to
mankind upon the emancipation and majority of their understanding; from
which must necessarily follow an improvement of their estate, and an
increase of their power over nature. For man, by the fall, lost at once
his state of innocence, and his empire over creation, both of which can
be partially recovered even in this life, the first by religion and
faith, the second by the arts and sciences. For creation did not become
entirely and utterly rebellious by the curse, but in consequence of the
Divine decree, “in the sweat of thy brow shalt thou eat bread,” she
is compelled by our labors (not assuredly by our disputes or magical
ceremonies), at length, to afford mankind in some degree his bread,
that is to say, to supply man’s daily wants.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 2: Selection from the Preface to the _Novum Organum_.]

[Footnote 3: Part II, Conclusion of the _Novum Organum_.]




                                  II

                          NICOLAUS COPERNICUS

                               1473-1543


 _One of the first and most striking contributions to modern science
 was the substitution of the Copernican for the Ptolemaic conception of
 the universe._

 _Nicolaus Copernicus was born in the Prussian village of Thorn,
 located on the Vistula River, February 19, 1473. Although destined for
 the Church, he became interested in medicine, which he studied at the
 University of Cracow. Later, he turned to mathematics and continued
 his studies at the Universities of Vienna, Bologna, Padua, Ferrara,
 and Rome. Although he settled down as canon at Frauenberg, Poland, and
 gratuitously practised medicine in conjunction with his ecclesiastical
 duties, he found considerable time for other intellectual pursuits.
 Reading widely in the Greek philosophers, he came across a statement
 that the earth moved in its own orbit. This idea deeply appealed to
 him. “Occasioned by this,” he wrote, “I also began to think of a
 motion of the earth, and although the idea seemed absurd, still, as
 others before me had been permitted to assume certain circles in order
 to explain the motions of the stars, I believed it would be readily
 permitted me to try whether on the assumption of some motion of the
 earth better explanations of the revolutions of the heavenly bodies
 might not be found. And thus I have, assuming the motions which I in
 the following work attribute to the earth, after long and careful
 investigation, finally found that when the motions of the other planets
 are referred to the circulation of the earth and are computed for the
 revolution of each star, not only do the phenomena necessarily follow
 therefrom, but the order and magnitude of the stars and all their orbs
 and the heaven itself are so connected that in no part can anything be
 transposed without confusion to the rest and to the whole universe.”_

 _In 1530 he issue a “Commentariolus” which outlined his theory, but
 his prudence prompted him to withhold the publication of his great
 work, “De Orbium Caelestium Revolutionibus,” until 1543. In May of that
 year the first printed copy was laid on his death-bed._


                    THE NEW IDEA OF THE UNIVERSE[4]

I can well believe, most holy father, that certain people, when they
hear of my attributing motion to the earth in these books of mine, will
at once declare that such an opinion ought to be rejected. Now, my own
theories do not please me so much as not to consider what others may
judge of them. Accordingly, when I began to reflect upon what those
persons who accept the stability of the earth, as confirmed by the
opinion of many centuries, would say when I claimed that the earth
moves, I hesitated for a long time as to whether I should publish that
which I have written to demonstrate its motion, or whether it would
not be better to follow the example of the Pythagoreans, who used to
hand down the secrets of philosophy to their relatives and friends only
in oral form. As I well considered all this, I was almost impelled to
put the finished work wholly aside, through the scorn I had reason to
anticipate on account of the newness and apparent contrariness of my
theory to reason.

My friends, however, dissuaded me from such a course and admonished
me that I ought to publish my book, which had lain concealed in my
possession not only nine years, but already into four times the ninth
year. Not a few other distinguished and very learned men asked me to do
the same thing, and told me that I ought not, on account of my anxiety,
to delay any longer in consecrating my work to the general service of
mathematicians.

But your holiness will perhaps not so much wonder that I have dared to
bring the results of my night labors to the light of day, after having
taken so much care in elaborating them, but is waiting instead to
hear how it entered my mind to imagine that the earth moved, contrary
to the accepted opinion of mathematicians--nay, almost contrary to
ordinary human understanding. Therefore I will not conceal from your
holiness that what moved me to consider another way of reckoning the
motions of the heavenly bodies was nothing else than the fact that the
mathematicians do not agree with one another in their investigations.
In the first place, they are so uncertain about the motions of the sun
and moon that they cannot find out the length of a full year. In the
second place, they apply neither the same laws of cause and effect, in
determining the motions of the sun and moon and of the five planets,
nor the same proofs. Some employ only concentric circles, others use
eccentric and epicyclic ones, with which, however, they do not fully
attain the desired end. They could not even discover nor compute the
main thing--namely, the form of the universe and the symmetry of its
parts. It was with them as if some should, from different places, take
hands, feet, head, and other parts of the body, which, although very
beautiful, were not drawn in their proper relations, and, without
making them in any way correspond, should construct a monster instead
of a human being.

Accordingly, when I had long reflected, on this uncertainty of
mathematical tradition, I took the trouble to read again the books of
all the philosophers I could get hold of, to see if some one of them
had not once believed that there were other motions of the heavenly
bodies. First I found in Cicero that Niceties had believed in the
motion of the earth. Afterwards I found in Plutarch, likewise, that
some others had held the same opinion. This induced me also to begin to
consider the movability of the earth, and, although the theory appeared
contrary to reason, I did so because I knew that others before me had
been allowed to assume rotary movements at will, in order to explain
the phenomena of these celestial bodies. I was of the opinion that I,
too, might be permitted to see whether, by presupposing motion in the
earth, more reliable conclusions than hitherto reached could not be
discovered for the rotary motions of the spheres. And thus, acting on
the hypothesis of the motion which, in the following book, I ascribe
to the earth, and by long and continued observations, I have finally
discovered that if the motion of the other planets be carried over to
the relation of the earth and this is made the basis for the rotation
of every star, not only will the phenomena of the planets be explained
thereby, but also the laws and the size of the stars; all their spheres
and the heavens themselves will appear so harmoniously connected that
nothing could be changed in any part of them without confusion in the
remaining parts and in the whole universe.


                    THAT THE UNIVERSE IS SPHERICAL

First we must remark that the universe is spherical in form, partly
because this form being a perfect whole requiring no joints, is the
most complete of all, partly because it makes the most capacious
form, which is best suited to contain and preserve everything; or
again because all the constituent parts of the universe, that is the
sun, moon, and the planets appear in this form; or because everything
strives to attain this form, as appears in the case of drops of water
and other fluid bodies if they attempt to define themselves. So no one
will doubt that this form belongs to the heavenly bodies.


                   THAT THE EARTH IS ALSO SPHERICAL

That the earth is also spherical is therefore beyond question, because
it presses from all sides upon its center. Although by reason of
the elevations of the mountains and the depressions of the valleys
a perfect circle cannot be understood, yet this does not affect the
general spherical nature of the earth. This appears in the following
manner. To those who journey towards the North the north pole of the
daily revolution of the heavenly sphere seems gradually to rise, while
the opposite seems to sink. Most of the stars in the region of the Bear
seem not to set, while some of the southern stars seem not to rise at
all. So Italy does not see Canopes which is visible to the Egyptians.
And Italy sees the outermost star of the Stream, which our region of a
colder zone does not know. On the other hand to those who go towards
the South the others seem to rise and those to sink which are high in
our region. Moreover, the inclination of the Poles to the diameter
of the earth bears always the same relation, which could happen only
in the case of a sphere. So it is evident that the earth is included
between the two poles, and is therefore spherical in form. Let us add
that the inhabitants of the East do not observe the eclipse of the sun
or of the moon which occurs in the evening, and the inhabitants of the
West those which occur in the morning, while those who dwell between
see those later and these earlier. That the water also has the same
form can be observed from ships, in that the land which cannot be seen
from the deck, is visible from the mast-tree. And conversely if a light
be placed at the mast-head it seems to those who remain on the shores
gradually to sink and at last still sinking to disappear. It is clear
that the water also according to its nature continually presses like
the earth downward, and does not rise above its banks higher than its
convexity permits. So the land extends above the ocean as much as the
land happens to be higher.


WHETHER THE EARTH HAS A CIRCULAR MOTION, AND CONCERNING THE LOCATION OF
                               THE EARTH

As it has been already shown that the earth has the form of a sphere,
we must consider whether a movement also coincides with this form, and
what place the earth holds in the universe. Without this there will be
no secure results to be obtained in regard to the heavenly phenomena.
The great majority of authors of course agree that the earth stands
still in the center of the universe, and consider it inconceivable and
ridiculous to suppose the opposite. But if the matter is carefully
weighed it will be seen that the question is not yet settled and
therefore by no means to be regarded lightly. Every change of place
which is observed is due, namely, to a movement of the observed object
or of the observer, or to movements of both, naturally in different
directions, for if the observed object and the observer move in the
same manner and in the same direction no movement will be seen. Now it
is from the earth that the revolution of the heavens is observed and it
is produced for our eyes. Therefore if the earth undergoes no movement
this movement must take place in everything outside of the earth, but
in the opposite direction than if everything on the earth moved, and
of this kind is the daily revolution. So this appears to affect the
whole universe, that is, everything outside the earth with the single
exception of the earth itself. If, however, one should admit that this
movement was not peculiar to the heavens, but that the earth revolved
from west to east, and if this was carefully considered in regard to
the apparent rising and setting of the sun, the moon and the stars,
it would be discovered that this was the real situation. Since the
sky, which contains and shelters all things, is the common seat of all
things, it is not easy to understand why motion should not be ascribed
rather to the thing contained than to the containing, to the located
rather than to the location. From this supposition follows another
question of no less importance, concerning the place of the earth,
although it has been accepted and believed by almost all, that the
earth occupies the middle of the universe. But if one should suppose
that the earth is not at the center of the universe, that, however,
the distance between the two is not great enough to be measured on the
orbits of the fixed stars, but would be noticeable and perceptible on
the orbit of the sun or of the planets: and if one was further of the
opinion that the movements of the planets appeared to be irregular
as if they were governed by a center other than the earth, then such
an one could perhaps have given the true reasons for the apparently
irregular movement. For since the planets appear now nearer and now
farther from the earth, this shows necessarily that the center of their
revolutions is not the center of the earth: although it does not settle
whether the earth increases and decreases the distance from them or
they their distance from the earth.


REFUTATION OF THE ARGUMENT OF THE ANCIENTS THAT THE EARTH REMAINS STILL
        IN THE MIDDLE OF THE UNIVERSE, AS IF IT WERE ITS CENTER

From this and similar reasons it is supposed that the earth rests at
the center of the universe and that there is no doubt of the fact.
But if one believed that the earth revolved, he would certainly be
of the opinion that this movement was natural and not arbitrary. For
whatever is in accord with nature produces results which are the
opposite of those produced by force. Things upon which force or an
outside power has acted, must be injured and cannot long endure: what
happens by nature, however, preserves itself well and exists in the
best condition. So Ptolemy feared without good reason that the earth
and all earthly objects subject to the revolution would be destroyed
by the act of nature, since this latter is opposed to artificial acts,
or to what is produced by the human spirit. But why did not he fear
the same, and in a much higher degree, of the universe, whose motion
must be as much more rapid as the heavens are greater than the earth?
Or has the heaven become so immense because it has been driven outward
from the center by the inconceivable power of the revolution; while if
it stood still, on the contrary, it would collapse and fall together?
But surely if this is the case the extent of the heavens would increase
infinitely. For the more it is driven higher by the outward force of
the movement, so much the more rapid will the movement become, because
of the ever increasing circle which must be traversed in 24 hours; and
conversely if the movement grows the immensity of the heavens grows. So
the velocity would increase the size and the size would increase the
velocity unendingly. According to the physical law that the endless
cannot wear away nor in any way move, the heavens must necessarily
stand still.

But it is said that beyond the sky no body, no place, no vacant space,
in fact nothing at all exists; then it is strange that some thing
should be enclosed by nothing. But if the heaven is endless and is
bounded only by the inner hollow, perhaps this establishes all the more
clearly the fact that there is nothing outside the heavens, because
everything is within it, but the heaven must then remain unmoved.
The highest proof on which one supports the finite character of the
universe is its movement. But whether the universe is endless or
limited we will leave to the physiologues; this remains sure for us
that the earth enclosed between the poles, is bounded by a spherical
surface. Why therefore should we not take the position of ascribing
to a movement conformable to its nature and corresponding to its
form, rather than suppose that the whole universe whose limits are
not and cannot be known moves? and why will we not recognize that
the appearance of a daily revolution belongs to the heavens, but the
actuality to the earth; and that the relation is similar to that of
which one says: “We run out of the harbor, the lands and cities retreat
from us.” Because if a ship sails along quietly, everything outside
of it appears to those on board as if it moved with the motion of
the boat, and the boatman thinks that the boat with all on board is
standing still, this same thing may hold without doubt of the motion
of the earth, and it may seem as if the whole universe revolved. What
shall we say, however, of the clouds and other things floating, falling
or raising in the air--except that not only does the earth move with
the watery elements belonging with it, but also a large part of the
atmosphere, and whatever else is in any way connected with the earth;
whether it is because the air immediately touching the earth has the
same nature as the earth, or that the motion has become imparted to the
atmosphere. A like astonishment must be felt if that highest region
of the air be supposed to follow the heavenly motion, as shown by
those suddenly appearing stars which the Greeks call comets or bearded
stars, which belong to that region and which rise and set like other
stars. We may suppose that part of the atmosphere, because of its great
distance from the earth, has become free from the earthly motion. So
the atmosphere which lies close to the earth and all things floating in
it would appear to remain still, unless driven here and there by the
wind or some other outside force, which chance may bring into play;
for how is the wind in the air different from the current in the sea?
We must admit that the motion of things rising and falling in the air
is in relation to the universe a double one, being always made up of a
rectilinear and a circular movement. Since that which seeks of its own
weight to fall is essentially earthy, so there is no doubt that these
follow the same natural law as their whole; and it results from the
same principle that those things which pertain to fire are forcibly
driven on high. Earthly fire is nourished with earthly stuff, and it
is said that the flame is only burning smoke. But the peculiarity of
the fire consists in this that it expands whatever it seizes upon,
and it carries this out so consistently that it can in no way and
by no machinery be prevented from breaking its bonds and completing
its work. The expanding motion, however, is directed from the center
outward; therefore if any earthly material is ignited it moves upward.
So to each single body belongs a single motion, and this is evinced
preferably in a circular direction as long as the single body remains
in its natural place and its entirety. In this position the movement
is the circular movement which as far as the body itself is concerned
is as if it did not occur. The rectilinear motion, however, seizes
upon those bodies which have wandered or have been driven from their
natural position or have been in any way disturbed. Nothing is so much
opposed to the order and form of the world as the displacement of one
of its parts. Rectilinear motion takes place only when objects are
not properly related, and are not complete according to their nature
because they have separated from their whole and have lost their unity.
Moreover, objects which have been driven outward or away, leaving out
of consideration the circular motion, do not obey a single, simple
and regular motion, since they cannot be controlled simply by their
lightness or by the force of their weight, and if in falling they have
at first a slow movement the rapidity of the motion increases as they
fall, while in the case of earthly fire which is forced upwards--and
we have no means of knowing any other kind of fire--we will see that
its motion is slow as if its earthly origin thereby showed itself.
The circular motion, on the other hand, is always regular, because it
is not subject to an intermittent cause. Those other objects, however,
would cease to be either light or heavy in respect to their natural
movement if they reached their own place, and thus they would fit into
that movement. Therefore if the circular movement is to be ascribed
to the universe as a whole and the rectilinear to the parts, we might
say that the revolution is to the straight line as the natural state
is to sickness. That Aristotle divided motion into three sorts, that
from the center out, that inward toward the center, and that around
about the center, appears to be merely a logical convenience, just
as we distinguish point, line and surface, although one cannot exist
without the others, and none of them are found apart from bodies. This
fact is also to be considered, that the condition of immovability is
held to be nobler and more divine than that of change and inconstancy,
which latter therefore should be ascribed rather to the earth than
to the universe, and I would add also that it seems inconsistent to
attribute motion to the containing and locating element rather than to
the contained and located object, which the earth is. Finally since the
planets plainly are at one time nearer and at another time farther from
the earth, it would follow, on the theory that the universe revolves,
that the movement of the one and same body which is known to take place
about a center, that is the center of the earth, must also be directed
toward the center from without and from the center outward. The
movement about the center must therefore be made more general, and it
suffices if that single movement be about its own center. So it appears
from all these considerations that the movement of the earth is more
probable than its fixity, especially in regard to the daily revolution,
which is most peculiar to the earth.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 4: Selections from the Introduction to _De Orbium
Caelestium Revolutionibus_.]




                                  III

                             JOHANN KEPLER

                               1571-1630


 _Tycho Brahe (1546-1601), nobleman of Denmark, studied law at
 the University of Copenhagen and became attracted to astronomical
 studies by the occurrence of a predicted eclipse. Constructing his
 own instruments, he made observations of the stars at Augsburg
 and Wittenberg, and in 1576 established the first observatory at
 Huen, where he continued his work for twenty years. Banished from
 Germany, he was invited by Emperor Rudolph to Prague, where he began
 his compilation of the Rudolphin Tables which listed many of his
 observations on the locations of the planets. Hearing of Kepler’s
 interest in astronomy, he secured the young German’s assistance and
 assigned to him the study of the planet Mars, which study Kepler
 continued after Tycho Brahe’s death in 1601._

 _Johann Kepler, the son of an innkeeper, was born December 27, 1571,
 in Württemberg and sent to a local school, from which he was removed
 when he was nine years old because of his father’s impoverishment.
 After three years of work in the tavern, he was sent to a monastic
 school and thence to the University of Tübingen. Although he was very
 frail in physique, he was a good student and attained high scholarly
 standing. Becoming interested in the Copernican theory, in 1599 he was
 invited by Tycho Brahe to become his assistant at Prague._

 _Kepler found his master’s tables sufficiently accurate in his
 efforts to discover some recognizable motion of the planet Mars which
 would account for its apparent positions. In the course of this work
 he corrected some of the Ptolemaic ideas which Copernicus had not
 completely abandoned. The latter retained the epicycle motion of the
 planets within their larger revolutions in cycles. In comparing this
 theory with his tables, Kepler found that it would not satisfactorily
 account for the positions of Mars; and he was therefore led to the
 long studies and mathematical computations which finally resulted
 in his discovery of the orbit of Mars, and to the establishment of
 the first two of his three famous laws: “1. the planet describes an
 ellipse, the sun being in one focus; 2. the straight line joining the
 planet to the sun sweeps out equal areas in equal intervals of time.”
 (Sedgwick and Tyler, pp. 211-213). He published these laws in 1609 in
 his “Commentaries on the Motions of Mars.”_

 _In 1611, when his patron, Emperor Rudolph, was compelled to
 abdicate, Kepler was left penniless, but he moved to Linz where he was
 appointed to a professorship. In 1619 he published his “Harmony of
 the World,” which contained his third law: “The squares of the times
 of revolution of any two planets (including the earth) about the sun
 are proportional to the cubes of their mean distances from the sun.”
 (Sedgwick and Tyler, p. 213). This was the triumph about which he wrote
 in the year of its discovery, 1618: “What I prophesied twenty-two years
 ago, as soon as I found the heavenly orbits were of the same number
 as the five (regular) solids, what I fully believed long before I
 had seen Ptolemy’s Harmonies, what I promised my friends in the name
 of this book, which I christened before I was sixteen years old, I
 urged as an end to be sought, that for which I joined Tycho Brahe, for
 which I settled at Prague, for which I have spent most of my life at
 astronomical calculations--at last I have brought to light, and seen to
 be true beyond my fondest hopes. It is not eighteen months since I saw
 the first ray of light, three months since the unclouded sun-glorious
 sight! burst upon me. Let nothing confine me: I will indulge my sacred
 ecstasy. I will triumph over mankind by the honest confession that I
 have stolen the golden vases of the Egyptians to raise a tabernacle for
 my God far away from the lands of Egypt. If you forgive me, I rejoice;
 if you are angry, I cannot help it. The book is written; the die is
 cast. Let it be read now or by posterity, I care not which. It may well
 wait a century for a reader, as God had waited six thousand years for
 an observer.” Kepler died at Ratisbon, November 15, 1630._


                   ON THE PRINCIPLES OF ASTRONOMY[5]

What is _astronomy_? It is the science of treating of the causes
of those celestial appearances which we who live on the earth observe
and which mark the changes of times and seasons; by the studying of
which we are able to predict for the future the face of the heavens,
that is, the stellar phenomena, and to assign fixed dates for those
which have occurred in the past.

_Why is it called astronomy?_ From the law (νουος) or governance
of the stars (ἀστρα), that is, of the motions in which the stars move,
just as economy is named from the law of domestic affairs (οἰκονουία)
and paedonomy (παιδονουία) from the ruling of youths.

_What is the relation of this science to the other sciences?_ 1)
It is a branch of physics because it investigates the causes of natural
objects and events, and because among its subjects are the motions of
the heavenly bodies, and because it has the same end as physics, to
inquire into the conformation of the world and its parts.

2) Astronomy is the soul of geography and hydrography, for the various
appearances of the sky in various districts and regions of the earth
and sea are known only by astronomy.

3) Chronology is dependent upon it, because the movements of the
heavenly bodies prescribe seasons and years and date the histories.

4) Meteorology is also its subordinate, for the stars move and
influence this sublunary nature and even men themselves.

5) It includes a large part of optics, because it has a subject in
common with that; that is, the light of the heavenly bodies, and
because it corrects many errors of sight in regard to the character of
the earth and its motions.

6) It is, however, subordinate to the general subject of mathematics
and uses arithmetic and geometry as its two wings, studying the extent
and form of the bodies and motions of the universe and computing the
periods, by these means expediting its demonstrations and reducing them
to use and practical value.

_How many, then, are the branches of astronomical study?_ The
departments of the study of astronomy are five; historical, in the
matter of observations, optical as to the hypothesis, physical as
to the causes of the hypotheses, arithmetical as to the tables and
calculations, mechanical as to its instruments.

       *       *       *       *       *

_Since we must begin with appearances, explain how the world seems to
be made up._ The world is commonly thought, accepting the testimony
of the eyes, to be an immense structure consisting of two parts, the
earth and the sky.

_What do men imagine concerning the figure of the earth?_ The
earth seems to be a broad plane extending in a circle in every
direction around the spectator. And from this appearance of a plane
bounded by a great circle the appellation, _orbis terrarum_,
the circle of the earth, has arisen, and has been taken over by the
Scripture and among other nations.

_What do men imagine to be the center of the earth?_ Each nation,
unless it has become familiar with the notion of the circle, thinks by
the instinct of nature and the error of vision that its country is in
the center or middle of this plane circle. So the common people among
the Jews believe still that Jerusalem, the earliest home of their race,
is situated at the center of the world.

_What do men think about the waters?_ Since men proceeding as far
as possible in any direction finally came upon the ocean, some have
thought that the earth is like a disc swimming in the waters, and that
the waters are held up by the lower part of the sky, whence poets have
called the ocean, the father of all things. Others believe that a strip
of land surrounds the ocean which keeps the water from flowing away,
and these suppose there is land under the water, saying that the water
is held up by the earth. Besides these there are still others who,
since the ocean seems higher than the land if it is looked at from the
edge of the shore, believe that the earth is, as it were, sunk in the
waters and supernaturally guarded by the omnipotence of God lest the
waters rushing in from the deep should overwhelm it.

_What do men imagine to be under both the land and the waters?_
There has been great discussion among men marveling concerning the
foundation which could bear up the great mass of the earth so that
it should remain for so many centuries firm and immovable and should
not sink; and Heraclitus among the early philosophers, and Lactantius
among the ecclesiastics said that it reached down to the lowest root of
things.

_How about the other part of the world, the sky and its extent?_
Men have thought that the sky was not much larger than the earth, and
indeed was connected with the earth and the ocean at the circumference
of the circle, so that it bounded the earth; and that anyone going
that far, if it could be done, would run up against the sky, blocking
further progress. With this idea of men the Scriptures also agreed.

So also the poets said that Mt. Atlas, a lofty mountain on the
farthest shore of Africa, bore up the sky on his shoulders, and Homer
placed the Aethiopeans at the extremities of the rising and setting
sun, thinking that because of the contiguity of the earth and sky
there, the sun was so close to them that it burned their skin.

_What form do they ascribe to the sky?_ The eyes ascribe to the
sky the shape of a tent, extending over our heads and beyond the
sun, moon and stars, or rather the shape of an arch overspanning the
terrestrial plane, with a long curve, so that the part of the sky just
over the head of the spectator is much nearer to him than the part that
touches the mountains.

_What have men conceived in regard to the motion of the sky?_
Whether the sky moves or stands still is not apparent to the sight
because the tenuity of its substance escapes the eyes, unless indeed
those things appear to stand still in which the eye can perceive no
variation. But the changing positions of the sun, moon and stars in
relation to the ends of the earth was apparent to the eyes. For the
sun seems to emerge from an opening between the sky and the immovable
mountains and ocean, as if coming out of a chamber, and having
traversed the vault of the sky seems to sink again in the opposite
region; so also the moon, and the planets, and the whole host of stars
proceed as if strictly marshalled and drawn up in line, first one and
then the other marching along, each in his order and place.

And so, since the ocean lies beyond the extreme lands, the mass of men
have thought that the sun plunges into the ocean and is extinguished,
and from the opposite region a new sun issues forth daily from the
ocean. The poets have used this figure in their creations. But,
indeed, there have been even philosophers who have declared that on
the farthest shores of Lusitania could be heard the roar of the ocean
extinguishing the flames of the sun, as Strabo recounts.

       *       *       *       *       *

_I understand the forms of the sky and the earth and the atmosphere
surrounding the earth, also the place of the earth in the universe; now
I would ask what causes the stars to seem to rise daily from the one
part of the horizon and to sink in the opposite part; the motion of the
sky or of the earth?_ The astronomy of Copernicus shows that our
sight has led us astray in regard to this motion; for the stars do not
actually come up from beyond the mountains and climb toward the zenith,
but rather the mountains which surround us and which are a part of the
surface of the earth are revolved along with the whole globe about its
axis from west to east and by this revolution the immovable stars of
the east are disclosed to us one after the other, and those of the west
are obscured, so the stars are not passing over us, but the vertical
point is moving through the fixed stars.

_You say that by this marvelous hypothesis may be explained
satisfactorily all the phenomena of the first motion and the spherical
theory._ Just so, and that is the scope of this section, to
demonstrate in fact what has been suggested in words.

_How do you expect to be able to prove this absurd hypothesis,
and by what arguments?_ It is possible to demonstrate that this
first motion results from the revolution of the earth about its axis,
while the heavenly bodies are at rest (as far as this first motion is
concerned), by seven kinds of arguments: 1) from the subject of the
motion; 2) from the velocity of the motion; 3) from the equableness of
the motion; 4) from the cause of the motion, or the moving principle;
5) from the motive instruments, that is, the axis and the poles; 6)
from the object of the first motion; and 7) from the indications or
results.

_Demonstrate it then from the subject of the motion._ Nature does
not seek difficult means when she can use simple ones. Now, by the
rotation of the earth, a very small body, about its axis, toward the
east, the same thing is accomplished as by the rotation of the immense
universe about its axis toward the west. Just as it is more likely that
a man’s head turns in the auditorium than that the auditorium is turned
about his head, so it is more credible that the earth is rotating from
west to east, than that the rest of the machine of the universe is
revolved from east to west, since in both cases the same thing results.

If the first motion is in the heavenly bodies, then they are subject
to two motions, one common to the whole universe, the other particular
to each sphere; but it is much more probable that the two motions
should be distinct in regard to their subjects, so that the second set
of motions, which is multifold, should belong to each sphere, and the
first, which is single, should belong to the single body of the earth,
and to it alone.

_Why cannot the whole machinery of the universe be moved?_ The
universe is either infinite or finite. Suppose it to be the former,
according to the opinion of William Gilbert, who thinks that the
omnipotence of God is illustrated in this that the universe extends
outward infinitely, so that the infinite power of the creator would be
recognized from the infinite extent of the creation. Although this may
be refuted by metaphysical arguments, no argument on either side can be
drawn from astronomy, in which trust is placed rather in the evidence
of the senses than in abstract reasonings not dependent on observation.
But supposing this universe to be infinite, Aristotle has shown that
the whole universe should not be moved about in a revolution since it
is the whole.

But let the universe be finite; then there is nothing outside the
universe which would locate the universe but should remain quiet
itself. Where there is nothing that rests there is no motion. For 1)
motion is the separation of a movable thing from its place and its
transfer to another place: 2) the motion of a machine about an axis and
quiescent poles cannot be grasped by the mind where there is nothing in
respect to which the poles remain still.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 5: From _The Epitome of Astronomy_.]




                                  IV

                            GALILEO GALILEI

                               1564-1642


 _Galileo Galilei, born at Pisa, February 15, 1564, was the son of
 a mathematician who, seeing no future in that profession, had him
 educated for the practice of medicine. But when Galileo was about
 eighteen years of age, while observing a large lamp swinging in
 the Pisa cathedral, he noticed that, regardless of the length of
 the oscillation, the time did not vary. In spite of his father’s
 discouragements, therefore, he became absorbed in mathematics and
 abandoned the study of medicine. Applying himself to the study of
 motion, he performed his famous experiment of letting bodies of
 different weights fall from the leaning tower of Pisa, proving that
 things of unequal weight, if heavier than the resistance of air, fall
 with the same speed. The doctrine of inertia which he deduced from
 this and similar experiments decisively answered the opponents of
 Copernicus; for the principle stated that bodies would continue to
 move in the same direction forever unless their course was disturbed
 or opposed by another force, and that the motion of bodies resulted
 from independent forces operating upon them. His treatise on the center
 of gravity in solids earned him a lectureship at the University of
 Pisa._

 _Meeting malignant opposition at Pisa, he secured the chair of
 mathematics at Padua (which he held from 1592 to 1610) and there
 continued his observations and experiments in physics and chemistry.
 He succeeded in making a crude thermometer in 1600. In 1609 he learned
 that Hans Lippershey, an optician of Middleburg, had succeeded in
 making a telescope. He thereupon made one of his own and improved it
 until it had a power of magnifying thirty-two times, enabling him to
 discover the mountainous surface of the moon, the moons of the planet
 Jupiter, the fact that Venus showed different sides like the moon, and
 that many small stars made up the Milky Way._

 _In 1610 he left Padua for Florence, and by 1613 openly declared
 his acceptance of Copernican ideas. Immediately he was opposed by
 theologians, and after being given an opportunity to renounce his
 adherence to the new system of astronomy, was sentenced in 1616 not to
 hold, teach, or defend it. In 1623, when his friend Maffeo was made
 Pope Urban VIII, he wrote his dialogues on the system of the world. He
 had much difficulty in getting them published and succeeded only when
 he assured the authorities that they were not heretical. It was quite
 evident, however, that the dialogues were slightly concealed arguments
 for the acceptance of the Copernican system and consequently in 1633
 he was summoned before the Inquisition and compelled to renounce his
 heresy. In 1637, a few months after he had discovered the librations
 of the moon, he lost his sight. He died five years later, January 8,
 1642._


          THE COPERNICAN VERSUS THE PTOLEMAIC ASTRONOMIES[6]

Formerly I used frequently to visit the marvelous city of Venice
and to meet there Signore Giovan Francesco Sagredo, a man of most
distinguished ancestry and remarkable intelligence. Thither also came
from Florence, Signore Filippo Salviati, whose least claim to renown
was his noble blood and great wealth; a noble mind, that held no
enjoyment of greater price than that of study and thought. With both
of these men I often discussed these questions, in the presence of
a Peripatetic philosopher, who apparently valued the acquisition of
knowledge in no way in so high a degree, as he did the renown which his
interpretations of Aristotle had gained for him.

Now that cruel death has robbed the cities of Venice and Florence
of these two enlightened men in the bloom of their years, I have
endeavored, as far as my weak powers may permit, to perpetuate their
fame in these pages by making them the speakers in this dialogue.
The valiant Peripatetic also shall not fail to appear; because of
his over-weaning love for the commentary of Simplicius, it seemed
permissible to omit his own name and let him pass under that of his
favorite author. May the souls of these two great men accept this
public testimony of my undying love; may the recollection of their
eloquence aid me in setting down for posterity the spoken discussions.


                              SECOND DAY

SALVIATI: We departed yesterday so often and so far from the
direct path of our discussion, that I can scarcely return to the right
point and proceed without your help.

SAGREDO: I find it quite intelligible that you are somewhat at
a loss, since you have had your head so full of both the things already
brought forward and things still to be discussed. I, however, who as
merely a listener have in mind only the things already discussed, may
I hope set our investigation straight by a brief summary of what has
been gone over. So, if my memory fails not, the chief result of our
yesterday’s conversation was that we tested thoroughly which of the
two theories was the more probable and better grounded; that according
to which the substance of the heavenly bodies is unproducible,
indestructible, unchangeable, intangible, in brief not subject to
any variation aside from change of location, and so presents a fifth
element which is entirely distinct from our elementary, producible,
destructible, changeable bodies; or the other view, according to which
an incongruity between parts of the universe is rejected, our earth
rather enjoys the same privileges as the rest of the constituent
bodies of the universe, in a word, is a freely moving ball just as
the moon, Jupiter, Venus, or any other planet. Finally we noticed the
many similarities in particular between the earth and the moon, and of
course with the moon more than any other planet because of the closer
and more definite knowledge which we possess of it by reason of its
less distance. Since we agreed that this second opinion possessed the
greater probability, the logical consequence, it seems to me, is that
we should investigate the question whether we should hold the world
immovable, as has been formerly believed in general, or movable as some
ancient philosophers believed and as some recent ones suppose: and if
movable, how its movement could have been produced.

SALV.: Let us begin our discussion with the admission
that whatever sort of motion may be ascribed the earth, we, as its
inhabitants and therefore partakers in the movement, would be
unconscious of it, as if it did not occur, since we can only take into
consideration earthly things. Therefore it is necessary that this
movement should seem to belong to all the other bodies and visible
objects in common which, separated from the earth, have no share in its
movement. The correct method of determining whether movement is to be
attributed to the earth, and what movement, is that one should inquire
and observe whether an apparent movement can be ascribed to the bodies
outside of the earth, which belongs to all of them in the same degree.
So a movement which, for example, can be supposed of the moon, and not
of Venus or Jupiter or other stars, cannot be peculiar to the earth.
Now there is such a general movement governing all other objects,
namely that which the sun, moon, planets, fixed stars, in a word the
whole universe with the single exception of the earth, seems to follow
from east to west within the space of twenty-four hours. This, at least
at first glance, may be just as well attributed to the earth alone, as
to the rest of the entire universe except the earth.

SAGR.: I understand clearly that your suggestion is correct.
An objection, however, forces itself upon me that I cannot solve. That
is, since Copernicus ascribes to the earth a further movement aside
from the daily one, according to the above mentioned principle this
should be apparently un-noticeable on the earth, but should be visible
in the rest of the universe. I come then to the conclusion that either
he plainly erred when he ascribed to the earth a movement to which
no counterpart is apparent in the firmament, or else such a movement
exists, and then Ptolemaus is guilty of a second error in that he did
not refute with arguments this movement as well as that daily rotation.

SALV.: Your objection is very just. If we take up this
other movement, you shall see how much superior in intelligence was
Copernicus to Ptolemaus, in that he saw what this one did not, namely
how wonderfully this second motion is reflected in the rest of the
heavenly bodies. For the present, however, we will leave this aside and
return to our first consideration. Proceeding from the most general
suppositions, I will present the arguments which seem to favor the
motion of the earth, in order then to hear the opposing arguments
of Signore Simplicio. First, then, when we consider the immense
circumference of the stellar sphere in comparison with the smallness
of the earth, which is contained in that several million times, and
therefore regard the velocity of motion which would be necessary for
an entire revolution in the course of a day and night, I am unable to
understand how any one could hold it more reasonable and credible that
it is this whole stellar sphere that moves and that the earth remains
still.

SAGR.: Even if universal phenomena which depend upon these
movements could be explained as readily by the one hypothesis as by
the other, yet by the first general impression I would regard as more
unreasonable the view that the whole universe moves; just as if any
one should climb to the top of your dome for the purpose of getting
a view of the city and its environs and then should demand that the
whole region be made to move around him to save him the trouble of
turning his head. In any event, there would have to be great advantages
connected with this theory, which were lacking in the other, in
order that such an absurdity should be balanced and outweighed and
should appear more credible than the opposite opinion. But Aristotle,
Ptolemaus, and Signore Simplicio must find such advantages in their
theory, and I should be glad if we might hear these advantages if they
exist, or if they do not, that some one would explain to me why they do
not and cannot exist.

SALV.: If, in spite of every sort of investigation, I am
able to find no such differences, I believe I have thereby discovered
that such difference does not exist. So in my opinion it is useless
to pursue this further: rather let us proceed. Motion is only so far
motion and acts as such, if it stands in relation to things which lack
motion. In relation to things that are all in the same degree affected
by it, it is as much without effect as if it did not take place. The
wares with which a ship is loaded move, when they depart from Venice
and arrive at Aleppo, passing Korfu, Candia, Cyprus etc; since Venice,
Korfu and Candia remain fixed and do not move with the ship. But in
respect to the bales, chests, and other pieces of baggage which are
on the ship as cargo or ballast, the movement of the ship itself from
Venice to Syria is as good as non-existent, since their position in
relation to one another does not change; and this is due to the fact
that the movement is a common one in which they all take part. If of
the wares on the ship one bale moves only an inch away from the chest,
this is for it a greater movement in relation to the chest, than the
whole journey of 2,000 miles which they undergo in common.

Therefore, since plainly the motion which many movable bodies undergo
in common is without effect and, with regard to their mutual position
toward one another, it is as if it did not exist, for there is no
change among them; and since it only affects the relative position
of such bodies as do not share in the movement, for in this case the
mutual relation is changed; since we have divided the universe into
two parts, of which one must be movable and the other immovable; then
for all purposes this movement will be of the same effect whether it
is ascribed to the earth alone or to all the rest of the universe. For
the working of such a motion is on nothing but the relative position in
which the earth and the heavenly bodies stand to one another, and aside
from this relative position nothing changes. If now it is indifferent
for accomplishing this result whether the earth alone moves and the
whole universe rests, or the earth rests and the whole universe is
subject to one common movement, who can believe that Nature--who by
common agreement does not employ great means when she can obtain the
same result by smaller ones--would have undertaken to set in motion
an immeasurable number of mighty bodies, and that with incredible
velocity, to accomplish what could be obtained by the moderate motion
of one single body around the center?

SIMPL.: I do not agree that that mighty movement would be as
if it did not happen in regard to the sun, the moon, the innumerable
host of fixed stars. Do you call it nothing that the sun goes from
one meridian to another, rises from one horizon, sinks under another,
brings now day, now night; that the moon goes through similar changes
and likewise the other planets, as well as the fixed stars?

SALV.: All the changes mentioned by you are such only with
respect to the earth. To demonstrate this, only imagine yourself away
from the earth; there is then no rising or setting of the sun, no
horizons, no meridians, no day, no night; in a word, by the movement
mentioned no change in the relation of the moon to the sun or to any
other star is evoked. All these changes have reference to the earth;
they are supposed only because the sun is first visible in China, then
Egypt, Greece, France, Spain, America, and so on, and so also for the
moon and the other heavenly bodies. The same process would occur in
the same way, if, without disturbing so vast a part of the universe,
the earth alone should be revolved.

The difficulty is however doubled since a second very important one is
added. That is, if one attributes to the firmament this mighty motion,
one must regard it as necessarily opposed to the particular movements
of all the planets, all of which indisputably have their own movements
from west to east, and in comparison very moderate movements at that.
One is then forced to the conclusion that they depart from that
rapid daily motion, namely from east to west, to go in the opposite
direction. But, if we suppose that the earth moves, the opposition of
motions disappears and the single movement from west to east fits in
with all the facts and explains them most satisfactorily.

SIMPL.: As far as this opposition of motions is concerned that
has little importance, since Aristotle proves that the circular motions
are not opposed to one another and that the apparent opposition cannot
actually be called so.

SALV.: Does Aristotle prove that or merely suppose it,
because it aids him for a certain purpose? If, according to his own
declaration, those things are opposed which mutually destroy one
another I do not see how two moving bodies which meet one another in a
circular motion should do one another less harm than if they meet on a
straight line.

SAGR.: Wait a moment, I pray. Tell me, Signore Simplicio, if
two knights run into one another with leveled lances on the open field,
if two squadrons or two streams on their way to the sea break through
and unite with one another, would you call such collisions opposed
movements?

SIMPL.: Of course we would call them opposed.

SAGR.: How then is there no opposition in circular motions?
For the movements mentioned take place upon the surface of the earth
or water, both of which are recognized to be circular in form and so
the motions must be circular. Do you understand, Signore Simplicio,
what circular motions are not opposed to one another? Two circles which
touch each other on the outside and of which the revolution of one is
in a reverse direction from that of the other. If, however, one circle
is within the other, then motions in different directions must be
opposed to one another.

SALV.: Whether opposed or not opposed is merely a strife of
words. I know that in fact it is simpler and more natural to accomplish
everything with one motion than to call in two. If you do not wish to
call them opposite, then call them reverse. Moreover, I mention this
introduction of a double movement not as something impossible, and in
no way propose to deduce from it a strong proof for the motion of the
earth, but merely a high degree of probability for it.

The improbability of the movement of the universe about the earth is
tripled, however, by the complete upsetting of that arrangement which
governs all the heavenly bodies whose circular motion is accepted not
doubtfully but with full assurance. That is, that in such cases the
larger the orbit the longer the time required for its completion,
and the smaller, the shorter. Saturn, whose course surpasses all the
planets in extent, completes it in thirty years. Jupiter revolves in a
smaller circle in twelve years. Mars in two, the moon in a month. We
see clearly in the case of the Medicean stars [the moons of Jupiter]
that the one nearest Jupiter goes through its orbit in a very short
time, namely, forty-two hours, the next nearest in three and a half
days, the third in seven days, and the farthest removed in sixteen
days. This thoroughly constant rule remains unchanged if we ascribe
the twenty-four hour movement to the revolution of the earth, but if
we suppose the earth to remain unmoved, we must proceed from the short
period of the moon to increasingly greater periods, to the two year
period of Mars, the twelve year period of Jupiter, the thirty year
period of Saturn, and then abruptly to a disproportionately larger
orbit, to which must also be ascribed the revolution in twenty-four
hours. And these suppositions entail the smallest part of the
disturbance of the otherwise constant law. For when one passes from
the orbit of Saturn to those of the fixed stars and attributes to them
even greater orbits, which correspond to the period of revolution
of many thousands of years, one must pass from this by a much more
disproportionate transition to that other movement and ascribe to them
a period of revolution about the earth of twenty-four hours. But if
the movement of the earth is supposed, the regularity of the period is
accounted for in the best possible way; from the slow period of Saturn
we arrive at the immovable fixed star.

A fourth difficulty also is encountered which must be added if
we suppose the motion of the smaller sphere. I mean the great
dissimilarity in movements of these stars, some of which must revolve
at a tremendous rate in immense circles, others slowly in smaller
circles, according as they are placed at greater or smaller distances
from the pole. And not only the size of the different circles and so
the velocity of movement varies greatly in different fixed stars, but
also the same stars change their courses and their velocity; herein
is the fifth difficulty. That is, those stars which 2,000 years ago
stood on the equator of the stellar sphere and thereafter moved in
the greatest circles, must now, since to-day they have moved several
degrees from it, move more slowly and in smaller circles. Within a
conceivable time it will happen that one of those which have been
continually moving will eventually reach the pole and cease to revolve,
then later, after a period of rest, begin to move again. The other
stars, however, which undoubtedly move, all have, as has been said, as
orbit an immense circle and move in it without change.

The improbability is increased (and this may be called a sixth
difficulty) for him who investigates basic principles, by the fact that
one cannot imagine the firmness which that immense sphere must possess,
in whose depths so many stars are so solidly fixed that in spite of
such varieties of motions they are held together in the revolution
without in any way changing their relative positions. But if according
to the most probable view the heavens are fluid, so that each star may
describe its own orbit, by what law and according to what principles
are their orbits governed, so that seen from the earth they appear as
if held in one sphere? To accomplish this it seems to me it would be
easier and more convenient to make them stationary instead of movable,
just as the paving stones in the market place are kept in order more
easily than the troops of children who race over them.

Finally the seventh objection; if we ascribe the daily revolution to
the highest heavens we must suppose this to be of such power and force
that it bears along the innumerable crowd of fixed stars, every one a
body of immense mass and much larger than the earth, further, all the
planets, although these by their nature move in an opposite direction.
Moreover, we must suppose that the element of fire and the greater
portion of the air is also borne along; therefore, singly and alone the
little earth ball withstands stubbornly and independently this mighty
force: a supposition that seems to me to have much against it. I cannot
explain how the earth, a body freely suspended and balanced on its
axis, inclined by nature as much toward motion as the rest, surrounded
by a fluid medium, is not seized on by this general revolution. We do
not encounter this difficulty, however, if we suppose the earth to
move, a body so small, so inconsiderable in comparison with the whole
universe that it could have no effect at all upon this.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 6: Translated from the _Dialogo dei due Massima Systemi del
Mondo_ (1632).]




                                   V

                            WILLIAM HARVEY

                               1578-1657


 _In 1615 William Harvey stated his theory of the circulation of the
 blood, which he derived from patient observations, in his lectures
 on anatomy. The theory was epoch-making in the history of physiology
 because it initiated the study of the chemical constituency of the
 blood and of its function in nutrition._

 _Harvey, born April 1, 1578, in the south of England, attended the
 University of Cambridge, and took his degree in 1597. The following
 four years he studied at Padua under Fabricius. In 1602, when he
 returned to England, he began the practice of medicine, and in 1609
 became connected with St. Bartholomew’s Hospital. He published his
 “Excercitatio” in 1628, served for several years as physician to
 Charles I, and retired in 1646 to private life. He died June 3,
 1657._

 _He described the process of his discovery as follows: “I frequently
 and seriously bethought me, and long revolved in my mind, what might be
 the quantity of blood which was transmitted, in how short a time its
 passage might be effected, and the like; and not finding it possible
 that this could be supplied by the juices of the ingested aliment
 without the veins on the one hand being drained, and the arteries on
 the other hand becoming ruptured through the excessive charge of blood,
 unless the blood should somehow find its way from the arteries into
 the veins, and so return to the right side of the heart; I began to
 think whether there might not be a motion, as it were, in a circle. Now
 this I afterwards found to be true; and I finally saw that the blood,
 forced by the action of the left ventricle into the arteries, was
 distributed to the body at large, and its several parts, in the same
 manner as it is sent through the lungs, impelled by the right ventricle
 into the pulmonary artery, and that it then passed through the veins
 and along the vena cava, and so round to the left ventricle in the
 manner already indicated,--which motion we may be allowed to call
 circular._”


                THE CIRCULATION OF BLOOD IN ANIMALS[7]

Thus far I have spoken of the passages of the blood from the veins
into the arteries, and of the manner in which it is transmitted and
distributed by the action of the heart; points to which some, moved
either by the authority of Galen or Columbus, or the reasonings of
others, will give in their adhesion. But what remains to be said upon
the quantity and source of the blood which thus passes, is of so novel
and unheard-of character, that I not only fear injury to myself from
the envy of the few, but I tremble lest I have mankind at large for my
enemies, so much doth wont and custom, that become as another nature,
and doctrine once sown and that hath struck deep root, and respect
for antiquity influence all men: Still the die is cast, and my trust
is in my love of truth, and the candour that inheres in cultivated
minds. And sooth to say, when I surveyed my mass of evidence, whether
derived from vivisections, and my various reflections on them, or from
the ventricles of the heart and the vessels that enter into and issue
from them, the symmetry and size of these conduits,--for nature doing
nothing in vain, would never have given them so large a relative size
without a purpose,--or from the arrangement and intimate structure
of the valves in particular, and of the other parts of the heart in
general, with many other things besides, I frequently and seriously
bethought me, and long revolved in my mind, what might be the quantity
of blood that was transmitted, in how short a time its passage might
be effected, and the like; and not finding it possible that this could
be supplied by the juices of the ingested aliment without the veins on
the one hand becoming drained, and the arteries on the other getting
ruptured, through the excessive charge of blood, unless the blood
should somehow find its way from the arteries into the veins, and so
return to the right side of the heart; I began to think whether there
might not be _A Motion, As It Were, In A Circle_. Now this I
afterward found to be true; and I finally saw that the blood, forced
by the action of the left ventricle into the arteries, was distributed
to the body at large, and its several parts, in the same manner as it
is sent through the lungs, impelled by the right ventricle into the
pulmonary artery, and that it then passes through the veins and along
the vena cava, and so round to the left ventricle in the manner already
indicated. Which motions we may be allowed to call circular, in the
same way as Aristotle says that the air and rain emulate the circular
motion of the superior bodies; for the moist earth, warmed by the sun,
evaporates; the vapours drawn upwards are condensed, and descending
in the form of rain, moisten the earth again; and by this arrangement
are generations of living things produced; and in like manner too are
tempests and meteors engendered by the circular motion, and by the
approach and recession of the sun.

And so, in all likelihood, does it come to pass in the body, through
the motion of the blood; the various parts are nourished, cherished,
quickened by the warmer, more perfect, vaporous, spiritous, and, as
I may say, alimentive blood; which, on the contrary, in contact with
these parts becomes cooled, coagulated, and, so to speak, effete;
whence it returns to its sovereign the heart, as if to its source,
or to the inmost home of the body, there to recover its state of
excellence, or perfection.

Here it resumes its due fluidity and receives an infusion of natural
heat--powerful, fervid, a kind of treasury of life, and is impregnated
with spirits, and it might be said with balsam; and thence it is again
dispersed; and all this depends on the motion and action of the heart.

The heart, consequently, is the beginning of life; the sun of the
microcosm, even as the sun in his turn might well be designated the
heart of the world; for it is the heart by whose virtue and pulse
the blood is moved, perfected, made apt to nourish, and is preserved
from corruption and coagulation; it is the household divinity which,
discharging its function, nourishes, cherishes, quickens the whole
body, and is indeed the foundation of life, the source of all action.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 7: From _An Anatomical Disquisition on the Motion of the
Heart-Blood in Animals_.]




                                  VI

                             ROBERT BOYLE

                               1627-1691


 _Robert Boyle, fourteenth child of the Earl of Cork, was born
 January 25, 1627, in Munster, Ireland. He went to Eton, studied under
 the rector of Stalbridge, and later traveled on the Continent under
 private tutors. On the death of his father in 1644, he inherited the
 manor at Stalbridge. At the age of eighteen he became associated with
 the English scientific investigators at Oxford who later founded
 the Royal Society, and engaged actively in physical experiments and
 researches. The greatest of his achievements was his discovery of the
 law of the compressibility of gases. He died December 30, 1691._


      THE DISCOVERY OF THE LAW OF THE COMPRESSIBILITY OF GASES[8]

We took a long glass tube, which, by a dexterous hand and the help of a
lamp, was in such a manner crooked at the bottom, that the part turned
up was almost parallel to the rest of the tube, and the orifice of
this shorter leg of the syphon (if I may so call the whole instrument)
being hermetically sealed, the length of it was divided into inches
(each of which was subdivided into eight parts) by a straight list of
paper, which, containing those divisions, was carefully pasted all
along it. Then putting in as much quicksilver as served to fill the
arch or bended part of the syphon, that the mercury standing in a level
might reach in one leg to the bottom of the divided paper, and just
to the same height or horizontal line in the other, we took care, by
frequently inclining the tube, so that the air might freely pass from
one leg into the other by the sides of the mercury (we took, I say,
care), that the air at last included in the shorter cylinder should be
the same laxity with the rest of the air about it. This done, we began
to pour quicksilver into the longer leg of the syphon, which, by its
weight pressing up that in the shorter leg, did by degrees straighten
the included air; and continuing this pouring in of quicksilver till
the air in the shorter leg was by condensation reduced to take up but
half the space it possessed (I say possessed, not filled) before, we
cast our eyes upon the longer leg of the glass, upon which we likewise
pasted a slip of paper carefully divided into inches and parts, and we
observed, not without delight and satisfaction, that the quicksilver
in that longer part of the tube was 29 inches higher than the other.
Now that this observation does both very well agree with and confirm
our hypothesis, will be easily discerned by him that takes notice what
we teach: and Monsieur Pascal and our English friend’s [Mr. Townley’s]
experiments prove, that the greater the weight is that leans upon the
air, the more forcible is its endeavor of dilation, and consequently
its power of resistance (as other springs are stronger when bent by
greater weights). For this being considered, it will appear to agree
rarely well with the hypothesis, that as according to it the air in
that degree of density, and correspondent measure of resistance, to
which the weight of the incumbent atmosphere had brought it, was unable
to counterbalance and resist the pressure of a mercurial cylinder of
about 29 inches, as we are taught by the Torricellian experiment; so
here the same air being brought to a degree of density about twice
as great as that it had before, obtains a spring twice as strong as
formerly. As may appear by its being able to sustain or resist a
cylinder of 29 inches in the longer tube, together with the weight of
the atmospherical cylinder that leaned upon those 29 inches of mercury;
and, as we just now inferred from the Torricellian experiment, was
equivalent to them.

(_The tube broke at this point and, unable to proceed after several
similar efforts, Boyle tried the converse experiment--to determine the
spring of rarefied air. A tube, about 6 feet in length, and sealed at
one end, was nearly filled with mercury, and into it was placed_)--

A slender glass pipe of about the bigness of a swan’s quill, and open
at both ends; all along of which was pasted a narrow list of paper,
divided into inches and half-quarters. This slender pipe being thrust
down into the greater tube almost filled with quicksilver, the glass
helped to make it swell to the top of the tube; and the quicksilver
getting in at the lower orifice of the pipe filled it up till the
mercury included in that was near about a level with the surface of
the surrounding mercury in the tube. There being, as near as we could
guess, little more than an inch of the slender pipe left above the
surface of the restagnant mercury, and consequently unfilled therewith,
the prominent orifice was carefully closed with sealing-wax melted;
after which the pipe was let alone for a while that the air, dilated a
little by the heat of the wax, might, upon refrigeration, be reduced
to its wonted density. And then we observed, by the help of the
above-mentioned list of paper, whether we had not included somewhat
more or somewhat less than an inch of air; and in either case we were
fain to rectify the error by a small hole made (with a heated pin) in
the wax, and afterward closed up again. Having thus included a just
inch of air, we lifted up the slender pipe by degrees, till the air
was dilated to an inch, an inch and a half, two inches, etc., and
observed in inches and eighths the length of the mercurial cylinder,
which, at each degree of the air’s expansion, was impelled above the
surface of the restagnant mercury in the tube. The observations being
ended, we presently made the Torricellian experiment with the above
mentioned great tube of 6 feet long, that we might know the height of
the mercurial cylinder for that particular day and hour, which height
we found to be 29-3/4 inches.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 8: From Thorpe, _Essays on Historical Chemistry_.]




                                  VII

                          CHRISTIAN HUYGHENS

                               1629-1695


 _Christian Huyghens was born at The Hague, April 14, 1629. He
 studied law in Breda, but becoming attracted to the study of
 mathematics he neglected his legal practice for it. In 1655 he
 improved the method of grinding telescopic lenses, and, assisted
 by his brother, discovered the sixth satellite of Saturn and the
 fact that it was belted with rings. In 1657 he presented to the
 States-General the first pendulum clock. In 1678 he evolved his wave
 theory of light, and published it at Leyden in 1690. He died at The
 Hague, June 8, 1695._


                      THE WAVE THEORY OF LIGHT[9]

Proofs in optics, as in every science in which mathematics is applied
to matter, are founded upon facts from experience--as for example,
that light moves in straight lines, that the angles of incidence and
reflection are equal, and that light rays are refracted in accordance
with the law of sines [i. e., that the ratio between the sines of the
incident and refracted ray is constant for the same substance.] For
this last law is now as generally and surely known as either of the
others.

Most writers in optics have been content to assume these facts, but
others more curious have attempted to discover the source and reason of
these phenomena, looking upon them as being in themselves interesting
data. Yet although they have propounded some ingenious theories,
intelligent readers still require a fuller explanation before being
entirely satisfied. Therefore I herein offer some considerations on the
matter with the hope of making clearer this branch of physics which has
not improperly gained the reputation of being very obscure.

I feel myself particularly indebted to those that first began to study
these profound subjects, and to lead us to hope them capable of orderly
explanation. Yet I have been surprised to find these very investigators
accepting arguments far from clear as if proof conclusive. No one has
yet offered even a probable explanation of the first two remarkable
phenomena of light,--why it moves in straight lines, and why rays from
any and all directions can cross one another without interference.

I shall attempt in this treatise to submit clearer and more probable
reasons, along the lines of modern philosophy, first for the
transmission of light, and, second, for its reflection when it meets
certain bodies.

Further, I shall explain the fact of rays said to undergo refraction in
passing through various transparent bodies. Here I shall consider also,
the refractions due to the differing densities of the atmosphere. Later
I shall investigate the remarkable refraction occurring in Icelandic
crystals. Finally, I shall study the different shapes necessary in
transparent and reflecting bodies in order to bring together rays upon
a single point or to deflect them in different ways. Here we shall see
how easy it is by our new theory to determine not alone the ellipses,
hyperbolas, and other curves which M. Descartes has so shrewdly
constructed for this end, but as well the curve that one surface of a
lens must have when the other surface is known, as spherical, plane, or
any other figure.

We cannot but believe that light is the motion of a certain material.
Thus when we reflect on its production, we discover that here on
the earth it is usually emitted from fire and flame, and that these
unquestionably contain bodies in rapid motion, since they can soften
and melt many other more solid substances. If we note its effects, we
see that when light is brought to a point, as, for example, by concave
mirrors, it can cause combustion the same as fire: that is, it can
force bodies apart, a power that certainly argues motion, at least in
that true science where one believes all natural phenomena to result
from mechanical causes. Moreover, in my mind we must either admit this
or give up all hope of ever understanding anything in natural science.

Since, according to this philosophy, it is believed certain that the
sensation of sight is produced only by the impulse of some form of
matter against the nerves at the base of the eye, we have yet another
reason for believing light to be a motion in the substance lying
between us and the body producing the light.

As soon as we consider, moreover, the enormous speed with which light
travels in every direction, and the fact that when rays come from
different directions, even from those exactly opposite, they cross
without interference, it must be plain that we do not see luminous
objects by means of particles transmitted from the objects to us, as a
shot or an arrow moves through the air. For surely this would not allow
for the two qualities of light just mentioned, particularly the latter
(that of speed). Light, then, is transmitted in some other way, a
comprehension of which we may get from our knowledge of how sound moves
through the air.

We know that sound is sent out in all directions through the medium of
the air, a substance invisible and impalpable, by means of a motion
that is communicated successively from one part of the air to the next;
and as this movement has the same speed in all directions, it must form
spherical surfaces that keep enlarging until at last they strike the
ear. Now there can be no doubt that light likewise reaches us from a
luminous substance through some motion caused in the matter lying in
the intervening space,--for we have seen above that this cannot take
place through transmission of matter from one place to another.

If, moreover, light requires time for its passage--a matter we shall
discuss in a moment--it will then follow that this movement is caused
in the substance gradually, and therefore is transmitted, like sound,
by surfaces and spherical waves. I call these _waves_ because of
their likeness to those formed when one throws a pebble into water,
which are examples of gradual propagation in circles, although from a
different cause and on a plane surface.

In regard to the question of light requiring time for its transmission,
let us consider whether there is any experimental evidence against it.

What experiments we can make here on the earth with sources of light
placed at great distances (although indicating that it does not take a
sensible time for light to pass over these distances) are subject to
the objection that these distances are yet too small, and that we can
only argue that the movement of light is enormously fast. M. Descartes
thought it to be instantaneous and based his opinion upon much better
reasons taken from the eclipse of the moon. Yet as I shall make clear,
even this evidence is not decisive. I shall state the matter in a
somewhat different way from his in order more easily to exhibit all the
consequences.

Suppose S to be the position of the sun, E A part of the orbit of the
earth, S E M a straight line intersecting in M, the orbit of the moon,
represented by the circle A M.

Now if light requires time--say an hour--to move the distance between
the earth and the moon, then [at the time of an eclipse] it follows
that when the earth has come to E its shadow, or the stoppage of the
light of the sun, will not yet have reached M [the moon], and will
not for an hour. Counting from the instant the earth reaches E, it
will be an hour before it will reach M if it is to be obscured there.
This eclipse will not be seen from the earth for yet another hour.
Suppose that during these two hours the earth has moved to X, the moon
appearing eclipsed at M, the sun still being seen at S. For I assume as
does Copernicus that the sun is fixed and since light moves in straight
lines, is always seen in its true position.

But as a matter of fact, we are assured that the eclipsed moon always
appears directly opposite the sun; while on the above supposition [that
light takes an hour in passing between the moon and the earth], its
position ought to be back of the straight line by the angle Y X M, the
supplement of the angle S X M. But this is not the case, for this angle
Y X M would be very easily noticed, it being about 33 degrees. For by
our analysis (found in the essay on the causes of the phenomena of
Saturn), the distance from the sun to the earth, S E, is about 12,000
times the diameter of the earth, and hence 400 times the distance of
the moon, which is 30 diameters. The angle X M E then will be nearly
400 times as great as E S X, which is 5 minutes, i. e., the angular
distance travelled by the earth in two hours [the earth traversing
almost a degree in a day]. Thus the angle E M X is almost 33 degrees,
and likewise the angle M X Y, being 5 minutes greater [than E M X].

Now it must be remembered that in this computation it is assumed that
the speed of light is such as to consume an hour in passing from here
to the moon. But if we assume it to take only a minute of time, then
the angle Y X M would amount to only 33 minutes, and if it only takes
ten seconds, this angle will be less than six minutes. Now so small
an angle is not observable in a lunar eclipse and hence it is not
permissible to argue that light is absolutely instantaneous.

It is rather unusual, we admit, to take for granted a speed 100,000
times as great as that of sound, which (following my experiments)
travels about 180 toises [about 1150 feet] in a second, or during a
pulse-beat. Yet this supposition is not at all impossible, for it is
not necessary to carry a body at such speed but only for motion to
traverse successively from one point to another.

Hence I do not hesitate in this matter to assume that the passage
of light takes time, for on this assumption all phenomena can be
explained, while on the contrary supposition none of them can be
explained. In fact, it seems to me and to many others as well, that
M. Descartes, whose purpose has been to discuss all physical matters
clearly, and who has certainly succeeded in this better than any one
before him, has written nothing on light and its qualities that is not
either hard to understand or even incomprehensible.

Moreover, this idea that I have propounded as an hypothesis has lately
been made a well nigh established fact by that keen calculation of
Roemer, whose method I will here take occasion to describe, on the
expectation that he will himself in the future fully confirm this
theory.

His method, the same as the one we have just discussed, is
astronomical. He shows not only that light takes time for its passage,
but calculates also its speed and that this must be at least six times
as much as the rate I have just given as an estimate.

In his demonstration he uses the eclipses of the small satellites that
revolve around Jupiter, and very frequently pass into his shadow.
Roemer’s reasoning is this:

Let S be the sun, B C D E the yearly orbit of the earth, J Jupiter and
G H the orbit of his nearest satellite, for this one because of its
short period is better suited to this investigation than any one of the
other three. Suppose G to be the point where the satellite enters, and
H where it leaves, Jupiter’s shadow.

Suppose that when the earth is at B, the satellite is seen to emerge
[at G], at some time before the last quarter. Were the earth to remain
stationary there, 42-1/2 hours would elapse before the next emergence
would take place, for this much time is taken by the satellite in
making one revolution in its orbit and returning to opposition to the
sun. For example, if the earth remained at B during 30 revolutions,
then after 30 times 42-1/2 hours, the satellite would again be seen
to emerge. If in the meantime the earth has moved to C, farther from
Jupiter, it is clear that if light requires time for its passage, the
emergence of the satellite will be seen later when the earth is at C
than when at B. For we must add to the 30 times 42-1/2 hours, the time
occupied by light in passing over the difference between the distances
[of the earth from Jupiter] G B and G C, i. e., M C. So in the other
quarter, when the earth travels from D to E, approaching Jupiter, the
eclipses will occur earlier when the earth is at E than when at D.

Now by many observations of these eclipses throughout ten years, it is
shown that these inequalities are actually of some moment, amounting to
as much as ten minutes or more: whence it is argued that in traversing
the whole diameter of the earth’s orbit, K L, double the distance from
the earth to the sun, light takes about 22 minutes.

The motion of Jupiter in its orbit while the earth passes from B
to C or from D to E has been taken into consideration in Roemer’s
calculation, where it is also proved that these inequalities cannot
be caused by any irregularity or eccentricity in the movement of the
satellite.

Now if we consider the enormous size of this diameter K L [the earth’s
orbit] which I have estimated to be about 24,000 times that of the
earth, we get some comprehension of the extraordinary speed of light.

Even if K L were only 22,000 diameters of the earth, a speed traversing
this distance in 22 minutes would be equal to the rate of a thousand
diameters a minute, i. e., 16 2-3 diameters a second (or a pulse-beat)
which makes more than 1,100 times 100,000 toises, since one diameter of
the earth equals 2,865 leagues, of which there are 25 to the degree,
and since in accordance with the very precise calculation made by M.
Picard in 1609 under orders from the king, each league contains 2,282
toises.

As I stated before sound moves only 180 toises per second. Hence
the speed of light is over 600,000 times as great as that of sound,
which, however, is very different from being instantaneous,--it is the
difference between any finite number and infinity. The theory that
light movements are propagated from point to point in time being thus
demonstrated, it follows that light moves in spherical waves, as does
sound.

But if they are alike in this regard, they are unlike in others, as
in the original cause of the motion that transmits them, the medium
through which they move, and the manner in which they are transmitted
in it.

We know that sound is caused by the rapid vibration of some body
(either as a whole or in part), this vibration setting in motion the
adjoining air. But light movements must arise at every point of the
luminous body, otherwise all the various parts of the body would not be
visible. This fact will be clearer from what follows.

In my judgment, this movement of light-giving bodies cannot be more
satisfactorily explained than by supposing that those that are fluid,
e. g., a flame, and probably the sun and stars, consist of particles
that float about in a much rarer medium, that sets them in violent
motion, causing them to strike against the still more minute particles
of the surrounding ether. In the case of light-giving solids such as
red-hot metal or carbon we may suppose this movement to be caused by
the rapid motions of the metal or wood, the particles on the surface
exciting the ether. Hence the vibration producing light must be much
shorter and faster than that causing sound, since we do not find that
sound disturbances give rise to light any more than the wave of the
hand through the air causes sound.

The next question is in regard to the nature of the medium through
which the vibration produced by light-giving bodies moves. I have
named it _ether_, but it plainly differs from the medium through
which sound moves. The latter is simply the air we feel and breathe,
and when it is removed from any space, the medium which carries light
still remains. This is shown by surrounding the sounding body in a
glass vessel, and exhausting the air by means of the air-pump that Mr.
Boyle has devised, and with which he has performed so many striking
experiments. In trying this experiment, however, it is best to set the
sounder on cotton or feathers so that it cannot communicate vibrations
to the glass receiver or the air-pump, a point hitherto neglected.
Then, when all the air has been exhausted, one catches no sound from
the metal when it is struck.

Hence we conclude not only that our atmosphere which cannot penetrate
glass is the medium through which sound acts, but that the medium
carrying light-vibrations is something different: for after the vessel
is exhausted of air, light passes through it as easily as before.

The last point is proven even more conclusively by the famous
experiment of Torricelli. [Fill a long closed glass tube with mercury,
then invert it.] The top of the glass tube not filled by the mercury
contains a high vacuum, but transmits light as well as when filled
with air. This demonstrates that there is within the tube some form
of matter different from air, and which penetrates either glass or
mercury, or both, though both are impenetrable to air. And if a like
experiment is tried with a little water on top of the mercury, it
becomes equally clear that the substance in question traverses either
glass or water or both.

In regard to the different methods of transmission of sound and light,
in the case of sound it is easy to see what happens when one remembers
that air can be compressed and reduced to a much smaller volume than
usual, and that it tends with the same force to expand to its original
volume. This quality, considered along with its penetrability retained
in spite of such condensation seems to show that it consists of small
particles that float about in rapid vibration in an ether consisting
of still more minute particles. Sound, then, is caused by the struggle
of these particles to escape when at any point in the course of a wave
they are more crowded together than at some other point.

Now the wonderful speed of light considered with its other qualities,
does not permit us to believe it to be transmitted in the same manner.
Therefore I shall try to explain the way in which I think it must
take place. I must first, however, describe that quality of hard
substances through which they transmit motion one to another. If one
take a number of balls of the same size of any hard substance, and
place them touching one another in one line, he will find that on
letting a ball of the same size strike against one end of the line,
the motion is transmitted in an instant to the other end of the line.
The last ball is driven from the line while the others are apparently
undisturbed, the ball that struck the line coming to a dead stop.
This is an illustration of a transmission of motion at great speed,
varying directly as the hardness of the balls. Yet it is certain that
this transmission is not instantaneous, but requires time. For if the
movement, or if you wish, the tendency to move, did not pass from one
ball to another in succession, they would all be set in motion at the
same instant and would all move forward at the same time. Now this is
so far from the case that only the last one leaves the row, and it has
the speed of the ball that first struck the line.

There are other experiments, also demonstrating that all bodies, even
those thought hardest, such as steel, glass and agate, are really
elastic, and bend a little, no matter whether they are in rods, balls,
or bodies of any other shape,--that is, they give slightly at the
point where struck, and at once regain their former shape. Thus I have
discovered that in letting a glass or agate ball strike on a large,
thick, flat piece of the same substance the surface of which has been
roughened by the breath, the place where it strikes is shown by a
circular indentation that varies in size directly as the force of the
blow. This indicates that the materials give when struck and then fly
back,--an event that necessarily takes time.

Now to apply such a motion to the explanation of light, there is
nothing in the way of our imagining the particles of ether to have
an almost complete hardness, and an elasticity as perfect as we need
wish. We need not here discuss the cause of either this hardness or
elasticity, as this would lead us too far from the question at issue.
I will remark, however, by the way, that these particles of ether,
in spite of their minuteness, are also composed of parts and that
their elasticity depends on a very rapid motion of a subtle substance
traversing them in all directions and making them take a structure
that offers a ready passage to this fluid. This agrees with the idea
of M. Descartes, except that I would not, like him, give the pores the
shape of round, hollow canals. This is so far from being at all absurd
or incomprehensible that it is easily credible that nature uses an
infinite series of different-sized molecules in order to produce her
marvelous effects.

Moreover, although we do not know the cause of elasticity, we cannot
have failed to notice that most bodies possess this characteristic;
hence it is not unreasonable to suppose that it is a quality of the
minute, invisible particles of the ether. And it is a fact that if one
looks for some other method of accounting for the gradual transmission
of light, he will have a hard time finding any supposition better
suited than elasticity to explain the fact of uniform speed. This
[uniform speed] seems to be a necessary assumption, for if the motion
slowed down when distributed over a great mass of matter at a far
distance from its source, then this great speed would at last be lost.
On the other hand, we suppose ether to have the property of elasticity
so that its particles regain their shape with equal activity whether
struck a hard or gentle blow. Thus the rate at which light would move
would remain constant.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 9: Translated from _Traité de la Lumière_.]




                                 VIII

                       ANTHONY VAN LEEUWENHOECK

                               1632-1723


 _Born in Delft, Holland, October 24, 1632, Anthony Van Leeuwenhoeck,
 a lens-maker for microscopes, made several important biological
 discoveries. In 1673 he noticed the red globules in the blood; in
 1675 he discovered animalculæ in water; in 1677 he described the
 spermatozoa; in 1690 he traced the passage of blood from the arteries
 into the veins. Among his other achievements were his investigations
 of the tubules of teeth, the solidity of hair, the structure of the
 epidermis, and his descriptions of insect anatomies. He announced most
 of his findings to the Royal Society of London. Against the generally
 accepted idea of spontaneous generation, he held that all things
 generated their kind. He died at Delft, August 26, 1723._


                    OBSERVATIONS ON ANIMALCULÆ[10]

In the year 1675, I discovered very small living creatures in rain
water, which had stood but few days in a new earthen pot glazed blue
within. This invited me to view this water with great attention,
especially those little animals appearing to me ten thousand times less
than those represented by M. Swammerdam, and by him called water-fleas,
or water-lice, which may be perceived in the water with the naked eye.

The first sort I several times observed to consist of 5, 6, 7, or 8
clear globules without being able to discern any film that held them
together, or contained them. When these animalcula or living atoms
moved, they put forth two little horns, continually moving. The space
between these two horns was flat, though the rest of the body was
roundish, sharpening a little towards the end, where they had a tail,
near four times the length of the whole body, of the thickness, by my
microscope, of a spider’s web; at the end of which appeared a globule
of the size of one of those which made up the body. These little
creatures, if they chanced to light on the least filament or string,
or other particle, were entangled therein, extending their body in a
long round, and endeavoring to disentangle their tail. Their motion of
extension and contraction continued a while; and I have seen several
thousands of these poor little creatures, within the space of a grain
of gross sand, lie fast clustered together in a few filaments.

I also discovered a second sort, of an oval figure; and I imagined
their head to stand on a sharp end. These were a little longer than
the former. The inferior part of their body is flat, furnished with
several extremely thin feet, which moved very nimbly. The upper part of
the body was round, and had within 8, 10, or 12 globules, where they
were very clear. These little animals sometimes changed their figure
into a perfect round, especially when they came to lie on a dry place.
Their body was also very flexible; for as soon as they struck against
the smallest fibre or string, their body was bent in, which bending
presently jerked out again. When I put any of them on a dry place, I
observed that, changing themselves into a round, their body was raised
pyramidal-wise, with an extant point in the middle; and having laid
thus a little while, with a motion of their feet, they burst asunder,
and the globules were presently diffused and dissipated, so that I
could not discern the least thing of any film, in which the globules
had doubtless been enclosed; and at this time of their bursting
asunder, I was able to discover more globules than when they were alive.

I observed a third sort of little animals, that were twice as long as
broad, and to my eye eight times smaller than the first. Yet I thought
I discerned little feet, whereby they moved very briskly, both in round
and straight line.

There was a fourth sort, which were so small that I was not able to
give them any figure at all. These were a thousand times smaller than
the eye of a large louse. These exceeded all the former in celerity. I
have often observed them to stand still as it were on a point, and then
turn themselves about with that swiftness, as we see a top turn round,
the circumference they made being no larger than that of a grain of
small sand, and then extending themselves straight forward, and by and
by lying in a bending posture. I discovered also several other sorts
of animals; these were generally made up of such soft parts, as the
former, that they burst asunder as soon as they came to want water.

May 26, it rained hard; the rain growing less, I caused some of that
rain-water running down from the house top, to be gathered in a clean
glass, after it had been washed two or three times with water. And in
this I observed some few very small living creatures, and seeing them,
I thought they might have been produced in the leaded gutters in some
water that had remained there before.

I perceived in pure water, after some days, more of those animals, as
also some that were somewhat larger. And I imagine, that many thousands
of these little creatures do not equal an ordinary grain of sand in
bulk; and comparing them with a cheese-mite, which may be seen to
move with the naked eye, I make the proportion of one of these small
water-creatures to a cheese-mite to be like that of a bee to a horse;
for, the circumference of one of these little animals in water is not
so large as the thickness of a hair in a cheese-mite.

In another quantity of rain-water, exposed for some days to the air,
I observed some thousands of them in a drop of water, which were of
the smallest sort that I had seen hitherto. And in some time after I
observed, besides the animals already noted, a sort of creatures that
were eight times as large, of almost a round figure; and as those very
small animalcula swam gently among each other, moving as gnats do in
the air, so did these larger ones move far more swiftly, tumbling round
as it were, and then making a sudden downfall.

In the waters of the river Maese I saw very small creatures of
different kinds and colours, and so small, that I could very hardly
discern their figures; but the number of them was far less than those
found in rain-water. In the water of a very cold well in the autumn, I
discovered a very great number of living animals very small, that were
exceedingly clear, and a little larger than the smallest I ever saw.
In sea-water I observed at first, a little blackish animal, looking as
if it had been made up of two globules. This creature had a peculiar
motion, resembling the skipping of a flea on white paper, so that it
might very well be called a water-flea; but it was far less than the
eye of that little animal, which Dr. Swammerdam calls the water-flea. I
also discovered little creatures therein that were clear, of the same
size with the former animal, but of an oval figure, having a serpentine
motion. I further noticed a third sort, which were very slow in their
motion; their body was of a mouse colour, clear toward the oval point;
and before the head and behind the body there stood out a sharp little
point angle-wise. This sort was a little larger. But there was yet a
fourth somewhat longer than oval. Yet of all these sorts there were
but a few of each. Some days after viewing this water, I saw 100 where
before I had seen but one; but these were of another figure, and not
only less, but they were also very clear, and of an oblong oval figure,
only with this difference, that their heads ended sharper; and although
they were a thousand times smaller than a small grain of sand, yet when
they lay out of the water in a dry place, they burst in pieces and
spread into three or four very little globules, and into some aqueous
matter, without any other parts appearing in them.

Having put about one-third of an ounce of whole pepper in water, and
it having lain about three weeks in the water, to which I had twice
added some snow-water, the other water being in great part exhaled;
I discerned in it with great surprise an incredible number of little
animals, of divers kinds, and among the rest, some that were three
or four times as long as broad; but their whole thickness did not
much exceed the hair of a louse. They had a very pretty motion, often
tumbling about and sideways; and when the water was let to run off from
them, they turned round like a top; at first their body changed into an
oval, and afterwards, when the circular motion ceased, they returned to
their former length. The second sort of creatures discovered in this
water, were of a perfect oval figure, and they had no less pleasing or
nimble a motion than the former; and these were in far greater numbers.
There was a third sort, which exceeded the two former in number, and
these had tails like those I had formerly observed in rain-water.
The fourth sort, which moved through the three former sorts, were
incredibly small, so that I judged, that if 100 of them lay one by
another, they would not equal the length of a grain of coarse sand;
and according to this estimate, 1,000,000 of them could not equal the
dimensions of a grain of such coarse sand. There was discovered a fifth
sort, which had near the thickness of the former, but almost twice the
length.

In snow-water, which had been about three years in a glass bottle
well stopped, I could discover no living creatures; and having poured
some of it into a porcelain tea-cup, and put therein half an ounce of
whole pepper, after some days I observed some animalcula, and those
exceedingly small ones, whose body seemed to me twice as long as broad,
but they moved very slowly, and often circularly. I observed also a
vast multitude of oval-figured animalcula, to the number of 8,000 in a
single drop.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 10: From the _Transactions of the Royal Society of
London_.]




                                  IX

                           SIR ISAAC NEWTON

                               1642-1727


 _Sir Isaac Newton, whose researches in light, gravitation, and
 mathematics are outstanding in the history of modern science, was born
 in Woolsthorpe, Lincolnshire, December 25, 1642. He was the son of an
 English farmer who died before Newton was born. His early education
 was interrupted by his mother’s poverty, but his ingenuity in making
 mechanical toys soon provided a means whereby he was enabled to return
 to school. He entered Cambridge University in 1661 and took his degree
 in 1665; two years later he was made a fellow of the university, and
 in 1669 became professor of mathematics._

 _In 1665 he discovered his method of fluxions, not greatly unlike
 Leibnitz’s Differential Calculus. In 1672 he was elected a fellow of
 the Royal Society and shortly afterwards sent them a paper describing
 how he had broken up light by means of a prism, demonstrating by that
 means the compound nature of the sun’s rays._

 _In 1687 elaborated his theory of gravitation in “Philosophiæ
 Naturalis Principia Mathematica.” This was the result of his
 reflections and researches dating from 1666, when he attempted to
 explain the moon’s motion by the hypothesis of the assumed influence
 of gravitation. In the meantime, through the use of telescopic
 instruments, French geographers had tested the spherical shape of the
 earth and had made a new and more accurate triangulation. Using the
 data which they supplied, Newton perceived that these data agreed
 with his theory that the force varied inversely as the square of the
 distance. Overcome with the emotion incident to the solution of a
 great problem, he begged a friend to complete his calculations, with
 the result that the new astronomy begun by Copernicus, and continued
 by Brahe, Kepler, and Galileo, was formulated and mathematically
 interpreted by a single mechanical principle._

 _Although he later made some chemical investigations, his papers
 were accidentally destroyed, and it is said that he never recovered
 from the shock of losing them. In 1695 he was made warden, and in 1699
 promoted to the mastership of the mint, which office he retained at a
 munificent salary until his death on March 20, 1727._


                     THE THEORY OF GRAVITATION[11]

             BOOK III. PROPOSITION V. THEOREM V. SCHOLIUM

The force which retains the celestial bodies in their orbits has been
hitherto called centripetal force; but it being now made plain that it
can be no other than a gravitating force, we shall hereafter call it
gravity. For the cause of that centripetal force which retains the moon
in its orbit will extend itself to all the planets.


                 BOOK III. PROPOSITION VI. THEOREM VI.

_That all bodies gravitate towards every planet; and that the weights
of bodies towards any the same planet, at equal distances from the
centre of the planet, are proportional to the quantities of matter
which they severally contain._

It has been, now of a long time, observed by others, that all sorts of
heavy bodies (allowance being made for the inequality of retardation
which they suffer from a small power of resistance in the air) descend
to the earth _from equal heights_ in equal times; and that
equality of times we may distinguish to a great accuracy, by the help
of pendulums. I tried the things in gold, silver, lead, glass, sand,
common salt, wood, water, and wheat. I provided two wooden boxes,
round and equal; I filled the one with wood, and suspended an equal
weight of gold (as exactly as I could) in the centre of oscillation
of the other. The boxes hanging by equal threads of 11 feet made a
couple of pendulums perfectly equal in weight and figure, and equally
receiving the resistance of the air. And, placing the one by the
other, I observed them to play together forwards and backwards, for
a long time, with equal vibrations ... and the like happened in the
other bodies. By these experiments, in bodies of the same weight, I
could manifestly have discovered a difference of matter less than
the thousandth part of the whole, had any such been. But, without
all doubt, the nature of gravity towards the planets is the same
as towards the earth.... Moreover, since the satellites of Jupiter
perform their revolutions in times which observe the sesquiplicate
proportion of their distances from Jupiter’s centre--that is, equal
at equal distances. And, therefore, these satellites, if supposed
to fall _towards Jupiter_ from equal heights, would describe
equal spaces in equal times, in like manner as heavy bodies do on
our earth.... If, at equal distances from the sun, any satellite, in
proportion to the quantity of its matter, did gravitate towards the
sun with a force greater than Jupiter in proportion to his, according
to any given proportion, suppose of _d_ to _e_; then the
distance between the centres of the sun and of the satellite’s orbit
would be always greater than the distance between the centres of the
sun and of Jupiter nearly in the sub-duplicate of that proportion; as
by some computations I have found. And if the satellite did gravitate
towards the sun with a force, lesser in the proportion of _e_ to
_d_, the distance of the centre of the satellite’s orbit from
the sun would be less than the distance of the centre of Jupiter from
the sun in the sub-duplicate of the same proportion. Therefore if, at
equal distances from the sun, the accelerative gravity of any satellite
towards the sun were greater or less than the accelerative gravity of
Jupiter towards the sun but one 1-1000 part of the whole gravity, the
distance of the centre of the satellite’s orbit from the sun would be
greater or less than the distance of Jupiter from the sun by one 1-2000
part of the whole distance--that is, by a fifth part of the distance
of the utmost satellite from the centre of Jupiter; an eccentricity of
the orbit which would be very sensible. But the orbits of the satellite
are concentric to Jupiter, and therefore the accelerative gravities of
Jupiter, and of all its satellites towards the sun, are equal among
themselves....

But further; the weights of all the parts of every planet towards
any other planet are one to another as the matter in the several
parts; for if some parts did gravitate more, others less, than for
the quantity of their matter, then the whole planet, according to the
sort of parts with which it most abounds, would gravitate more or less
than in proportion to the quantity of matter in the whole. Nor is it
of any moment whether these parts are external or internal; for if,
for example, we should imagine the terrestrial bodies with us to be
raised up to the orb of the moon, to be there compared with its body;
if the weights of such bodies were to the weights of the external parts
of the moon as the quantities of matter in the one and in the other
respectively; but to the weights of the internal parts in a greater or
less proportion, then likewise the weights of those bodies would be to
the weight of the whole moon in a greater or less proportion; against
what we have showed above.

Cor. 1. Hence the weights of bodies do not depend upon their forms and
textures; for if the weights could be altered with the forms, they
would be greater or less, according to the variety of forms in equal
matter; altogether against experience.

Cor. 2. Universally, all bodies about the earth gravitate towards the
earth; and the weights of all, at equal distances from the earth’s
centre, are as the quantities of matter which they severally contain.
This is the quality of all bodies within the reach of our experiments;
and therefore (by rule 3) to be affirmed of all bodies whatsoever....

Cor. 5. The power of gravity is of a different nature from the power of
magnetism; for the magnetic attraction is not as the matter attracted.
Some bodies are attracted more by the magnet; others less; most bodies
not at all. The power of magnetism in one and the same body may be
increased and diminished; and is sometimes far stronger, for the
quantity of matter, than the power of gravity; and in receding from
the magnet decreases not in the duplicate but almost in the triplicate
proportion of the distance, as nearly as I could judge from some rude
observations.


                BOOK III. PROPOSITION VII. THEOREM VII.

_That there is a power of gravity tending to all bodies, proportional
to the several quantities of matter which they contain._

That all the planets mutually gravitate one towards another, we have
proved before; as well as that the force of gravity towards every
one of them, considered apart, is reciprocally as the square of the
distance of places from the centre of the planet. And thence (by prop.
69, book I, and its corollaries) it follows, that the gravity tending
towards all the planets is proportional to the matter which they
contain.

Moreover, since all the parts of any planet A gravitate towards any
other planet B; and the gravity of every part is to the gravity of the
whole as the matter of the part to the matter of the whole; and (by law
3) to every action corresponds an equal reaction; therefore the planet
B will, on the other hand, gravitate towards all the parts of the
planet A; and its gravity towards any one part will be to the gravity
towards the whole as the matter of the part to the matter of the whole.
Q. E. D.

Cor. 1. Therefore the force of gravity towards any whole planet arises
from, and is compounded of, the forces of gravity towards all its
parts. Magnetic and electric attractions afford us examples of this;
for all attraction towards the whole arises from the attractions
towards the several parts. The thing may be easily understood in
gravity, if we consider a greater planet as formed of a number of
lesser planets meeting together in one globe, for _hence it would
appear_ that the force of the whole must arise from the forces of
the component parts. If it is objected that, according to this law, all
bodies with us must mutually gravitate one towards another, I answer,
that since the gravitation towards these bodies is to the gravitation
towards the whole earth as these bodies are to the whole earth, the
gravitation towards them must be far less than to fall under the
observation of our senses.

Cor. 2. The force of gravity towards the several particles of any body
is reciprocally as the square of the distance from the particles; as
appears from cor. 3, prop. 74, book I.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 11: Translated from the _Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia
Mathematica_.]




                                   X

                           BENJAMIN FRANKLIN

                               1706-1790


 _Benjamin Franklin, representative of the rationalist tendencies
 of the eighteenth century, was born in Boston, January 17, 1706.
 His early life and political missions are intimately related in his
 “Autobiography,” a classic in American literature. Apart from his
 political services to the cause of American independence, he attained
 distinction in the field of scientific researches and experiments. In
 1746 he began the experiments in electricity which resulted in his
 identification of electricity with lightning. He died in Philadelphia,
 April 17, 1790._


             THE IDENTITY OF LIGHTNING AND ELECTRICITY[12]

But points have a property, by which they draw on as well as throw
off the electrical fluid, at greater distances than blunt bodies can.
That is, as the pointed part of an electrified body will discharge the
atmosphere of that body, or communicate it farthest to another body,
so the point of an unelectrified body will draw off the electrical
atmosphere from an electrified body, farther than a blunter part of
the same unelectrified body will do. Thus, a pin held by the head,
and the point presented to an electrified body, will draw off its
atmosphere at a foot distance; where, if the head were presented
instead of the point, no such effect would follow. To understand
this, we may consider, that, if a person standing on the floor would
draw off the electrical atmosphere from an electrified body, an iron
crow and a blunt knitting-needle, held alternately in his hand, and
presented for that purpose, do not draw with different forces in
proportion to their different masses. For the man, and what he holds in
his hand, be it large or small, are connected with the common mass of
unelectrified matter; and the force with which he draws is the same in
both cases, it consisting in the different proportion of electricity
in the electrified body, and that common mass. But the force, with
which the electrified body retains its atmosphere by attracting it, is
proportioned to the surface over which the particles are placed; that
is, four square inches of that surface retain their atmosphere with
four times the force that one square inch retains its atmosphere. And,
as in plucking the hairs from the horse’s tail, a degree of strength
not sufficient to pull away a handful at once, could yet easily strip
it hair by hair, so a blunt body presented cannot draw off a number of
particles at once, but a pointed one, with no greater force, takes them
away easily, particle by particle.

These explanations of the power and operation of points, when they
first occurred to me, and while they first floated in my mind, appeared
perfectly satisfactory; but now I have written them, and considered
them more closely, I must own I have some doubts about them; yet, as I
have at present nothing better to offer in their stead, I do not cross
them out; for, even a bad solution read, and its faults discovered, has
often given rise to a good one, in the mind of an ingenious reader.

Nor is it of much importance to us to know the manner in which nature
executes her laws; it is enough if we know the laws themselves. It is
of real use to know that China left in the air unsupported, will fall
and break; but how it comes to fall, and why it breaks, are matters of
speculation. It is a pleasure indeed to know them, but we can preserve
our China without it.

Thus, in the present case, to know this power of points may possibly
be of some use to mankind, though we should never be able to explain
it. The following experiments, as well as those in my first paper, show
this power. I have a large prime conductor, made of several thin sheets
of clothier’s pasteboard, formed into a tube, near ten feet long and a
foot diameter. It is covered with Dutch embossed paper, almost totally
gilt. This large metallic surface supports a much greater electrical
atmosphere than a rod of iron of fifty times the weight would do. It
is suspended by silk lines, and when charged will strike, at near two
inches distance, a pretty hard stroke, so as to make one’s knuckles
ache. Let a person standing on the floor present the point of a needle,
at twelve or more inches distance from it, and while the needle is
so presented, the conductor cannot be charged, the point drawing off
the fire as fast as it is thrown on by the electrical globe. Let it
be charged, and then present the point at the same distance, and it
will suddenly be discharged. In the dark you may see the light on the
point, when the experiment is made. And if the person holding the point
stands upon wax, he will be electrified by receiving the fire at that
distance. Attempt to draw off the electricity with a blunt body, as
a bolt of iron round at the end, and smooth, (a silversmith’s iron
punch, inch thick, is what I use,) and you must bring it within the
distance of three inches before you can do it, and then it is done
with a stroke and crack. As the pasteboard tube hangs loose on silk
lines, when you approach it with the punch-iron, it likewise will move
towards the punch, being attracted while it is charged, but if, at the
same instant, a point be presented as before, it retires again, for the
point discharges it. Take a pair of large brass scales, of two or more
feet beam, the cords of the scales being silk. Suspend the beam by a
pack-thread from the ceiling, so that the bottom of the scales may be
about a foot from the floor; the scales will move round in a circle
by the untwisting of the pack-thread. Set the iron punch on the end
upon the floor, in such a place as that the scales may pass over it
in making their circle; then electrify one scale by applying the wire
of a charged phial to it. As they move round, you see that scale draw
nigher to the floor, and dip more when it comes over the punch; and, if
that be placed at a proper distance, the scale will snap and discharge
its fire into it. But, if a needle be stuck on the end of the punch,
its point upward, the scale, instead of drawing nigh to the punch, and
snapping, discharges its fire silently through the point, and rises
higher from the punch. Nay, even if the needle be placed upon the floor
near the punch, its point upward, the end of the punch, though so much
higher than the needle, will not attract the scale and receive its
fire, for the needle will get it and convey it away, before it comes
nigh enough for the punch to act. And this is constantly observable
in these experiments, that the greater quantity of electricity on the
pasteboard tube, the farther it strikes or discharges its fire, and the
point likewise will draw it off at a still greater distance.

Now if the fire of electricity and that of lightning be the same,
as I have endeavoured to show at large in a former paper, this
pasteboard tube and these scales may represent electrified clouds. If
a tube of only ten feet long will strike and discharge its fire on
the punch at two or three inches distance, an electrified cloud of
perhaps ten thousand acres may strike and discharge on the earth at a
proportionately greater distance. The horizontal motion of the scales
over the floor, may represent the motion of the clouds over the earth;
and the erect iron punch, a hill or high building; and then we see how
electrified clouds, passing over hills or high buildings at too great
a height to strike, may be attracted lower till within their striking
distance, And, lastly, if a needle fixed on the punch with its point
upright, or even on the floor below the punch, will draw the fire from
the scale silently at a much greater than the striking distance, and so
prevent its descending towards the punch; or if in its course it would
have come nigh enough to strike, yet being first deprived of its fire
it cannot, and the punch is thereby secured from the stroke; I say, if
these things are so, may not the knowledge of this power of points be
of use to mankind, in preserving houses, churches, ships, &c., from
the stroke of lightning, by directing us to fix, on the highest parts
of those edifices, upright rods of iron made sharp as a needle, and
gilt to prevent rusting, and from the foot of those rods a wire down
the outside of the building into the ground, or down round one of the
shrouds of a ship, and down her side till it reaches the water? Would
not these pointed rods probably draw the electrical fire silently out
of a cloud before it came nigh enough to strike, and thereby secure us
from that most sudden and terrible mischief?

To determine the question, whether the clouds that contain lightning
are electrified or not, I would propose an experiment to be tried where
it may be done conveniently. On the top of some high tower or steeple,
place a kind of sentry-box, ... big enough to contain a man and an
electrical stand. From the middle of the stand let an iron rod rise
and pass bending out of the door, and then upright twenty or thirty
feet, pointed very sharp at the end. If the electrical stand be kept
clean and dry, a man standing on it, when such clouds are passing low,
might be electrified and afford sparks, the rod drawing fire to him
from a cloud. If any danger to the man should be apprehended (though I
think there would be none), let him stand on the floor of his box, and
now and then bring near to the rod the loop of wire that has one end
fastened to the leads, he holding it by a wax handle, so the sparks, if
the rod is electrified, will strike from the rod to the wire, and not
affect him.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 12: From Franklin’s correspondence with Peter Collinson, July
29, 1750. _Works of Benjamin Franklin_, Philadelphia, 1809, Vol.
III, pp. 45-49.]




                                  XI

                               LINNAEUS

                               1707-1778


 _Carl von Linné [Linnaeus] was born May 13, 1707, at Rashult in
 Smaland, Sweden. At the age of four he showed a precocious interest
 in plants, an interest which seriously interfered with his studies
 when he went to school. When his father was about to remove him, a
 friend urged that the boy be fitted for the profession of medicine.
 Linnaeus entered the university at Lund in 1727, but in the following
 year transferred to Upsala. In 1732, at the expense of the Academy
 of Sciences, he explored Lapland. Later he made pilgrimages to many
 of the most eminent professors of Europe, returning to Stockholm in
 1738. After his marriage, in 1739, he was appointed professor at
 Upsala, where he continued his work in botany and established it on a
 rational basis. He died January 10, 1778, noted as one of the foremost
 botanists of his time, having discovered sex in plants and given his
 name to a famous botanical system of classification._


                         THE SEX OF PLANTS[13]

The organs common in general to all plants are: 1st. The root, with its
capillary vessels, extracting nourishment from the ground. 2nd. The
leaves, which may be called the limbs, and which, like the feet and
wings of animals, are organs of motion; for being themselves shaken by
the external air, they shake and exercise the plant. 3rd. The trunk,
containing the medullary substance, which is nourished by the bark, and
for the most part multiplied into several compound plants. 4th. The
fructification, which is the true body of the plant, set at liberty by
a metamorphosis, and consists only of the organs of generation; it is
often defended by a calyx, and furnished with petals, by means of which
it in a manner flutters in the air.

Many flowers have no calyx, as several of the lily tribe, the
Hippuris, etc., many want the corolla, as grasses, and the plants
called apetalous; but there are none more destitute of stamina and
pistilla, those important organs destined to the formation of fruit.
We therefore infer from experience that the stamina are the male
organs of generation, and the pistilla of the female; and as many
flowers are furnished with both at once, it follows that such flowers
are hermaphrodites. Nor is this so wonderful, as that there should be
any plants in which the different sexes are distinct individuals; for
plants being immovably fixed to one spot, cannot like animals, travel
in search of a mate. There exists, however, in some plants a real
difference of sex. From seeds of the same mother, some individuals
shall be produced, whose flowers exhibit stamina without pistilla, and
may therefore properly be called male; while the rest being furnished
with pistilla without stamina are therefore denominated females; and
so uniformly does this take place, that no vegetable was ever found to
produce female flowers without flowers furnished with stamina being
produced, either on the same individual or on another plant of the same
species, and _vice versa_.

As all seed vessels are destined to produce seeds, so are the stamina
to bear the pollen, or fecundating powder. All seeds contain within
their membranes a certain medullary substance, which swells when dipped
into warm water. All pollen, likewise, contains in its membrane an
elastic substance, which, although very subtle, and almost invisible,
by means of warm water often explodes with great vehemence. While
plants are in flower, the pollen falls from their antheræ, and is
dispersed abroad, as seeds are dislodged from their situation when
the fruit is ripe. At the same time that the pollen is scattered, the
pistillum presents its stigma, which is then in its highest vigour,
and, for a portion of the day at least, is moistened with a fine dew.
The stamina either surround this stigma, or if the flowers are of the
drooping kind, they are bent towards one side, so that the pollen can
easily find access to the stigma, where it not only adheres by means of
the dew of that part, but the moisture occasions its bursting, by which
means its contents are discharged. That issued from it being mixed with
the fluid of the stigma, is conveyed to rudiments of the seed. Many
evident instances of this present themselves to our notice; but I have
nowhere seen it more manifest than in the Jacobean Lily (_Amarylis
formosissima_), the pistillum of which, when sufficient heat is
given the plant to make it flower in perfection, is bent downwards and
from its stigma issues a drop of limpid fluid, so large that one would
think it in danger of falling to the ground. It is, however, gradually
reabsorbed into the style about three or four o’clock and becomes
invisible until about ten the next morning, when it appears again; by
noon it attains its largest dimensions; and in the afternoon, by a
gentle and scarcely perceptible decrease it returns to its source. If
we shake the antheræ over the stigma, so that the pollen may fall on
this limpid drop, we see the fluid soon after become turbid and assume
a yellow color; and we perceive little rivulets, or opaque streaks
running from the stigma towards the rudiments of the seed. Some time
afterwards, when the drop has totally disappeared, the pollen may be
observed adhering to the stigma, but of an irregular figure, having
lost its original form. No one, therefore, can assent to what Morland
and others have asserted, that the pollen passes into the stigma,
pervades the style and enters the tender rudiments of the seed, as
Leeuwenhoeck supposed his worms to enter the ova. A most evident proof
of the falsehood of this opinion may be obtained from any species of
_Mirabilis_ (Marvel of Peru), whose pollen is so very large that
it almost exceeds the style itself in thickness, and, falling on the
stigma, adheres firmly to it; that organ sucking and exhausting the
pollen, as a cuttle fish devours everything that comes within its
grasp. One evening in the month of August, I removed all the stamina
from three flowers of the _Mirabilis Longiflora_, at the same time
destroying all the rest of the flowers which were expanded; I sprinkled
these three flowers with the pollen of _Mirabilis Jalappa_; the
seed-buds swelled, but did not ripen. Another evening I performed a
similar experiment, only sprinkling the flowers with the pollen of the
same species; all these flowers produced ripe seeds.

Some writers have believed that the stamina are parts of the
fructification, which serve only to discharge an impure or
excrementitious matter, and by no means formed for so important a work
as generation. But it is very evident that these authors have not
sufficiently examined the subject; for, as in many vegetables, some
flowers are furnished with stamina only, and others only with pistilla;
it is altogether impossible that stamina situated at so very great a
distance from the fruit, as on a different branch, or perhaps on a
separate plant, should serve to convey any impurities from the embryo.

No physiologist could demonstrate, _a priori_, the necessity of
the masculine fluid to the rendering the eggs of animals prolific, but
experience has established it beyond a doubt. We therefore judge _a
posteriori_ principally, of the same effect in plants.

In the month of January, 1760, the _Antholyza Cunonia_ flowered
in a pot in my parlour, but produced no fruit, the air of the room not
being sufficiently agitated to waft the pollen to the stigma. One day,
about noon, feeling the stigma very moist, I plucked off one of the
antheræ, by means of a fine pair of forceps, and gently rubbed it on
one part of the expanded stigmata. The spike of flowers remained eight
or ten days longer; when I observed, in gathering the branch for my
herbarium, that the fruit of that flower only on which the experiment
had been made, had swelled to the size of a bean. I then dissected this
fruit and discovered that one of the three cells contained seeds in
considerable number, the other two being entirely withered.

In the month of April I sowed the seeds of hemp (_Cannabis_) in
two different pots. The young plants came up so plentifully, that each
pot contained thirty or forty. I placed each by the light of a window,
but in different and remote apartments. The hemp grew extremely well
in both pots. In one of them I permitted the male and female plants
to remain together, to flower and bear fruit, which ripened in July,
being macerated in water, and committed to the earth, sprung up in
twelve days. From the other, however, I removed all the male plants,
as soon as they were old enough for me to distinguish them from the
females. The remaining females grew very well, and presented their long
pistilla in great abundance, these flowers continuing a very long time,
as if in expectation of their mates; while the plants in the other pot
had already ripened their fruit, their pistilla having, quite in a
different manner, faded as soon as the males had discharged all their
pollen. It was truly a beautiful and truly admirable spectacle to see
the unimpregnated females preserve their pistilla so long green and
flourishing, not permitting them to begin to fade till they had been
for a very considerable time exposed in vain, to the access of the
male pollen.

Afterwards, when these virgin plants began to decay through age, I
examined all their calyces in the presence of several botanists and
found them large and flourishing, although every one of the seed-buds
was brown, compressed, membranaceous, and dry, not exhibiting any
appearance of cotyledons or pulp. Hence I am perfectly convinced that
the circumstance which authors have recorded, of the female hemp having
produced seeds, although deprived of the male, could only have happened
by means of pollen brought by the wind from some distant place. No
experiment can be more easily performed than the above; none more
satisfactory in demonstrating the generation of plants.

The _Clutia tenella_ was in like manner kept growing in my window
during the months of June and July. The male plant was in one pot,
the female in another. The latter abounded with fruit, not one of its
flowers proving abortive. I removed the two pots into different windows
of the same apartment; still all the female flowers continued to become
fruitful. At length I took away the male entirely, leaving the female
alone, and cutting off all the flowers which it had already borne.
Every day new ones appeared from the axila of every leaf; each remained
eight or ten days, after which their foot stalks turning yellow, they
fell barren to the ground. A botanical friend, who had amused himself
with observing this phenomenon with me, persuaded me to bring, from the
stove in the garden, a single male flower, which he placed over one of
the female ones, then in perfection, tying a piece of red silk around
its pistillum. The next day the male flower was taken away, and this
single seed-bud remained, and bore fruit. Afterwards I took another
male flower out of the same stove, and with a pair of slender forceps
pinched off one of its antheræ, which I afterwards gently scratched
with a feather, so that a very small portion of its pollen was
discharged upon one of the three stigmata of a female flower, the other
two stigmata being covered with paper. This fruit likewise attained its
due size, and on being cut transversely, exhibited one cell filled with
a large seed, and the other two empty. The rest of the flowers, being
unimpregnated, faded and fell off. This experiment may be performed
with as little trouble as the former.

The _Datisca cannabina_ came up in my garden from seed ten years
ago, and has every year been plentifully increased by means of its
perennial root. Flowers in great number have been produced by it; but,
being all female, they proved abortive. Being desirous of producing
male plants, I obtained more seeds from Paris. Some more plants were
raised; but these likewise to my great mortification, all proved
females, and bore flowers, but no fruit. In the year 1757 I received
another parcel of seeds. From these I obtained a few male plants, which
flowered in 1758. These were planted at a great distance from the
females; and when their flowers were just ready to emit their pollen,
holding a paper under them, I gently shook the spike of panicle with
my finger, till the paper was almost covered with the yellow powder. I
carried this to the females, which were flowering in another part of
the garden, and placed it over them. The cold nights of the year in
which this experiment was made, destroyed these Datiscas, with many
other plants, much earlier than usual. Nevertheless, when I examined
the flowers of those plants, which I had sprinkled with the fertilizing
powder, I found the seeds of their due magnitude; while in the more
remote Datiscas, which had not been impregnated with pollen, no traces
of seeds were visible.

Several species of Momordica, cultivated by us, like other Indian
vegetables, in close stoves, have frequently borne female flowers;
which, although at first very vigorous, after a short time have
constantly faded and turned yellow, without perfecting any seed, till
I instructed the gardener, as soon as he observed a female flower, to
gather a male one, and place it above the female. By this contrivance
we are so certain of obtaining fruit that we dare pledge ourselves to
make any female flowers fertile that shall be fixed on.

The _Jatropha urens_ has flowered every year in my hot-house; but
the female flowers coming before the males, in a week’s time dropped
their petals and faded before the latter were opened; from which cause
no fruit has been produced, but the _germina_ themselves have
fallen off. We have therefore never had any fruit of the Jatropha till
the year 1752, when the male flowers were in vigour on a tall tree,
at the same time that the females began to appear on a small Jatropha
which was growing in a garden-pot. I placed this pot under the other
tree, by which means the female flowers bore seeds, which grew on being
sown. I have frequently amused myself with taking the male flowers from
one plant, and scattering them over the female flowers of another, and
have always found the seeds of the latter impregnated by it.

Two years ago I placed a piece of paper under some of these male
flowers and afterwards folded up the pollen which had fallen upon it,
preserving it so folded up, if I remember right, four or six weeks,
at the end of which time another branch of the same Jatropha was in
flower. I then took the pollen, which I had so long preserved in paper,
and strewed it over three female flowers, the only ones at that time
expanded. The three females proved fruitful, while all the rest, which
grew in the same bunch, fell off abortive.

The interior petals of the _Ornithogalum_, commonly but improperly
called _Canadense_, cohere so closely together that they only just
admit the air to the germen and will scarcely permit the pollen of
another flower to pass; this plant produced every day new flowers and
fruit, the fructification never failing in any instance; I therefore,
with the utmost care, extracted the antheræ from one of the flowers
with a hooked needle, and as I hoped, this single flower proved barren.
This experiment was repeated about a week after with the same success.

I removed all of the antheræ out of a flower of _Chelidonium
corniculatum_ (scarlet-horned poppy), which was growing in a remote
part of the garden, upon the first opening of its petals, and stripped
off all the rest of the flowers; another day I treated another flower
of the same plant in a similar manner, but sprinkled the pistillum of
this with the pollen borrowed from another plant of the same species;
the result was, that the first flower produced no fruit, but the second
afforded very perfect seed. My design in this experiment was to prove
that the mere removal of the antheræ from a flower is not in itself
sufficient to render the germen abortive.

Having the _Nicotiana fruticosa_ growing in a garden-pot, and
producing plenty of flowers and seed, I extracted the antheræ from the
newly expanded flowers before they had burst, at the same time cutting
away all the other flowers; this germen produced no fruit, nor did it
even swell.

I removed an urn, in which the _Asphodelus fistulosus_ was
growing, to one corner of the garden, and from one of the flowers
which had lately opened, I extracted its antheræ; this caused the
impregnation to fail. Another day I treated another flower in the same
manner; but, bringing a flower from a plant in a different part of the
garden, with which I sprinkled the pistillum of the mutilated one, its
germen became by that means fruitful.

_Ixia chinensis_, flowering in my stove, the windows of which
were shut, all its flowers proved abortive. I therefore took one of
its antheræ in a pair of pincers, and with them sprinkled the stigmata
of two flowers, and the next day one stigma only of a third flower;
the seed-buds of these flowers remained, grew to a large size and bore
seed, the fruit of the third, however, contained ripe seed only in one
of its cells.

To relate more experiments would only be to fatigue the reader
unnecessarily. All nature proclaims the truth I have endeavored to
inculcate, and every flower bears witness to it. Any person may make
the experiment for himself with any plant he pleases, only taking
care to place the pot in which it is growing, in the window of a room
sufficiently out of reach of other flowers; and I will venture to
promise him that he will obtain no perfect fruit unless pollen has
access to the pistillum.

Logan’s experiments on the Mays are perfectly satisfactory, and
manifestly show that the pollen does not enter the style, or arrive
at the germen, but that it is exhausted by the genital fluid of the
pistillum. And as in animals no conception can take place, unless the
genital fluid of the female be discharged at the same moment as the
impregnating liquor of the male; so in plants, generation fails, unless
the stigma be moist with prolific dew.

Husbandmen know, by long experience, that if rain falls while rye is
in flower, by coagulating the pollen of its antheræ, it occasions the
emptiness of many husks in the ear.

Gardeners remark the same thing every year in fruit trees. Their
blossoms produce no fruit if they have unfortunately been exposed to
long-continued rains.

Aquatic plants rise above the water at the time of flowering, and
afterwards again subside, for no other reason, than that the pollen may
safely reach the stigma.

The white water-lily (_Nymphaea alba_) raises itself every morning
out of the water and opens its flowers, so that by noon at least three
inches of its flower-stalk may be seen above the surface. In the
evening it is closely shut up, and withdrawn again; for about four
o’clock in the afternoon the flower closes, and remains all night under
water; which was observed full two thousand years since, even as long
ago as the time of Theophrastus, who has described this circumstance
in the _Nymphaea Lotus_, a plant so much resembling our white
water-lily that they are only distinguished from each other by the
leaves of the Lotus being indented. Theophrastus gives the following
account of this vegetable, in his _History of Plants_, book IV.,
chap. 10: “It is said to withdraw its flowers into the Euphrates,
which continue to descend till midnight, to so great a depth that at
daybreak they are out of reach of the hand; after which it rises again,
and in the course of the morning appears above the water, and expands
its flowers, rising higher and higher, till it is a considerable
height above the surface.” The very same thing may be observed in the
_Nymphaea alba_.

Many flowers close themselves in the evening and before rain, lest the
pollen should be coagulated; but after the discharge of the pollen
they always remain open. Such of them as do not shut up, incline their
flowers downward in those circumstances, and several flowers, which
come forth in the moisture of spring, droop perpetually. The manner in
which the Parnassia and Saxifrage move their antheræ to the stigma is
well known. The common Rue, a plant everywhere to be met with, moves
one of its antheræ every day to the stigma, till all of them in their
turns have deposited their pollen there.

The Neapolitan star flower (_Ornithogalum nutans_) has six broad
stamina, which stand close together in the form of a bell, the three
external ones being but half the length of the others; so that it seems
impossible for their antheræ ever to convey their pollen to the stigma;
but nature, by an admirable contrivance, bends the summits of these
external stamina inwards between the other filaments, so that they are
enabled to accomplish their purpose.

The Plaintain tree (_Musa_) bears two kinds of hermaphrodite
flowers; some have imperfect antheræ, others only the rudiments of
stigmata; as the last mentioned kind appear after the others, they
cannot impregnate them, consequently no seeds are produced in our
gardens, and scarcely ever on the plants cultivated in India. An event
happened this year, which I have long wished for; two plaintain-trees
flowering with me so fortunately that one of them brought forth its
first female blossoms at the time that male ones began to appear on the
other. I eagerly ran to collect antheræ from the first plant, in order
to scatter them over the newly-expanded females, in hopes of obtaining
seed from them, which no botanist has yet been able to do. But when I
came to examine the antheræ I found even the largest of them absolutely
empty and void of pollen, consequently unfit for impregnating the
females; the seeds of this plant, therefore, can never be perfected in
our gardens. I do not doubt, however, that real male plants of this
species may be found in its native country, bearing flowers without
fruit, which the gardeners have neglected; while the females in this
country produce imperfect fruit, without seeds, like the female fig;
and, like that tree, are increased easily by suckers. The fruit,
therefore, of the plaintain-tree scarcely attains anything like its due
size, the larger seed-buds only ripening, without containing anything
in them.

The day would sooner fail me than examples. A female date-bearing palm
flowered many years at Berlin, without producing any seeds. But the
Berlin people taking care to have some of the blossoms of the male
tree, which was then flowering at Leipsic, sent them by the post, they
obtained fruit by that means; and some dates, the offspring of this
impregnation, being planted in my garden, sprung up, and to this day
continue to grow vigorously. Kœmpfer formerly told us how necessary
it was found by the oriental people, who live upon the produce of
palm-trees, and are the true Lotophagi, to plant some male trees among
the females, if they hoped for any fruit; hence, it is the practice of
those who make war in that part of the world to cut down all the male
palms, that a famine may afflict their proprietors; sometimes even
the inhabitants themselves destroy the male trees, when they dread an
invasion, that their enemies may find no sustenance in the country.

Leaving these instances, and innumerable others, which are so well
known to botanists that they would by no means bear the appearance of
novelty, and can only be doubted by those persons who neither have
observed nature, nor will they take the trouble to study her, I pass
to a fresh subject, concerning which much new light is wanted; I mean
hybrid, or mule vegetables, the existence and origin of which we shall
now consider.

I shall enumerate three or four real mule plants, to whose origin I
have been an eye-witness.

1. _Veronica spuria_, described in Amœnitates Acad. vol. III. p.
35, came from the impregnation of _Veronic maratima_ by _Verbena
officinalis_; it is easily propagated by cuttings, and agrees
perfectly with its mother in fructification, and with its father in
leaves.

2. _Delphinium hybridum_, sprung up in a part of the garden where
_Delphinium clatum_ and _Aconitum Napellus_ grew together;
it resembles its mother as much in its internal parts, that is, in
fructification as it does its father (the _Aconitum_) in outward
structure, or leaves; and, owing its origin to plants so nearly allied
to each other, it propagates itself by seed; some of which I now send
with this Dissertation.

3. _Hieracium Taraxici_, gathered in 1753 upon our mountains by
Dr. Solander, in its thick, brown, woolly calyx; in its stem being
hairy towards the top, and in its bracteæ, as well as in every part of
its fructification, resembles so perfectly its mother, _Hieracium
alpinum_, that an inexperienced person might mistake one for the
other; but in the smoothness of its leaves, in their indentations and
whole structure, it so manifestly agrees with its father, _Leontodon
Taraxacum_ (Dandelion), that there can be no doubt of its origin.

4. _Tragopogon hybridum_ attracted my notice the autumn before
last, in a part of the garden where I had planted _Tragopogon
pratense_, and _Tragopogon porrifolium_; but winter coming on,
destroyed its seeds. Last year, while the _Tragopogon pratense_
was in flower I rubbed off its pollen early in the morning, and
about eight o’clock sprinkled its stigmata with some pollen of the
_Tragopogon porrifolium_, marking the calyces by tying a thread
round them. I afterwards gathered the seeds when ripe, and sowed them
that autumn in another place; they grew, and produced this year, 1759,
purple flowers yellow at the base, seeds of which I now send. I doubt
whether any experiment demonstrates the generation of plants more
certainly than this.

There can be no doubt that these are all new species produced by
hybrid generation. And hence we learn, that a mule offspring is
the exact image of its mother in its medullary substance, internal
nature, or fructification, but resembles its father in leaves. This
is a foundation upon which naturalists may build much. For it seems
probable that many plants, which now appear different species of
the same _genus_, may in the beginning have been but one plant,
having arisen merely from hybrid generation. Many of those Geraniums
which grow at the Cape of Good Hope, and have never been found wild
anywhere but in the south parts of Africa, and which, as they are
distinguished from all other Geraniums by their single-leaved calyx,
many-flowered foot-stalk, irregular corolla, seven fertile stamina,
and three mutilated ones, and by their naked seeds furnished with
downy awns; so they agree together in all these characters, although
very various in their roots, stems and leaves; these Geraniums, I say,
would almost induce a botanist to believe that the species of one
_genus_ in vegetables are only so many different plants as there
have been different associations with the flowers of one species, and
consequently a _genus_ is nothing else than a number of plants
sprung from the same mother by different fathers. But whether all
these species be the offspring of time; whether, in the beginning
of all things, the Creator limited the number of future species, I
dare not presume to determine. I am, however, convinced this mode of
multiplying plants does not interfere with the system or general scheme
of nature; as I daily observe that insects, which live upon one species
of a particular _genus_, are contented with another of the same
_genus_.

A person who has once seen the _Achyranthes aspera_, and remarked
its spike, the parts of its flower, its small and peculiarly formed
nectaria, as well as its calyces bent backwards as the fruit ripens,
would think it very easy at any time to distinguish these flowers
from all others in the universe; but when he finds the flowers of
_Achyranthes indica_ agreeing with them even in their minutest
parts, and at the same time observes the large, thick, obtuse,
undulated leaves of the last-mentioned plant, he will think he sees
_Achyranthes aspera_ masked in the foliage of _Xanthium
strumarium_. But I forbear to mention any more instances.

Here is a new employment for botanists, to attempt the production of
new species of vegetables by scattering the pollen of various plants
over various widowed females. And if these remarks should meet with
a favourable reception, I shall be the more induced to dedicate what
remains of my life to such experiments, which recommend themselves by
being at the same time agreeable and useful. I am persuaded by many
considerations that those numerous and most valuable varieties of
plants which are used for culinary purposes, have been produced in
this manner, as the several kinds of cabbages, lettuces, etc.; and I
apprehend this is the reason of their not being changed by a difference
of soil. Hence I cannot give my assent to the opinion of those who
imagine all varieties to have been occasioned by change of soil; for,
if this were the case, the plants would return to their original form,
if removed again to their original situation.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 13: From the _Publications of the Linnaean Society_.]




                                  XII

                             JOSEPH BLACK

                               1728-1799


 _Joseph Black, born in 1728 at Bordeaux, France, was educated in
 Belfast and at the University of Glasgow. Before he took his M.D.
 degree he showed that alkalies were formed, not by their absorbing
 “phlogiston,” but by their having carbonic acid gas, or “fixed air,”
 as a component. In 1753 he was appointed lecturer on chemistry at
 Glasgow, and in 1776 became professor of chemistry at Edinburgh. In
 1763 he announced his discovery of latent heat, a principle which
 has been of great practical value. He died in Edinburgh, December 6,
 1799._


                THE DISCOVERY OF CARBONIC ACID GAS[14]

Hoffman, in one of his observations, gives the history of a powder
called _Magnesia Alba_, which has been long used, and esteemed as
a mild and tasteless purgative; but the method of preparing it was not
generally known before he made it public.

It was originally obtained from a liquor called the _Mother of
nitre_, which is produced in the following manner:

Salt-petre is separated from the brine which first affords it, or from
the water with which it is washed out of nitrous earths, by the process
commonly used in crystallizing salts. In this process, the brine is
gradually diminished, and at length reduced to a small quantity of
an unctuous bitter saline liquor, affording no more salt-petre by
evaporation, but, if urged with a brisk fire, drying up into a confused
mass, which attracts water strongly, and becomes fluid again when
exposed to the open air.

To this liquor the workmen have given the name of the _Mother of
nitre_; and Hoffman, finding it composed of the magnesia united
to an acid, obtained a separation of these, either by exposing the
compound to a strong fire, in which the acid was dissipated, and the
magnesia remained behind, or by the addition of an alkali, which
attracted the acid to itself: and this last method he recommends as
the best. He likewise makes an inquiry into the nature and virtues
of the powder thus prepared; and observes, that it is an absorbent
earth, which joins readily with all acids, and must necessarily destroy
any acidity it meets in the stomach; but that its purgative power is
uncertain, for sometimes it has not the least effect of that kind.
As it is a mere insipid earth, he rationally concludes it to be a
purgative only when converted into a sort of neutral salt by an acid
in the stomach, and that its effect is therefore proportional to the
quantity of this acid.

Although magnesia appears from this history of it, to be a very
innocent medicine; yet, having observed that some hypochondriacs,
who used it frequently, were subject to flatulencies and spasms, he
seems to have suspected it of some noxious quality. The circumstances,
however, which gave rise to his suspicion, may very possibly have
proceeded from the imprudence of his patients; who, trusting too much
to magnesia (which is properly a palliative in that disease) and
neglecting the assistance of other remedies, allowed their disorder
to increase upon them. It may, indeed, be alleged that magnesia, as a
purgative, is not the most eligible medicine for such constitutions, as
they agree best with those that strengthen, stimulate, and warm; which
the saline purges, commonly used, are not observed to do. But there
seems at last to be no objection to its use, when children are troubled
with an acid in their stomach: for, gentle purging, in this case, is
very proper; and it is often more conveniently procured by means of
magnesia, than of any other medicine, on account of its being entirely
insipid.

The above-mentioned Author, observing, some time after, that a bitter
saline liquor, similar to that obtained from the brine of salt-petre,
was likewise produced by the evaporation of those waters which contain
common salt, had the curiosity to try if this would also yield a
magnesia. The experiment succeeded: And he thus found out another
process for obtaining this powder; and at the same time assured
himself, by experiments, that the product from both was exactly the
same.

My curiosity led me, some time ago, to inquire more particularly into
the nature of magnesia, and especially to compare its properties with
those of the other absorbent earths, of which there plainly appeared to
me to be very different kinds, although commonly confounded together
under one name. I was indeed led to this examination of the absorbent
earths, partly by the hope of discovering a new sort of lime and
lime-water, which might possibly be a more powerful solvent of the
stone, than that commonly used; but was disappointed in my expectations.

I have had no opportunity of seeing Hoffman’s first magnesia, or the
liquor from which it is prepared, and have therefore been obliged to
make my experiments upon the second.

In order to prepare it, I at first employed the bitter saline liquor
called _bittern_, which remains in the pans after the evaporation
of sea-water. But as that liquor is not always easily procured, I
afterwards made use of a salt called Epsom salt, which is separated
from the bittern by crystallization, and is evidently composed of
magnesia and the vitriolic acid.

There is likewise a spurious kind of Glauber salt, which yields plenty
of magnesia, and seems to be no other than Epsom salt, of sea-water
reduced to crystals of a larger size. And common salt also affords
a small quantity of this powder; because, being separated from the
bittern by one hasty crystallization only, it necessarily contains a
portion of that liquor.

Those who would prepare a magnesia from Epsom salt, may use the
following process:

Dissolve equal quantities of Epsom salt, and of pearl ashes,
separately, in a sufficient quantity of water; purify each solution
from its dregs, and mix them accurately together by violent agitation.
Then make them just to boil over a brisk fire.

Add now to the mixture, three or four times its quantity of hot water;
after a little agitation, allow the magnesia to settle to the bottom,
and decant off as much of the water as possible. Pour on the same
quantity of cold water; and, after settling, decant it off in the
same manner. Repeat this washing with the cold water ten or twelve
times, or even oftener, if the magnesia be required perfectly pure for
chemical experiments.

When it is sufficiently washed, the water may be strained and squeezed
from it in a linen cloth; for very little of the magnesia passes
through.

The alkali in the mixture, uniting with the acid, separates it from
the magnesia; which, not being of itself soluble in water, must
consequently appear immediately under a solid form. But the powder
which thus appears is not entirely magnesia; part of it is the neutral
salt formed from the union of the acid and alkali. This neutral salt
is found, upon examination, to agree in all respects with vitriolated
tartar, and requires a large quantity of hot water to dissolve it. As
much of it is therefore dissolved as the water can take up; the rest
is dispersed through the mixture, in the form of a powder. Hence the
necessity of washing the magnesia with so much trouble; for the first
effusion of hot water is intended to dissolve the whole of the salt,
and the subsequent additions of cold water to wash away this solution.

The caution given, of boiling the mixture, is not unnecessary: if it
be neglected, the whole of the magnesia is not accurately separated at
once; and, by allowing it to rest for some time, that powder concretes
into minute grains, which, when viewed with the microscope, appear to
be assemblages of needles diverging from a point. This happens more
especially when the solutions of the Epsom salt, and of the alkali,
are diluted with too much water before they are mixed together. Thus,
if a dram of Epsom salt, and of salt of tartar, be dissolved each in
four ounces of water, and be mixed, and then allowed to rest three or
four days, the whole of the magnesia will be formed into these grains.
Or, if we filtrate the mixture soon after it is made, and heat the
clear liquor which passes through, it will become turbid, and deposit a
magnesia.


An ounce of magnesia was exposed in a crucible, for about an hour, to
such a heat as is sufficient to melt copper. When taken out, it weighed
three drams and one scruple, or had lost 7-12 of its former weight.

I repeated, with the magnesia prepared in this manner, most of those
experiments I had already made upon it before calcination, and the
result was as follows:--

It dissolves in all the acids, and with these composes salts exactly
similar to those described in the first set of experiments: But, what
is particularly to be remarked, it is dissolved without any the least
degree of effervescence.

It slowly precipitates the corrosive sublimate of mercury, in the form
of a black powder.

It separates the volatile alkali in salt-ammoniac from the acid, when
it is mixed with a warm solution of that salt. But it does not separate
an acid from a calcareous earth, nor does it introduce the least change
upon lime-water.

Lastly, when a dram of it is digested with an ounce of water in a
bottle for some hours, it does not make any the least change in the
water. The magnesia, when dried, is found to have gained ten grains;
but it neither effervesces with acids, nor does it sensibly affect
lime-water.

Observing magnesia to lose such a remarkable proportion of its weight
in the fire, my next attempts were directed to the investigation of
this volatile part; and, among other experiments, the following seemed
to throw some light upon it:--

Three ounces of magnesia were distilled in a glass retort and receiver,
the fire being gradually increased until the magnesia was obscurely red
hot. When all was cool, I found only five drams of a whitish water in
the receiver, which had a faint smell of the spirit of hartshorn, gave
a green colour to the juice of violets, and rendered the solutions of
corrosive sublimate, and of silver, very slightly turbid. But it did
not sensibly effervesce with acids.

The magnesia, when taken out of the retort, weighed an ounce, three
drams, and thirty grains, or had lost more than half of its weight. It
still effervesced pretty briskly with acids, though not so strongly as
before this operation.

The fire should have been raised here to the degree requisite for
the perfect calcination of magnesia. But, even from this imperfect
experiment, it is evident, that, of the volatile parts contained in
that powder, a small proportion only is water; the rest cannot, it
seems, be retained in vessels, under a visible form. Chemists have
often observed in their distillations that part of a body has vanished
from their senses notwithstanding the utmost care to retain it; and
they have always found, upon further inquiry, that subtle part to be
air, which having been imprisoned in the body, under a solid form, was
set free, and rendered fluid and elastic by the fire. We may therefore
safely conclude, that the volatile matter lost in the calcination of
magnesia, is mostly air; and hence the calcined magnesia does not emit
air, or make an effervescence when mixed with acids.

The water, from its properties, seems to contain a small portion of
volatile alkali, which was probably formed from the earth, air and
water, from some of these combined together; and perhaps also from a
small quantity of inflammable matter, which adhered accidently to the
magnesia. Whenever chemists meet with this salt, they are inclined to
ascribe its origin to some animal or putrid vegetable substance; and
this they have always done, when they obtained it from the calcareous
earths, all of which afford a small quantity of it. There is, however,
no doubt, that it can sometimes be produced independently of any such
mixture, since many fresh vegetables, and tartar, afford a considerable
quantity of it. And how can it, in the present instance, be supposed,
that any animal or vegetable matter adhered to the magnesia, while it
was dissolved by an acid, separated from this by an alkali, and washed
with so much water?

Two drams of magnesia were calcined in a crucible, in the manner
described above, and thus reduced to two scruples and twelve grains.
This calcined magnesia was dissolved in a sufficient quantity of spirit
of vitriol, and then again separated from the acid by the addition of
an alkali, of which a large quantity is necessary for this purpose. The
magnesia being very well washed and dried, weighed one dram and fifty
grains. It effervesced violently, or emitted a large quantity of air,
when thrown into acids; formed a red powder, when mixed with a solution
of sublimate; separated the calcareous earths from an acid, and
sweetened lime-water; and had thus recovered all those properties which
it had but just now lost by calcination. Nor had it only recovered
its original properties, but acquired besides an addition of weight,
nearly equal to what had been lost in the fire; and as it is found to
effervesce with acids, part of the addition must certainly be air.

This air seems to have been furnished by the alkali, from which it
was separated by the acid; for Dr. Hales has clearly proved, that
alkaline salts contain a large quantity of fixed air, which they emit
in great abundance when joined to a pure acid. In the present case, the
alkali is really joined to an acid, but without any visible emission
of air; and yet the air is not retained in it; for the neutral salt,
into which it is converted, is the same in quantity, and in every other
respect, as if the acid employed had not been previously saturated with
magnesia, but offered to the alkali in its pure state, and had driven
the air out of it in their conflict. It seems therefore evident, that
the air was forced from the alkali by the acid, and lodged itself in
the magnesia.

These considerations led me to try a few experiments, whereby I might
know what quantity of air is expelled from an alkali, or from magnesia,
by acids.

Two drams of a pure fixed alkaline salt, and an ounce of water, were
put into a Florentine flask, which, together with its contents, weighed
two ounces and two drams. Some oil of vitriol diluted with water was
dropped in, until the salt was exactly saturated; which it was found to
be, when two drams, two scruples and three grains of this acid had been
added. The phial with its contents now weighed two ounces, four drams
and fifteen grains. One scruple, therefore, and eight grains, were lost
during the ebullition; of which a trifling portion may be water, or
something of the same kind; the rest is air.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 14: From _Experiments upon Magnesia, Quicklime, and some
other Alkaline Substances_ (1775).]




                                 XIII

                           JOSEPH PRIESTLEY

                               1733-1804


 _Joseph Priestley, born in Yorkshire, England, March 13, 1733, was
 a Unitarian minister. In 1774 he discovered oxygen, which he called
 “dephlogisticated air.” Because of his liberal political ideas he was
 persecuted by his countrymen, and in 1794 emigrated to Northumberland,
 Pennsylvania, where he lived until his death, February 6, 1804._


                      THE DISCOVERY OF OXYGEN[15]

Presently, after my return from abroad, I went to work upon the
_mercurius calcinatus_, which I had procured from Mr. Cadet; and,
with a very moderate degree of heat, I got from about one-fourth of
an ounce of it, an ounce-measure of air, which I observed to be not
readily imbibed, either by the substance itself from which it had
been expelled (for I suffered them to continue a long time together
before I transferred the air to any other place) or by water, in which
I suffered this air to stand a considerable time before I made any
experiment upon it.

In this air, as I had expected, a candle burned with a vivid flame; but
what I observed new at this time (November 19), and which surprised me
no less than the fact I had discovered before, was, that, whereas a
few moments agitation in water will deprive the modified nitrous air
of its property of admitting a candle to burn in it; yet, after more
than ten times as much agitation as would be sufficient to produce this
alteration in the nitrous air, no sensible change was produced in this.
A candle still burned in it with a strong flame; and it did not, in
the least, diminish common air, which I have observed that nitrous air,
in this state, in some measure does.

But I was much more surprised, when, after two days, in which this air
had continued in contact with water (by which it was diminished about
one-twentieth of its bulk) I agitated it violently in water about five
minutes, and found that a candle still burned in it as well as in
common air. The same degree of agitation would have made phlogisticated
nitrous air fit for respiration indeed, but it would certainly have
extinguished a candle.

These facts fully convinced me, that there must be a very material
difference between the constitution of air from _mercurius
calcinatus_, and that of phlogisticated nitrous air, notwithstanding
their resemblance in some particulars. But though I did not doubt that
the air from _mercurius calcinatus_ was fit for respiration, after
being agitated in water, as every kind of air without exception, on
which I have tried the experiment, had been, I still did not suspect
that it was respirable in the first instance; so far was I from having
any idea of this air being, what it really was, much superior, in this
respect, to the air of the atmosphere.

In this ignorance of the real nature of this kind of air, I continued
from this time (November) to the 1st of March following; having, in the
meantime, been intent upon my experiments on the vitriolic acid air
above recited, and the various modifications of air produced by spirit
of nitre, an account of which will follow. But in the course of this
month, I not only ascertained the nature of this kind of air, though
very gradually, but was led to it by the complete discovery of the
constitution of the air we breathe.

Till this 1st of March, 1775, I had so little suspicion of the air from
_mercurius calcinatus_, &c., being wholesome, that I had not even
thought of applying it to the test of nitrous air; but thinking (as my
reader must imagine I frequently must have done) on the candle burning
in it after long agitation in water, it occurred to me at last to make
the experiment; and putting one measure of nitrous air to two measures
of this air, I found, not only that it was diminished, but that it was
diminished quite as much as common air, and that the redness of the
mixture was likewise equal to that of a similar mixture of nitrous and
common air.

After this I had no doubt but that the air from _mercurius
calcinatus_ was fit for respiration, and that it had all the other
properties of genuine common air. But I did not take notice of what I
might have observed, if I had not been so fully possessed by the notion
of there being no air better than common air, that the redness was
really deeper, and the diminution something greater than common air
would have admitted.

Moreover, this advance in the way of truth, in reality, threw me back
into error, making me give up the hypothesis I had first formed, viz.
that the _mercurius calcinatus_ had extracted spirit of nitre
from the air; for I now concluded, that all the constituent parts of
the air were equally, and in their proper proportion, imbibed in the
preparation of this substance, and also in the process of making red
lead. For at the same time that I made the above mentioned experiment
on the air from _mercurius calcinatus_, I likewise observed that
the air which I had extracted from red lead, after the fixed air was
washed out of it, was of the same nature, being diminished by nitrous
air like common air: but, at the same time, I was puzzled to find that
air from the red precipitate was diminished in the same manner, though
the process for making this substance is quite different from that of
making the two others. But to this circumstance I happened not to give
much attention.

I wish my reader be not quite tired with the frequent repetition of the
word surprise, and others of similar import; but I must go on in that
style a little longer. For the next day I was more surprised than ever
I had been before, with finding that, after the above-mentioned mixture
of nitrous air and the air from _mercurius calcinatus_, had stood
all night, (in which time the whole diminution must have taken place;
and, consequently, had it been common air, it must have been made
perfectly noxious, and entirely unfit for respiration or inflammation)
a candle burned in it, and even better than in common air.

I cannot, at this distance of time, recollect what it was that I had in
view in making this experiment; but I know I had no expectation of the
real issue of it. Having acquired a considerable degree of readiness in
making experiments of this kind, a very slight and evanescent motive
would be sufficient to induce me to do it. If, however, I had not
happened, for some other purpose, to have had a lighted candle before
me I should probably never have made the trial; and the whole train
of my future experiments relating to this kind of air might have been
prevented.

Still, however, having no conception of the real cause of this
phenomenon, I considered it as something very extraordinary; but as
a property that was peculiar to air that was extracted from these
substances, and adventitious; and I always spoke of the air to my
acquaintance as being substantially the same thing with common air.

I particularly remember my telling Dr. Price, that I was myself
perfectly satisfied of its being common air, as it appeared to be so
by the test of nitrous air; though, for the satisfaction of others, I
wanted a mouse to make the proof quite complete.

On the 8th of this month I procured a mouse, and put it into a glass
vessel, containing two ounce-measures of the air from _mercuris
calcinatus_. Had it been common air, a full-grown mouse, as this
was, would have lived in it about a quarter of an hour. In this air,
however, my mouse lived a full half hour; and though it was taken out
seemingly dead, it appeared to have been only exceedingly chilled; for,
upon being held to fire, it presently revived, and appeared not to have
received any harm from the experiment.

By this I was confirmed in my conclusion, that the air extracted
from _mercurius calcinates_, &c., was, at least, as good as
common air; but I did not certainly conclude that it was any better;
because, though one mouse would live only a quarter of an hour in a
given quantity of air, I knew it was not impossible but that another
mouse might have lived in it half an hour; so little accuracy is
there in this method of ascertaining the goodness of air; and indeed
I have never had recourse to it for my own satisfaction, since the
discovery of that most ready, accurate, and elegant test that nitrous
air furnishes. But in this case I had a view to publishing the most
generally satisfactory account of my experiments that the nature of the
thing would admit of.

This experiment with the mouse, when I had reflected upon it some time,
gave me so much suspicion that the air into which I had put it was
better than common air, that I was induced, the day after, to apply
the test of nitrous air to a small part of that very quantity of air
which the mouse had breathed so long; so that, had it been common air,
I was satisfied it must have been very nearly, if not altogether, as
noxious as possible, so as not to be affected by nitrous air; when,
to my surprise again, I found that though it had been breathed so
long, it was still better than common air. For after mixing it with
nitrous air, in the usual proportion of two to one, it was diminished
in the proportion of four and one-half to three and one-half; that
is, the nitrous air had made it two-ninths less than before, and this
in a very short space of time; whereas I had never found that, in the
longest time, any common air was reduced more than one-fifth of its
bulk by any proportion of nitrous air, nor more than one-fourth by any
phlogistic process whatever. Thinking of this extraordinary fact upon
my pillow, the next morning I put another measure of nitrous air to the
same mixture, and, to my utter astonishment, found that it was farther
diminished to almost one-half of its original quantity. I then put a
third measure to it; but this did not diminish it any farther; but,
however, left it one measure less than it was even after the mouse had
been taken out of it.

Being now fully satisfied that this air, even after the mouse had
breathed it half an hour, was much better than common air; and having
a quantity of it still left, sufficient for the experiment, viz. an
ounce-measure and a half, I put the mouse into it; when I observed that
it seemed to feel no shock upon being put into it, evident signs of
which would have been visible, if the air had not been very wholesome;
but that it remained perfectly at its ease another full half hour, when
I took it out quite lively and vigorous. Measuring the air the next
day, I found it to be reduced from one and one-half to two-thirds of an
ounce-measure. And after this, if I remember well (for in my register
of the day I only find it noted, that it was considerably diminished
by nitrous air), it was nearly as good as common air. It was evident,
indeed, from the mouse having been taken out quite vigorous, that the
air could not have been rendered very noxious.

For my farther satisfaction I procured another mouse, and putting it
into less than two ounce-measures of air extracted from _mercurius
calcinatus_ and air from red precipitate (which, having found
them to be of the same quality, I had mixed together) it lived
three-quarters of an hour. But not having had the precaution to set the
vessel in a warm place, I suspect that the mouse died of cold. However,
as it had lived three times as long as it could probably have lived in
the same quantity of common air, and I did not expect much accuracy
from this kind of a test, I did not think it necessary to make any more
experiments with mice.

Being now fully satisfied of the superior goodness of this kind of air,
I proceeded to measure that degree of purity, with as much accuracy
as I could, by the test of nitrous air; and I began with putting one
measure of nitrous air to two measures of this air, as if I had been
examining common air; and now I observed that the diminution was
evidently greater than common air would have suffered by the same
treatment. A second measure of nitrous air reduced it to two-thirds
of its original quantity, and a third measure to one-half. Suspecting
that the diminution could not proceed much farther, I then added only
half a measure of nitrous air, by which it was diminished still more;
but not much, and another half-measure made it more than half of its
original quantity; so that, in this case, two measures of this air took
more than two measures of nitrous air, and yet remained less than half
of what it was. Five measures brought it pretty exactly to its original
dimensions.

At the same time, air from the red precipitate was diminished in
the same proportion as that from _mercurius calcinatus_, five
measures of nitrous air being received by two measures of this without
any increase of dimensions. Now as common air takes about one-half
of its bulk of nitrous air, before it begins to receive any addition
to its dimensions from more nitrous air, and this air took more than
four half-measures before it ceased to be diminished by more nitrous
air, and even five half-measures made no addition to its original
dimensions, I conclude that it was between four and five times as good
as common air. It will be seen that I have since procured air better
than this, even between five and six times as good as the best common
air that I have ever met with.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 15: From _Experiments and Observations on Different Kinds
of Air_, Vol. II, (1775).]




                                  XIV

                            HENRY CAVENDISH

                               1731-1810


 _Henry Cavendish, the discoverer of hydrogen, was born of English
 parents in Nice, October 10, 1731. He studied at Cambridge University,
 England, and in 1760 joined the Royal Society, devoting his great
 fortune to the advancement of science. He discovered hydrogen in 1766,
 and later, using Priestley’s discovery of oxygen, found that the two
 gases combined under certain physical conditions to produce water.
 Besides his studies in chemistry, he made some interesting discoveries
 in physics. In 1783 he proposed the theory that heat was a motion
 rather than a substance; and in 1798 he computed the density of the
 earth to be about five and a half times that of water. He died at
 Clapham, February 24, 1810._


         THE COMBINATION OF HYDROGEN AND OXYGEN INTO WATER[16]

In Dr. Priestley’s last volume of experiments is related an experiment
of Mr. Warltire’s, in which it is said that, on firing a mixture of
common and inflammable air by electricity in a close copper vessel
holding about three pints, a loss of weight was always perceived, on
an average about two grains, though the vessel was stopped in such a
manner that no air could escape by the explosion. It is also related,
that on repeating the experiment in glass vessels, the inside of the
glass, though clean and dry before, immediately became dewy; which
confirmed an opinion he had long entertained, that common air deposits
its moisture by phlogistication. As the latter experiment seemed likely
to throw great light on the subject I had in view, I thought it well
worth examining more closely. The first experiment also, if there was
no mistake in it, would be very extraordinary and curious; but it did
not succeed with me; for though the vessel I used held more than Mr.
Warltire’s, namely, 24,000 grains of water, and though the experiment
was repeated several times with different proportions of common and
inflammable air, I could never perceive a loss of weight of more than
one-fifth of a grain, and commonly none at all. It must be observed,
however, that though there were some of the experiments in which it
seemed to diminish a little in weight, there were none in which it
increased.

In all the experiments, the inside of the glass globe became dewy,
as observed by Mr. Warltire; but not the least sooty matter could be
perceived. Care was taken in all of them to find how much the air was
diminished by the explosion, and to observe its test. The result is as
follows, the bulk of the inflammable air being expressed in decimals of
the common air:

------+-----------+----------+-------------+------------+--------
      |           |          |Air Remaining|Test of this|
Common|Inflammable|Diminution|  after the  | Air in the |Standard
 Air  |     Air   |          |  Explosion  |First Method|
------+-----------+----------+-------------+------------+--------
  1   |   1.241   |   .686   |    1.555    |     .055   |   .0
      |   1.955   |   .642   |    1.423    |     .063   |   .0
      |    .706   |   .647   |    1.059    |     .066   |   .0
      |    .423   |   .612   |     .811    |     .097   |   .03
      |    .331   |   .476   |     .855    |     .339   |   .27
      |    .206   |   .294   |     .912    |     .648   |   .58
------+-----------+----------+-------------+------------+---------

In these experiments the inflammable air was procured from zinc, as it
was in all my experiments, except where otherwise expressed: but I made
two more experiments, to try whether there was any difference between
the air from zinc and that from iron, the quantity of inflammable air
being the same in both, namely, 0.331 of the common; but I could not
find any difference to be depended on between the two kinds of air,
either in the diminution which they suffered by the explosion, or the
test of the burnt air.

From the fourth experiment it appears, that 423 measures of inflammable
air are nearly sufficient to phlogisticate completely 1000 of common
air; and that the bulk of the remaining air after the explosion is then
very little more than four-fifths of the common air employed; so that
as common air cannot be reduced to a much less bulk than that by any
method of phlogistication, we may safely conclude, that when they are
mixed in this proportion, and exploded, almost all the inflammable air,
and about one-fifth part of the common air, lose their elasticity, and
are condensed into the dew which lines the glass.

The better to examine the nature of this dew, 500,000 grain measures
of inflammable air were burnt with about two and one-half times the
quantity of common air, and the burnt air made to pass through a glass
cylinder eight feet long and three-quarters of an inch in diameter,
in order to deposit the dew. The two airs were conveyed slowly into
this cylinder by separate copper pipes, passing through a brass plate
which stopped up the end of the cylinder; and as neither inflammable
nor common air can burn by themselves, there was no danger of the flame
spreading into the magazines from which they were conveyed. Each of
these magazines consisted of a large tin vessel, inverted into another
vessel just big enough to receive it. The inner vessel communicated
with the copper pipe, and the air was forced out of it by pouring water
into the outer vessel; and in order that the quantity of common air
expelled should be two and one-half times that of the inflammable, the
water was let into the outer vessels by two holes in the bottom of the
same tin pan, the hole which conveyed the water into that vessel in
which the common air was confined being two and one-half times as big
as the other.

In trying the experiment, the magazines being first filled with their
respective airs, the glass cylinder was taken off, and water let, by
the two holes, into the outer vessel, till the airs began to issue from
the ends of the copper pipes; they were then set on fire by a candle,
and the cylinder put on again in its place. By this means upwards of
135 grains of water were condensed in the cylinder, which had no taste
nor smell, and which left no sensible sediment when evaporated to
dryness; neither did it yield any pungent smell during evaporation; in
short, it seemed pure water.

In my first experiment, the cylinder near that part where the air
was fired was a little tinged with sooty matter, but very slightly
so; and that little seemed to proceed from the putty with which the
apparatus was luted, and which was heated by the flame; for in another
experiment, in which it is contrived so that the luting should not be
much heated, scarce any sooty tinge could be perceived.

By the experiments with the globe it appeared, that when inflammable
and common air are exploded in a proper proportion, almost all the
inflammable air, and nearly one-fifth of the common air, lose their
elasticity, and are condensed into dew. And by this experiment it
appears, that this dew is plain water, and consequently that almost all
the inflammable air and about one-fifth of the common air, are turned
into pure water.

In order to examine the nature of the matter condensed on firing a
mixture of dephlogisticated and inflammable air, I took a glass globe
holding 8,800 grain measures, furnished with a brass cock and an
apparatus for firing air by electricity. This globe was well exhausted
by an air-pump, and then filled with a mixture of inflammable and
dephlogisticated air, by shutting the cock, fastening a bent glass tube
to its mouth, and letting up the end of it into a glass jar inverted
into water, and containing a mixture of 19,500 grain measures of
dephlogisticated air, and 37,000 of inflammable; so that, upon opening
the cock, some of this mixed air rushed through the bent tube, and
filled the globe. The cock was then shut, and the included air fired by
electricity, by which means almost all of it lost its elasticity. The
cock was then again opened, so as to let in more of the same air, to
supply the place of that destroyed by the explosion, which was again
fired, and the operation continued till almost the whole of the mixture
was let into the globe and exploded. By this means, though the globe
held not more than the sixth part of the mixture, almost the whole of
it was exploded therein, without any fresh exhaustion of the globe.

As I was desirous to try the quantity and test of this burnt air,
without letting any water into the globe, which would have prevented my
examining the nature of the condensed matter, I took a larger globe,
furnished also with a stop cock, exhausted it by an air-pump, and
screwed it on upon the cock of the former globe; upon which, by opening
both cocks, the air rushed out of the smaller globe into the larger,
till it became of equal density in both; then, by shutting the cock of
the larger globe, unscrewing it again from the former, and opening it
under water, I was enabled to find the quantity of the burnt air in
it; and consequently, as the proportion which the contents of the two
globes bore to each other was known, could tell the quantity of burnt
air in the small globe before the communication was made between them.
By this means the whole quantity of the burnt air was found to be 2,950
grain measures; its standard was 1.85.

The liquor condensed in the globe, in weight about thirty grains, was
sensibly acid to the taste, and by saturation with fixed alkali, and
evaporation, yielded near two grains of nitre; so that it consisted
of water united to a small quantity of nitrous acid. No sooty matter
was deposited in the globe. The dephlogisticated air used in this
experiment was procured from red precipitate, that is, from a solution
of quicksilver in spirit of nitre distilled till it acquires a red
colour.

As it was suspected, that the acid contained in the condensed liquor
was no essential part of the dephlogisticated air, but was owing to
some acid vapour which came over in making it and had not been absorbed
by the water, the experiment was repeated in the same manner, with some
more of the same air, which had been previously washed with water, by
keeping it a day or two in a bottle with some water, and shaking it
frequently; whereas that used in the preceding experiment had never
passed through water, except in preparing it. The condensed liquor was
still acid.

The experiment was also repeated with dephlogisticated air, procured
from red lead by means of oil of vitriol; the liquor condensed was
acid, but by an accident I was prevented from determining the nature of
the acid.

I also procured some dephlogisticated air from the leaves of plants, in
the manner of Doctors Ingenhousz and Priestley, and exploded it with
inflammable air as before; the condensed liquor still continued acid,
and of the nitrous kind.

In all these experiments the proportion of inflammable air was such,
that the burnt air was not much phlogisticated; and it was observed,
that the less phlogisticated it was, the more acid was the condensed
liquor. I therefore made another experiment, with some more of the
same air from plants, in which the proportion of inflammable air was
greater, so that the burnt air was almost completely phlogisticated,
its standard being 1-10. The condensed liquor was then not at all acid,
but seemed pure water; so that it appears, that with this kind of
dephlogisticated air, the condensed liquor is not at all acid, when the
two airs are mixed in such a proportion that the burnt air is almost
completely phlogisticated, but is considerably so when it is not much
phlogisticated.

In order to see whether the same thing would obtain with air procured
from red precipitate, I made two more experiments with that kind
of air, the air in both being taken from the same bottle, and the
experiment tried in the same manner, except that the proportions of
inflammable air were different. In the first, in which the burnt air
was almost completely phlogisticated, the condensed liquor was not at
all acid. In the second, in which its standard was 1.86, that is, not
much phlogisticated, it was considerably acid; so that with this air,
as well as with that from plants, the condensed liquor contains, or is
entirely free from, acid, according as the burnt air is less or more
phlogisticated; and there can be little doubt but that the same rule
obtains with any other kind of dephlogisticated air.

In order to see whether the acid, formed by the explosion of
dephlogisticated air obtained by means of the vitriolic acid, would
also be of the nitrous kind, I procured some air from turbith mineral,
and exploded it with inflammable air, the proportion being such that
the burnt air was not much phlogisticated. The condensed liquor
manifested an acidity, which appeared, by saturation with a solution
of salt of tartar, to be of the nitrous kind; and it was found, by the
addition of some _terra ponderosa salita_, to contain little or no
vitriolic acid.

When inflammable air was exploded with common air, in such a proportion
that the standard of the burnt air was about 4-10, the condensed
liquor was not in the least acid. There is no difference, however, in
this respect between common air, and dephlogisticated air mixed with
phlogisticated in such a proportion as to reduce it to the standard of
common air; for some dephlogisticated air from red precipitate, being
reduced to this standard by the addition of perfectly phlogisticated
air, and then exploded with the same proportion of inflammable air as
the common air was in the foregoing experiment, the condensed liquor
was not in the least acid.

From the foregoing experiments it appears, that when a mixture of
inflammable and dephlogisticated air is exploded in such proportion
that the burnt air is not much phlogisticated, the condensed liquor
contains a little acid, which is always of the nitrous kind,
whatever substance the dephlogisticated air is procured from; but
if the proportion be such that the burnt air is almost entirely
phlogisticated, the condensed liquor is not at all acid, but seems
pure water, without any addition whatever; and as, when they are mixed
in that proportion, very little air remains after the explosion,
almost the whole being condensed, it follows that almost the whole
of the inflammable and dephlogisticated air is converted into pure
water. It is not easy, indeed, to determine from these experiments
what proportion the burnt air, remaining after the explosions, bore to
the dephlogisticated air employed, as neither the small nor the large
globe could be perfectly exhausted of air, and there was no saying
with exactness what quantity was left in them; but in most of them,
after allowing for this uncertainty, the true quantity of burnt air
seemed not more than 1-17 of the dephlogisticated air employed, or
1-50 of the mixture. It seems, however, unnecessary to determine this
point exactly, as the quantity is so small, that there can be little
doubt but that it proceeds only from the impurities mixed with the
dephlogisticated and inflammable air, and consequently that, if those
airs could be obtained perfectly pure, the whole would be condensed.

With respect to common air, and dephlogisticated air reduced by the
addition of phlogisticated air to the standard of common air, the
case is different; as the liquor condensed in exploding them with
inflammable air, I believe I may say in any proportion, is not at all
acid; perhaps because if they are mixed in such a proportion as that
the burnt air is not much phlogisticated, the explosion is too weak,
and not accompanied with sufficient heat.

All the foregoing experiments, on the explosion of inflammable air
with common and dephlogisticated airs, except those which relate to
the cause of the acid found in the water, were made in the summer
of the year 1781, and were mentioned by me to Dr. Priestley, who
in consequence of it made some experiments of the same kind, as he
relates in a paper printed in the preceding volume of the Transactions.
During the last summer also, a friend of mine gave some account of
them to M. Lavoisier, as well as of the conclusion drawn from them
that dephlogisticated air is only water deprived of phlogiston; but
at that time so far was M. Lavoisier from thinking any such opinion
warranted, that, till he was prevailed upon to repeat the experiment
himself, he found some difficulty in believing that nearly the whole
of the two airs could be converted into water. It is remarkable, that
neither of these gentlemen found any acid in the water produced by the
combustion; which might proceed from the latter having burnt two airs
in a different manner from what I did; and from the former having used
a different kind of inflammable air, namely, that from charcoal, and
perhaps having used a greater proportion of it.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 16: From _Experiments with Airs--Transactions of Royal
Society of London_ (1784).]




                                  XV

                         SIR WILLIAM HERSCHEL

                               1738-1822


 _Sir William Herschel was born in Hanover, Germany, November 15,
 1738, the son of a bandmaster. At an early age he was compelled to
 earn his own living by playing in the band of the Hanoverian Guards.
 In 1766, after some years of financial straits, he found work as
 an organist at Bath. Studying languages and mathematics without
 assistance from tutors, he became interested in “the music of the
 spheres” which developed into a scientific attitude in astronomy. He
 managed, in spite of his poverty, to construct specula for a telescope
 and in 1781, with one of his own instruments, he discovered the
 planet Uranus, one of the most romantic discoveries in the history of
 science. Among his other discoveries were two of the satellites of
 Uranus, two more of Saturn, and the fact that the moon was without
 atmosphere; he also described many of the binary stars, discovered
 many nebulous stars (which prepared the way for the nebular theory of
 the universe), and made the inference from the movements of the stars
 that the whole solar system was rushing towards the constellation
 of Hercules. After his death, August 25, 1822, his son, Sir John
 Herschel, continued his work in astronomy._


                                   I

                      THE DISCOVERY OF URANUS[17]

                          ACCOUNT OF A COMET

On Tuesday, the 13th of March, 1781, between 10 and 11 in the evening,
while examining the small stars in the neighborhood of H Geminorum, I
perceived one that appeared visibly larger than the rest: being struck
with its uncommon magnitude, I compared it to H Geminorum and the
small star in the quartile between Auriga and Gemini, and finding it
so much larger than either of them, suspected it to be a comet. I was
then engaged in a series of observations on the parallax of the fixed
stars, which I hope soon to have the honour of laying before the R.S.,
and those observations requiring very high powers, I had ready at hand
several magnifiers of 227, 460, 932, 1536, 2010, &c., all of which I
have successfully used on that occasion. The power I had on when I
first saw the comet was 227. From experience I knew that the diameters
of the fixed stars are not proportionally magnified with higher powers,
as the planets are; I therefore now put on the powers of 460 and 932,
and found the diameter of the comet increased in proportion to the
power, as it ought to be, on the supposition of its not being a fixed
star, while the diameters of the stars to which I compared it, were not
increased in the same ratio. Also, that the comet being magnified much
beyond what its light would admit of, appeared hazy and ill-defined
with these great powers, while the stars preserved that lustre and
distinctness which from many thousand observations I knew they would
retain. The sequel has shown that my surmises were well founded, this
proving to be the comet we have lately observed.


                                  II

                     ON THE NAME OF THE NEW PLANET

By the observations of the most eminent astronomers in Europe it
appears that the new star, which I had the honour of pointing out
to them in March, 1781, is a primary planet of our solar system. A
body so nearly related to us by its similar condition and situation,
in the unbounded expanse of the starry heavens, must often be the
subject of conversation, not only of astronomers, but of every lover
of science in general. This consideration, then, makes it necessary
to give it a name, by which it may be distinguished from the rest of
the planets and fixed stars. In the fabulous ages of ancient times
the appellations of Mercury, Venus, Mars, Jupiter, and Saturn, were
given to the planets, as being the names of their principal heroes
and divinities. In the present more philosophical era, it would
hardly be allowable to have recourse to the same method, and call
on Juno, Apollo, Pallas or Minerva, for a name to our new heavenly
body. The first consideration in any particular event, or remarkable
incident, seems to be its chronology; if in any future age it should be
asked, when this last-found planet was discovered it would be a very
satisfactory answer to say, “In the reign of King George the Third.” As
a philosopher, then, the name of Georgium Sidus presents itself to me,
as an appellation which will conveniently convey the information of the
time and country where and when it was brought to view.


                                  III

                 ON NEBULOUS STARS, PROPERLY SO CALLED

In one of his late examinations of a space in the heavens, which
he had not reviewed before, Dr. H. discovered a star of about the
eighth magnitude, surrounded with a faintly luminous atmosphere, of a
considerable extent. The phenomenon was so striking that he could not
help reflecting on the circumstance that attended it, which appeared to
be of a very instructive nature, and such as might lead to inferences
which will throw a considerable light on some points relating to the
construction of the heavens.

Cloudy or nebulous stars have been mentioned by several astronomers;
but this name ought not to be applied to the objects which they have
pointed out as such; for, on examination, they proved to be either
mere clusters of stars, plainly to be distinguished with his large
instruments, or such nebulous appearances as might be reasonably
supposed to be occasioned by a multitude of stars at a vast distance.
The milky way itself consists entirely of stars, and by imperceptible
degrees he was led on from most evident congeries of stars to other
groups in which the lucid points were smaller, but still very plainly
to be seen; and from them to such wherein they could but barely be
suspected, till he arrived at last to spots in which no trace of a star
was to be discerned. But then the gradations to these later were by
such well-connected steps as left no room for doubt but that all these
phenomena were equally occasioned by stars, variously dispersed in the
immense expanse of the universe.

When Dr. H. pursued these researches, he was in the situation of a
natural philosopher who follows the various species of animals and
insects from the height of their perfection down to the lowest ebb of
life; when, arriving at the vegetable kingdom, he can scarcely point
out to us the precise boundary where the animal ceases and the plant
begins; and may even go so far as to suspect them not to be essentially
different. But recollecting himself, he compares, for instance, one
of the human species to a tree, and all doubt of the subject vanishes
before him. In the same manner we pass through gentle steps from a
coarse cluster of stars, such as the Pleiades, the Præserpe, the milky
way, the cluster in the Crab, the nebula in Hercules, that near the
preceding hip of Bootis, the 17th, 38th, 41st of the 7th class of his
catalogues, the 10th, 20th, 35th of the 6th class, the 33d, 48th, 213th
of the 1st, the 12th, 150th, 756th of the 2d, and the 18th, 140th,
725th of the 3d, without any hesitation, till we find ourselves brought
to an object such as the nebula in Orion, where we are still inclined
to remain in the once adopted idea, of stars exceedingly remote,
and inconceivably crowded, as being the occasion of that remarkable
appearance. It seems, therefore, to require a more dissimilar object
to set us right again. A glance like that of the naturalist, who casts
his eye from the perfect animal to the perfect vegetable, is wanting to
remove the veil from the mind of the astronomer. The object mentioned
above is the phenomenon that was wanting for this purpose. View, for
instance, the 19th cluster of the 6th class, and afterwards cast your
eye on this cloudy star, and the result will be no less decisive than
that of the naturalist alluded to. Our judgment will be, that the
nebulosity about the star is not of a starry nature.

But that we may not be too precipitate in these new decisions, let us
enter more at large into the various grounds which induced us formerly
to surmise, that every visible object, in the extended and distant
heavens, was of the starry kind, and collate them with those which now
offer themselves for the contrary opinion. It has been observed, on a
former occasion, that all the smaller parts of other great systems,
such as the planets, their rings and satellites, the comets, and such
other bodies of the like nature as may belong to them, can never be
perceived by us, on account of the faintness of light reflected from
small opaque objects: in the present remarks, therefore, all these are
to be entirely set aside.

A well connected series of objects, such as mentioned above, has led
us to infer that all nebulæ consist of stars. This being admitted, we
were authorized to extend our analogical way of reasoning a little
further. Many of the nebulæ had no other appearance than that whitish
cloudiness, on the blue ground on which they seemed to be projected;
and why the same cause should not be assigned to explain the most
extensive nebulosities, as well as those that amounted only to a
few minutes of a degree in size, did not appear. It could not be
inconsistent to call up a telescopic milky way, at an immense distance,
to account for such a phenomenon; and if any part of the nebulosity
seemed detached from the rest, or contained a visible star or two,
the probability of seeing a few near stars, apparently scattered over
the far distant regions of myriads of sidereal collections, rendered
nebulous by their distance, would also clear up these singularities.

In order to be more easily understood in his remarks on the comparative
disposition of the heavenly bodies, Dr. H. mentions some of the
particulars which introduced the ideas of connection and disjunction:
for these, being properly founded on an examination of objects that
may be reviewed at any time, will be of considerable importance to the
validity of what we may advance with regard to the lately discovered
nebulous stars. On June 27, 1786, he saw a beautiful cluster of very
small stars of various sizes, about 15' in diameter, and very rich
of stars. On viewing this object, it is impossible to withhold our
assent to the idea which occurs, that these stars are connected so far
with one another as to be gathered together, within a certain space,
of little extent when compared to the vast expanse of the heavens.
As this phenomenon has been repeatedly seen in a thousand cases, Dr.
H. thinks he may justly lay great stress on the idea of such stars
being connected. On September 9, 1779, he discovered a very small star
near _ε_ Bootis. The question here occurring, whether it had any
connection with _ε_ or not, was determined in the negative; for,
considering the number of stars scattered in a variety of places, it is
very far from being uncommon, that a star at a great distance should
happen to be nearly in a line drawn from the sun through _ε_, and
thus constitute the observed double star. September 7, 1782, when Dr.
H. first saw the planetary nebula near υ Aquarii, he pronounced it to
be a system whose parts were connected together. Without entering
into any kind of calculation, it is evident that a certain degree of
light within a very small space, joined to the particular shape this
object presents to us, which is nearly round, and even in its deviation
consistent with regularity, being a little elliptical, ought naturally
to give us the idea of a conjunction in the things that produce it.
And a considerable addition to this argument may be derived from a
repetition of the same phenomenon, in nine or ten more of a similar
construction.

When Dr. H. examined the cluster of stars, following the head of the
Great Dog, he found on March 19, 1786, that there was within this
cluster a round, resolvable nebula, of about 2' in diameter, and nearly
an equal degree of light throughout. Here, considering that the cluster
was free from nebulosity in other parts, and that many such clusters,
as well as such nebulæ, exist in divers parts of the heavens, it seemed
very probable that the nebula was unconnected with the cluster; and
that a similar reason would as easily account for this appearance as
it had resolved the phenomenon of the double star near e Bootis; that
is, a casual situation of our sun and the two other objects nearly in
a line. And though it may be rather more remarkable, that this should
happen with two compound systems, which are not by far so numerous
as single stars, we have, to make up for this singularity, a much
larger space in which it may take place, the cluster being of a very
considerable extent.

On February 15, 1786, Dr. H. discovered that one of his planetary
nebulæ had a spot in the centre, which was more luminous than the rest,
and with long attention, a very bright, round, well-defined centre
became visible. He remained not a single moment in doubt, but that
the bright centre was connected with the rest of the apparent disc.
October 6, 1785, he found a very bright, round nebula, of about 1-1/2'
in diameter. It has a large, bright nucleus in the middle, which is
undoubtedly connected with the luminous parts about it. And though
we must confess, that if this phenomenon, and many more of the same
nature, recorded in the catalogues of nebulæ, consist of clustering
stars, we find ourselves involved in some difficulty to account for the
extraordinary condensation of them about the centre; yet the idea of
a connection between the outward parts and these very condensed ones
within, is by no means lessened on that account.

There is a telescopic milky way, which Dr. H. has traced out in the
heavens in many sweeps made from the year 1783 to 1789. It takes up
a space of more than 60 square degrees of the heavens, and there are
thousands of stars scattered over it: among others, four that form a
trapezium, and are situated in the well known nebula of Orion, which
is included in the above extent. All these stars, as well as the four
mentioned, he takes to be entirely unconnected with the nebulosity
which involves them in appearance. Among them is also _δ_ Orionis,
a cloudy star, improperly so called by former astronomers; but it does
not seem to be connected with the milkiness any more than the rest.

Dr. H. now comes to some other phenomena, that, from their singularity,
merit undoubtedly a very full discussion. Among the reasons which
induced us to embrace the opinion that all very faint milky nebulosity
ought to be ascribed to an assemblage of stars is, that we could
not easily assign any other cause of sufficient importance for such
luminous appearances, to reach us at the immense distance we must
suppose ourselves to be from them. But if an argument of considerable
force should now be brought forward, to show the existence of luminous
matter, in a state of modification very different from the construction
of a sun or star, all objections, drawn from our incapacity of
accounting for new phenomena on old principles, he thinks, will lose
their validity.

Hitherto Dr. H. has been showing, by various instances in objects whose
places are given, in what manner we may form ideas of connection, and
its contrary, by an attentive inspection of them only; he now relates
a series of observations, with remarks on them as they are delivered,
from which he afterwards draws a few simple conclusions, that seem to
be of considerable importance.

October 16, 1784. A star of about the ninth magnitude, surrounded by a
milky nebulosity, or chevelure, of about 3' in diameter. The nebulosity
is very faint, and a little extended or elliptical, the extent being
not far from the meridian, or a little from north preceding to south
following. The chevelure involves a small star, which is about 1-1/2'
north of the cloudy star; other stars of equal magnitude are perfectly
free from this appearance. (R.A. 5h 57m 4s. P.D. 96° 22'). His present
judgment concerning this remarkable object is, that the nebulosity
belongs to the star which is situated in its centre. The small one, on
the contrary, which is mentioned as involved, being one of many that
are profusely scattered over this rich neighbourhood, he supposes to
be quite unconnected with this phenomenon. A circle of 3' in diameter
is sufficiently large to admit another small star, without any bias to
the judgment he formed concerning the one in question. It might appear
singular, that such an object should not have immediately suggested
all the remarks contained in this paper; but about things that appear
new we ought not to form opinions too hastily, and his observations
on the construction of the heavens were then but entered on. In this
case, therefore, it was the safest way to lay down a rule not to reason
on the phenomena that might offer themselves, till he should be in
possession of a sufficient stock of materials to guide his researches.

October 16, 1784. A small star of about the 11th or 12th magnitude,
very faintly affected with milky nebulosity; other stars of the same
magnitude were perfectly free from this appearance. Another observation
mentions five or six small stars within the space of 3 or 4', all very
faintly affected in the same manner, and the nebulosity suspected to
be a little stronger about each star. But a third observation rather
opposes this increase of the faintly luminous appearance. (R. A. 6h
Om 33s. P. D. 96° 13'). Here the connection between the stars and the
nebulosity is not so evident as to amount to conviction; for which
reason we shall pass on to the next.

       *       *       *       *       *

November 25, 1788. A star of about the 9th magnitude, surrounded with
very faint milky nebulosity; other stars of the same size are perfectly
free from that appearance. Less than 1' in diameter. The star is either
not round or double (a).

March 23, 1789. A bright, considerably well-defined nucleus, with a
very faint, small, round chevelure (b). The connection admits of no
doubt; but the object is not perhaps of the same nature with those
called cloudy stars.

April 14, 1789. A considerable, bright, round nebula; having a large
place in the middle of nearly an equal brightness; but less bright
towards the margin (c). This seems rather to approach the planetary
sort.

March 5, 1790. A pretty considerable star of the 9th or 10th
magnitude, visibly affected with a very faint nebulosity of little
extent, all around. A power of 300 showed the nebulosity of greater
extent (d). The connection is not to be doubted.

March 19, 1790. A very bright nucleus, with a small, very faint
chevelure, exactly round. In a low situation, where the chevelure
could hardly be seen, this object would put on the appearance of an
ill-defined, planetary nebula, of 6, 8 or 10" diameter (e).

November 13, 1790. A most singular phenomenon! A star of about the 8th
magnitude, with a faint luminous atmosphere, of a circular form, and
of about 3' in diameter. The star is perfectly in the centre, and the
atmosphere is so diluted, faint, and equal throughout, that there can
be no surmise of its consisting of stars; nor can there be a doubt of
the evident connection between the atmosphere and the star. Another
star not much less in brightness, and in the same field with the above,
was perfectly free from any such appearance. This last object is so
decisive in every particular, Dr. H. says, that we need not hesitate
to admit it as a pattern, from which we are authorised to draw the
following important consequences:

Supposing the connection between the star and its surrounding
nebulosity to be allowed, we argue, that one of the two following cases
must necessarily be admitted: In the first place, if the nebulosity
consist of stars that are very remote, which appear nebulous on account
of the small angles their mutual distances subtend at the eye, by which
they will not only, as it were, run into each other, but also appear
extremely faint and diluted; then, what must be the enormous size of
the central point, which outshines all the rest in so superlative a
degree as to admit of no comparison! In the next place, if the star be
larger than common, how very small and compressed must be those other
luminous points that are the occasion of the nebulosity which surrounds
the central one! As, by the former supposition, the luminous central
point must far exceed the standard of what we call a star, so, in the
latter, the shining matter about the centre will be much too small to
come under the same denomination; we therefore either have a central
body which is not a star, or have a star which is involved in a shining
fluid, of a nature totally unknown to us. Dr. H. can adopt no other
sentiment than the latter, since the probability is certainly not for
the existence of so enormous a body as would be required to shine like
a star of the eighth magnitude, at a distance sufficiently great to
cause a vast system of stars to put on the appearance of a very diluted
milky nebulosity.

But what a field of novelty is here opened to our conceptions! A
shining fluid, of a brightness sufficient to reach us from the remote
regions of a star of the 8th, 9th, 10th, or 12th magnitude, and of an
extent so considerable as to take up 3, 4, 5, or 6 minutes in diameter!
Can we compare it to the coruscation of the electric fluid in the
aurora borealis? Or to the more magnificent cone of the zodiacal light
as we see it in the spring or autumn? The latter, notwithstanding Dr.
H. has observed it to reach at least 90° from the sun, is yet of so
little extent and brightness, as probably not to be perceived even by
the inhabitants of Saturn or the Georgian planet, and must be utterly
invisible at the remoteness of the nearest fixed star.

More extensive views may be derived from this proof of the existence
of a shining matter. Perhaps it has been too hastily surmised that
all milky nebulosity, of which there is so much in the heavens, is
owing to starlight only. These nebulous stars may serve as a clue to
unravel other mysterious phenomena. If the shining fluid that surrounds
them is not so essentially connected with these nebulous stars, but
that it can also exist without them, which seems to be sufficiently
probable, and will be examined hereafter, we may with great facility
explain that very extensive, telescopic nebulosity, which, as before
mentioned, is expanded over more than 60° of the heavens, about the
constellation of Orion; a luminous matter accounting much better for it
than clustering stars at a distance. In this case we may also pretty
nearly guess at its situation, which must commence somewhere about the
range of the stars of the 7th magnitude, or a little farther from us,
and extend unequally in some places perhaps to the regions of those
of the 9th, 10th, 11th, and 12th. The foundation for this surmise is,
that not unlikely some of the stars that happen to be situated in a
more condensed part of it, or that perhaps by their own attraction
draw together some quantity of this fluid greater than what they are
entitled to by their situation in it, will, of course, assume the
appearance of cloudy stars; and many of those named are either in this
stratum of luminous matter, or very near it.

It has been said above, that in nebulous stars the existence of the
shining fluid does not seem to be so essentially connected with the
central points that it might not also exist without them. For this
opinion we may assign several reasons. One of them is the greater
resemblance of the chevelure of these stars and the diffused extensive
nebulosity mentioned before, which renders it highly probable that
they are of the same nature. Now, if this be admitted, the separate
existence of the luminous matter, or its independence of a central
star, is fully proved. We may also judge, very confidently, that the
light of this shining fluid is no kind of reflection from the star in
the centre; for, as we have already observed, reflected light could
never reach us at the great distance we are from such objects. Besides,
how impenetrable would be an atmosphere of a sufficient density to
reflect so great a quantity of light! And yet we observe, that the
outward parts of the chevelure are nearly as bright as those that are
close to the star; so that this supposed atmosphere ought to give no
obstruction to the passage of the central rays. If therefore this
matter is self-luminous, it seems more fit to produce a star by its
condensation than to depend on the star for its existence.

Many other diffused nebulosities, besides that about the constellation
of Orion, have been observed or suspected; but some of them are
probably very distant, and run far out into space. For instance, about
5m in time preceding _x_ Cygni, Dr. H. suspects as much of it
as covers near 4 square degrees; and much about the same quantity
44m preceding the 125 Tauri. A space of almost 8 square degrees, 6m
preceding _α_ Trianguli, seems to be tinged with milky nebulosity.
Three minutes preceding the 46 Eridani, strong, milky nebulosity is
expanded over more than 2 square degrees. Fifty-four minutes preceding
the 13th _Canum venaticorum_, and again 48m preceding the same
star, the field of view affected with whitish nebulosity throughout
the whole breadth of the sweep, which was 2° 39'. Four minutes
following the 57 Cygni a considerable space is filled with faint,
milky nebulosity, which is pretty bright in some places, and contains
the 37th nebula of the 5th class, in the brightest part of it. In the
neighbourhood of the 44th Piscium, very faint nebulosity appears to
be diffused over more than 9 square degrees of the heavens. Now all
these phenomena, as we have already seen, will admit of a much easier
explanation by a luminous fluid than by stars at an immense distance.

The nature of planetary nebulæ, which has hitherto been involved in
much darkness, may now be explained with some degree of satisfaction,
since the uniform and very considerable brightness of their apparent
disc accords remarkably well with a much condensed, luminous fluid;
whereas, to suppose them to consist of clustering stars, will not so
completely account for the milkiness or soft tint of their light, to
produce which it would be required that the condensation of the stars
should be carried to an almost inconceivable degree of accumulation.
The surmise of the regeneration of stars, by means of planetary nebulæ,
expressed in a former paper, will become more probable, as all the
luminous matter contained in one of them, when gathered together into a
body of the size of a star, would have nearly such a quantity of light
as we find the planetary nebulæ to give. To prove this experimentally,
we may view them with a telescope that does not magnify sufficiently
to show their extent, by which means we shall gather all their light
together into a point, when they will be found to assume the appearance
of small stars; that is, of stars at the distance of those which we
call of the 8th, 9th, or 10th magnitude. Indeed this idea is greatly
supported by the discovery of a well-defined, lucid point, resembling
a star, in the centre of one of them; for the argument which has been
used, in the case of nebulous stars, to show the probability of the
existence of luminous matter, which rested on the disparity between a
bright point and its surrounding shining fluid, may here be alleged
with equal justice. If the point be a generating star, the further
accumulation of the already much condensed, luminous matter may
complete it in time.

How far the light that is perpetually emitted from millions of suns may
be concerned in this shining fluid, it might be presumptuous to attempt
to determine; but, notwithstanding the inconceivable subtilty of the
particles of light, when the number of the emitting bodies is almost
infinitely great, and the time of the continual emission indefinitely
long, the quantity of emitted particles may well become adequate to the
constitution of a shining fluid, or luminous matter, provided a cause
can be found that may retain them from flying off, or reunite them. But
such a cause cannot be difficult to guess at, when we know that light
is so easily reflected, refracted, inflected and deflected; and that,
in the immense range of its course, it must pass through innumerable
systems, where it cannot but frequently meet with many obstacles to
its rectilinear progression not to mention the great counteraction
of the united attractive force of whole sidereal systems, which must
be continually exerting their power on the particles while they are
endeavouring to fly off. However, we shall lay no stress on a surmise
of this kind, as the means of verifying it are wanting; nor is it of
any immediate consequence to us to know the origin of the luminous
matter. Let it suffice, that its existence is rendered evident, by
means of nebulous stars.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 17: This excerpt and the one following are from the report
by Herschel in the _Transactions of the Royal Society of London_;
the third is an abstract from the same report, the conclusion, however,
being by Herschel.]




                                  XVI

                         KARL WILHELM SCHEELE

                               1742-1786


 _Karl Wilhelm Scheele, who discovered independently of the English
 chemists the double constitution of air, was born in Stralsund,
 Pomerania, December 19, 1742. At an early age he manifested interest
 in pharmacy, and during his career as an apothecary engaged in various
 experiments in chemistry. He published his “Treatise on Air and Fire”
 in 1777. He died at Köping, May 21, 1786._


                      THE CONSTITUENTS OF AIR[18]

1. It is the object and chief business of chemistry to separate
skilfully substances into their constituents, to discover their
properties, and to compound them in different ways. How difficult it
is, however, to carry out such operations with the greatest accuracy,
can only be unknown to one who either has never undertaken this
occupation, or at least has not done so with sufficient attention.

2. Hitherto chemical investigators are not agreed as to how many
elements or fundamental materials compose all substances. In fact this
is one of the most difficult problems; some indeed hold that there
remains no further hope of searching out the elements of substances.
Poor comfort for those who feel their greatest pleasure in the
investigation of natural things! Far is he mistaken, who endeavours
to confine chemistry, this noble science, within such narrow bounds!
Others believe that earth and phlogiston are the things from which all
material nature has derived its origin. The majority seem completely
attached to the peripatetic elements.

3. I must admit that I have bestowed no little trouble upon this
matter in order to obtain a clear conception of it. One may reasonably
be amazed at the ideas and conjectures which authors have recorded
on the subject, especially when they give a decision respecting the
phenomenon of fire; and this very matter was of the greatest importance
to me. I perceived the necessity of a knowledge of fire, because
without this it is not possible to make any experiment; and without
fire and heat it is not possible to make use of the action of any
solvent. I began accordingly to put aside all explanations of fire; I
undertook a multitude of experiments in order to fathom this beautiful
phenomenon as fully as possible. I soon found, however, that one could
not form any true judgment regarding the phenomena which fire presents,
without a knowledge of the air. I saw, after carrying out a series of
experiments, that air really enters into the mixture of fire, and with
it forms a constituent of flame and of sparks. I learned accordingly
that a treatise like this, on fire, could not be drawn up with proper
completeness without taking the air also into consideration.

4. Air is that fluid invisible substance which we continually breathe,
which surrounds the whole surface of the earth, is very elastic, and
possesses weight. It is always filled with an astonishing quantity
of all kinds of exhalations, which are so finely subdivided in it
that they are scarcely visible even in the sun’s rays. Water vapours
always have the preponderance amongst these foreign particles. The
air, however, is also mixed with another elastic substance resembling
air, which differs from it in numerous properties, and is, with good
reason, called aerial acid by Professor Bergman. It owes its presence
to organised bodies, destroyed by putrefaction or combustion.

5. Nothing has given philosophers more trouble for some years than just
this delicate acid or so-called fixed air. Indeed it is not surprising
that the conclusions which one draws from the properties of this
elastic acid are not favourable to all who are prejudiced by previously
conceived opinions. These defenders of the Paracelsian doctrine believe
that the air is in itself unalterable; and, with Hales, that it really
unites with substances thereby losing its elasticity; but that it
regains its original nature as soon as it is driven out of these by
fire or fermentation. But since they see that the air so produced is
endowed with properties quite different from common air, they conclude,
without experimental proofs, that this air has united with foreign
materials, and that it must be purified from these admixed foreign
particles by agitation and filtration with various liquids. I believe
that there would be no hesitation in accepting this opinion, if one
could only demonstrate clearly by experiments that a given quantity
of air is capable of being completely converted into fixed or other
kind of air by the admixture of foreign materials; but since this has
not been done, I hope I do not err if I assume as many kinds of air as
experiment reveals to me. For when I have collected an elastic fluid,
and observe concerning it that its expansive power is increased by heat
and diminished by cold, while it still uniformly retains its elastic
fluidity, but also discover in it properties and behavior different
from those of common air, then I consider myself justified in believing
that this is a peculiar kind of air. I say that air thus collected must
retain its elasticity even in the greatest cold, because otherwise an
innumerable multitude of varieties of air would have to be assumed,
since it is very probable that all substances can be converted by
excessive heat into a vapour resembling air.

6. Substances which are subjected to putrefaction or to destruction by
means of fire diminish, and at the same time consume, a part of the
air; sometimes it happens that they perceptibly increase the bulk of
the air, and sometimes finally that they neither increase nor diminish
a given quantity of air--phenomena which are certainly remarkable.
Conjectures can here determine nothing with certainty, at least they
can only bring small satisfaction to a chemical philosopher, who must
have his proofs in his hands. Who does not see the necessity of making
experiments in this case, in order to obtain light concerning this
secret of nature?

7. General properties of ordinary air.

(1.) Fire must burn for a certain time in a given quantity of air.
(2.) If, so far as can be seen, this fire does not produce during
combustion any fluid resembling air, then, after the fire has gone
out of itself, the quantity of air must be diminished between a third
and a fourth part. (3.) It must not unite with common water. (4.) All
kinds of animals must live for a certain time in a confined quantity of
air. (5.) Seeds, as for example peas, in a given quantity of similarly
confined air, must strike roots and attain a certain height with the
aid of some water and of a moderate heat.

Consequently, when I have a fluid resembling air in its external
appearance, and find that it has not the properties mentioned, even
when only one of them is wanting, I feel convinced that it is not
ordinary air.

8. Air must be composed of elastic fluids of two kinds.

First Experiment.--I dissolved one ounce of alkaline liver of sulphur
in eight ounces of water; I poured four ounces of this solution into an
empty bottle capable of holding 24 ounces of water, and closed it most
securely with a cork; I then inverted the bottle and placed the neck
in a small vessel with water; in this position I allowed it to stand
for fourteen days. During this time the solution had lost a part of its
red colour and had also deposited some sulphur: afterwards I took the
bottle and held it in the same position in a larger vessel with water,
so that the mouth was under and the bottom above the water-level, and
withdrew the cork under the water; immediately water rose with violence
into the bottle. I closed the bottle again, removed it from the water,
and weighed the fluid which it contained. There were 10 ounces. After
substracting from this the four ounces of solution of sulphur there
remain six ounces, consequently it is apparent from this experiment
that of 20 parts of air six parts have been lost in 14 days.

9. Second Experiment.--(a) I repeated the preceding experiment with the
same quantity of liver of sulphur, but with this difference that I only
allowed the bottle to stand a week tightly closed. I then found that of
20 parts of air only 4 had been lost. (b) On another occasion I allowed
the very same bottle to stand four months; the solution still possessed
a somewhat dark yellow colour. But no more air had been lost than in
the first experiment, that is to say six parts.

10. Third Experiment.--I mixed two ounces of caustic ley, which
was prepared from alkali of tartar and unslaked lime and did not
precipitate lime-water, with half an ounce of the preceding solution of
sulphur, which likewise did not precipitate lime-water. This mixture
had a yellow colour. I poured it into the same bottle, and after this
had stood fourteen days, well closed, I found the mixture entirely
without colour and also without precipitate. I was enabled to conclude
that the air in this bottle had likewise diminished, from the fact that
air rushed into the bottle with a hissing sound after I had made a
small hole in the cork.

11. Fourth Experiment.--(a) I took four ounces of a solution of
sulphur in lime-water; I poured this solution into a bottle and closed
it tightly. After 14 days the yellow colour had disappeared, and of 20
parts of air 4 parts had been lost. The solution contained no sulphur,
but had allowed a precipitate to fall which was chiefly gypsum. (b.)
Volatile liver of sulphur likewise diminishes the bulk of air. (c.)
Sulphur, however, and volatile spirit of sulphur, undergo no alteration
in it.

12. Fifth Experiment.--I hung up over burning sulphur, linen rags which
were dipped in a solution of alkali of tartar. After the alkali was
saturated with the volatile acid, I placed the rags in a flask, and
closed the mouth most carefully with a wet bladder. After three weeks
had elapsed I found the bladder strongly pressed down; I inverted
the flask, held its mouth in water and made a hole in the bladder;
thereupon water rose with violence into the flask and filled the fourth
part.

13. Sixth Experiment.--I collected in the bladder the nitrous acid
which arises on the dissolution of the metals in nitrous acid, and
after I had tied the bladder tightly I laid it in a flask and secured
the mouth very carefully with a wet bladder. The nitrous air gradually
lost its elasticity, the bladder collapsed, and became yellow as if
corroded by _aqua fortis_. After 14 days I made a hole in the
bladder tied over the flask, having previously held it, inverted, under
water; the water rose rapidly into the flask, and it remained only
two-thirds empty.

14. Seventh Experiment.--(a.) I immersed the mouth of a flask in a
vessel with oil of turpentine. The oil rose in the flask a few lines
every day. After the lapse of 14 days the fourth part of the flask
was filled with it. I allowed it to stand for three weeks longer, but
the oil did not rise higher. All those oils which dry in the air, and
become converted into resinous substances, possess this property. Oil
of turpentine, however, and linseed oil rise up sooner if the flask is
previously rinsed out with a concentrated sharp ley. (b.) I poured two
ounces of colourless and transparent animal oil of Dippel into a bottle
and closed it very tightly; after the expiration of two months the oil
was thick and black. I then held the bottle, inverted, under water and
drew out the cork; the bottle immediately became one-fourth filled with
water.

15. Eighth Experiment.--(a.) I dissolved two ounces of vitriol of iron
in thirty-two ounces of water, and precipitated this solution with
a caustic ley. After the precipitate had settled, I poured away the
clear fluid and put the dark green precipitate of iron so obtained,
together with the remaining water, into the before-mentioned bottle (§
8), and closed it tightly. After 14 days (during which time I shook the
bottle frequently) this green calx of iron had acquired the colour of
crocus of iron, and of 40 parts of air 12 had been lost. (b.) When iron
filings are moistened with some water and preserved for a few weeks
in a well closed bottle, a portion of the air is likewise lost. (c.)
The solution of iron in vinegar has the same effect upon air. In this
case the vinegar permits the dissolved iron to fall out in the form of
a yellow crocus, and becomes completely deprived of this metal. (d.)
The solution of copper prepared in closed vessels with spirit of salt
likewise diminishes air. In none of the foregoing kinds of air can
either a candle burn or the smallest spark glow.

16. It is seen from these experiments that phlogiston, the simple
inflammable principle, is present in each of them. It is known that the
air strongly attracts to itself the inflammable part of substances and
deprives them of it: not only this may be seen from the experiments
cited, but it is at the same time evident that on the transference of
the inflammable substance to the air a considerable part of the air
is lost. But that inflammable substance alone is the cause of this
action, is plain from this, that, according to the tenth paragraph,
not the least trace of sulphur remains over, since, according to my
experiments this colourless ley contains only some vitriolated tartar.
The eleventh paragraph likewise shows this. But since sulphur alone,
and also the volatile spirit of sulphur, have no effect upon the air (§
11. c), it is clear that the decomposition of liver of sulphur takes
place according to the laws of double affinity--that is to say, that
the alkalies and lime attract the vitriolic acid, and the air attracts
the phlogiston.

It may also be seen from the above experiments, that a given quantity
of air can only unite with, and at the same time saturate, a certain
quantity of the inflammable substance: this is evident from the ninth
paragraph, letter b. But whether the phlogiston which was lost by the
substances was still present in the air left behind in the bottle,
or whether the air which was lost had united and fixed itself with
the materials such as liver of sulphur, oils, &c., are questions of
importance.

From the first view, it would necessarily follow that the inflammable
substance possessed the property of depriving the air of part of its
elasticity, and that in consequence of this it becomes more closely
compressed by the external air. In order now to help myself out of
these uncertainties, I formed the opinion that any such air must
be specifically heavier than ordinary air, both on account of its
containing phlogiston and also of its greater condensation. But how
perplexed was I when I saw that a very thin flask which was filled with
this air, and most accurately weighed, not only did not counterpoise
an equal quantity of ordinary air, but was even somewhat lighter. I
then thought that the latter view might be admissible; but in that case
it would necessarily follow also that the lost air could be separated
again from the materials employed. None of the experiments cited seemed
to me capable of showing this more clearly than that according to the
tenth paragraph, because this residuum, as already mentioned, consists
of vitriolated tartar and alkali. In order therefore to see whether the
lost air had been converted into fixed air, I tried whether the latter
shewed itself when some of the caustic ley was poured into lime-water;
but in vain--no precipitation took place. Indeed, I tried in several
ways to obtain the lost air from this alkaline mixture, but as the
results were similar to the foregoing, in order to avoid prolixity I
shall not cite these experiments. Thus much I see from the experiments
mentioned, that the air consists of two fluids, differing from each
other, the one of which does not manifest in the least the property
of attracting phlogiston, while the other, which composes between the
third and the fourth part of the whole mass of the air, is peculiarly
disposed to such attraction. But where this latter kind of air has gone
to after it has united with the inflammable substance, is a question
which must be decided by further experiments, and not by conjectures.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 18: Translated from _Treatise on Air and Fire_ (1777).]




                                 XVII

                       ANTOINE LAURENT LAVOISIER

                               1743-1794


 _Antoine Laurent Lavoisier was born in Paris, August 26, 1743.
 After an early life spent in diligent study, in 1766 he was awarded
 a prize for his essay on the best method of lighting Paris. His
 attention having been called to the English experiments on gases
 made by Priestley and Cavendish, he attacked the current phlogiston
 conception of combustion and stated that Priestley’s “dephlogisticated
 air” was the universal acidifying gas, and gave it the name of
 “oxygen.” Systematizing chemistry and renaming the elements and their
 compounds, he came to believe that chemical reactions had the certainty
 of mathematical equations. From this he derived the idea of the
 persistence of matter, regardless of changes, now established as one of
 the basic concepts of modern science. During the French Revolution a
 charge was brought against him and he was sent to the guillotine on May
 8, 1794._


                     THE NATURE OF COMBUSTION[19]

I venture to submit to the Academy to-day a new theory of combustion,
or rather, to speak with that reserve to whose law I submit myself,
an hypothesis, by the aid of which all the phenomena of combustion,
calcination, and even to some extent those accompanying the respiration
of animals are explained in a very satisfactory manner. I had already
laid the foundations of this hypothesis p. 279-280 of vol. I. of my
_Opuscules physiques et chimiques_; but I admit that trusting
little to my own knowledge, I did not then dare to put forward an
opinion which might seem singular, and which was directly opposed to
the theory of Stahl and of many celebrated men who have followed him.

Though perhaps some of the reasons which then checked me still remain
to-day, nevertheless, the facts which have multiplied since that
time, and which seem to me favorable to my views, have confirmed
me in my opinion: though not, perhaps, any stronger, I have become
more confident, and I think I have sufficient proofs, or at least
probabilities, so that even those who may not be of my opinion cannot
blame me for having written.

In general in the combustion of bodies four constant phenomena are
observable, which seem to be laws from which nature never departs.
Though these phenomena may be found implicitly stated in other memoirs,
yet I cannot dispense with recalling them here in a few words.


                           FIRST PHENOMENON

All combustion sets free matter either of fire or light.


                           SECOND PHENOMENON

Bodies can burn only in a very small number of kinds of gases (airs),
or rather there can be combustion only in one kind of air, that which
Mr. Priestley has named dephlogisticated air, and which I should call
pure air. Not only will the bodies which we call combustibles not burn
in a vacuum or in any other kind of air, they are, on the contrary,
extinguished there as promptly as if they had been plunged into water
or any other liquid.


                           THIRD PHENOMENON

In all combustion there is destruction or decomposition of the pure
air in which the combustion takes place, and the body burned increases
in weight exactly in proportion to the quantity of air destroyed or
decomposed.


                           FOURTH PHENOMENON

In all combustion the body burned changes to an acid by the addition
of the substance which has increased its weight: thus, for example,
if sulphur is burned under a receiver the product of the combustion is
vitriolic acid; if phosphorus be burned the product is phosphoric acid;
if a carboniferous substance, the product is fixed air, otherwise known
as acid of lime (carbonic acid, etc.).

(Note: I would remark in passing that the number of acids is infinitely
greater than has been supposed.)

The calcination of metals is subject to exactly the same laws, and it
is with very great reason that Mr. Macquer has treated it as a slow
combustion; thus, 1°, in all metallic combustion there is a liberating
of fire matter (_matière du feu_); 2°, veritable calcination can
take place only in pure air; 3°, there is a combination of the air with
the substance calcined, but with this difference, that in place of
forming an acid with it there results from it a particular combination
known as metallic calx.

This is not the place to point out the analogy which exists between the
respiration of animals, combustion and calcination; I shall return to
that in the sequel to this memoir.

These different phenomena of the calcination of metals and of
combustion are explained in a very happy manner by Stahl’s hypothesis;
but it is necessary with him to suppose the existence of fire matter
(_matière du feu_) or of fixed phlogiston in the metals, in
sulphur and in all bodies which he regards as combustibles; yet if the
partisans of Stahl’s doctrine are asked to prove the existence of fire
matter in combustible bodies, they fall necessarily into a vicious
circle and are obliged to reply that combustible bodies contain fire
matter because they burn, and that they burn because they contain fire
matter. It is easy to see that in the last analysis this is explaining
combustion by combustion.

The existence of fire matter, or phlogiston, in metals, in sulphur,
etc., is then really only an hypothesis, a supposition which, once
admitted, explains, it is true, some of the phenomena of calcination
and combustion; but if I show that these very phenomena may be
explained in quite as natural a way by the opposite hypothesis, that
is to say, without supposing the existence of either fire matter or
phlogiston in the substances called combustible, Stahl’s system will be
shaken to its foundations.

No doubt you will not fail to ask me first what I understand by fire
matter. I reply with Franklin, Boerhaave and some of the philosophers
of old, that the matter of fire or of light is a very subtle, very
elastic fluid, which surrounds every part of the planet we live
on, which penetrates with more or less ease the substances which
compose that, and which tends, when it is free, to come to a state of
equilibrium in all.

I will add, borrowing the chemical phraseology, that this fluid is the
solvent of a large number of substances; that it combines with them
in the same way that water does with salt, and the acids with metals,
and that the bodies thus combined and dissolved by the igneous fluid
lose in part the properties which they had before the combination and
acquire new ones which bring them nearer (make them more like) the fire
matter.

It is thus, as I have shown in a memoir deposited with the secretary
of this Academy, that every aeriform fluid, every kind of air, is a
resultant of the combination of some substance, solid or fluid, with
the matter of fire or of light; and it is to this combination that
aeriform fluids owe their elasticity, their specific volatility, their
rarity, and all the other properties which ally (_rapprochent_)
them to the igneous fluid.

Pure air, according to this, what Mr. Priestley calls dephlogisticated
air, is an igneous compound into which the matter of fire or of light
enters as solvent, and into which some other substance enters as a
base; but if, in any solution whatever, a substance is presented to
the base with which that has greater affinity, it unites with this
instantly and the solvent which it leaves is set free.

The same thing happens with the air in combustion; the substance
which burns steals away the base; then the fire matter which served
as its solvent becomes free, regains its rights and escapes with the
characteristics by which we know it; that is to say, with flame, heat
and light.

To elucidate whatever may seem obscure in this theory let us apply it
to some examples: when a metal is calcined in pure air, the base of the
air, which has less affinity for its own solvent than for the metal,
unites with the latter as it melts and converts it into metallic calx.
This combination of the base of the air with the metal is proved 1st,
by the increase in weight which the latter undergoes in calcination;
2nd, by the almost total using up of the air under the receiving bell.
But, if the base of the air was held in solution by the fire matter,
in proportion as this base combined with the metal, the fire matter
should become free and produce, in freeing itself, flame and light. You
understand that the more speedy the calcination of the metal, that is
to say, the more fixation of the air takes place in a given time, the
more fire matter will be liberated, and, consequently, the more marked
and obvious the combustion will be.


I might apply this theory successively to all combustions, but as
I shall have frequent occasion to return to this subject, I will
content myself at this time with these general illustrations. So, to
resume, the air is composed, according to my idea, of fire matter as
a dissolvent combined with a substance which serves it as a base,
and which in some way neutralizes it; whenever a substance for which
it has a greater affinity is brought into contact with this base, it
leaves its solvent; then the fire-substance regains its rights, its
properties, and appears to our eyes with heat, flame and light.

Pure air, the dephlogisticated air of Mr. Priestley, is then, according
to this opinion, the real combustible body, and perhaps the only one of
that nature, and it is seen that it is no longer necessary, in order
to explain the phenomena of combustion, to suppose that there exists
a large quantity of fire fixed in all the substances which we call
combustible, but that it is very probable, on the contrary, that very
little of it exists in metals, in sulphur, phosphorus, and in most of
the very solid, heavy and compact bodies, and, perhaps even that there
exists in these substances only free fire matter, in virtue of the
property which this matter has of putting itself in equilibrium with
all surrounding bodies.

Another striking reflection which comes to the support of the preceding
ones, is that almost all substances may exist in three different
states: under a solid form, under a liquid form, that is to say
melted, or in the state of air or vapor. These three states depend
solely on the quantity, more or less, of fire matter with which these
substances are interpenetrated and with which they are combined.
Fluidity, vaporization, elasticity, are then properties characteristic
of the presence of fire and of a great abundance of fire; solidity,
compactness, on the contrary, are evidences of its absence. By so much
then as it is demonstrated that aeriform substances and air itself
contain a large quantity of fire in combination, by so much it is
probable that solid bodies contain little of it.

For the rest, I repeat, in attacking here the doctrine of Stahl, it was
not my purpose to substitute for it a rigorously demonstrated theory,
but only an hypothesis which seemed to me more probable, more in
conformity with the laws of nature, and one which appeared to involve
less forced explanations and fewer contradictions.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 19: _On Combustion_, Vol. II, p. 225.]




                                 XVIII

                           ALESSANDRO VOLTA

                               1745-1827


 _Alessandro Volta, born at Como, Italy, February 18, 1745, became
 teacher of physics at Como in 1774, and five years later accepted a
 professorship at Pavia. Becoming interested in Galvani’s experiments
 with electricity on the muscles of a frog, he applied them in his
 attempts to confirm his own theory that the frog’s muscles were a
 sensitive electrometer. In doing this he conceived the voltaic pile,
 which produced the first constant electrical current--a discovery which
 had immense effects in later studies in electricity. He died at Como,
 March 5, 1827._


                      NEW GALVANIC INSTRUMENT[20]

ON THE ELECTRICITY EXCITED BY THE MERE CONTACT OF CONDUCTING SUBSTANCES
                          OF DIFFERENT KINDS

The chief of these results, and which comprehends nearly all the
others, is the construction of an apparatus which resembles in its
effects, viz. (such as giving shocks to the arms, &c.,) the Leyden
phial, and still better, electric batteries weakly charged; acting
continually, or whose charge, after each explosion, recharges itself
again; which in short becomes perpetual, from one infallible charge,
from one action or impulse on the electric fluid; but which besides
differs essentially from the other, by this continual action which
is proper to it, and because that instead of consisting, like the
ordinary phials and electric batteries, in one or more isolated plates,
or thin layers of those bodies deemed the only electrics, and armed
with conductors or bodies called non-electrics, this new apparatus is
formed only of a number of these last bodies, chosen even among the
best conductors, and so the farthest removed, according to the usual
opinion, from the electric principle. This astonishing apparatus is
nothing but an assemblage of a number of good conductors of a different
kind, arranged in a certain manner. Thus, 30, 40, 60, or more pieces
of copper, or better of silver, each applied to a piece of tin or
still better of zinc, and an equal number of layers of water, or of
some other liquid which may be a better conductor than simple water,
as salt water, lye, &c., or of bits of card or leather, &c., soaked
in such liquids. Of such layers interposed between each couple or
combination of two different metals, one such alternate series, and
always in the same order, of these three kinds of conductors, is all
that constitutes M. Volta’s new instrument; which imitates so well
the effects of the Leyden phial or electric batteries; not indeed
with the force and explosions of these, when highly charged; but only
equalling the effects of a battery charged to a very weak degree, of
a battery, however, having an immense capacity, but which besides
infinitely surpasses the virtue and the power of these same batteries;
as it has no need, like them, of being charged beforehand, by means
of a foreign electricity; and as it is capable of giving the usual
commotion as often as ever it is properly touched. This apparatus, as
it resembles more the natural electric organ of the torpedo, or of the
electric eel than the Leyden phial and the ordinary electric batteries,
M. Volta calls the artificial electric organ. For the construction of
this instrument, M. Volta provides some dozens of small round metal
plates of copper, or tin, or best of silver, about an inch in diameter,
like shillings or half-crowns, and an equal number of plates of tin,
or much better of zinc, of the same shape and size. These pieces he
places exactly one upon another, forming a column, pillar or pile. He
provides also as many round pieces of card, or leather, or such like
spongy matter, capable of imbibing and retaining much of the water, or
other liquid, when soaked in it. These soaked roullets or circles are
to be a little less in diameter than the small metal discs or plates,
that they may not jut out beyond them. All these discs are then placed
horizontally on a table, one over another continually alternating, in a
pile as high as will well support itself without tottering and falling
down: beginning with a plate of either of the metals, as for instance,
the silver, then upon that one of zinc, over which is to be put the
soaked card; then other three discs, over these in the same order, viz.
a silver, next a zinc, and then another moistened card, &c.

After having raised the pile to about 20 of these stages or triads of
plates, it will be already capable, not only of affecting Cavallo’s
electrometer, assisted by the condenser, so as to raise it 10 or 15°,
charging it by a simple touching, so as to cause it to give a spark,
&c., as also to strike the fingers with which we touch the top or
bottom of the column, with several small snaps, the fingers being
wetted with water. But if to the 20 sets of triplets of the plates be
added 20 or 30 more, disposed in the same order, the actions of the
extended pile will be much stronger, and be felt through the arms up to
the shoulders; and by continuing the touchings, the pains in the hands
become insupportable.

M. Volta constructs and combines his apparatus in various ways and
forms, more or less powerful, convenient or amusing. One is as follows
(Fig. 1, pl. 13,), which he calls a _couronne de tasses_. He
disposes in a row a number of cups of wood, or earth, or glass, or
any thing but metal, half filled with pure water, or salt water or
lye; these are all made to communicate in a kind of chain, by several
metallic arcs of which one arm or link, Aa, or only the extremity A,
immersed in one of the cups, is of copper, or of copper silvered,
and the other Z, immersed in the following cup, is of tin, or rather
of zinc, the other two being soldered together near the crown of
the arch. It is evident that a series of these cups, thus connected
together, either in a straight or curved line, by the two metals and
the intermediate liquid, is similar to the pillar or pile before
described, and consequently will exhibit similar effects. Thus, to
produce commotion or sensation in the hands and arms, we need only dip
one hand into one of the cups and the finger of the other hand into
another cup, sufficiently far from the former; and the action will be
so much the stronger as the two cups are farther asunder, or have the
more intermediate cups; and consequently the greatest by touching the
first and the last in the chain.

       *       *       *       *       *

M. Volta concludes with various remarks and cautions in using this
instrument; showing that it is perpetual in its virtue, renewing its
charge spontaneously, and serving most of the purposes of the ordinary
electrical machines, and even affecting and manifesting its power by
most of the human senses, viz. feeling, tasting, hearing, and seeing.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 20: From the _Transactions of the Royal Society of
London_.]




                                  XIX

                         PIERRE SIMON LAPLACE

                               1749-1827


 _Pierre Simon Laplace, born at Beaumont-en-Auge, Normandy, March
 28, 1749, became a teacher of mathematics at Beaufort before he was
 eighteen years old. He gained d’Alembert’s attention by a letter
 which he wrote to him on the principles of mathematics. After 1770
 he engaged with Lagrange in determining the permanency of the solar
 system by studying its perturbations and interactions, and finally
 suggested how these changes were periodic. His monumental work, in five
 volumes, “Mechanics of the Heavens” (1799-1825), gave a comprehensive
 description of the movements of the solar system, and his “System of
 the World” proposed the nebular theory of the origin of the universe.
 His researches were important in the development of modern astronomy
 because he substituted a dynamic for the descriptive point of view. He
 died at Arcueil, March 5, 1827._


                      THE NEBULAR HYPOTHESIS[21]

Buffon is the only individual that I know of, who, since the discovery
of the true system of the world, endeavoured to investigate the origin
of the planets and satellites. He supposed that a comet, by impinging
on the Sun, carried away a torrent of matter, which was reunited far
off, into globes of different magnitudes and at different distances
from this star. These globes, when they cool and become hardened,
are the planets and their satellites. This hypothesis satisfies the
first of the five preceding phenomena[22]; for it is evident that all
bodies thus formed should move very nearly in the plane which passes
through the centre of the Sun, and through the direction of the torrent
of matter which has produced them: but the four remaining phenomena
appear to me inexplicable on this supposition. Indeed, the absolute
motion of the molecules of a planet ought to be in the same direction
as the motion of the centre of gravity; but it by no means follows
from this, that the motion of rotation of a planet should be also in
the same direction. Thus the Earth may revolve from east to west, and
yet the absolute motion of each of its molecules may be directed from
west to east. This observation applies also to the revolution of the
satellites, of which the direction in the same hypothesis, is not
necessarily the same as that of the motion of projection of the planets.

The small eccentricity of the planetary orbits is a phenomenon,
not only difficult to explain on this hypothesis, but altogether
inconsistent with it. We know from the theory of central forces, that
if a body which moves in a re-entrant orbit about the Sun, passes
very near the body of the Sun, it will return constantly to it, at
the end of each revolution. Hence it follows that if the planets were
originally detached from the Sun, they would touch it, at each return
to this star; and their orbits, instead of being nearly circular,
would be very eccentric. Indeed it must be admitted that a torrent
of matter detached from the Sun, cannot be compared to a globe which
just skims by its surface; from the impulsions which the parts of this
torrent receive from each other, combined with their mutual attraction,
they may, by changing the direction of their motions, increase the
distances of their perihelions from the Sun. But their orbits should
be extremely eccentric, or at least all the orbits would not be q. p.
circular, except by the most extraordinary chance. Finally, no reason
can be assigned on the hypothesis of Buffon, why the orbits of more
than one hundred comets, which have been already observed, should be
all very eccentric. The hypothesis, therefore, is far from satisfying
the preceding phenomena. Let us consider whether we can assign the true
cause.

Whatever may be its nature, since it has produced or influenced the
direction of the planetary motions, it must have embraced them all
within the sphere of its action; and considering the immense distance
which intervenes between them, nothing could have effected this but
a fluid of almost indefinite extent. In order to have impressed on
them all a motion q. p. circular and in the same direction about the
Sun, this fluid must environ this star, like an atmosphere. From a
consideration of the planetary motions, we are therefore brought to
the conclusion, that in consequence of an excessive heat, the solar
atmosphere originally extended beyond the orbits of all the planets,
and that it has successively contracted itself within its present
limits.

In the primitive state in which we have supposed the Sun to be, it
resembles those substances which are termed nebulæ, which, when seen
through telescopes, appear to be composed of a nucleus, more or less
brilliant, surrounded by a nebulosity, which, by condensing on its
surface, transforms it into a star. If all the stars are conceived to
be similarly formed, we can suppose their anterior state of nebulosity
to be preceded by other states, in which the nebulous matter was more
or less diffuse, the nucleus being at the same time more or less
brilliant. By going back in this manner, we shall arrive at a state
of nebulosity so diffuse, that its existence can with difficulty be
conceived.

For a considerable time back, the particular arrangement of some stars
visible to the naked eye, has engaged the attention of philosophers.
Mitchel remarked long since how extremely improbable it was that the
stars composing the constellation called the Pleiades, for example,
should be confined within the narrow space which contains them, by the
sole chance of hazard; from which he inferred that this group of stars,
and the similar groups which the heavens present to us, are the effects
of a primitive law of nature. These groups are a general result of the
condensation of nebulæ of several nuclei; for it is evident that the
nebulous matter being perpetually attracted by these different nuclei,
ought at length to form a group of stars, like to that of the Pleiades.
The condensation of nebulæ consisting of two nuclei, will in like
manner form stars very near to each other, revolving the one about the
other like to the double stars, whose respective motions have been
already recognized.

But in what manner has the solar atmosphere determined the motions of
rotation and revolution of the planets and satellites? If these bodies
had penetrated deeply into this atmosphere, its resistance would cause
them to fall on the Sun. We may therefore suppose that the planets
were formed at its successive limits, by the condensation of zones of
vapours, which it must, while it was cooling, have abandoned in the
plane of its equator.

Let us resume the results which we have given in the tenth chapter of
the preceding book. The Sun’s atmosphere cannot extend indefinitely;
its limit is the point where the centrifugal force arising from the
motion of rotation balances the gravity; but according as the cooling
contracts the atmosphere, and condenses the molecules which are near
to it, on the surface of the star, the motion of rotation increases;
for, in virtue of the principle of areas, the sum of the areas
described by the _radius vector_ of each particle of the Sun and
its atmosphere, and projected on the plane of its equator, is always
the same. Consequently the rotation ought to be quicker, when these
particles approach to the centre of the Sun. The centrifugal force
arising from this motion becoming thus greater; the point where the
gravity is equal to it, is nearer to the centre of the Sun. Supposing,
therefore, what is natural to admit, that the atmosphere extended at
any epoch as far as this limit, it ought, according as it cooled,
to abandon the molecules, which are situated at this limit, and at
the successive limits produced by the increased rotation of the Sun.
These particles, after being abandoned, have continued to circulate
about this star, because their centrifugal force was balanced by their
gravity. But as this equality does not obtain for these molecules
of the atmosphere which are situated on the parallels to the Sun’s
equator, these have come nearer by their gravity to the atmosphere
according as it condensed, and they have not ceased to belong to it
inasmuch as by their motion, they have approached to the plane of this
equator.

Let us now consider the zones of vapours, which have been successively
abandoned. These zones ought, according to all probability, to form by
their condensation, and by the mutual attraction of their particles,
several concentrical rings of vapours circulating about the Sun. But
mutual friction of the molecules of each ring ought to accelerate
some and retard others, until they all had acquired the same angular
motion. Consequently the real velocities of the molecules which are
farther from the Sun, ought to be greatest. The following cause ought
likewise to contribute to this difference of velocities: The most
distant particles of the Sun, and which, by the effects of cooling
and condensation, have collected so as to constitute the superior
part of the ring, have always described areas proportional to the
times, because the central force by which they are actuated has been
constantly directed to this star; but this constancy of areas requires
an increase of velocity, according as they approach more to each other.
It appears that the same cause ought to diminish the velocity of the
particles, which, situated near the ring, constitute its inferior part.

If all the particles of a ring of vapours continued to condense without
separating, they would at length constitute a solid or a liquid ring.
But the regularity which this formation requires in all the parts of
the ring, and in their cooling, ought to make this phenomenon very
rare. Thus the solar system presents but one example of it; that of the
rings of Saturn. Almost always each ring of vapours ought to be divided
into several masses, which, being moved with velocities which differ
little from each other, should continue to revolve at the same distance
about the Sun. These masses should assume a spheroidical form, with a
rotatory motion in the direction of that of their revolution, because
their inferior particles have a less real velocity than the superior;
they have therefore constituted so many planets in a state of vapour.
But if one of them was sufficiently powerful, to unite successively by
its attraction, all the others about its centre, the ring of vapours
would be changed into one sole spheroidical mass, circulating about
the Sun, with a motion of rotation in the same direction with that
of revolution. This last case has been the most common; however, the
solar system presents to us the first case, in the four small planets
which revolve between Mars and Jupiter, at least unless we suppose
with Olbers, that they originally formed one planet only, which was
divided by an explosion into several parts, and actuated by different
velocities. Now if we trace the changes which a further cooling ought
to produce in the planets formed of vapours, and of which we have
suggested the formation, we shall see to arise in the centre of each
of them, a nucleus increasing continually, by the condensation of the
atmosphere which environs it. In this state, the planet resembles the
Sun in the nebulous state, in which we have first supposed it to be;
the cooling should therefore produce at the different limits of its
atmosphere, phenomena similar to those which have been described,
namely, rings and satellites circulating about its centre in the
direction of its motion of rotation, and revolving in the same
direction on their axes. The regular distribution of the mass of rings
of Saturn about its centre and in the plane of its equator, results
naturally from this hypothesis, and, without it, is inexplicable. Those
rings appear to me to be existing proofs of the primitive extension of
the atmosphere of Saturn, and of its successive condensations. Thus,
the singular phenomena of the small eccentricities of the orbits of the
planets and satellites, of the small inclination of these orbits to the
solar equator, and of the identity in the direction of the motions of
rotation and revolution of all those bodies with that of the rotation
of the Sun, follow the hypothesis which has been suggested, and render
it extremely probable. If the solar system was formed with perfect
regularity, the orbits of the bodies which compose it would be circles,
of which the planes, as well as those of the various equators and
rings, would coincide with the plane of the solar equator. But we may
suppose that the innumerable varieties which must necessarily exist in
the temperature and density of different parts of these great masses,
ought to produce the eccentricities of their orbits, and the deviations
of their motions, from the plane of this equator.

In the preceding hypothesis, the comets do not belong to the solar
system. If they be considered, as we have done, as small nebulæ,
wandering from one solar system to another, and formed by the
condensation of the nebulous matter, which is diffused so profusely
throughout the universe, we may conceive that when they arrive in
that part of space where the attraction of the Sun predominates, it
should force them to describe elliptic or hyperbolic orbits. But
as their velocities are equally possible in every direction, they
must move indifferently in all directions, and at every possible
inclination to the elliptic; which is conformable to observation. Thus
the condensation of the nebulous matter, which explains the motions
of rotation and revolution of the planets and satellites in the same
direction, and in orbits very little inclined to each other, likewise
explains why the motions of the comets deviate from this general law.

The great eccentricity of the orbits of the comets, is also a result of
our hypothesis. If those orbits are elliptic, they are very elongated,
since their greater axes are at least equal to the radius of the sphere
of activity of the Sun. But these orbits may be hyperbolic; and if the
axes of these hyperbolæ are not very great with respect to the mean
distance of the Sun from the Earth, the motion of the comets which
describe them will appear to be sensibly hyperbolic. However, with
respect to the hundred comets, of which the elements are known, not
one appears to move in a hyperbola; hence the chances which assign
a sensible hyperbola are extremely rare relatively to the contrary
chances. The comets are so small, that they only become sensible when
their perihelion distance is inconsiderable. Hitherto this distance
has not surpassed twice the diameter of the Earth’s orbit, and most
frequently, it has been less than the radius of this orbit. We may
conceive, that in order to approach so near to the Sun, their velocity
at the moment of their ingress within its sphere of activity, must have
an intensity and direction confined within very narrow limits. If we
determine by the analysis of probabilities, the ratio of the chances
which in these limits, assign a sensible hyperbola to the chances which
assign an orbit, which may without sensible error be confounded with a
parabola, it will be found that there is at least six thousand to unity
that a nebula which penetrates within the sphere of the Sun’s activity
so as to be observed, will either describe a very elongated ellipse,
or an hyperbola, which, in consequence of the magnitude of its axis
will be as to sense confounded with a parabola in the part of its orbit
which is observed. It is not therefore surprising that hitherto no
hyperbolic motions have been recognized.

The attraction of the planets, and perhaps also the resistance of the
ethereal media, ought to change several cometary orbits into ellipses,
of which the greater axes are much less than the radius of the sphere
of the solar activity. It is probable that such a change was produced
in the orbit of the comet of 1759, the greater axis of which was not
more than thirty-five times the distance of the Sun from the Earth. A
still greater change was produced in the orbits of the comets of 1770
and of 1805.

If in the zones abandoned by the atmosphere of the Sun, there are any
molecules too volatile to be united to each other, or to the planets,
they ought in their circulation about this star to exhibit all the
appearances of the zodiacal light, without opposing any sensible
resistance to the different bodies of the planetary system, both on
account of their great rarity and also because their motion is very
nearly the same as that of the planets which they meet.

An attentive examination of all the circumstances of this system
renders our hypothesis still more probable. The primitive fluidity of
the planets is clearly indicated by the compression of their figure,
conformably to the laws of the mutual attraction of their molecules; it
is moreover demonstrated by the regular diminution of gravity, as we
proceed from the equator to the poles. This state of primitive fluidity
to which we are conducted by astronomical phenomena, is also apparent
from those which natural history points out. But in order fully to
estimate them, we should take into account the immense variety of
combinations formed by all the terrestial substances which were mixed
together in a state of vapour, when the depression of their temperature
enabled their elements to unite; it is necessary likewise to consider
the wonderful changes which this depression ought to cause in the
interior and at the surface of the earth, in all its productions, in
the constitution and pressure of the atmosphere, in the ocean, and in
all substances which it held in a state of solution. Finally, we should
take into account the sudden changes, such as great volcanic eruptions,
which must at different epochs have deranged the regularity of these
changes. Geology, thus studied under the point of view which connects
it with astronomy, may, with respect to several objects, acquire both
precision and certainty.

One of the most remarkable phenomena of the solar system is the
rigorous equality which is observed to subsist between the angular
motions of rotation and revolution of each satellite. It is infinity to
unity that this is not the effect of hazard. The theory of universal
gravitation makes infinity to disappear from this improbability, by
shewing that it is sufficient for the existence of this phenomenon,
that at the commencement these motions did not differ much. Then,
the attraction of the planet would establish between them a perfect
equality; but at the same time it has given rise to a periodic
oscillation in the axis of the satellite directed to the planet, of
which oscillation the extent depends on the primitive difference
between these motions. As the observations of Mayer on the libration
of the Moon, and those which Bouvard and Nicollet made for the
same purpose, at my request, did not enable us to recognize this
oscillation; the difference on which it depends must be extremely
small, which indicates with every appearance of probability the
existence of a particular cause, which has confined this difference
within very narrow limits, in which the attraction of the planet might
establish between the mean motions of rotation and revolution a rigid
equality, which at length terminated by annihilating the oscillation
which arose from this equality. Both these effects result from our
hypothesis; for we may conceive that the Moon, in a state of vapour,
assumed in consequence of the powerful attraction of the earth the
form of an elongated spheroid, of which the greater axis would be
constantly directed towards this planet, from the facility with which
the vapours yield to the slightest force impressed upon them. The
terrestrial attraction continuing to act in the same manner, while
the Moon is in a state of fluidity, ought at length, by making the
two motions of this satellite to approach each other, to cause their
difference to fall within the limits, at which their rigorous equality
commences to establish itself. Then this attraction should annihilate,
by little and little, the oscillation which this equality produced on
the greater axis of the spheroid directed towards the earth. It is in
this manner that the fluids which cover this planet, have destroyed by
their friction and resistance the primitive oscillations of its axis
of rotation, which is only now subject to the nutation resulting from
the actions of the Sun and Moon. It is easy to be assured that the
equality of the motions of rotation and revolution of the satellites
ought to oppose the formation of rings and secondary satellites, by the
atmospheres of these bodies. Consequently observation has not hitherto
indicated the existence of any such. The motions of the three first
satellites of Jupiter present a phenomenon still more extraordinary
than the preceding; which consists in this, that the mean longitude of
the first, minus three times that of the second, plus twice that of
the third, is constantly equal to two right angles. There is the ratio
of infinity to one, that this equality is not the effect of chance.
But we have seen, that in order to produce it, it is sufficient if at
the commencement, the mean motions of these three bodies approached
very near to the relation which renders the mean motion of the first,
minus three times that of the second, plus twice that of the third,
equal to nothing. Then their mutual attraction rendered this ratio
rigorously exact, and it has moreover made the mean longitude of the
first minus three times that of the second, plus twice that of the
third, equal to a semicircumference. At the same time, it gave rise to
a periodic inequality, which depends on the small quantity, by which
the mean motions originally deviated from the relation which we have
just announced. Notwithstanding all the care Delambre took in his
observations, he could not recognize this inequality, which, while it
evinces its extreme smallness, also indicates, with a high degree of
probability, the existence of a cause which makes it to disappear. In
our hypothesis, the satellites of Jupiter, immediately after their
formation, did not move in a perfect vacuo; the less condensable
molecules of the primitive atmospheres of the Sun and planet would
then constitute a rare medium, the resistance of which being different
for each of the stars, might make the mean motions to approach by
degrees to the ratio in question; and when these movements had thus
attained the conditions requisite, in order that the mutual attraction
of the three satellites might render this relation accurately true, it
perpetually diminished the inequality which this relation originated,
and eventually rendered it insensible. We cannot better illustrate
these effects than by comparing them to the motion of a pendulum,
which, actuated by a great velocity, moves in a medium, the resistance
of which is inconsiderable. It will first describe a great number of
circumstances; but at length its motion of circulation perpetually
decreasing, it will be converted into an oscillatory motion, which
itself diminishing more and more, by the resistance of the medium, will
eventually be totally destroyed, and then the pendulum, having attained
a state of repose, will remain at rest for ever.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 21: Translated from _Exposition du Système du Monde_,
(Paris, 1796).]

[Footnote 22: viz: “The motions of the planets in the same direction,
and very nearly in the same plane; the motions of the satellites
in the same direction as those of the planets; the motions of the
rotation of these different bodies and also of the sun, in the same
direction as their motions of projection, and in planes very little
inclined to each other; the small eccentricity of the orbits of the
comets and satellites; finally, the great eccentricity of the orbits
of the comets, their inclinations being at the same time entirely
indeterminate.”]




                                  XX

                             EDWARD JENNER

                               1749-1823


 _Edward Jenner, born May 17, 1749, at Berkeley, Gloucestershire,
 England, studied surgery under John Hunter at London, and returned
 to his native town to practise. Having learned, about 1796, that
 milk-maids who had caught the cow-pox were immune from small-pox, he
 began at once to make investigations and to conduct experiments. This
 led to his “Inquiry,” published in 1798, in which he made public his
 theory of vaccination. His discovery created widespread interest, but
 although the theory at once met with the most virulent criticism,
 vaccination was soon widely accepted. By 1801, ten thousand persons
 were vaccinated in England, and the beneficent results justified its
 wide adoption. He died of apoplexy, January 26, 1823._


                     THE THEORY OF VACCINATION[23]

The deviation of Man from the state in which he was originally placed
by Nature seems to have proved to him a prolific source of Diseases.
From the love of splendour, from the indulgences of luxury, and from
his fondness for amusement, he has familiarised himself with a great
number of animals, which may not originally have been intended for his
associates.

The Wolf, disarmed of ferocity, is now pillowed in the lady’s lap. The
Cat, the little Tyger of our island, whose natural home is the forest,
is equally domesticated and caressed. The Cow, the Hog, the Sheep, and
the Horse, are all, for a variety of purposes, brought under his care
and dominion.

There is a disease to which the Horse, from his state of
domestication, is frequently subject. The Farriers have termed it the
Grease. It is an inflammation and swelling in the heel, from which
issues matter possessing properties of a very peculiar kind, which
seems capable of generating a disease in the Human Body (after it has
undergone the modification which I shall presently speak of), which
bears so strong a resemblance to the Small-pox that I think it highly
probable it may be the source of that disease.

In this Dairy Country a great number of Cows are kept, and the office
of milking is performed indiscriminately by Men and Maid Servants. One
of the former having been appointed to apply dressings to the heels
of a Horse affected with the Grease, and not paying due attention to
cleanliness, incautiously bears his part in milking the Cows, with some
particles of the infectious matter adhering to his fingers. When this
is the case, it commonly happens that a disease is communicated to
the Cows, and from the Cows to the Dairy-maids, which spreads through
the farm until most of the cattle and domestics feel its unpleasant
consequences. This disease has obtained the name of the Cow-pox. It
appears on the nipples of the Cows in the form of irregular pustules.
At their first appearance they are commonly of a palish blue, or
rather of a colour somewhat approaching to livid, and are surrounded
by an erysipelatous inflammation. These pustules, unless a timely
remedy be applied, frequently degenerate into phagedenic ulcers, which
prove extremely troublesome. The animals become indisposed, and the
secretion of milk is much lessened. Inflamed spots now begin to appear
on different parts of the hands of the domestics employed in milking,
and sometimes on the wrists, which quickly run on to suppuration, first
assuming the appearance of the small vesications produced by a burn.
Most commonly they appear about the joints of the fingers, and at their
extremities; but whatever parts are affected, if the situation will
admit, these superficial suppurations put on a circular form, with
their edges more elevated than their centre, and of a colour distantly
approaching to blue. Absorption takes place, and tumours appear in
each axilla. The system becomes affected--the pulse is quickened; and
shiverings, with general lassitude and pains about the loins and limbs,
with vomiting, come on. The head is painful, and the patient is now
and then even affected with delirium. These symptoms, varying in their
degrees of violence, generally continue from one day to three or four,
leaving ulcerated sores about the hands, which, from the sensibility of
the parts, are very troublesome, and commonly heal slowly, frequently
becoming phagedenic, like those from whence they sprung. The lips,
nostrils, eyelids, and other parts of the body, are sometimes affected
with sores; but these evidently arise from their being needlessly
rubbed or scratched with the patient’s infected fingers. No eruptions
on the skin have followed the decline of the feverish symptoms in any
instance that has come under my inspection, one only excepted, and in
this case a very few appeared on the arms: they were very minute, of a
vivid red colour, and soon died away without advancing to maturation;
so that I cannot determine whether they had any connection with the
preceding symptoms.

Thus the disease makes its progress from the Horse to the nipple of the
Cow, and from the Cow to the Human Subject.

Morbid matter of various kinds, when absorbed into the system, may
produce effects in some degree similar; but what renders the Cow-pox
virus so extremely singular is, that the person who has been thus
affected is forever after secure from the infection of the Small-pox;
neither exposure to the _variolous effluvia_, nor the insertion of
the matter into the skin producing this distemper.

 [I shall now conclude this Inquiry with some general observations on
 the subject, and on some others which are interwoven with it.]

Although I presume it may be unnecessary to produce further testimony
in support of my assertion “that Cow-pox protects the human
constitution from the infection of the Small-pox,” yet it affords me
considerable satisfaction to say that Lord Somerville, the president of
the Board of Agriculture, to whom this paper was shown by Sir Joseph
Banks, has found upon inquiry that the statements were confirmed by
the concurring testimony of Mr. Dolland, a surgeon, who resides in a
dairy country remote from this, in which these observations were made.
With respect to the opinion adduced “that the source of the infection
is a peculiar morbid matter arising in the horse,” although I have not
been able to prove it from actual experiments conducted immediately
under my own eye, yet the evidence I have adduced appears sufficient to
establish it.

They who are not in the habit of conducting experiments may not be
aware of the coincidence of circumstances necessary for their being
managed so as to prove perfectly decisive; nor how often men engaged in
professional pursuits are liable to interruptions which disappoint them
almost at the instant of their being accomplished.

 [However, I feel no room for hesitation respecting the common origin
 of the disease, being well convinced that it never appears among the
 cows (except it can be traced to a cow introduced among the general
 herd which has been previously infected, or to an infected servant),
 unless they have been milked by someone who, at the same time, has the
 care of a horse affected with diseased heels.

 The spring of 1797, which I intended particularly to have devoted
 to the completion of this investigation, proved, from its dryness,
 remarkably adverse to my wishes; for it frequently happens, while
 the farmers’ horses are exposed to the cold rains which fall at that
 season that their heels become diseased, and no Cow-pox then appeared
 in the neighbourhood.]

The active quality of the virus from the horses’ heels is greatly
increased after it has acted on the nipples of the cow, as it rarely
happens that the horse affects his dresser with sores, and as rarely
that a milk-maid escapes the infection when she milks infected cows.
It is most active at the commencement of the disease, even before it
has acquired a pus-like appearance; indeed I am not confident whether
this property in the matter does not entirely cease as soon as it is
secreted in the form of pus. I am induced to think it does cease,
and that it is the thin darkish-looking fluid only, oozing from the
newly-formed cracks in the heels, similar to what sometimes appears
from erysipelatous blisters, which gives the disease. Nor am I certain
that the nipples of the cows are at all times in a state to receive
the infection. The appearance of the disease in the spring and the
early part of the summer, when they are disposed to be affected with
spontaneous eruptions so much more frequently than at other seasons,
induces me to think that the virus from the horse must be received
upon them when they are in this state, in order to produce effects;
experiments, however, must determine these points. But it is clear that
when the Cow-pox virus is once generated, that the cows cannot resist
the contagion, in whatever state their nipples may chance to be, if
they are milked with an infected hand.

Whether the matter, either from the cow or the horse, will affect the
sound skin of the human body, I cannot positively determine; probably
it will not, unless on those parts where the cuticle is extremely thin,
as on the lips for example. I have known an instance of a poor girl
who produced an ulceration on her lip by frequently holding her finger
to her mouth to cool the raging of a Cow-pox sore by blowing upon it.
The hands of the farmers’ servants here, from the nature of their
employments, are constantly exposed to those injuries which occasion
abrasions of the cuticle, to punctures from thorns and such like
accidents; so that they are always in a state to feel the consequences
of exposure to infectious matter.

 [It is singular to observe that the Cow-pox virus, although it renders
 the constitution unsusceptible of the variolous, should, nevertheless,
 leave it unchanged with respect to its own action. I have already
 produced an instance to point out this, and shall now corroborate it
 with another.

 Elizabeth Wynne, who had the Cow-pox in the year 1759, was inoculated
 with variolous matter, without effect, in the year 1797, and again
 caught the Cow-pox in the year 1798. When I saw her, which was on the
 8th day after she received the infection, I found her infected with
 general lassitude, shiverings, alternating with heat, coldness of the
 extremities, and a quick and irregular pulse. These symptoms were
 preceded by a pain in the axilla.]

It is curious also to observe that the virus, which with respect to
its effects is undetermined and uncertain previously to its passing
from the horse through the medium of the cow, should then not only
become more active, but should invariably and completely possess those
specific properties which induce in the human constitution symptoms
similar to those of the variolous fever, and effect in it that peculiar
change which forever renders it unsusceptible of the variolous
contagion.

May it not then be reasonably conjectured that the source of the
Small-pox is morbid matter of a peculiar kind, generated by a disease
in the horse, and that accidental circumstances may have again and
again arisen, still working new changes upon it, until it has acquired
the contagious and malignant form under which we now commonly see it
making its devastations amongst us? And, from a consideration of the
change which the infectious matter undergoes from producing a disease
on the cow, may we not conceive that many contagious diseases, now
prevalent among us, may owe their present appearance not to a simple,
but to a compound origin? For example, is it difficult to imagine that
the measles, scarlet fever, and the ulcerous sore throat with a spotted
skin, have all sprung from the same source, assuming some variety in
their forms according to the nature of their new combinations? The same
question will apply respecting the origin of many other contagious
diseases, which bear a strong analogy to each other.

There are certainly more forms than one, without considering the common
variation between the confluent and distinct, in which the Small-pox
appears in what is called the natural way. About seven years ago a
species of Small-pox spread through many of the towns and villages of
this part of Gloucestershire: it was of so mild a nature that a fatal
instance was scarcely ever heard of, and consequently so little dreaded
by the lower orders of the community that they scrupled not to hold the
same intercourse with each other as if no infectious disease had been
present among them. I never saw nor heard of an instance of its being
confluent. The most accurate manner, perhaps, in which I can convey
an idea of it, is, by saying that had fifty individuals been taken
promiscuously and infected by exposure to this contagion, they would
have had as mild and light a disease as if they had been inoculated
with variolous matter in the usual way. The harmless manner in which it
showed itself could not arise from any peculiarity either in the season
or the weather, for I watched its progress upwards of a year without
perceiving any variation in its general appearance. I consider it then
as a variety of the Small-pox.

 [In some of the preceding cases I have noticed the attention that was
 paid to the state of the variolous matter previous to the experiment
 of inserting it into the arms of those who had gone through the
 Cow-pox. This I conceived to be of great importance in conducting
 these experiments, and were it always properly attended to by those
 who inoculate for the Small-pox, it might prevent much subsequent
 mischief and confusion. With the view of enforcing so necessary a
 precaution, I shall take the liberty of digressing so far as to
 point out some unpleasant facts relative to mismanagement in this
 particular, which have fallen under my own observation.]

A medical gentleman (now no more), who for many years inoculated
in this neighbourhood, frequently preserved the variolous matter
intended for his use, on a piece of lint or cotton, which, in its
fluid state, was put into a vial, corked, and conveyed into a warm
pocket; a situation certainly favourable for speedily producing
putrefaction in it. In this state (not infrequently after it had been
taken several days from the pustules) it was inserted into the arms
of his patients, and brought on inflammation of the incised parts,
swellings of the axillary glands, fever, and sometimes eruptions. But
what was this disease? Certainly not the Small-pox; for the matter
having from putrefaction lost, or suffered a derangement in its
specific properties, was no longer capable of producing that malady,
those who had been inoculated in this manner being as much subject
to the contagion of the Small-pox, as if they had never been under
the influence of this artificial disease; and many, unfortunately,
fell victims to it, who thought themselves in perfect security. The
same unfortunate circumstance of giving a disease, supposed to be the
Small-pox, with inefficacious variolous matter, having occurred under
the direction of some other practitioners within my knowledge, and
probably from the same incautious method of securing the variolous
matter, I avail myself of this opportunity of mentioning what I
conceive to be of great importance; and, as a further cautionary hint,
I shall again digress so far as to add another observation on the
subject of Inoculation.

Whether it be yet ascertained by experiment, that the quantity of
variolous matter inserted into the skin makes any difference with
respect to the subsequent mildness or violence of the disease, I know
not; but I have the strongest reason for supposing that if either the
punctures or incisions be made so deep as to go through it, and wound
the adipose membrane, that the risk of bringing on a violent disease is
greatly increased. I have known an inoculator, whose practice was “to
cut deep enough (to use his own expression) to see a bit of fat,” and
there to lodge the matter. The great number of bad cases, independent
of inflammations and abscesses on the arms, and the fatality which
attended this practice was almost inconceivable; and I cannot account
for it on any other principle than that of the matter being placed in
this situation instead of the skin.

At what period the Cow-pox was first noticed here is not upon record.
Our oldest farmers were not unacquainted with it in their earliest
days, when it appeared among their farms without any deviation from
the phenomena which it now exhibits. Its connection with the Small-pox
seems to have been unknown to them. Probably the general introduction
of inoculation first occasioned the discovery.

Its rise in this country may not have been of very remote date, as the
practice of milking cows might formerly have been in the hands of women
only; which I believe is the case now in some other dairy countries,
and consequently that the cows might not in former times have been
exposed to the contagious matter brought by the men servants from the
heels of horses. Indeed a knowledge of the source of the infection is
new in the minds of most of the farmers in this neighbourhood, but it
has at length produced good consequences; and it seems probable from
the precautions they are now disposed to adopt, that the appearance
of the Cow-pox here may either be entirely extinguished or become
extremely rare.

Should it be asked whether this investigation is a matter of mere
curiosity, or whether it tends to any beneficial purpose, I should
answer that, notwithstanding the happy effects of inoculation, with
all the improvements which the practice has received since its first
introduction into this country, it not very infrequently produces
deformity of the skin, and sometimes, under the best management, proves
fatal.

These circumstances must naturally create in every instance some degree
of painful solicitude for its consequences. But as I have never known
fatal effects arise from the Cow-pox, even when impressed in the most
unfavourable manner, producing extensive inflammations and suppurations
on the hands; and as it clearly appears that this disease leaves the
constitution in a state of perfect security from the infection of
the Small-pox, may we not infer that a mode of inoculation may be
introduced preferable to that at present adopted, especially among
those families which, from previous circumstances, we may judge to be
predisposed to have the disease unfavourably? It is an excess in the
number of pustules which we chiefly dread in the Small-pox; but, in
the Cow-pox, no pustules appear, nor does it seem possible for the
contagious matter to produce the disease from effluvia, or by any other
means than contact, and that probably not simply between the virus and
the cuticle; so that a single individual in a family might at any time
receive it without the risk of infecting the rest, or of spreading a
distemper that fills a country with terror.

 [Several instances have come under my observation which justify the
 assertion that the disease cannot be propagated by effluvia. The first
 boy whom I inoculated with the matter of Cow-pox slept in a bed while
 the experiment was going forward, with two children who had never gone
 through either that disease or the Small-pox, without infecting either
 of them.

 A young woman who had the Cow-pox to a great extent, several sores
 which maturated having appeared on the hands and wrists, slept in the
 same bed with a fellow-dairymaid, who never had been infected with
 either the Cow-pox or the Small-pox, but no indisposition followed.

 Another instance has occurred of a young woman on whose hands were
 several large suppurations from the Cow-pox, who was at the same time
 a daily nurse to an infant, but the complaint was not communicated to
 the child.]

In some other points of view the inoculation of this disease appears
preferable to the variolous inoculation.

In constitutions predisposed to scrofula, how frequently we see the
inoculated Small-pox rouse into activity that distressful malady.
This circumstance does not seem to depend on the manner in which the
distemper has shown itself, for it has as frequently happened among
those who have had it mildly, as when it has appeared in the contrary
way. There are many, who from some peculiarity in the habit resist the
common effects of variolous matter inserted into the skin, and who
are in consequence haunted through life with the distressing idea of
being insecure from subsequent infection. A ready mode of dissipating
anxiety originating from such a cause must now appear obvious. And, as
we have seen that the constitution may at any time be made to feel the
fertile attack of Cow-pox, might it not, in many chronic diseases, be
introduced into the system, with the probability of affording relief,
upon well-known physiological principles?

Although I say the system may at any time be made to feel the febrile
attack of Cow-pox, yet I have a single instance before me where the
virus acted locally only, but it is not in the least probable that
the same person would resist the action both of Cow-pox virus and the
variolous.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 23: From _An Inquiry into the Cause and Effects of the
Variolae Vaccinae_.]




                                  XXI

                             COUNT RUMFORD

                               1753-1814


 _Sir Benjamin Thompson, Count Rumford, was born in Woburn,
 Massachusetts, March 26, 1753, a member of an old New England family.
 After a very romantic youth and early manhood in which he underwent
 many exciting adventures as a British loyalist at the time of the
 American Revolution, he was sent to England with despatches by the
 British expeditionary authorities and there found employment in the
 office of the Secretary of State. After the close of the Revolution
 he went to Bavaria, where he became Minister of War and Grand
 Chamberlain. In 1791 he was made a count of the Holy Roman Empire. In
 1796 President Adams invited him to return to America to become an
 inspector of artillery, but he declined; and at about the same time he
 became interested in problems of heat, light, and fuel. His suggestions
 ultimately became the basis for the doctrine of the conservation of
 energy. He died at Auteuil, August 25, 1814._


                        THE NATURE OF HEAT[24]

After I had long meditated upon a way of putting this interesting
problem entirely out of doubt by a perfectly conclusive experiment, I
thought finally that I had discovered it, and I think so still.

I argued that if the existence of caloric was a fact, it must be
absolutely impossible for a body or for several individual bodies,
which together made one whole, to communicate this substance
continuously to various other bodies by which they were surrounded,
without this substance gradually being entirely exhausted.

A sponge filled with water, and hung by a thread in the middle of a
room filled with dry air, communicates its moisture to the air, it is
true, but soon the water evaporates and the sponge can no longer give
out moisture. On the contrary, a bell sounds without interruption when
it is struck, and gives out its sound as often as we please without the
slightest perceptible loss. Moisture is a substance; sound is not.

It is well known that two hard bodies, if rubbed together, produce
much heat. Can they continue to produce it without finally becoming
exhausted? Let the result of experiment decide this question.

It would be too tedious to describe here in detail all the experiments
which I undertook with a view of answering in a decisive manner this
important and disputed question. They may be found in my memoir, “On
the Source of Heat excited by Friction.” I have had it printed in
the _Philosophical Transactions_ for the year 1798; still these
experiments bear too close a relation to my later researches on heat
for me to omit attempting at least to give the reader a clear idea of
the experiments and of their results.

The apparatus which I used in these investigations is too complicated
to be represented in this place; still it will not be difficult for
the reader to form a conception of the principal experiments and their
results.

Let A be the vertical section of a brass rod which is an inch in
diameter and is fastened in an upright position on a stout block,
B; it is provided at its upper end with a massive hemisphere of the
same metal, three and a half inches in diameter. C is a similar rod,
likewise vertical, to the lower end of which is fastened a similar
hemisphere. Both hemispheres must fit each other in such a way that
both the rods stand in a perfectly straight vertical line.

D is the vertical section of a globular metallic vessel twelve inches
in diameter, which is provided with a cylindrical neck three inches
long and three and three-quarter inches in diameter. The rod A goes
through a hole in the bottom of the vessel, is soldered into the
vessel, and serves as a support to keep it in its proper position.

The centre of the ball, made up of the two hemispheres which lie the
one upon the other, is in the centre of the globular vessel, so that,
if the vessel is filled with water, the water covers the ball as well
as a part of each of the brass rods.

If now the hemispheres be pressed strongly together, and at the same
time the rod C be turned, by some means or other, about its axis,
a very considerable quantity of heat is generated by means of the
friction which takes place between the flat surfaces of the two
hemispheres.

The quantity of the heat excited in this manner is exactly proportional
to the force with which the two surfaces are pressed together, and to
the rapidity of the friction. When this force was equal to the pressure
of ten thousand pounds, and when the rod was turned with such rapidity
about its axis that it revolved thirty-two times a minute, the quantity
of heat generated by the continual rubbing of the two surfaces together
was extraordinarily great. It was equal to the quantity given off by
the flame of nine wax-candles of moderate size all burning together.

The quantity of heat generated in this manner during a given time is
manifestly the same, whether the globular vessel D is filled with
water, and the surfaces of the two hemispheres rub on each other in
this liquid, or whether there is no water in the vessel, and the
apparatus by which the friction is produced is simply surrounded by air.

The source of the heat which is generated by this apparatus is
inexhaustible. As long as the rod C is turned about its axis, so long
will heat be produced by the apparatus, and always to the same amount.

If the globe-shaped vessel D is filled with water, this water becomes
hotter and hotter, and finally begins to boil. I have myself in this
way boiled a considerable quantity of water.

If this experiment is performed in winter when the temperature of the
air is but little above the freezing-point, and if the vessel D is
filled with a mixture of water and pounded ice, the quantity of heat
caused in a given time by the rubbing together of the two surfaces can
be expressed very exactly by the amount of ice melted by this heat.

Since the apparatus affords heat continuously, and always to the same
amount, we can melt in this way as much ice as we please.

But whence comes this heat? This is the contested point, to determine
which was the real aim of the experiment.

It is certain that it comes neither from the decomposition of the
water nor from the decomposition of the air. Various experiments
on this point, which I have described at length in my memoir in
the _Philosophical Transactions_, are more than sufficient to
establish this fact beyond doubt.

Just as little does it come from a change in the capacity for heat
brought about by friction in the metal of which the hemispheres are
composed. This is shown, first, by the continuance and uniformity of
the production of the heat; and, secondly, by an experiment bearing
directly on this point, by which I am convinced that not the slightest
change had taken place in the capacity of the metal for heat.

Just as little does it come from the rods which are attached to
the hemispheres, for these rods were always warm, the hemispheres
communicating heat to them.

Much less could this heat come from the air of the water immediately
surrounding the hemispheres, for the apparatus communicated heat to
both these fluids without cessation.

Whence, then, came this heat? and what is heat actually?

I must confess that it has always been impossible for me to explain
the results of such experiments except by taking refuge in the very
old doctrine which rests on the supposition that heat is nothing but a
vibratory motion taking place among the particles of bodies.

A bell, on being struck, immediately gives forth a sound, and the
oscillations of the air produced by these vibrations forthwith cause a
quivering motion in those bodies with which they come in contact. On
the other hand, a sponge filled with water cannot give off its moisture
to the bodies in its vicinity for any length of time without itself
losing moisture.

A very illustrious philosopher, for whom I have always entertained the
greatest respect, and whom, moreover, I have the good fortune to count
among my most intimate friends, M. Bertholet, has, in his admirable
_Essai de Statique Chimique_, attempted to explain the results
of this investigation, and to reconcile them with that theory of heat
which is founded upon the hypothesis of caloric.

If a man as learned, as honest, as worthy, and as renowned as is
M. Bertholet spares no pains in opposing the errors of a natural
philosopher or chemist, one cannot and dare not keep silence unless he
wishes to acknowledge himself vanquished. If, however, one can produce
proofs--a fortunate thing for all those who find themselves driven to
similar self-vindication--that the objections of M. Bertholet have no
foundation, he has done very much towards establishing beyond doubt the
opinions and facts in question.

I will now endeavor to answer the objections which M. Bertholet has
offered to my explanation of the above-mentioned experiments; and, that
the reader may be in a position to give to these objections their just
value, I will insert them here in the writer’s own words.

 “Count Rumford has made a curious experiment with regard to the heat
 which may be excited by friction. He causes a blunt borer to revolve
 very rapidly (this borer revolved about its axis only thirty-two times
 a minute) in a brass cylinder weighing thirteen pounds, English weight
 (the cylinder weighed one hundred and thirteen pounds and somewhat
 more), and says that he observed that this borer in the course of
 two (one and a half) hours, and under a pressure equal to 100 cwt.,
 reduced to powder 4145 grains (8-1/2 ounces Troy) of brass, and that
 an amount of heat was generated during this operation sufficient
 to bring to boil 26.38 pounds of water, previously cooled to the
 freezing-point. He asserts that he did not discover the slightest
 difference between the specific heat of the metallic dust and that of
 the brass which had not experienced the friction. Hence he supposes
 that the heat was excited by the pressure alone, and was not at all
 due to caloric, as is the opinion of most chemists.

 “I will for the present satisfy myself with simply inquiring whether
 it necessarily follows from this experiment that we must renounce
 entirely the received theory of caloric, according to which it is
 regarded as a substance which enters into combination with bodies, or
 whether this result cannot be explained in a satisfactory manner by
 applying to the case in question those laws of nature in accordance
 with which the operations of heat are manifested under other
 conditions.

 “If the evolution of heat be regarded as a consequence of the decrease
 of volume caused by the pressure, then not only the metallic powder,
 but also all the rest of the brass cylinder must have contributed,
 though not in an equal manner, to this evolution, by the powerful
 expansive effort of that portion which experienced the greatest
 pressure, and consequently acquired the greatest temperature, without
 being able to assume the dimensions proper to this same temperature on
 account of the less heated and less expanded parts; consequently there
 must have arisen, necessarily, a certain condensation of the metal
 in respect of its natural dimensions, which condensation gradually
 decreased from the point where the pressure was greatest to the
 surface. We may suppose that this operation took place in a similar
 manner in all parts of the cylinder.

 “As a consequence of this decrease of volume, an amount of caloric was
 given out equal to that which would have caused a similar increase
 of volume, on the supposition, that is, that the specific heat of
 the metal does not change through this range of the scale of the
 thermometer, and that the expansions are equal; and this, considering
 the range of temperatures and the consequent expansions, is probably
 not far from the truth. The entire amount of heat disengaged would
 have raised the cylinder to about 180° of Reaumur’s scale; and if
 the expansion of brass by heat is equal to that of iron, which has
 been found to be 1-75000 for each degree of the thermometer, the 180
 degrees would have caused an expansion of 18-75000 in each direction,
 and the decrease of volume must have brought about the same degree of
 heat if we suppose that the pressure stood in equal relation to this
 expansion.

 “Now there is a change, and sometimes a very considerable one, wrought
 in the specific gravity of a metal, by percussion, by the action of
 a fly-wheel, or by the compression of a wire-drawing machine. It
 appears, for example, that the specific gravity of platina and of
 iron, on being forged, is thus increased by a twentieth part.

 “Hence it appears that the experiment of Count Rumford is far from
 explaining satisfactorily a property which is well known, and called
 in question by no one.

 “It is easy, it is true, to arrange side by side in an imposing manner
 the phenomena of heat; if, however, you were to say to one who has
 little or no knowledge of chemical speculations, ‘Count Rumford’s
 cylinder has, in the course of two hours, by means of a violent
 friction, afforded all the heat required to dissolve in water, without
 changing its temperature, 15 kilogrammes of ice, or as much as 2
 hectogrammes (6-1/2 ounces) of oxygen would require [_sic_] in
 its combination with phosphorus,’ I do not know at which of these
 phenomena he would be most astonished.

 “The slight changes which can take place in the amount of combined
 caloric have so inconsiderable an influence on the capacity for work
 of the caloric within the narrow limits of the thermometric scale,
 that it cannot be computed. Moreover, we have not, as yet, adequate
 data for determining the nature of the changes in this respect which
 take place in a solid body in consequence of the particular condition
 of condensation into which it has been brought by means of certain
 mechanical force, and by degrees of heat differing greatly from each
 other.

 “Besides, Rumford, in the experiment to determine the specific heat
 of the filings of bell-metal thus obtained, heated them to the
 temperature of boiling water. But this extremely elastic heat would
 very naturally as soon as left to itself, and especially during the
 operation just mentioned, resume that state of expansion and that
 capacity for heat which is proper to it at a given temperature, so
 that the effect of the pressure to which it has been subjected partly
 disappears again, just as a piece of metal which has been hammered
 resumes its natural properties on being annealed.”

In reply to these remarks, I will call to mind what follows.

1st. The discovery which I made, that no considerable change had
taken place in the specific heat of the metallic dust produced by the
friction, led me in no way to the supposition that the heat excited
in the experiment could not come from the caloric set free. I only
found that the source of this heat was inexhaustible. To explain this
phenomenon, which has never yet been explained, is the point now in
question, and I do not see how it can be explained except by giving up
altogether the hypothesis adopted in regard to caloric.

2d. If we actually suppose (and it is far from having been proved)
that the simple pressing together of a metal is sufficient to expel
the caloric contained in it; still the explanation of such a natural
phenomenon would be advanced little or none; for since the action of
the force which causes the pressure is continuous, the condensation
of the metal brought about by this force would in a short time reach
its maximum; and if really in this operation ever so much caloric had
been disengaged from the metal, still it would very soon disperse. The
rubbing surfaces, on the contrary, continue to give forth heat, and
that always to the same amount.

3d. In regard to the objection made to the experiment which was
undertaken with a view of determining whether a change had taken place
in the capacity of the metallic dust for heat, this can very readily be
answered, and in such a way that nothing, it seems to me, can be said
against it. If the temperature of boiling water were really sufficient
to give to these small, forcibly condensed particles of metal the
quantity of heat necessary to bring them back to their original
condition as far as their capacity for heat is concerned, then, as the
water by which the apparatus was surrounded finally began to boil,
they must, without doubt, have taken the necessary amount of heat from
this water. If, now, these particles of metal received finally from
the water the caloric which in the beginning they imparted to it,
the question arises, whence came the caloric which served to heat,
not only the water, but also the metal and the objects immediately
surrounding it?

I am far from desiring to deceive anyone by an imposing arrangement
of facts; but the facts in my experiments were so very striking that
it was altogether impossible for me to help instituting comparisons
and making calculations with regard to them which would make them
clear, especially to those not yet sufficiently acquainted with such
investigations.

I will now close my remarks with an entirely new computation. I will
show whether it is probable that the metal could supply all the heat
which was produced by friction in the experiment in question. If we are
to make this supposition, we must, in the first place, allow that all
the heat came directly from the particles of metal which were separated
from the solid mass of metal by the friction; for, since the mass
remained in the same condition throughout the entire experiment, it is
evident that it could contribute in no measure to the effect produced.

We will now inquire how much heat would have been developed if the
experiment had been carried on without cessation, until the whole mass
of metal had been reduced to powder by the friction.

After the experiment had lasted an hour and a half, there were 4145
grains (Troy) of the metallic dust, and during that time an amount of
heat was produced by the friction sufficient to raise 26.58 pounds of
ice-cold water to the boiling point.

Since the mass of metal weighed 113.13 pounds, or 791,190 grains, all
this metal would have been reduced to powder if the experiment had
lasted uninterruptedly, day and night, for 477-1/2 hours, or for 19
days 21-1/2 hours, and during this time an amount of heat would have
been produced sufficient to have raised 5078 pounds of water to the
boiling-point.

Since the metal used in this experiment showed a capacity for heat
which was to that of water as 0.11 to 1, it is evident that this amount
of heat would have been sufficient to raise a mass of the same metal
46,165 pounds in weight through 180 degrees of Fahrenheit’s scale, or
from the temperature of melting ice to that of boiling water.

This amount of heat would be sufficient to melt a mass of metal sixteen
times heavier than that which I used in the experiment.

Is it at all conceivable that such an enormous quantity of caloric
could really be present in this body? But even this supposition would
be by no means sufficient for the explanation of the fact in question,
as I have shown by a decisive experiment that the capacity of the metal
for heat has not sensibly altered.

Whence, then, came the caloric which the apparatus furnished in such
abundance?

I leave this question to be answered by those persons who believe in
the actual existence of caloric.

In my opinion, I have made it sufficiently evident that it was
impossible for it to come from the metallic bodies which were rubbed
together, and I am absolutely unable to imagine how it can have come
from any other object in the neighborhood of the apparatus, for all
these objects received their heat constantly from the apparatus itself.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 24: From _An Enquiry Concerning the Source of Heat Excited
by Friction_ (1798)--_Transactions of the Royal Society of
London_.]




                                 XXII

                              JOHN DALTON

                               1766-1844


 _John Dalton, son of a weaver, was born in Cumberland,
 England, September 5, 1766. After an early life spent in teaching in
 elementary schools, in 1793 he became a teacher of mathematics and
 philosophy at New College, Manchester. He began his researches into the
 combination of gases in 1800 and discovered that gases expanded equally
 with the same pressure and heat. He announced his discovery in a paper
 read before the Manchester Society in 1801. From further experiments
 he derived his theory that gases combined with one another in definite
 proportions, and evolved his atomic theory to explain the results.
 Awarded the King’s medal in 1822, he was further honored by a pension
 granted in 1833. He died May 27, 1844._


                         THE ATOMIC THEORY[25]

There are three distinctions in the kinds of bodies, or three states,
which have more especially claimed the attention of philosophical
chemists; namely, those which are marked by the terms elastic fluids,
liquids, and solids. A very familiar instance is exhibited to us
in water, of a body which, in certain circumstances, is capable of
assuming all the three states. In steam we recognize a perfectly
elastic fluid, in water a perfect liquid, and in ice a complete solid.
These observations have tacitly led to the conclusion which seems
universally adopted, that all bodies of sensible magnitude, whether
liquid or solid, are constituted of a vast number of extremely small
particles, or atoms of matter bound together by a force of attraction,
which is more or less powerful according to circumstances, and which
as it endeavours to prevent their separation, is very properly called
in that view, attraction of cohesion; but as it collects them from a
dispersed state (as from steam into water) it is called attraction of
aggregation, or more simply, affinity. Whatever names it may go by,
they will signify one and the same power. It is not my design to call
in question this conclusion, which appears completely satisfactory;
but to show that we have hitherto made no use of it, and that the
consequence of the neglect has been a very obscure view of chemical
agency, which is daily growing more so in proportion to the new lights
attempted to be thrown upon it.

The opinions I more particularly allude to, are those of Bertholet
on the Laws of chemical affinity; such as that chemical agency is
proportional to the mass, and that in all chemical unions there exist
insensible gradations in the proportions of the constituent principles.
The inconsistence of these opinions, both with reason and observation,
cannot, I think, fail to strike every one who takes a proper view of
the phenomena.

Whether the ultimate particles of a body, such as water, are all
alike, that is, of the same figure, weight, etc., is a question of
some importance. From what is known, we have no reason to apprehend
a diversity in these particulars: if it does exist in water, it must
equally exist in the elements constituting water, namely, hydrogen and
oxygen. Now it is scarcely possible to conceive how the aggregates
of dissimilar particles should be so uniformly the same. If some of
the particles of water were heavier than others, if a parcel of the
liquid on any occasion were constituted principally of these heavier
particles, it must be supposed to affect the specific gravity of the
mass, a circumstance not known. Similar observations may be made on
other substances. Therefore we may conclude that the ultimate particles
of all homogeneous bodies are perfectly alike in weight, figure, etc.
In other words, every particle of water is like every other particle
of water; every particle of hydrogen is like every other particle of
hydrogen, etc.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 25: From a note entitled _On the Constitution of Bodies_
which Dalton wrote and had incorporated in Thomas Thompson’s _System
of Chemistry_ (3d edition, 1807).]




                                 XXIII

                     MARIE FRANÇOIS XAVIER BICHAT

                               1771-1802


 _Bichat was born in the French town of Thoirette (Department of
 Ain), November 14, 1771. At the University of Lyons he was especially
 interested in anatomy, surgery, and natural history. In 1793, because
 of the Revolution, he fled to Paris, where he studied under the eminent
 surgeon Desault. In 1800 he distinguished between animal and organic
 functions and after many dissections he developed, in 1801, his famous
 doctrine of tissues. He died July 22, 1802, from injuries received in a
 fall._


                      THE DOCTRINE OF TISSUES[26]

                          OBJECT OF THE WORK

The general doctrine of this work has not precisely the character of
any of those which have prevailed in medicine. Opposed to that of
Boerhaave, it differs from that of Stahl and those authors who, like
him, refer everything in the living economy to a single principle,
purely speculative, ideal, and imaginary, whether designated by the
name of soul, vital principle, or archeus. The general doctrine of this
work consists in analyzing with precision the properties of living
bodies, in showing that every physiological phenomenon is ultimately
referable to these properties considered in their natural state;
that every pathological phenomenon derives from their augmentation,
diminution, or alteration; that every therapeutic phenomenon has for
its principle the restoration of that part of the natural type, from
which it has been changed; in determining with precision the cases
in which each property is brought into action; in distinguishing
accurately in physiology as well as in medicine, that which is
derived from one, and that which flows from others; in ascertaining by
rigorous induction the natural and morbific phenomena which the animal
properties produce, and those which are derived from the organic;
and in pointing out when the animal sensibility and contractility
are brought into action, and when the organic sensibility and the
sensible or insensible contractility. We shall be easily convinced upon
reflection, that we cannot precisely estimate the immense influence
of the vital properties in the physiological sciences, before we have
considered these properties in the point of view in which I have
presented them. It will be said, perhaps, that this manner of viewing
them is still a theory; I will answer that it is a theory like that
which shows in the physical sciences, gravity, elasticity, affinity,
etc., as the primitive principles of the facts observed in these
sciences. The relation of these properties as causes to the phenomena
as effects, is an axiom so well known in physics, chemistry, astronomy,
etc., at the present day, that it is unnecessary to repeat it. If this
work establishes an analogous axiom in the physiological sciences, its
object will be attained.


             OBSERVATIONS UPON THE ORGANIZATION OF ANIMALS

The properties, whose influence we have just analyzed, are not
absolutely inherent in the particles of matter that are the seat of
them. They disappear when these scattered particles have lost their
organic arrangement. It is to this arrangement that they exclusively
belong; let us treat of it here in a general way.

All animals are an assemblage of different organs, which, executing
each a function, concur in their own manner, to the preservation of
the whole. It is several separate machines in a general one, that
constitutes the individual. Now these separate machines are themselves
formed by many textures of a very different nature, and which really
compose the elements of these organs. Chemistry has its simple bodies,
which form, by the combination of which they are susceptible, the
compound bodies; such are caloric, light, hydrogen, oxygen, carbon
azote, phosphorus, etc. In the same way anatomy has its simple
textures, which, by their combinations four with four, six with six,
eight with eight, etc., make the organs. These textures, are, 1st,
the cellular; 2d, the nervous of animal life; 3d, the nervous of
organic life; 4th, the arterial; 5th, the venous; 6th, the texture
of the exhalants; 7th, that of the absorbents and their glands; 8th,
the osseous; 9th, the medullary; 10th, the cartilaginous; 11th, the
fibrous; 12th, the fibro-cartilaginous; 13th, the muscular of animal
life; 14th, the muscular of organic life; 15th, the mucous; 16th, the
serous; 17th, the synovial; 18th, the glandular; 19th, the dermoid;
20th, the epidermoid; 21st, the pilous.

These are the true organized elements of our bodies. Their nature is
constantly the same, wherever they are met with. As in chemistry, the
simple bodies do not alter, notwithstanding the different compound ones
they form. The organized elements of man form the particular object of
this work.

The idea of thus considering abstractly the different simple textures
of our bodies, is not the work of the imagination; it rests upon the
most substantial foundation, and I think it will have a powerful
influence upon physiology as well as practical medicine. Under whatever
point of view we examine them, it will be found that they do not
resemble each other; it is nature and not science that has drawn the
line of distinction between them.

1st. Their forms are everywhere different; here they are flat, there
round. We see the simple textures arranged as membranes, canals,
fibrous fasciæs, etc. No one has the same external character with
another, considered as to their attributes of thickness or size.
These differences of form, however, can only be accidental, and the
same texture is sometimes seen under many different appearances; for
example, the nervous appears as a membrane in the retina, and as cords
in the nerves. This has nothing to do with their nature; it is then
from the organization of the properties that the principal differences
should be drawn.

2dly. There is no analogy in the organization of the simple textures.
We shall see that this organization results from parts that are common
to all, and from those that are peculiar to each; but the common parts
are all differently arranged in each texture. Some unite in abundance
the cellular texture, the blood vessels and the nerves; in others, one
or two of these three common parts are scarcely evident or entirely
wanting. Here there are only the exhalants and absorbents of nutrition;
there the vessels are more numerous for other purposes. The capillary
network, wonderfully multiplied, exists in certain textures; in
others this network can hardly be demonstrated. As to the peculiar
part, which essentially distinguishes the texture, the differences
are striking. Color, thickness, hardness, density, resistance, etc.,
nothing is similar. More inspection is sufficient to show a number of
characteristic attributes of each clearly different from the others.
Here is a fibrous arrangement, there a granulated one; here it is
lamellated, there circular. Notwithstanding these differences, authors
are not agreed as to the limits of the different textures. I have had
recourse, in order to leave no doubt upon this point, to the action
of different re-agents. I have examined every texture, submitted them
to the action of caloric, air, water, the acids, the alkalies, the
neutral salts, etc., drying, putrefaction, maceration, boiling, etc.;
the products of many of these actions have altered in a different
manner each kind of texture. Now it will be seen that the results have
almost all been different, that in these various changes each acts in
a particular way, each gives results of its own, no one resembling
another.

There has been considerable inquiry to ascertain whether the arterial
coats are fleshy, whether the veins are of an analogous nature, etc. By
comparing the results of my experiments upon the different textures,
the question is easily resolved. It would seem at first view that all
these experiments upon the intimate texture of systems answer but
little purpose; I think, however, that they have effected a useful
object, in fixing with precision the limits of each organized texture;
for the nature of these textures being unknown, their differences can
be ascertained only by the different results they furnish.

3rdly. In giving to each system a different organic arrangement,
nature has also endowed them with different properties. You will
see in the subsequent part of this work, that what we call texture
presents degrees indefinitely varying, from the muscles, the skin,
the cellular membrane, etc., which enjoy it in the highest degree,
to the cartilages, the tendons, the bones, etc., which are almost
destitute of it. Shall I speak of the vital properties? See the
animal sensibly predominant in the nerves, contractility of the same
kind particularly marked in the voluntary muscles, sensible organic
contractility, forming the peculiar property of the involuntary,
insensible contractility and sensibility of the same nature, which is
not separated from it more than from the preceding, characterizing
especially the glands, the skin, the serous surfaces, etc., etc. See
each of these simple textures combining, in different degrees, more or
less of these properties, and consequently living with more or less
energy.

There is but little difference arising from the number of vital
properties they have in common; when these properties exist in many,
they take in each a distinctive and peculiar character. This character
is chronic, if I may so express myself, in the bones, the cartilages,
the tendons, etc.; it is acute in the muscles, the skin, the glands,
etc.

Independently of this general difference, each texture has a particular
kind of force, of sensibility, etc. Upon this principle rests the whole
theory of secretion, of exhalation, of absorption, and of nutrition.
The blood is a common reservoir, from which each texture chooses that
which is adapted to its sensibility, to appropriate and keep it, and
afterwards reject it.

Much has been said since the time of Bordeu, of the peculiar life of
each organ, which is nothing else than that particular character which
distinguishes the combination of the vital properties of one organ
from those of another. Before these properties had been analyzed with
exactness and precision, it was clearly impossible to form a correct
idea of this peculiar life. From the recount I have just given of it,
it is evident that the greatest part of the organs being composed of
very different simple textures, the idea of a peculiar life can only
apply to these simple textures, and not to the organs themselves.

Some examples will render the point of doctrine which is important,
more evident. The stomach is composed of the serous, organic muscular,
mucous, and of almost all the common textures, as the arterial, the
venous, etc., which we can consider separately. Now if you should
attempt to describe in a general manner, the peculiar life of the
stomach, it is evidently impossible that you could give a very precise
and exact idea of it. In fact the mucous surface is so different
from the serous, and both so different from the muscular, that by
associating them together, the whole would be confused. The same is
true of the intestines, the bladder, the womb, etc.; if you do not
distinguish what belongs to each of the textures that form the compound
organs, the term peculiar life will offer nothing but vagueness and
uncertainty. This is so true, that oftentimes the same textures
alternately belong or are foreign to their organs. The same portion of
the peritoneum, for example, enters or does not enter, into the gastric
viscera, according to their fulness or vacuity.

Shall I speak of the pectoral organs? What has the life of the
fleshy texture of the heart in common with that of the membrane that
surrounds it? Is not the pleura independent of the pulmonary texture?
Has this texture nothing in common with the membrane that surrounds
the bronchia? Is it not the same with the brain with relation to its
membranes, of the different parts of the eye, the ear, etc.?

When we study a function it is necessary carefully to consider in a
general manner, the compound organ that performs it; but when you
wish to know the properties and life of this organ, it is absolutely
necessary to decompose it. In the same way, if you seek only general
notions of anatomy, you can study each organ as a whole; but it is
essential to separate the textures, if you have a desire to analyze
with accuracy its intimate structure.


     CONSEQUENCES OF THE PRECEDING PRINCIPLES RELATIVE TO DISEASE

What I have been saying leads to important consequences, as it respects
those acute or chronic diseases that are local; for those which, like
most fevers, affect almost simultaneously every part, cannot be much
elucidated by the anatomy of systems. The first then will engage our
attention.

Since diseases are only alterations of the vital properties, and each
texture differs from the others in its properties, it is evident that
there must be a difference also in the diseases. In every organ, then,
composed of different textures, one may be diseased, while the others
remain sound; now this happens in a great many cases; let us take the
principal organs, for example.

1st. Nothing is more rare than affections of the mass of the
brain; nothing is more common than inflammation of the _tunica
arachnoides_ that covers it. 2d. Oftentimes one membrane of the
eye only is affected, the others preserving their ordinary degree of
vitality. 3d. In convulsions or paralysis of the muscles of the larynx,
the mucous surface is unaffected; and on the other hand, the muscles
perform their functions as usual in catarrhs of this surface. Both
these affections are foreign to the cartilages, and _vice versa_.
4th. We observe a variety of different alterations in the texture
of the pericardium, but hardly ever in that of the heart itself; it
remains sound while the other is inflamed. The ossification of the
common membrane of the red blood does not extend to the neighboring
textures. 5th. When the membrane of the bronchia is the seat of
catarrh, the pleura is hardly affected at all, and reciprocally in
pleurisy the first is scarcely ever altered. In peripneumonia, when an
enormous infiltration in the dead body shows the excessive inflammation
that has existed during life in the pulmonary texture, the serous and
mucous surfaces often appear not to have been affected. Those who open
dead know that they are frequently healthy in incipient phthisis.
6th. We speak of a bad stomach, a weak stomach; this most commonly
should be understood as applying to the mucous surface only. Whilst
this secretes with difficulty the nutritive juices, without which
digestion is impaired, the serous surface exhales as usual its fluid,
the muscular coat continues to contract, etc. In ascites, in which
the serous surface exhales more lymph than in a natural state, the
mucous oftentimes performs its functions perfectly well, etc. 7th.
All authors have said much of the inflammation of the stomach, the
intestines, the bladder, etc. For myself, I believe that this disease
rarely ever affects at first the whole of any of these organs, except
in the case where poison or some other deleterious substance acts upon
them. There are for the mucous surface of the stomach and intestines,
acute and chronic catarrhs; for the peritoneum serous inflammations;
perhaps even for the layer of organic muscles that separates the two
membranes, there is a particular kind of inflammation, though we have
as yet hardly anything certain upon this point; but the stomach, the
intestines, and the bladder are not suddenly affected with these
three diseases. A diseased texture can affect those near it, but the
primitive affection seizes only upon one. I have examined a great
number of bodies in which the peritoneum was inflamed either upon the
intestines, the stomach, the pelvis, or universally; now very often
when this affection is chronic, and almost always when it is acute,
the subjacent organs remain sound. I have never seen this membrane
exclusively diseased upon one organ, while that of neighboring ones
remain untouched; its affection is propagated more or less remotely.
I know not why authors have hardly ever spoken of its inflammation,
and have placed to the account of the subjacent viscera that which
most often belongs only to this. There are almost as many cases
of peritonitis as of pleurisy, and yet while these last have been
particularly noticed the others are almost entirely overlooked.
Oftentimes that part of the peritoneum corresponding to an organ,
is much inflamed; we see it in the case of the stomach; we observe
especially after the suppression of the lochia or the menses, that it
is the portion that lines the pelvis that is first affected. But soon
the affection becomes more or less general; at least examinations after
death prove it satisfactorily. 8th. Certainly the acute or chronic
catarrh of the bladder, or womb even, has nothing in common with the
inflammation of that portion of the peritoneum corresponding with
these organs. 9th. Every one knows that diseases of the periosteum
have oftentimes no connection with the bone, and _vice versa_,
that frequently the marrow is for a long time affected, while both the
others remain sound. There is no doubt that the osseous, medullary
and fibrous textures have their peculiar affections which we shall
not confound with the idea we may form of the diseases of the bones.
The same can be said of the intestines, of the stomach, etc., in
relation to their mucous, serous, muscular textures, etc. 10th. Though
the muscular and tendinous textures are combined in a muscle, their
diseases are very different. 11th. You must not think that the synovial
is subject to the same diseases as the ligaments that surround it, etc.

I think the more we observe diseases, and the more we examine bodies,
the more we shall be convinced of the necessity of considering local
diseases, not under the relations of the compound organs, which are
rarely ever affected as a whole, but under that of their different
textures, which are almost always attacked separately.

When the phenomena of disease are sympathetic, they follow the same
laws as when they arise from a direct affection. Much has been said
of the sympathies of the stomach, the intestines, the bladder, the
lungs, etc. But it is impossible to form an idea of them, if they
are referred to the organ as a whole, separate from the different
textures. 1st. When in the stomach, the fleshy fibres contract by the
influence of another organ and produce vomiting, they alone receive
the influence, which is not extended either to the serous or mucous
surfaces; if it were, they would be the seat, the one of exhalation,
the other of sympathetic exhalation and secretion. 2d. It is certain
that when the action of the liver is sympathetically increased, so
that it pours out more bile, the portion of peritoneum that covers it
does not throw out more serum, because it is not affected by it. It
is the same of the kidney, the pancreas, etc. 3d. For the same reason
the gastric organs upon which the peritoneum is spread do not partake
of the sympathetic influences that it experiences. I shall say as much
of the lungs in relation to the pleura, the brain in relation to the
_tunica arachnoides_, the heart to the pericardium, etc. 4th. It
is undeniable that in all sympathetic convulsions, the fleshy texture
alone is affected, and that the tendinous is not so at all. 5th. What
has the fibrous membrane of the testicles in common with the sympathies
of its peculiar texture? 6th. No doubt a number of sympathetic pains
that we refer to the bones, are seated exclusively in the marrow.

I could cite many other examples to prove, that it is not this or that
organ that sympathizes as a whole, but only this or that texture in
the organs; besides, this an immediate consequence of the nature of
sympathies. In fact the sympathies are but aberrations of the vital
properties; now these properties vary according to each texture; the
sympathies of these textures then would do the same.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 26: Translated from _Traité sur les Membranes_ (1800).]




                                 XXIV

                            AMADEO AVOGADRO

                               1776-1856


 _Avogadro, who continued the researches of Dalton and Gay-Lussac,
 was born in Turin, Italy, June 9, 1776. In 1796, after receiving the
 doctor’s degree in law from the University of Turin, he was employed
 by the government for the following ten years. He began his work in
 science in 1806 and three years later was made professor of physics at
 Vercelli. In 1811 he announced his famous law. According to Merz, since
 the time of Boyle “it had been known that equal volumes of different
 gases under equal pressure change their volumes equally if the
 pressure is varied equally, and it was also known that equal volumes
 of different gases under equal pressure change their volumes equally
 with equal rise of temperature. These facts suggested to Avogadro, and
 almost simultaneously to Ampère, the very simple assumption that this
 is owing to the fact that equal volumes of different gases contain an
 equal number of the smallest independent particles of matter. This is
 Avogadro’s celebrated hypothesis. It was the first step in the direct
 physical verification of the atomic view of matter.”_

 _In 1820 Avogadro became professor of physics at Turin University,
 where he remained for many years. He died July 9, 1856._


        THE MOLECULES IN GASES PROPORTIONAL TO THE VOLUMES[27]

                                  I.

M. Gay-Lussac has shown in an interesting Memoir (_Mémoires de la
Société d’Arcueil_, Tome II.) that gases always unite in a very
simple proportion by volume, and that when the result of the union is a
gas, its volume also is very simply related to those of its components.
But the quantitative proportions of substances in compounds seem only
to depend on the relative number of molecules which combine, and on the
number of composite molecules which result. It must then be admitted
that very simple relations also exist between the volumes of gaseous
substances and the numbers of simple or compound molecules which form
them. The first hypothesis to present itself in this connection, and
apparently even the only admissible one, is the supposition that the
number of integral molecules in any gases is always the same for equal
volumes, or always proportional to the volumes. Indeed, if we were
to suppose that the number of molecules contained in a given volume
were different for different gases, it would scarcely be possible
to conceive that the law regulating the distance of molecules could
give in all cases relations so simple as those which the facts just
detailed compel us to acknowledge between the volume and the number
of molecules. On the other hand, it is very well conceivable that
the molecules of gases being at such a distance that their mutual
attraction cannot be exercised, their varying attraction for caloric
may be limited to condensing a greater or smaller quantity around
them, without the atmosphere formed by this fluid having any greater
extent in the one case than in the other, and, consequently, without
the distance between the molecules varying; or, in other words, without
the number of molecules contained in a given volume being different.
Dalton, it is true, has proposed a hypothesis directly opposed to
this, namely, that the quantity of caloric is always the same for the
molecules of all bodies whatsoever in the gaseous state, and that the
greater or less attraction for caloric only results in producing a
greater or less condensation of this quantity around the molecules,
and thus varying the distance between the molecules themselves. But
in our present ignorance of the manner in which this attraction of
the molecules for caloric is exerted, there is nothing to decide
us _a priori_ in favour of the one of these hypotheses rather
than the other; and we should rather be inclined to adopt a neutral
hypothesis, which would make the distance between the molecules and
the quantities of caloric vary according to unknown laws, were it not
that the hypothesis we have just proposed is based on that simplicity
of relation between the volumes of gases on combination, which would
appear to be otherwise inexplicable.

Setting out from this hypothesis, it is apparent that we have the means
of determining very easily the relative masses of the molecules of
substances obtainable in the gaseous state, and the relative number
of these molecules in compounds; for the ratios of the masses of the
molecules are then the same as those of the densities of the different
gases at equal temperature and pressure, and the relative number of
molecules in a compound is given at once by the ratio of the volumes
of the gases that form it. For example, since the numbers 1.10359 and
0.07321 express the densities of the two gases oxygen and hydrogen
compared to that of atmospheric air as unity, and the ratio of the two
numbers consequently represents the ratio between the masses of equal
volumes of these two gases, it will also represent on our hypothesis
the ratio of the masses of their molecules. Thus the mass of the
molecule of oxygen will be about 15 times that of the molecule of
hydrogen, or, more exactly, as 15.074 to 1. In the same way the mass
of the molecule of nitrogen will be to that of hydrogen as 0.96913 to
0.07321, that is, as 13, or more exactly 13.238, to 1. On the other
hand, since we know that the ratio of the volumes of hydrogen and
oxygen in the formation of water is 2 to 1, it follows that water
results from the union of each molecule of oxygen with two molecules of
hydrogen. Similarly, according to the proportions by volume established
by M. Gay-Lussac for the elements of ammonia, nitrous oxide, nitrous
gas, and nitric acid, ammonia will result from the union of one
molecule of nitrogen with three of hydrogen, nitrous oxide from one
molecule of oxygen with two of nitrogen, nitrous gas from one molecule
of nitrogen with one of oxygen, and nitric acid from one of nitrogen
with two of oxygen.


                                  II.

There is a consideration which appears at first sight to be opposed to
the admission of our hypothesis with respect to compound substances.
It seems that a molecule composed of two or more elementary molecules
should have its mass equal to the sum of the masses of these molecules;
and that in particular, if in a compound one molecule of one substance
unites with two or more molecules of another substance, the number
of compound molecules should remain the same as the number of
molecules of the first substance. Accordingly, on our hypothesis when
a gas combines with two or more times its volume of another gas, the
resulting compound, if gaseous, must have a volume equal to that of
the first of these gases. Now, in general, this is not actually the
case. For instance, the volume of water in the gaseous state is, as
M. Gay-Lussac has shown, twice as great as the volume of oxygen which
enters into it, or, what comes to the same thing, equal to that of the
hydrogen instead of being equal to that of the oxygen. But a means
of explaining facts of this type in conformity with our hypothesis
presents itself naturally enough: we suppose, namely, that the
constituent molecules of any simple gas whatever (i. e., the molecules
which are at such a distance from each other that they cannot exercise
their mutual action) are not formed of a solitary elementary molecule,
but are made up of a certain number of these molecules united by
attraction to form a single one; and further, that when molecules of
another substance unite with the former to form a compound molecule,
the integral molecule which should result splits up into two or more
parts (or integral molecules) composed of half, quarter, &c., the
number of elementary molecules going to form the constituent molecule
of the first substance, combined with half, quarter, &c., the number of
constituent molecules of the second substance that ought to enter into
combination with one constituent molecule of the first substance (or,
what comes to the same thing, combined with a number equal to this last
of half-molecules, quarter-molecules, &c., of the second substance);
so that the number of integral molecules of the compound becomes
double, quadruple, &c., what it would have been if there had been no
splitting-up, and exactly what is necessary to satisfy the volume of
the resulting gas.

On reviewing the various compound gases most generally known, I only
find examples of duplication of the volume relatively to the volume of
that one of the constituents which combines with one or more volumes
of the other. We have already seen this for water. In the same way,
we know that the volume of ammonia gas is twice that of the nitrogen
which enters into it. M. Gay-Lussac has also shown that the volume of
nitrous oxide is equal to that of the nitrogen which forms part of
it, and consequently is twice that of the oxygen. Finally, nitrous
gas, which contains equal volumes of nitrogen and oxygen, has a
volume equal to the sum of the two constituent gases, that is to say,
double that of each of them. Thus in all these cases there must be a
division of the molecule into two; but it is possible that in other
cases the division might be into four, eight, &c. The possibility of
this division of compound molecules might have been conjectured _a
priori_; for otherwise the integral molecules of bodies composed
of several substances with a relatively large number of molecules,
would come to have a mass excessive in comparison with the molecules
of simple substances. We might therefore imagine that nature had some
means of bringing them back to the order of the latter, and the facts
have pointed out to us the existence of such means. Besides, there
is another consideration which would seem to make us admit in some
cases the division in question; for how could one otherwise conceive
a real combination between two gaseous substances uniting in equal
volumes without condensation, such as takes place in the formation of
nitrous gas? Supposing the molecules to remain at such a distance that
the mutual attraction of those of each gas could not be exercised,
we cannot imagine that a new attraction could take place between the
molecules of one gas and those of the other. But on the hypothesis
of division of the molecule, it is easy to see that the combination
really reduces two different molecules to one, and that there would be
contraction by the whole volume of one of the gases if each compound
molecule did not split up into two molecules of the same nature. M.
Gay-Lussac clearly saw that, according to the facts, the diminution of
volume on the combination of gases cannot represent the approximation
of their elementary molecules. The division of molecules on combination
explains to us how these two things may be made independent of each
other.


                                 III.

Dalton, on arbitrary suppositions as to the most likely relative number
of molecules in compounds, has endeavoured to fix ratios between the
masses of the molecules of simple substances. Our hypothesis, supposing
it well founded, puts us in a position to confirm or rectify his
results from precise data, and, above all, to assign the magnitude of
compound molecules according to the volumes of the gaseous compounds,
which depend partly on the division of molecules entirely unsuspected
by this physicist.

Thus Dalton supposes that water is formed by the union of hydrogen and
oxygen, molecule to molecule. From this, and from the ratio by weight
of the two components, it would follow that the mass of the molecule of
oxygen would be to that of hydrogen as 7-1/2 to 1 nearly, or, according
to Dalton’s evaluation, as 6 to 1. This ratio on our hypothesis is,
as we saw, twice as great, namely, as 15 to 1. As for the molecule of
water, its mass ought to be roughly expressed by 15 + 2 = 17 (taking
for unity that of hydrogen), if there were no division of the molecule
into two; but on account of this division it is reduced to half, 8-1/2,
or more exactly 8.537, as may also be found directly by dividing the
density of aqueous vapour 0.625 (Gay-Lussac) by the density of hydrogen
0.0732. This mass only differs from 7, that assigned to it by Dalton,
by the difference in the values for the composition of water; so that
in this respect Dalton’s result is approximately correct from the
combination of two compensating errors,--the error in the mass of the
molecule of oxygen, and his neglect of the division of the molecule.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 27: Translated from _Essai d’une manière de déterminer
les masses relatives des molécules élémentaires des corps,
et les proportions selon lesquelles elles entrent dans les
combinaisons_--_Journal de Physique_, (1811).]




                                  XXV

                           SIR HUMPHREY DAVY

                               1778-1829


 _Born December 17, 1778, in Cornwall, Sir Humphrey Davy was
 apprenticed in 1794 to a surgeon-apothecary at Penzance in whose
 service he became interested in chemistry. Made superintendent of a
 hospital in 1798, he had opportunities for gaining acquaintance with
 influential men who in turn recommended him to Count Rumford. Through
 the latter’s assistance he was appointed lecturer on chemistry at the
 newly-founded Royal Institution where, in spite of his unattractive
 appearance, he gained considerable reputation. In 1807 he advanced a
 theory which partly explained electrolysis; in the following year he
 discovered strontium and magnesium; and in 1809, chlorine. In 1812 he
 was knighted; and shortly after his marriage, in the same year, he
 injured an eye while experimenting and was compelled to interrupt his
 work for a short time. In 1815 he invented the safety-lamp used by
 miners. In 1818 he was created a baronet, and was elected President
 of the Royal Society in 1820. He died May 29, 1829, at Geneva,
 Switzerland, at the age of fifty-one._


 ON SOME NEW PHENOMENA OF CHEMICAL CHANGES PRODUCED BY ELECTRICITY[28]

                                              _Read November 19, 1807._

                             INTRODUCTION.

In the Bakerian Lecture which I had the honour of presenting to the
Royal Society last year, I described a number of decompositions
and chemical changes produced in substances of known composition by
electricity, and I ventured to conclude from the general principles
on which the phenomena were capable of being explained, that the new
methods of investigation promised to lead to a more intimate knowledge
than had hitherto been obtained, concerning the true elements of bodies.

This conjecture, then sanctioned only by strong analogies, I am now
happy to be able to support by some conclusive facts. In the course of
a laborious experimental application of the powers of electro-chemical
analysis, to bodies which have appeared simple when examined by common
chemical agents, or which at least have never been decomposed, it has
been my good fortune to obtain new and singular results.

Such of the series of experiments as are in a tolerably mature state,
and capable of being arranged in a connected order, I shall detail
in the following sections, particularly those which demonstrate the
decomposition and composition of the fixed alkalies, and the production
of the new and extraordinary bodies which constitute their bases.

In speaking of novel methods of investigation, I shall not fear to be
minute. When the common means of chemical research have been employed,
I shall mention only results. A historical detail of the progress
of the investigation, of all the difficulties that occurred, and of
the manner in which they were overcome, and of all the manipulations
employed, would far exceed the limits assigned to this Lecture. It is
proper to state, however, that when general facts are mentioned, they
are such only as have been deduced from processes carefully performed
and often repeated.


    ON THE METHODS USED FOR THE DECOMPOSITION OF THE FIXED ALKALIES

The researches I had made on the decomposition of acids, and of
alkaline and earthy neutral compounds, proved that the powers of
electrical decomposition were proportional to the strength of the
opposite electricities in the circuit, and to the conducting power and
degree of concentration of the materials employed.

In the first attempts, that I made on the decomposition of the fixed
alkalies, I acted upon aqueous solutions of potash and soda, saturated
at common temperatures, by the highest electrical power I could
command, and which was produced by a combination of Voltaic batteries
belonging to the Royal Institution, containing 24 plates of copper and
zinc of 12 inches square, 100 plates of 6 inches, and 150 of 4 inches
square, charged with solutions of alum and nitrous acid; but in these
cases, though there was a high intensity of action, the water of the
solutions alone was affected, and hydrogen and oxygen disengaged with
the production of much heat and violent effervescence.

The presence of water appearing thus to prevent any decomposition, I
used potash in igneous fusion. By means of a stream of oxygen gas from
a gasometer applied to the flame of a spirit lamp, which was thrown
on a platina spoon containing potash, this alkali was kept for some
minutes in a strong red heat, and in a state of perfect fluidity.
The spoon was preserved in communication with the positive side of
the battery of the power of 100 of 6 inches, highly charged; and the
connection from the negative side was made by a platina wire.

By this arrangement some brilliant phenomena were produced. The potash
appeared a conductor in a high degree, and as long as the communication
was preserved, a most intense light was exhibited at the negative wire,
and a column of flame, which seemed to be owing to the development of
combustible matter, arose from the point of contact.

When the order was changed, so that the platina spoon was made
negative, a vivid and constant light appeared at the opposite point:
there was no effect of inflammation round it; but aeriform globules,
which inflamed in the atmosphere, rose through the potash.

The platina, as might have been expected, was considerably acted upon;
and in the cases when it had been negative, in the highest degree.

The alkali was apparently dry in this experiment; and it seemed
probable that the inflammable matter arose from its decomposition.
The residual potash was unaltered; it contained indeed a number of
dark grey metallic particles, but these proved to be derived from the
platina.

I tried several experiments on the electrization of potash rendered
fluid by heat, with the hopes of being able to collect the combustible
matter, but without success; and I only attained my object by employing
electricity as the common agent for fusion and decomposition.

Though potash, perfectly dried by ignition, is a non-conductor, yet it
is rendered a conductor by a very slight addition of moisture, which
does not perceptibly destroy its aggregation; and in this state it
readily fuses and decomposes by strong electrical powers.

A small piece of pure potash, which had been exposed for a few seconds
to the atmosphere, so as to give conducting power to the surface, was
placed upon an insulated disc of platina, connected with the negative
side of the battery of the power of 250 of 6 and 4, in a state of
intense activity; and a platina wire, communicating with the positive
side, was brought in contact with the upper surface of the alkali. The
whole apparatus was in the open atmosphere.

Under these circumstances a vivid action was soon observed to take
place. The potash began to fuse at both its points of electrization.
There was a violent effervescence at the upper surface; at the lower,
or negative surface, there was no liberation of elastic fluid; but
small globules having a high metallic lustre, and being precisely
similar in visible characters to quicksilver, appeared, some of which
burnt with explosion and bright flame, as soon as they were formed, and
others remained, and were merely tarnished, and finally covered by a
white film which formed on their surfaces.

These globules, numerous experiments soon showed to be the substance
I was in search of, and a peculiar inflammable principle the basis
of potash. I found that the platina was in no way connected with the
result, except as the medium for exhibiting the electrical powers of
decomposition; and a substance of the same kind was produced when
pieces of copper, silver, gold, plumbago, or even charcoal were
employed for completing the circuit.

The phenomenon was independent of the presence of air; I found that it
took place when the alkali was in the vacuum of an exhausted receiver.

The substance was likewise produced from potash fused by means of
a lamp, in glass tubes confined by mercury, and furnished with
hermetically inserted platina wires by which the electrical action
was transmitted. But this operation could not be carried on for any
considerable time; the glass was rapidly dissolved by the action of
the alkali, and this substance soon penetrated through the body of the
tube.

Soda, when acted upon in the same manner as potash, exhibited an
analogous result; but the decomposition demanded greater intensity
of action in the batteries, or the alkali was required to be in much
thinner and smaller pieces. With the battery of 100 of 6 inches in full
activity I obtained good results from pieces of potash weighing from
40 to 70 grains, and of a thickness which made the distance of the
electrified metallic surfaces nearly a quarter of an inch; but with a
similar power it was impossible to produce the effects of decomposition
on pieces of soda of more than 15 or 20 grains in weight, and that only
when the distance between the wires was about 1/8 or 1/10 of an inch.

The substance produced from potash remained fluid at the temperature of
the atmosphere at the time of its production; that from soda, which was
fluid in the degree of heat of the alkali during its formation, became
solid on cooling, and appeared having the lustre of silver.

When the power of 250 was used, with a very high charge for the
decomposition of soda, the globules often burnt at the moment of their
formation, and sometimes violently exploded and separated into smaller
globules, which flew with great velocity through the air in a state of
vivid combustion, producing a beautiful effect of continued jets of
fire.


 THEORY OF THE DECOMPOSITION OF THE FIXED ALKALIES; THEIR COMPOSITION
                            AND PRODUCTION

As in all decompositions of compound substances which I had previously
examined, at the same time that combustible bases were developed at
the negative surface in the electrical circuit, oxygen was produced,
and evolved or carried into combination at the positive surface, it
was reasonable to conclude that this substance was generated in a
similar manner by the electrical action upon the alkalies; and a number
of experiments made above mercury, with the apparatus for excluding
external air, proved that this was the case.

When solid potash, or soda in its conducting state, was included
in glass tubes furnished with electrified platina wires, the new
substances were generated at the negative surfaces; the gas given out
at the other surface proved by the most delicate examination to be pure
oxygen; and unless an excess of water was present, no gas was evolved
from the negative surface.

In the synthetical experiments, a perfect coincidence likewise will be
found.

I mentioned that the metallic lustre of the substance from potash
immediately became destroyed in the atmosphere, and that a white crust
formed upon it. This crust I soon found to be pure potash, which
immediately deliquesced, and new quantities were formed, which in their
turn attracted moisture from the atmosphere till the whole globule
disappeared, and assumed the form of a saturated solution of potash.

When globules were placed in appropriate tubes containing common air
or oxygen gas confined by mercury, an absorption of oxygen took place;
a crust of alkali instantly formed upon the globule; but from the want
of moisture for its solution, the process stopped, the interior being
defended from the action of the gas.

With the substance from soda, the appearances and effects were
analogous.

When the substances were strongly heated, confined in given proportions
of oxygen, a rapid combustion with a brilliant white flame was
produced, and the metallic globules were found converted into a white
and solid mass, which in the case of the substance from potash was
found to be potash, and in the case of that from soda, soda.

Oxygen gas was absorbed in this operation, and nothing emitted which
affected the purity of the residual air.

The alkalies produced were apparently dry, or at least contained no
more moisture than might well be conceived to exist in the oxygen
gas absorbed; and their weights considerably exceeded those of the
combustible matters consumed.

The processes on which these conclusions are founded will be fully
described hereafter, when the minute details which are necessary will
be explained, and the proportions of oxygen, and of the respective
inflammable substances which enter into union to form the fixed
alkalies, will be given.

It appears, then, that in these facts there is the same evidence
for the decomposition of potash and soda into oxygen and two
peculiar substances, as there is for the decomposition of sulphuric
and phosphoric acids and the metallic oxides into oxygen and their
respective combustible bases.

In the analytical experiments, no substances capable of decomposition
are present but the alkalies and a minute portion of moisture; which
seems in no other way essential to the result, than in rendering them
conductors at the surface: for the new substances are not generated
till the interior, which is dry, begins to be fused; they explode when
in rising through the fused alkali they come in contact with the heated
moistened surface; they cannot be produced from crystallised alkalies,
which contain much water; and the effect produced by the electrization
of ignited potash, which contains no sensible quantity of water,
confirms the opinion of their formation independently of the presence
of this substance.

The combustible bases of the fixed alkalies seem to be repelled as
other combustible substances, by positively electrified surfaces, and
attracted by negatively electrified surfaces, and the oxygen follows
the contrary order; or the oxygen being naturally possessed of the
negative energy, and the bases of the positive, do not remain in
combination when either of them is brought into an electrical state
opposite to its natural one. In the synthesis, on the contrary, the
natural energies or attractions come in equilibrium with each other;
and when these are in a low state at common temperatures, a slow
combination is effected; but when they are exalted by heat, a rapid
motion is the result; and as in other like cases with the production of
fire.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 28: From the _Transactions of the Royal Society of
London_.]




                                 XXVI

                            MICHAEL FARADAY

                               1791-1867


 _Born on September 22, 1791, at Newington, Surrey, England,
 Michael Faraday was the son of a blacksmith. After an early and very
 elementary education, he was apprenticed in 1805 to a book-binder in
 whose service he read widely and thus educated himself. Developing an
 interest in physics, he attended the evening lectures of Sir Humphrey
 Davy who, in 1813, engaged him as an assistant. Seven years later he
 wrote a history of electro-magnetism and succeeded, in the same year,
 in getting a needle to rotate fully around a live wire. In 1823 he
 liquefied chlorine, an experiment which destroyed the old notion of the
 permanent distinction between gases and liquids. In 1831 he discovered
 magneto-electric induction and advanced the conception of “lines of
 magnetic force.” In 1845, in trying to send polarized rays of light
 through heavy magnetized glass, he found that the magnet’s action
 interrupted the passage of the light and that magnetization caused the
 plane of polarization to rotate. He died August 25, 1867._


                         ON FLUID CHLORINE[29]

                                                 _Read March 13, 1823._

It is well known that before the year 1810, the solid substance
obtained by exposing chlorine, as usually procured, to a low
temperature, was considered as the gas itself reduced into that form;
and that Sir Humphrey Davy first showed it to be a hydrate, the pure
dry gas not being considerable even at a temperature of 40° F.

I took advantage of the late cold weather to procure crystals of this
substance for the purpose of analysis. The results are contained
in a short paper in the Quarterly Journal of Science, Vol. XV. Its
composition is very nearly 27.7 chlorine, 72.3 water, or 1 proportional
of chlorine, and 10 of water.

The President of the Royal Society having honoured me by looking at
these conclusions, suggested, that an exposure of the substance to
heat under pressure, would probably lead to interesting results; the
following experiments were commenced at his request. Some hydrate
of chlorine was prepared, and being dried as well as could be by
pressure in bibulous paper, was introduced into a sealed glass tube,
the upper end of which was then hermetically closed. Being placed
in water at 60°, it underwent no change; but when put into water
at 100°, the substance fused, the tube became filled with a bright
yellow atmosphere, and, on examination, was found to contain two
fluid substances: the one, about three-fourths of the whole, was of
a faint yellow colour, having very much the appearance of water; the
remaining fourth was a heavy bright yellow fluid, lying at the bottom
of the former, without any apparent tendency to mix with it. As the
tube cooled, the yellow atmosphere condensed into more of the yellow
fluid, which floated in a film on the pale fluid, looking very like
chloride of nitrogen; and at 70° the pale portion congealed, although
even at 32° the yellow portion did not solidify. Heated up to 100° the
yellow fluid appeared to boil, and again produced the bright coloured
atmosphere.

By putting the hydrate into a bent tube, afterwards hermetically
sealed, I found it easy, after decomposing it by a heat of 100°, to
distil the yellow fluid to one end of the tube, and so separate it from
the remaining portion. In this way a more complete decomposition of the
hydrate was effected, and, when the whole was allowed to cool, neither
of the fluids solidified at temperatures above 34°, and the yellow
portion not even at 0°. When the two were mixed together they gradually
combined at temperatures below 60°, and formed the same solid substance
as that first introduced. If, when the fluids were separated, the tube
was cut in the middle, the parts flew asunder as if with an explosion,
the whole of the yellow portion disappeared, and there was a powerful
atmosphere of chlorine produced; the pale portion on the contrary
remained, and when examined, proved to be a weak solution of chlorine
in water, with a little muriatic acid, probably from the impurity of
the hydrate used. When that end of the tube in which the yellow fluid
lay was broken under a jar of water, there was an immediate production
of chlorine gas.

I at first thought that muriatic acid and euchlorine had been formed;
then, that two new hydrates of chlorine had been produced; but at
last I suspected that the chlorine had been entirely separated from
the water by the heat and condensed into a dry fluid by the mere
pressure of its own abundant vapour. If that were true, it followed,
that chlorine gas, when compressed, should be condensed into the
same fluid, and, as the atmosphere in the tube in which the fluid
lay was not very yellow at 50° or 60°, it seemed probable that the
pressure required was not beyond what could readily be obtained by a
condensing syringe. A long tube was therefore furnished with a cap and
stop-cock, then exhausted of air and filled with chlorine, and being
held vertically with the syringe upwards, air was forced in, which
thrust the chlorine to the bottom of the tube, and gave a pressure of
about 4 atmospheres. Being now cooled, there was an immediate deposit
in films, which appeared to be hydrate, formed by water contained in
the gas and vessels, but some of the yellow fluid was also produced.
As this however might also contain a portion of the water present,
a perfectly dry tub and apparatus were taken, and the chlorine left
for some time over a bath of sulphuric acid before it was introduced.
Upon throwing in air and giving pressure, there was now no solid film
formed, but the clear yellow fluid was deposited, and more abundantly
still upon cooling. After remaining some time it disappeared, having
gradually mixed with the atmosphere above it, but every repetition of
the experiment produced the same results.

Presuming that I had now a right to consider the yellow fluid as pure
chlorine in the liquid state, I proceeded to examine its properties,
as well as I could when obtained by heat from the hydrate. However
obtained, it always appears very limpid and fluid, and excessively
volatile at common pressure. A portion was cooled in its tube to 0°;
it remained fluid. The tube was then opened, when a part immediately
flew off, leaving the rest so cooled by the evaporation as to remain a
fluid under the atmospheric pressure. The temperature could not have
been higher than 40° in this case; as Sir Humphrey Davy has shown
that dry chlorine does not condense at that temperature under common
pressure. Another tube was opened at a temperature of 50°; a part of
the chlorine volatilised, and cooled the tube so much as to condense
the atmospheric vapour on it as ice.

A tube having the water at one end and the chlorine at the other was
weighed, and then cut in two; the chlorine immediately flew off, and
the loss being ascertained was found to be 1.6 grains: the water
left was examined and found to contain some chlorine: its weight was
ascertained to be 5.4 grains. These proportions, however, must not
be considered as indicative of the true composition of hydrate of
chlorine; for, from the mildness of the weather during the time when
these experiments were made, it was impossible to collect the crystals
of hydrate, press, and transfer them, without losing much chlorine; and
it is also impossible to separate the chlorine and water in the tube
perfectly, or keep them separate, as the atmosphere within will combine
with the water, and gradually reform the hydrate.

Before cutting the tube, another tube had been prepared exactly like it
in form and size, and a portion of water introduced into it, as near as
the eye could judge, of the same bulk as the fluid chlorine: this water
was found to weigh 1.2 grains; a result, which, if it may be trusted,
would give the specific gravity of fluid chlorine as 1.33; and from its
appearance in, and on water, this cannot be far wrong.


                      ELECTRICITY FROM MAGNETISM

                                              _Read November 24, 1831._

1. The power which electricity of tension possesses of causing an
opposite electrical state in its vicinity has been expressed by the
general term Induction; which, as it has been received into scientific
language, may also, with propriety, be used in the same general sense
to express the power which electrical currents may possess of inducing
any particular state upon matter in their immediate neighborhood,
otherwise indifferent. It is with this meaning that I purpose using it
in the present paper.

2. Certain effects of the induction of electrical currents have already
been recognized and described: as those of magnetization; Ampère’s
experiments of bringing a copper disc near to a flat spiral; his
repetition with electro-magnets of Arago’s extraordinary experiments,
and perhaps a few others. Still it appeared unlikely that these
could be all the effects which induction by currents could produce;
especially as, upon dispensing with iron, almost the whole of them
disappear, whilst yet an infinity of bodies, exhibiting definite
phenomena of induction with electricity of tension still remain to be
acted upon by the induction of electricity in motion.

3. Further: whether Ampère’s beautiful theory were adopted, or any
other, or whatever reservation were mentally made, still it appeared
very extraordinary, that, as every electric current was accompanied by
a corresponding intensity of magnetic action at right angles to the
current, good conductors of electricity, when placed within the sphere
of this action, should not have any current induced through them, or
some sensible effect produced equivalent in force to such a current.

4. These considerations, with their consequence, the hope of obtaining
electricity from ordinary magnetism, have stimulated me at various
times to investigate experimentally the inductive effect of electric
currents. I lately arrived at positive results; and not only had my
hopes fulfilled, but obtained a key which appeared to me to open out a
full explanation of Arago’s magnetic phenomena, and also to discover a
new state, which may probably have great influence in some of the most
important effects of electric currents.

5. These results I purpose describing, not as they were obtained, but
in such a manner as to give the most concise view of the whole.


                EVOLUTION OF ELECTRICITY FROM MAGNETISM

27. A welded ring was made of soft round bar-iron, the metal being
seven-eighths of an inch in thickness, and the ring six inches in
external diameter. Three helices were put round one part of this ring,
each containing about twenty-four feet of copper wire one-twentieth
of an inch thick; they were insulated from the iron and each other,
and superposed in the manner before described (6), occupying about
nine inches in length upon the ring. They could be used separately or
conjointly; the group may be distinguished by the letter A. On the
other part of the ring about sixty feet of similar copper wire in two
pieces were applied in the same manner, forming a helix B, which had
the same common direction with the helices of A, but being separated
from it at each extremity by about half an inch of the uncovered iron.

28. The helix B, was connected by copper wires with a galvanometer
three feet from the ring. The helices of A were connected end to
end so as to form one common helix, the extremities of which were
connected with a battery of ten pairs of plates four inches square. The
galvanometer was immediately affected, and to a degree far beyond what
has been described when with a battery of tenfold power helices without
iron were used (10); but though the contact was continued, the effect
was not permanent, for the needle soon came to rest in its natural
position, as if quite indifferent to the attached electro-magnetic
arrangement. Upon breaking the contact with the battery, the needle
was again powerfully deflected, but in the contrary direction to that
induced in the first instance.

29. Upon arranging the apparatus so that B should be out of use, the
galvanometer be connected with one of the three wires of A (27), and
the other two made into a helix through which the current from the
trough (28) was passed, similar but rather more powerful effects were
produced.

30. When the battery contact was made in one direction, the
galvanometer-needle was deflected on the one side; if made in the other
direction, the deflection was on the other side. The deflection on
breaking the battery contact was always the reverse of that produced
by completing it. The deflection on making a battery contact always
indicated an induced current in the opposite direction to that from
the battery; but on breaking the contact the deflection indicated
an induced current in the same direction as that of the battery.
No making or breaking of the contact at B side, or in any part of
the galvanometer circuit, produced any effect at the galvanometer.
No continuance of the battery current caused any deflection of the
galvanometer-needle. As the above results are common to all these
experiments, and to similar ones with ordinary magnets to be hereafter
detailed, they need not be again particularly described.

31. Upon using the power of 100 pairs of plates (10) with this ring,
the impulse at the galvanometer, when contact was completed or broken,
was so great as to make the needle spin round rapidly four or five
times, before the air and terrestrial magnetism could reduce its motion
to mere oscillation.

39. But as might be supposed that in all the preceding experiments of
this section, it was by some peculiar effect taking place during the
formation of the magnet, and not by its mere virtual approximation,
that the momentary induced current was excited, the following
experiment was made. All the similar ends of the compound hollow
helix (34) were bound together by copper wire, forming two general
terminations, and these were connected with the galvanometer. The soft
iron cylinder (34) was removed, and a cylindrical magnet three-quarters
of an inch in diameter and eight inches and a half in length, used
instead. One end of this magnet was introduced into the axis of the
helix and then, the galvanometer-needle being stationary, the magnet
was suddenly thrust in; immediately the needle was deflected in the
same direction as if the magnet had been formed by either of the two
preceding processes (34, 36). Being left in, the needle resumed its
first position, and then the magnet being withdrawn the needle was
deflected in the opposite direction. These effects were not great; but
by introducing and withdrawing the magnet, so that the impulse each
time should be added to those previously communicated to the needle,
the latter could be made to vibrate through an arc of 180° or more.

40. In this experiment the magnet must not be passed entirely through
the helix, for then a second action occurs. When the magnet is
introduced the needle at the galvanometer is deflected in a certain
direction; but being in, whether it be pushed quite through or
withdrawn, the needle is deflected in a direction the reverse of that
previously produced. When the magnet is passed in and through at one
continuous motion, the needle moves one way, is then suddenly stopped,
and finally moves the other way.

41. If such a hollow helix as that described (34) be laid east and west
(or in any other constant position), and a magnet be retained east and
west, its marked pole always being one way; then whichever end of the
helix the magnet goes in at, and consequently whichever pole of the
magnet enters first, still the needle is deflected the same way: on the
other hand, whichever direction is followed in withdrawing the magnet,
the deflection is constant, but contrary to that due to its entrance.

57. The various experiments of this section prove, I think, most
completely the production of electricity from ordinary magnetism.
That its intensity should be very feeble and quantity small,
cannot be considered wonderful, when it is remembered that like
thermo-electricity it is evolved entirely within the substance of
metals retaining all their conducting power. But an agent which is
conducted along the metallic wires in the manner described; which,
whilst so passing possesses the peculiar magnetic actions and force
of a current of electricity; which can agitate and convulse the limbs
of a frog; and which, finally, can produce a spark by its discharge
through charcoal (32), can only be electricity. As all the effects can
be produced by ferruginous electro-magnets (34), there is no doubt that
arrangements like the magnets of Professors Moll, Henry, Ten Eyke, and
others, in which as many as two thousand pounds have been lifted, may
be used for these experiments; in which case not only a brighter spark
may be obtained, but wires also ignited, and, as the current can pass
liquids (23), chemical action be produced. These effects are still
more likely to be obtained when the magneto-electric arrangements to
be explained in the fourth section are excited by the powers of such
apparatus.

58. The similarity of action, almost amounting to identity, between
common magnets and either electro-magnets or volta-electric currents,
is strikingly in accordance with and confirmatory of M. Ampère’s
theory, and furnishes powerful reasons for believing that the action
is the same in both cases; but, as a distinction in language is still
necessary, I propose to call the agency thus exerted by ordinary
magnets, magneto-electric or magnelectric induction (26).

59. The only difference which powerfully strikes the attention as
existing between volta-electric and magneto-electric induction, is the
suddenness of the former, and the sensible time required by the latter:
but even in this early state of investigation there are circumstances
which seem to indicate, that upon further inquiry this difference will,
as a philosophical distinction, disappear (68).


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 29: This excerpt and the one following are from the
_Transactions of the Royal Society of London_.]




                                 XXVII

                             JOSEPH HENRY

                               1797-1878


 _Born at Albany, New York, December 17, 1797, Joseph Henry prepared
 for the profession of medicine, but an appointment as an assistant
 engineer on the state road diverted his interests toward mechanics.
 In 1826 he was appointed instructor of physics at Albany Institute,
 now the Albany Boys Academy, where he conducted his first experiments
 in electricity. In 1828 he first produced a strong electro-magnet by
 winding fine insulated wire around a piece of soft iron, and soon
 succeeded in exciting his electro-magnet at a distance by the use of
 high intensity batteries made up of many cells. Demonstrating that
 the number of coils of fine wire about a magnet had as much influence
 as the intensity of the current and that after winding many coils
 around the soft iron magnet it could still be made magnetic, he
 suggested the principle which Morse later used in the telegraph. In
 1832 he discovered that in a long conductor the primary current, by an
 induction upon itself, produced a number of secondary currents that
 greatly increased the intensity of the discharge._

 _He was appointed professor of natural philosophy at Princeton
 University in 1832 and became secretary of the Smithsonian Institution
 in 1846. He died in Washington, May 13, 1878._


     ON THE PRODUCTION OF CURRENTS AND SPARKS OF ELECTRICITY FROM
                             MAGNETISM[30]

Although the discoveries of Oersted, Arago, Faraday, and others, have
placed the intimate connection of electricity and magnetism in a most
striking point of view, and although the theory of Ampère has referred
all the phenomena of both these departments of science to the same
general laws, yet until lately one thing remained to be proved by
experiment, in order more fully to establish their identity; namely,
the possibility of producing electrical effects from magnetism.
It is well known that surprising magnetic results can readily be
obtained from electricity, and at first sight it might be supposed
that electrical effects could with equal facility be produced from
magnetism; but such has not been found to be the case, for although the
experiment has often been attempted, it has nearly as often failed.

It early occurred to me that if galvanic magnets on my plan were
substituted for ordinary magnets, in researches of this kind, more
success might be expected. Besides their great powers these magnets
possess other properties, which render them important instruments in
the hands of the experimenter; their polarity can be instantaneously
reversed, and their magnetism suddenly destroyed or called into full
action, according as the occasion may require. With this view, I
commenced, last August, the construction of a much larger galvanic
magnet than, to my knowledge, had before been attempted, and also made
preparations for a series of experiments with it on a large scale,
in reference to the production of electricity from magnetism. I was,
however, at that time accidentally interrupted in the prosecution of
these experiments, and have not been able since to resume them until
within the last few weeks, and then on a much smaller scale than was
at first intended. In the meantime, it has been announced in the 117th
number of the _Library of Useful Knowledge_, that the result
so much sought after has at length been found by Mr. Faraday of the
Royal Institution. It states that he has established the general fact,
that when a piece of metal is moved in any direction, in front of a
magnetic pole, electrical currents are developed in the metal, which
pass in a direction at right angles to its own motion, and also that
the application of this principle affords a complete and satisfactory
explanation of the phenomena of magnetic rotation. No detail is given
of the experiments, and it is somewhat surprising that results so
interesting, and which certainly form a new era in the history of
electricity and magnetism, should not have been more fully described
before this time in some of the English publications; the only mention
I have found of them is the following short account from the _Annals
of Philosophy_ for April, under the head of Proceedings of the Royal
Institution:

 “Feb. 17.--Mr. Faraday gave an account of the first two parts of
 his researches in electricity; namely, Volta-electric induction and
 magneto-electric induction. If two wires, A and B, be placed side by
 side, but not in contact, and a Voltaic current be passed through
 A, there is instantly a current produced by induction in B, in the
 opposite direction. Although the principal current in A be continued,
 still the secondary current in B is not found to accompany it, for
 it ceases after the first moment, but when the principal current is
 stopped, then there is a second current produced in B, in the opposite
 direction to that of the first produced by the inductive action, or in
 the same direction as that of the principal current.

 “If a wire, connected at both extremities with a galvanometer,
 be coiled in the form of a helix around a magnet, no current of
 electricity takes place in it. This is an experiment which has been
 made by various persons hundreds of times, in the hope of evolving
 electricity from magnetism, and in other cases in which the wishes of
 the experimenter and the facts are opposed to each other, has given
 rise to very conflicting conclusions. But if the magnet be withdrawn
 from or introduced into such a helix, a current of electricity is
 produced whilst the magnet is in motion, and is rendered evident by
 the deflection of the galvanometer. If a single wire be passed by a
 magnetic pole, a current of electricity is induced through it which
 can be rendered sensible.”

Before having any knowledge of the method given in the above account, I
had succeeded in producing electrical effects in the following manner,
which differs from that employed by Mr. Faraday, and which appears to
me to develop some new and interesting facts. A piece of copper wire,
about thirty feet long and covered with elastic varnish, was closely
coiled around the middle of the soft iron armature of the galvanic
magnet described in Vol. XIX of the _American Journal of Science_,
and which, when excited, will readily sustain between six hundred and
seven hundred pounds. The wire was wound upon itself so as to occupy
only about one inch of the length of the armature which is seven inches
in all. The armature, thus furnished with the wire, was placed in its
proper position across the ends of the galvanic magnet, and there
fastened so that no motion could take place. The two protecting ends
of the helix were dipped into two cups of mercury, and there connected
with a distant galvanometer by means of two copper wires, each about
forty feet long. This arrangement being completed, I stationed myself
near the galvanometer and directed an assistant at a given word to
immerse suddenly, in a vessel of dilute acid, the galvanic battery
attached to the magnet. At the instant of immersion, the north end
of the needle was deflected 30° to the west, indicating a current
of electricity from the helix surrounding the armature. The effect,
however, appeared only as a single impulse, for the needle, after a few
oscillations, resumed its former undisturbed position in the magnetic
meridian, although the galvanic action of the battery, and consequently
the magnetic power, was still continued. I was, however, much surprised
to see the needle suddenly deflected from a state of rest to about 20°
to the east, or in a contrary direction when the battery was withdrawn
from the acid, and again deflected to the west when it was re-immersed.
This operation was repeated many times in succession, and uniformly
with the same result, the armature the whole time remaining immovably
attached to the poles of the magnet, no motion being required to
produce the effect, as it appeared to take place only in consequence of
the instantaneous development of the magnetic action in one, and the
sudden cessation of it in the other.

This experiment illustrates most strikingly the reciprocal action of
the two principles of electricity and magnetism, if indeed it does not
establish their absolute identity. In the first place, magnetism is
developed in the soft iron of the galvanic magnet by the action of the
currents of electricity from the battery, and secondly, the armature,
rendered magnetic by contact with the poles of the magnet, induces in
its turn currents of electricity in the helix which surrounds it; we
have thus, as it were, electricity converted into magnetism and this
magnetism again into electricity.

Another fact was observed which is somewhat interesting, inasmuch as it
serves in some respects to generalize the phenomena. After the battery
had been withdrawn from the acid, and the needle of the galvanometer
suffered to come to a state of rest after the resulting deflection, it
was again deflected in the same direction by partially detaching the
armature from the poles of the magnet to which it continued to adhere
from the action of the residual magnetism, and in this way, a series of
deflections, all in the same direction, was produced by merely slipping
off the armature by degrees until the contact was entirely broken. The
following extract from the register of the experiments exhibits the
relative deflections observed in one experiment of this kind.

At the instant of immersion of the battery, deflection 40° west.

At the instant of emersion of the battery, deflection 18° east.

Armature partially detached, deflection 7° east.

Armature entirely detached, deflection 12° west.

The effect was reversed in another experiment, in which the needle was
turned to the west in a series of deflections by dipping the battery
but a small distance into the acid at first and afterwards immersing it
by degrees.

From the foregoing facts it appears that a current of electricity is
produced, for an instant, in a helix of copper wire surrounding a piece
of soft iron whenever magnetism is induced in the iron; and a current
in an opposite direction when the magnetic action ceases; also that an
instantaneous current in one or the other direction accompanies every
change in the magnetic intensity of the iron.

Since reading the account before given of Mr. Faraday’s method of
producing electrical currents I have attempted to combine the effects
of motion and induction; for this purpose a rod of soft iron ten inches
long and one inch and a quarter in diameter, was attached to a common
turning lathe, and surrounded with four helices of copper wire in such
a manner that it could be suddenly and powerfully magnetized, while
in rapid motion, by transmitting galvanic currents through three of
the helices; the fourth being connected with the distant galvanometer
was intended to transmit the current of induced electricity; all the
helices were stationary while the iron rod revolved on its axis within
them. From a number of trials in succession, first with the rod in one
direction, then in the opposite, and next in a state of rest, it was
concluded that no perceptible effect was produced on the intensity of
the magneto-electric current by a rotary motion of the iron combined
with its sudden magnetization.

The same apparatus, however, furnished the means of measuring
separately the relative power of motion and induction in producing
electrical currents. The iron rod was first magnetized by currents
through the helices attached to the battery and while in this state
one of its ends was quickly introduced into the helix connected with
the galvanometer; the deflection of the needle in this case was
seven degrees. The end of the rod was next introduced into the same
helix while in its natural state and then suddenly magnetized; the
deflection in this instance amounted to thirty degrees, showing a great
superiority in the method of induction.

The next attempt was to increase the magneto-electric effect while the
magnetic power remained the same, and in this I was more successful.
Two iron rods six inches long and one inch in diameter were each
surrounded by two helices and then placed perpendicularly on the
face of the armature, and between it and the poles of the magnet,
so that each rod formed, as it were, a prolongation of the poles,
and to these the armature adhered when the magnet was excited. With
this arrangement, a current from one helix produced a deflection of
thirty-seven degrees; from two helices both on the same rod, fifty-two
degrees, and from three fifty-nine degrees; but when four helices
were used, the deflection was only fifty-five degrees, and when to
these were added the helix of smaller wire around the armature, the
deflection was no more than thirty degrees. This result may perhaps
have been somewhat affected by the want of proper insulation in the
several spires of the helices; it, however, establishes the fact that
an increase in the electric current is produced by using at least
two or three helices instead of one. The same principle was applied
to another arrangement which seems to afford the maximum of electric
development from a given magnetic power; in place of the two pieces of
iron and the armature used in the last experiments, the poles of the
magnet were connected by a single rod of iron, bent into the form of a
horse-shoe, and its extremities filed perfectly flat so as to come in
perfect contact with the faces of the poles; around the middle of the
arch of this horse-shoe, two strands of copper wire were tightly coiled
one over the other. A current from one of these helices deflected the
needle one hundred degrees, and when both were used the needle was
deflected with such force as to make a complete circuit. But the most
surprising effect was produced when, instead of passing the current
through the long wires to the galvanometer, the opposite ends of the
helices were held nearly in contact with each other, and the magnet
suddenly excited; in this case a small but vivid spark was seen to pass
between the ends of the wires, and this effect was repeated as often as
the state of intensity of the magnet was changed.

In these experiments the connection of the battery with the wires from
the magnet was not formed by soldering, but by two cups of mercury,
which permitted the galvanic action on the magnet to be instantaneously
suspended and the polarity to be changed and rechanged without removing
the battery from the acid; a succession of vivid sparks was obtained
by rapidly interrupting and forming the communication by means of one
of these cups; but the greatest effect was produced when the magnetism
was entirely destroyed and instantaneously reproduced by a change of
polarity.

It appears from the May number of the _Annals of Philosophy_ that
I have been anticipated in this experiment of drawing sparks from the
magnet by Mr. James D. Forbes of Edinburgh, who obtained a spark on the
30th of March; my experiment being made during the last two weeks of
June. A simple notification of his result is given, without any account
of the experiment, which is reserved for a communication to the Royal
Society of Edinburgh; my result is therefore entirely independent of
his and was undoubtedly obtained by a different process.


           ELECTRICAL SELF-INDUCTION IN A LONG HELICAL WIRE

I have made several other experiments in relation to the same subject,
but which more important duties will not permit me to verify in time
for this paper. I may, however, mention one fact which I have not seen
noticed in any work, and which appears to me to belong to the same
class of phenomena as those before described; it is this: when a small
battery is moderately excited by diluted acid, and its poles, which
should be terminated by cups of mercury, are connected by a copper
wire not more than a foot in length, no spark is perceived when the
connection is either formed or broken; but if a wire thirty or forty
feet long be used instead of the short wire, though no spark will be
perceptible when the connection is made, yet when it is broken by
drawing one end of the wire from its cup of mercury, a vivid spark
is produced. If the action of the battery be very intense, a spark
will be given by the short wire; in this case it is only necessary to
wait a few minutes until the action partially subsides, and until no
more sparks are given from the short wire; if the long wire be now
substituted a spark will again be obtained. The effect appears somewhat
increased by coiling the wire into a helix; it seems also to depend in
some measure on the length and thickness of the wire. I can account for
these phenomena only by supposing the long wire to become charged with
electricity, which by its reaction on itself projects a spark when the
connection is broken.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 30: Silliman’s _American Journal of Science_, July,
1832, Vol. XXII, pp. 403-408; _Scientific Writings_, Vol. I., p.
73.]




                                XXVIII

                           SIR CHARLES LYELL

                               1797-1875


 _Sir Charles Lyell, the son of a Scottish botanist of literary
 tastes, was born at Kinnordy, Scotland, November 14, 1797. He went to
 Oxford University, from which he graduated in 1819. He was admitted to
 the bar in 1825. In 1827 he abandoned law for geology, and published
 his “Principles of Geology” in 1830-1833. Lyell’s thesis was that
 all the past changes of the earth were explainable by forces now
 operative--an idea which underlies modern geology. He published his
 “Antiquity of Man” in 1863, providing proofs of man’s long existence
 on earth and thus contributing to the establishment of the Darwinian
 theory. He died February 22, 1875._


 UNIFORMITY IN THE SERIES OF PAST CHANGES IN THE ANIMATE AND INANIMATE
                               WORLD[31]


_Origin of the doctrine of alternate periods of repose and
disorder._--It has been truly observed that when we arrange the
fossiliferous formations in chronological order, they constitute
a broken and defective series of monuments; we pass without any
intermediate gradations from systems of strata which are horizontal, to
other systems which are highly inclined--from rocks of peculiar mineral
composition to others which have a character wholly distinct--from one
assemblage of organic remains to another, in which frequently nearly
all the species, and a large part of the genera, are different. These
violations of continuity are so common as to constitute in most regions
the rule rather than the exception, and they have been considered by
many geologists as conclusive in favour of sudden revolutions in the
inanimate and animate world. We have already seen that according to
the speculations of some writers, there have been in the past history
of the planet alternate periods of tranquility and convulsion, the
former enduring for ages, and resembling the state of things now
experienced by man; the other brief, transient, and paroxysmal, giving
rise to new mountains, seas, and valleys, annihilating one set of
organic beings and ushering in the creation of another.

It will be the object of the present chapter to demonstrate that
these theoretical views are not borne out by a fair interpretation of
geological monuments. It is true that in the solid framework of the
globe we have a chronological chain of natural records, many links of
which are wanting: but a careful consideration of all the phenomena
leads to the opinion that the series was originally defective--that
it has been rendered still more so by time--that a great part of what
remains is inaccessible to man, and even of that fraction which is
accessible nine-tenths or more are to this day unexplored.

The readiest way, perhaps, of persuading the reader that we may
dispense with great and sudden revolutions in the geological order
of events is by showing him how a regular and uninterrupted series
of changes in the animate and inanimate world must give rise to such
breaks in the sequence, and such unconformability of stratified rocks,
as are usually thought to imply convulsions and catastrophes. It is
scarcely necessary to state that the order of events thus assumed to
occur, for the sake of illustration, should be in harmony with all
the conclusions legitimately drawn by geologists from the structure
of the earth, and must be equally in accordance with the changes
observed by man to be now going on in the living as well as in the
inorganic creation. It may be necessary in the present state of science
to supply some part of the assumed course of nature hypothetically;
but if so, this must be done without any violation of probability,
and always consistently with the analogy of what is known both of the
past and present economy of our system. Although the discussion of so
comprehensive a subject must carry the beginner far beyond his depth,
it will also, it is hoped, stimulate his curiosity, and prepare him to
read some elementary treatises on geology with advantage, and teach
him the bearing on that science of the changes now in progress on the
earth. At the same time it may enable him the better to understand the
intimate connection between the Second and Third Books of this work,
one of which is occupied with the changes of the inorganic, the latter
with those of the organic creation.

In pursuance, then, of the plan above proposed, I will consider
in this chapter, first, the laws which regulate the denudation of
strata and the deposition of sediment; secondly, those which govern
the fluctuation in the animate world; and thirdly, the mode in which
subterranean movements affect the earth’s crust.


_Uniformity of change considered, first, in reference to denudation
and sedimentary deposition._--First, in regard to the laws governing
the deposition of new strata. If we survey the surface of the globe,
we immediately perceive that it is divisible into areas of deposition
and non-deposition; or, in other words, at any given time there are
spaces which are the recipients, others which are not the recipients,
of sedimentary matter. No new strata, for example, are thrown down on
dry land, which remains the same from year to year; whereas, in many
parts of the bottom of seas and lakes, mud, sand, and pebbles are
annually spread out by rivers and currents. There are also great masses
of limestone growing in some seas, chiefly composed of corals and
shells, or, as in the depths of the Atlantic, of chalky mud made up of
foraminifera and diatomaceæ.

As to the dry land, so far from being the receptacle of fresh
accessions of matter, it is exposed almost everywhere to waste away.
Forests may be as dense and lofty as those of Brazil, and may swarm
with quadrupeds, birds, and insects, yet at the end of thousands of
years one layer of black mould a few inches thick may be the sole
representative of those myriads of trees, leaves, flowers, and fruits,
those innumerable bones and skeletons of birds, quadrupeds, and
reptiles, which tenanted the fertile region. Should this land be at
length submerged, the waves of the sea may wash away in a few hours
the scanty covering of mould, and it may merely import a darker shade
of colour to the next stratum of marl, sand, or other matter newly
thrown down. So also at the bottom of the ocean where no sediment is
accumulating, seaweed, zoophytes, fish, and even shells, may multiply
for ages and decompose, leaving no vestige of their form or substance
behind. Their decay, in water, although more slow, is as certain and
eventually as complete as in the open air. Nor can they be perpetuated
for indefinite periods in a fossil state, unless imbedded in some
matrix which is impervious to water, or which at least does not allow
a free percolation of that fluid, impregnated as it usually is, with
a slight quantity of carbonic or other acid. Such a free percolation
may be prevented either by the mineral nature of the matrix itself,
or by the superposition of an impermeable stratum; but if unimpeded,
the fossil shell or bone will be dissolved and removed, particle after
particle, and thus entirely effaced, unless petrification or the
substitution of some mineral for the organic matter happen to take
place.

That there has been land as well as sea at all former geological
periods, we know from the fact that fossil trees and terrestrial plants
are imbedded in rocks of every age, except those which are so ancient
as to be very imperfectly known to us. Occasionally lacrustine and
fluviatile shells, or the bones of amphibious or land reptiles, point
to the same conclusion. The existence of dry land at all periods of the
past implies, as before mentioned, the partial deposition of sediment,
or its limitation to certain areas; and the next point to which I shall
call the reader’s attention is the shifting of these areas from one
region to another.

First, then, variations in the site of sedimentary deposition are
brought about independently of subterranean movements. There is always
a slight change from year to year, or from century to century. The
sediment of the Rhone, for example, thrown in the Lake of Geneva, is
now conveyed to a spot a mile and a half distant from that where it
accumulated in the tenth century, and six miles from the point where
the delta began originally to form. We may look forward to the period
when this lake will be filled up, and then the distribution of the
transported matter will be suddenly altered, for the mud and sand
brought down from the Alps will thenceforth, instead of being deposited
near Geneva, be carried nearly 200 miles southwards, where the Rhone
enters the Mediterranean.

In the deltas of large rivers, such as those of the Ganges and Indus,
the mud is first carried down for many centuries through one arm,
and on this being stopped up it is discharged by another, and may
then enter the sea at a point 50 or 100 miles distant from its first
receptacle. The direction of marine currents is also liable to be
changed by various accidents, as by the heaping up of new sandbanks, or
the wearing away of cliffs and promontories.

But, secondly, all these causes of fluctuation in the sedimentary areas
are entirely subordinate to those great upward or downward movements
of lands, which will be presently spoken of, as prevailing over large
tracts of the globe. By such elevation or subsidence certain spaces
are gradually submerged, or made gradually to emerge: in the one case
sedimentary deposition may be suddenly renewed after having been
suspended for one or more geological periods, in the other as suddenly
made to cease after having continued for ages.

If deposition be renewed after a long interval, the new strata will
usually differ greatly from the sedimentary rocks previously formed
in the same place, and especially if the older rocks have suffered
derangement, which implies a change in the physical geography of the
district since the previous conveyance of sediment to the same spot. It
may happen, however, that, even where the two groups, the superior and
the inferior, are horizontal and conformable to each other, they may
still differ entirely in mineral character, because, since the origin
of the older formation, the geography of some distant country has
been altered. In that country rocks before concealed may have become
exposed by denudation; volcanoes may have burst out and covered the
surface with scoriæ and lava; or new lakes, intercepting the sediment
previously conveyed from the upper country, may have been formed by
subsidence; and other fluctuations may have occurred, by which the
materials brought down from thence by rivers to the sea have acquired a
distinct mineral character.

It is well known that the stream of the Mississippi is charged with
sediment of a different colour from that of the Arkansas and Red
Rivers, which are tinged with red mud, derived from rocks of porphyry
and red gypseous clays in “the far west.” The waters of the Uruguay,
says Darwin, draining a granitic country, are clear and black, those
of the Parana, red. The mud with which the Indus is loaded, says
Burnes, is of a clayey hue, that of the Chenab, on the other hand, is
reddish, that of the Sutlej is more pale. The same causes which make
these several rivers, sometimes situated at no great distance the one
from the other, to differ greatly in the character of their sediment,
will make the waters draining the same country at different epochs,
especially before and after great revolutions in physical geography,
to be entirely dissimilar. It is scarcely necessary to add that marine
currents will be affected in an analogous manner in consequence of the
formation of new shoals, the emergence of new islands, the subsidence
of others, the gradual waste of neighbouring coasts, the growth of
new deltas, the increase of coral reefs, volcanic eruptions, and other
changes.


_Uniformity of change considered, secondly, in reference to the
living creation._--Secondly, in regard to the vicissitudes of
the living creation, all are agreed that the successive groups of
sedimentary strata found in the earth’s new crust are not only
dissimilar in mineral composition for reasons above alluded to, but are
likewise distinguishable from each other by their organic remains. The
general inference drawn from the study and comparison of the various
groups, arranged in chronological order, is this: that at successive
periods distinct tribes of animals and plants have inhabited the land
and waters, and that the organic types of the newer formations are more
analogous to species now existing than those of more ancient rocks. If
we then turn to the present state of the animate creation, and inquire
whether it has now become fixed and stationary, we discover that, on
the contrary, it is in a state of continual flux--that there are many
causes in action which tend to the extinction of species, and which are
conclusive against the doctrine of their unlimited durability.

There are also causes which give rise to new varieties and races in
plants and animals, and new forms are continually supplanting others
which had endured for ages. But natural history has been successfully
cultivated for so short a period, that a few examples only of local,
and perhaps but one or two of absolute, extirpation of species can as
yet be proved, and these only where the interference of man has been
conspicuous. It will nevertheless appear evident, from the facts and
arguments detailed in the chapters which treat of the geographical
distribution of species in the next volume, that man is not the only
exterminating agent; and that, independently of his intervention, the
annihilation of species is promoted by the multiplication and gradual
diffusion of every animal or plant. It will also appear that every
alteration in the physical geography and climate of the globe cannot
fail to have the same tendency. If we proceed still farther, and
inquire whether new species are substituted from time to time for those
which die out, we find that the successive introduction of new forms
appears to have been a constant part of the economy of the terrestrial
system, and if we have no direct proof of the fact it is because the
changes take place so slowly as not to come within the period of exact
scientific observation. To enable the reader to appreciate the gradual
manner in which a passage may have taken place from an extinct fauna to
that now living, I shall say a few words on the fossils of successive
Tertiary periods. When we trace the series of formations from the more
ancient to the more modern, it is in these Tertiary deposits that we
first meet with assemblages of organic remains having a near analogy to
the fauna of certain parts of the globe in our own time. In the Eocene,
or oldest subdivisions, some few of the testacea belong to existing
species, although almost all of them, and apparently all the associated
vertebrata, are now extinct. These Eocene strata are succeeded by a
great number of more modern deposits, which depart gradually in the
character of their fossils from the Eocene type, and approach more and
more to that of the living creation. In the present state of science,
it is chiefly by the aid of shells, that we are enabled to arrive at
these results, for of all classes the testacea are the most generally
diffused in a fossil state, and may be called the medals principally
employed by nature in recording the chronology of past events. In the
Upper Miocene rocks (No. 5 of the table, p. 135) we begin to find a
considerable number, although still a minority, of recent species,
intermixed with some fossils common to the preceding, or Eocene,
epoch. We then arrive at the Pliocene strata, in which species now
contemporary with man begin to preponderate, and in the newest of
which nine-tenths of the fossils agree with species still inhabiting
the neighbouring sea. It is in the Post-Tertiary strata, where all
the shells agree with species now living, that we have discovered the
first or earliest known remains of man associated with the bones of
quadrupeds, some of which are of extinct species.

In thus passing from the older to the newer members of the Tertiary
system, we meet with many chasms, but none which separate entirely,
by a broad line of demarcation, one state of the organic world from
another. There are no signs of an abrupt termination of one fauna and
flora, and the starting into life of new and wholly distinct forms.
Although we are far from being able to demonstrate geologically an
insensible transition from the Eocene to the Miocene, or even from the
latter to the recent fauna, yet the more we enlarge and perfect our
general survey, the more nearly do we approximate to such a continuous
series, and the more gradually are we conducted from times when many of
the genera and nearly all the species were extinct, to those in which
scarcely a single species flourished, which we do not know to exist
at present. Dr. A. Philippi, indeed, after an elaborate comparison
of the fossil tertiary shells of Sicily with those now living in the
Mediterranean, announced, as the result of his examination, that there
are strata in that island which attest a very gradual passage from a
period when only thirteen in a hundred of the shells were like the
species now living in the sea, to an era when the recent species had
attained a proportion of ninety-five in a hundred. There is, therefore,
evidence, he says, in Sicily of this revolution in the animate world
having been effected “without the intervention of any convulsion
or abrupt changes, certain species having from time died out, and
others having been introduced, until at length the existing fauna was
elaborated.”

In no part of Europe is the absence of all signs of man or his works,
in strata of comparatively modern date, more striking than in Sicily.
In the central parts of that island we observe a lofty table-land and
hills, sometimes rising to the height of 3,000 feet, capped with a
limestone, in which from 70 to 85 per cent of the fossil testacea are
specifically identical with those now inhabiting the Mediterranean.
These calcareous and other argillaceous strata of the same age are
intersected by deep valleys which appear to have been gradually formed
by denudation, but have not varied materially in width or depth since
Sicily was first colonized by the Greeks. The limestone, moreover,
which is of so late a date in geological chronology, was quarried for
building those ancient temples of Girgenti and Syracuse, of which the
ruins carry us back to a remote era in human history. If we are lost
in conjectures when speculating on the ages required to lift up these
formations to the height of several thousand feet above the sea, and
to excavate the valleys, how much more remote must be the era when the
same rocks were gradually formed beneath the waters!

The intense cold of the Glacial period was spoken of in the tenth
chapter. Although we have not yet succeeded in detecting proofs of the
origin of man antecedently to that epoch, we have yet found evidence
that most of the testacea, and not a few of the quadrupeds, which
preceded, were of the same species as those which followed the extreme
cold. To whatever local disturbances this cold may have given rise in
the distribution of species, it seems to have done little in effecting
their annihilation. We may conclude, therefore, from a survey of
the tertiary and modern strata, which constitute a more complete and
unbroken series than rocks of older date, that the extinction and
creation of species have been, and are, the result of a slow and
gradual change in the organic world.


_Uniformity of change considered, thirdly, in reference to
subterranean movements._--Thirdly, to pass on to the last of the
three topics before proposed for discussion, the reader will find, in
the account given in the Second Book, Vol. II., of the earthquakes
recorded in history, that certain countries have, from time immemorial,
been rudely shaken again and again; while others, comprising by
far the largest part of the globe, have remained to all appearance
motionless. In the regions of convulsion rocks have been rent asunder,
the surface has been forced up into ridges, chasms have opened, or the
ground throughout large spaces has been permanently lifted up above
or let down below its former level. In the regions of tranquillity
some areas have remained at rest, but others have been ascertained,
by a comparison of measurements made at different periods, to have
arisen by an insensible motion, as in Sweden, or to have subsided very
slowly, as in Greenland. That these same movements, whether ascending
or descending, have continued for ages in the same direction has been
established by historical or geological evidence. Thus we find on the
opposite coasts of Sweden that brackish water deposits, like those
now forming in the Baltic, occur on the eastern side, and upraised
strata filled with purely marine shells, now proper to the ocean, on
the western coast. Both of these have been lifted up to an elevation
of several hundred feet above high-water mark. The rise within the
historical period has not amounted to many yards, but the greater
extent of antecedent upheaval is proved by the occurrence in inland
spots, several hundred feet high, of deposits filled with fossil shells
of species now living either in the ocean or the Baltic.

It must in general be more difficult to detect proofs of slow and
gradual subsidence than of elevation, but the theory which accounts for
the form of circular coral reefs and lagoon islands, and which will
be explained in the concluding chapter of this work, will satisfy the
reader that there are spaces on the globe, several thousand miles in
circumference, throughout which the downward movement has predominated
for ages, and yet the land has never, in a single instance, gone down
suddenly for several hundred feet at once. Yet geology demonstrates
that the persistency of subterranean movements in one direction has
not been perpetual throughout all past time. There have been great
oscillations of level, by which a surface of dry land has been
submerged to a depth of several thousand feet, and then at a period
long subsequent raised again and made to emerge. Nor have the regions
now motionless been always at rest; and some of those which are at
present the theatres of reiterated earthquakes have formerly enjoyed
a long continuance of tranquillity. But, although disturbances have
ceased after having long prevailed, or have recommenced after a
suspension of ages, there has been no universal disruption of the
earth’s crust or desolation of the surface since times the most
remote. The non-occurrence of such a general convulsion is proved by
the perfect horizontality now retained by some of the most ancient
fossiliferous strata throughout wide areas.

That the subterranean forces have visited different parts of the globe
at successive periods is inferred chiefly from the unconformability of
strata belonging to groups of different ages. Thus, for example, on the
borders of Wales and Shropshire, we find the slaty beds of the ancient
Silurian system inclined and vertical, while the beds of the overlying
carboniferous shale and sandstone are horizontal. All are agreed that
in such a case the older set of strata had suffered great disturbance
before the deposition of the newer or carboniferous beds, and that
these last have never since been violently fractured, nor have ever
been bent into folds, whether by sudden or continuous lateral pressure.
On the other hand, the more ancient or Silurian group suffered only a
local derangement, and neither in Wales nor elsewhere are all the rocks
of that age found to be curved or vertical.

In various parts of Europe, for example, and particularly near Lake
Wener in the south of Sweden, and in many parts of Russia, the
Silurian strata maintain the most perfect horizontality; and a similar
observation may be made respecting limestones and shales of like
antiquity in the great lake district of Canada and the United States.
These older rocks are still as flat and horizontal as when first
formed; yet, since their origin, not only have most of the actual
mountain-chains been uplifted, but some of the very rocks of which
those mountains are composed have been formed, some of them by igneous
and others by aqueous action.

It would be easy to multiply instances of similar unconformability
in formations of other ages; but a few more will suffice. The
carboniferous rocks before alluded to as horizontal on the borders
of Wales are vertical in the Mendip hills in Somersetshire, where
the overlying beds of the New Red Sandstone are horizontal. Again,
in the Wolds of Yorkshire the last-mentioned sandstone supports on
its curved and inclined beds the horizontal Chalk. The Chalk again is
vertical on the flanks of the Pyrenees, and the tertiary strata repose
unconformably upon it.

As almost every country supplies illustrations of the same phenomena,
they who advocate the doctrine of alternate periods of disorder and
repose may appeal to the facts above described, as proving that every
district has been by turns convulsed by earthquakes and then respited
for ages from convulsions. But so it might with equal truth be affirmed
that every part of Europe has been visited alternately by winter and
summer, although it has always been winter and always summer in some
part of the planet, and neither of these seasons has ever reigned
simultaneously over the entire globe. They have been always shifting
from place to place; but the vicissitudes which recur thus annually
in a single spot are never allowed to interfere with the invariable
uniformity of seasons throughout the whole planet.

So, in regard to subterranean movements, the theory of the perpetual
uniformity of the force which they exert on the earth’s crust is quite
consistent with the admission of their alternate development and
suspension for long and indefinite periods within limited geographical
areas.

If, for reasons before stated, we assume a continual extinction of
species and appearance of others on the globe, it will then follow
that the fossils of strata formed at two distant periods on the same
spot will differ even more certainly than the mineral composition of
those strata. For rocks of the same kind have sometimes been reproduced
in the same district after a long interval of time; whereas all the
evidence derived from fossil remains is in favour of the opinion that
species which have once died out have never been reproduced. The
submergence, then, of land must be often attended by the commencement
of a new class of sedimentary deposits, characterized by a new set of
fossil animals and plants, while the reconversion of the bed of the sea
into land may arrest at once and for an indefinite time the formation
of geological monuments. Should the land again sink, strata will again
be formed; but one or many entire revolutions in animal or vegetable
life may have been completed in the interval.

As to the want of completeness in the fossiliferous series, which
may be said to be almost universal, we have only to reflect on what
has been already said of the laws governing sedimentary deposition,
and those which give rise to fluctuations in the animate world, to
be convinced that a very rare combination of circumstances can alone
give rise to such a superposition and preservation of strata as will
bear testimony to the gradual passage from one state of organic life
to another. To produce such strata nothing less will be requisite
than the fortunate coincidence of the following conditions: first, a
never-failing supply of sediment in the same region throughout a period
of vast duration; secondly, the fitness of the deposit in every part
for the permanent preservation of imbedded fossils; and, thirdly, a
gradual subsidence to prevent the sea or lake from being filled up and
converted into land.

It will appear in the chapter on coral reefs, that, in certain parts
of the Pacific and Indian Oceans, most of these conditions, if not
all, are complied with, and the constant growth of coral, keeping
pace with the sinking of the bottom of the sea, seems to have gone on
so slowly, for such indefinite periods, that the signs of a gradual
change in organic life might probably be detected in that quarter of
the globe if we could explore its submarine geology. Instead of the
growth of coralline limestone, let us suppose, in some other place,
the continuous deposition of fluviatile mud and sand, such as the
Ganges and Brahmapootra have poured for thousands of years into the
Bay of Bengal. Part of this bay, although of considerable depth,
might at length be filled up before an appreciable amount of change
was effected in the fish, mollusca, and other inhabitants of the sea
and neighbouring land. But if the bottom be lowered by sinking at
the same rate that it is raised by fluviatile mud, the bay can never
be turned into dry land. In that case one new layer of matter may be
superimposed upon another for a thickness of many thousand feet, and
the fossils of the inferior beds may differ greatly from those entombed
in the uppermost, yet every intermediate gradation may be indicated in
the passage from an older to a newer assemblage of species. Granting,
however, that such an unbroken sequence of monuments may thus be
elaborated in certain parts of the sea, and that the strata happen
to be all of them well adapted to preserve the included fossils from
decomposition, how many accidents must still concur before these
submarine formations will be laid open to our investigation! The whole
deposit must first be raised several thousand feet, in order to bring
into view the very foundation; and during the process of exposure the
superior beds must not be entirely swept away by denudation.

In the first place, the chances are nearly as three to one against
the mere emergence of the mass above the waters, because nearly
three-fourths of the globe are covered by the ocean. But if it be
upheaved and made to constitute part of the dry land, it must also,
before it can be available for our instruction, become part of that
area already surveyed by geologists. In this small fraction of land
already explored, and still very imperfectly known, we are required to
find a set of strata deposited under peculiar conditions, and which,
having been originally of limited extent, would have been probably much
lessened by subsequent denudation.

Yet it is precisely because we do not encounter at every step the
evidence of such gradations from one state of the organic world to
another, that so many geologists have embraced the doctrine of great
and sudden revolutions in the history of the animate world. Not content
with simply availing themselves, for the convenience of classification,
of those gaps and chasms which here and there interrupt the continuity
of the chronological series, as at present known, they deduce, from the
frequency of these breaks in the chain of records, an irregular mode of
succession in the events themselves, both in the organic and inorganic
world. But, besides that some links of the chain which once existed are
now entirely lost and others concealed from view, we have good reason
to suspect that it was never complete originally. It may undoubtedly be
said that strata have been always forming somewhere, and therefore at
every moment of past time Nature has added a page to her archives; but,
in reference to this subject, it should be remembered that we can never
hope to compile a consecutive history by gathering together monuments
which were originally detached and scattered over the globe. For, as
the species of organic beings contemporaneously inhabiting remote
regions are distinct, the fossils of the first of several periods which
may be preserved in any one country, as in America for example, will
have no connection with those of a second period found in India, and
will therefore no more enable us to trace the signs of a gradual change
in the living creation, than a fragment of Chinese history will fill up
a blank in the political annals of Europe.

The absence of any deposits of importance containing recent shells in
Chili, or anywhere on the western shore of South America, naturally led
Mr. Darwin to the conclusion that “where the bed of the sea is either
stationary or rising, circumstances are far less favourable than where
the level is sinking to the accumulation of conchiferous strata of
sufficient thickness and extension to resist the average vast amount
of denudation.” In like manner the beds of superficial sand, clay, and
gravel, with recent shells, on the coasts of Norway and Sweden, where
the land has risen in Post-tertiary times, are so thin and scanty as to
incline us to admit a similar proposition. We may in fact assume that
in all cases where the bottom of the sea has been undergoing continuous
elevation, the total thickness of sedimentary matter accumulating
at depths suited to the habitation of most of the species of shells
can never be great, nor can the deposits be thickly covered with
superincumbent matter, so as to be consolidated by pressure. When they
are upheaved, therefore, the waves on the beach will bear down and
disperse the loose materials; whereas, if the bed of the sea subsides
slowly, a mass of strata containing abundance of such species as live
at moderate depths, may be formed and may increase in thickness to any
amount. It may also extend horizontally over a broad area, as the water
gradually encroaches on the subsiding land.

Hence it will follow that great violations of continuity in the
chronological series of fossiliferous rocks will always exist, and the
imperfection of the record, though lessened, will never be removed by
future discoveries. For not only will no deposits originate on the
dry land, but those formed in the sea near land, which is undergoing
constant upheaval, will usually be too slight in thickness to endure
for ages.

In proportion as we become acquainted with larger geographical
areas, many of the gaps, by which a chronological table is rendered
defective, will be removed. We were enabled by aid of the labours of
Prof. Sedgwick and Sir Roderick Murchison, to intercalate, in 1838,
the marine strata of the Devonian period, with their fossil shells,
corals, and fish, between the Silurian and Carboniferous rocks.
Previously the marine fauna of these last-mentioned formations wanted
the connecting links which now render the passage from the one to
the other much less abrupt. In like manner the Upper Miocene has no
representative in England, but in France, Germany, and Switzerland it
constitutes a most instructive link between the living creation and the
middle of the great Tertiary period. Still we must expect, for reasons
before stated, that chasms will forever continue to occur, in some
parts of our sedimentary series.


_Concluding remarks on the consistency of the theory of gradual
change with the existence of great breaks in the series._--To
return to the general argument pursued in this chapter, it is assumed,
for reasons above explained, that a slow change of species is in
simultaneous operation everywhere throughout the habitable surface
of sea and land; whereas the fossilization of plants and animals is
confined to those areas where new strata are produced. These areas,
as we have seen, are always shifting their position, so that the
fossilizing process, by means of which the commemoration of the
particular state of the organic world, at any given time, is effected,
may be said to move about, visiting and revisiting different tracts in
succession.

To make still more clear the supposed working of this machinery, I
shall compare it to a somewhat analogous case that might be imagined
to occur in the history of human affairs. Let the mortality of the
population of a large country represent the successive extinction
of species, and the births of new individuals the introduction of
new species. While these fluctuations are gradually taking place
everywhere, suppose commissioners to be appointed to visit each
province of the country in succession, taking an exact account of the
number, names and individual peculiarities of all the inhabitants,
and leaving in each district a register containing a record of this
information. If, after the completion of one census, another is
immediately made on the same plan, and then another, there will at
last be a series of statistical documents in each province. When
those belonging to any one province are arranged in chronological
order, the contents of such as stand next to each other will differ
according to the length of the intervals of time between the taking of
each census. If, for example, there are sixty provinces, and all the
registers are made in a single year and renewed annually, the number
of births and deaths will be so small, in proportion to the whole
of the inhabitants, during the interval between the compiling of two
consecutive documents, that the individuals described in such documents
will be nearly identical; whereas, if the survey of each of the sixty
provinces occupies all the commissioners for a whole year, so that they
are unable to revisit the same place until the expiration of sixty
years, there will then be an almost entire discordance between the
persons enumerated in two consecutive registers in the same province.
There are, undoubtedly, other causes, besides the mere quantity of
time, which may augment or diminish the amount of discrepancy. Thus,
at some periods, a pestilential disease may have lessened the average
duration of human life; or a variety of circumstances may have caused
the births to be unusually numerous, and the population to multiply;
or a province may be suddenly colonized by persons migrating from
surrounding districts.

These exceptions may be compared to the accelerated rate of
fluctuations in the fauna and flora of a particular region, in which
the climate and physical geography may be undergoing an extraordinary
degree of alteration.

But I must remind the reader that the case above proposed has no
pretensions to be regarded as an exact parallel to the geological
phenomena which I desire to illustrate; for the commissioners are
supposed to visit the different provinces in rotation; whereas the
commemorating processes by which organic remains become fossilized,
although they are always shifting from one area to the other, are yet
very irregular in their movements. They may abandon and revisit many
spaces again and again, before they once approach another district;
and, besides this source of irregularity, it may often happen that,
while the depositing process is suspended, denudation may take place,
which may be compared to the occasional destruction by fire or other
causes of some of the statistical documents before mentioned. It is
evident that where such accidents occur the want of continuity in the
series may become indefinitely great, and that the monuments which
follow next in succession will by no means be equidistant from each
other in point of time.

If this train of reasoning be admitted, the occasional distinctness of
the fossil remains, in formations immediately in contact, would be a
necessary consequence of the existing laws of sedimentary deposition
and subterranean movement, accompanied by a constant dying-out and
renovation of species.

As all the conclusions above insisted on are directly opposed to
opinions still popular, I shall add another comparison, in the hope of
preventing any possible misapprehension of the argument. Suppose we
had discovered two buried cities at the foot of Vesuvius, immediately
superimposed upon each other, with a great mass of tuff and lava
intervening, just as Portici and Resina, if now covered with ashes,
would overlie Herculaneum. An antiquary might possibly be entitled to
infer, from the inscriptions on public edifices, that the inhabitants
of the inferior and older city were Greeks, and those of the modern
town Italians. But he would reason very hastily if he also concluded
from these data, that there had been a sudden change from the Greek
to the Italian language in Campania. But if he afterwards found three
buried cities, one above the other, the intermediate one being Roman,
while, as in the former example, the lowest was Greek and the uppermost
Italian, he would then perceive the fallacy of his former opinion and
would begin to suspect that the catastrophes, by which the cities
were inhumed, might have no relation whatever to the fluctuations in
the language of the inhabitants; and that, as the Roman tongue had
evidently intervened between the Greek and Italian, so many other
dialects may have been spoken in succession, and the passage from the
Greek to the Italian may have been very gradual, some terms growing
obsolete, while others were introduced from time to time.

If this antiquary could have shown that the volcanic paroxysms of
Vesuvius were so governed as that cities should be buried one above the
other, just as often as any variation occurred in the language of the
inhabitants, then, indeed, the abrupt passage from a Greek to a Roman,
and from a Roman to an Italian city, would afford proof of fluctuations
no less sudden in the language of the people.

So, in Geology, if we could assume that it is part of the plan of
Nature to preserve, in every region of the globe, an unbroken series
of monuments to commemorate the vicissitudes of the organic creation,
we might infer the sudden extirpation of species, and the simultaneous
introduction of others, as often as two formations in contact are found
to include dissimilar organic fossils. But we must shut our eyes to the
whole economy of the existing causes, aqueous, igneous, and organic,
if we fail to perceive that such is not the plan of Nature.

I shall now conclude the discussion of a question with which we have
been occupied since the beginning of the fifth chapter--namely, whether
there has been any interruption, from the remotest periods, of one
uniform and continuous system of change in the animate and inanimate
world. We were induced to enter into that inquiry by reflecting how
much the progress of opinion in Geology had been influenced by the
assumption that the analogy was slight in kind, and still more slight
in degree, between the causes which produced the former revolutions
of the globe, and those now in every-day operation. It appeared clear
that the earlier geologists had not only a scanty acquaintance with
existing changes, but were singularly unconscious of the amount of
their ignorance. With the presumption naturally inspired by this
unconsciousness, they had no hesitation in deciding at once that time
could never enable the existing powers of nature to work out changes
of great magnitude, still less such important revolutions as those
which are brought to light by Geology. They therefore felt themselves
at liberty to indulge their imaginations in guessing at what might be,
rather than inquiring what is; in other words, they employed themselves
in conjecturing what might have been the course of Nature at a remote
period, rather than in the investigation of what was the course of
Nature in their own times.

It appeared to them far more philosophical to speculate on the
possibilities of the past, than patiently to explore the realities of
the present; and having invented theories under the influences of such
maxims, they were consistently unwilling to test their validity by the
criterion of their accordance with the ordinary operations of Nature.
On the contrary, the claims of each new hypothesis to credibility
appeared enhanced by the great contrast, in kind or intensity, of the
causes referred to and those now in operation.

Never was there a dogma more calculated to foster indolence, and
to blunt the keen edge of curiosity, than this assumption of the
discordance between the ancient and existing causes of change. It
produced a state of mind unfavourable in the highest degree to the
candid reception of the evidence of those minute but incessant
alterations which every part of the earth’s surface is undergoing,
and by which the condition of its living inhabitants is continually
made to vary. The student, instead of being encouraged with the
hope of interpreting the enigmas presented to him in the earth’s
structure--instead of being prompted to undertake laborious inquiries
into the natural history of the organic world, and the complicated
effects of the igneous and aqueous causes now in operation--was taught
to despond from the first. Geology, it was affirmed, could never rise
to the rank of an exact science; the greater number of phenomena
must forever remain inexplicable, or only be partially elucidated by
ingenious conjectures. Even the mystery which invested the subject was
said to constitute one of its principal charms, affording, as it did,
full scope to the fancy to indulge in a boundless field of speculation.

The course directly opposed to this method of philosophizing consists
in an earnest and patient inquiry, how far geological appearances are
reconcilable with the effect of changes now in progress, or which
may be in progress in regions inaccessible to us, but of which the
reality is attested by volcanoes and subterranean movements. It also
endeavours to estimate the aggregate result of ordinary operations
multiplied by time, and cherishes a sanguine hope that the resources
to be derived from observation and experiment, or from the study of
Nature such as she now is, are very far from being exhausted. For this
reason all theories are rejected which involve the assumption of sudden
and violent catastrophes and revolutions of the whole earth, and its
inhabitants--theories which are restrained by no reference to existing
analogies, and in which a desire is manifested to cut, rather than
patiently to untie, the Gordian knot.

We have now, at least, the advantage of knowing, from experience, that
an opposite method has always put geologists on the road that leads
to truth--suggesting views which, although imperfect at first, have
been found capable of improvement, until at last adopted by universal
consent; while the method of speculating on a former distinct state of
things and causes has led invariably to a multitude of contradictory
systems, which have been overthrown one after the other--have been
found incapable of modification--and which have often required to be
precisely reversed.

The remainder of this work will be devoted to an investigation of the
changes now going on in the crust of the earth and its inhabitants.
The importance which the student will attach to such researches will
mainly depend on the degree of confidence which he feels in the
principles above expounded. If he firmly believes in the resemblance
or identity of the ancient and present system of terrestrial changes,
he will regard every fact collected respecting the causes in diurnal
action as affording him a key to the interpretation of some mystery in
the past. Events which have occurred at the most distant periods in
the animate and inanimate world will be acknowledged to throw light
on each other, and the deficiency of our information respecting some
of the most obscure parts of the present creation will be removed.
For as, by studying the external configuration of the existing land
and its inhabitants, we may restore in imagination the appearance of
the ancient continents which have passed away, so may we obtain from
the deposits of ancient seas and lakes an insight into the nature
of the subaqueous processes now in operation, and of many forms of
organic life which, though now existing, are veiled from sight. Rocks,
also, produced by subterranean fire in former ages, at great depths
in the bowels of the earth, present us, when upraised by gradual
movements, and exposed to the light of heaven, with an image of those
changes which the deep-seated volcano may now occasion in the nether
regions. Thus, although we are mere sojourners on the surface of the
planet, chained to a mere point in space, enduring but for a moment of
time, the human mind is not only enabled to number worlds beyond the
unassisted ken of mortal eye, but to trace the events of indefinite
ages before the creation of our race, and is not even withheld from
penetrating into the dark secrets of the ocean, or the interior of
the solid globe; free, like the spirit which the poet described as
animating the universe,

                     --_ire per omnes_
    _Terrasque, tractusque maris, coelumque profundum_.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 31: From the _Principles of Geology_, Bk. I, Ch. XIII.]




                                 XXIX

                            CHARLES DARWIN

                               1809-1882


 _Charles Robert Darwin, the grandson of Erasmus Darwin, was born at
 Shrewsbury, England, February 12, 1809. He studied at both Edinburgh
 and Cambridge, and graduated from the latter in 1831. From 1831 to 1836
 he served as a naturalist on the “Beagle,” which made a trip around the
 world in the interests of science. The voyage served as a post-graduate
 course for Darwin, who then first adopted his evolutionary ideas and
 developed as an original investigator. Reading Malthus, in 1838, on
 the problem of population and the food supply, he integrated Malthus’
 ideas into his own views of biology. In 1844 be began his “Origin of
 Species,” which he completed in 1859. In 1858 he received a paper
 from Alfred Russell Wallace, then in the Malay Archipelago, which
 proposed the same theory of natural selection. Darwin believed that
 when organisms increased much faster than the means of subsistence,
 the ratios varied, and in the conditions produced by these natural
 causes only those organisms survived which were best fitted to their
 environment. He applied his concept to human evolution in his “Descent
 of Man,” published in 1871. He died April 19, 1882, and was buried in
 Westminster Abbey._


                         NATURAL SELECTION[32]

How will the struggle for existence, briefly discussed in the last
chapter, act in regard to variation? Can the principle of selection,
which we have seen is so potent in the hands of man, apply under
nature? I think we shall see that it can act most efficiently. Let
the endless number of slight variations and individual differences
occurring in our domestic productions, and, in a lesser degree, in
those under nature, be borne in mind; as well as the strength of the
hereditary tendency. Under domestication, it may be truly said that the
whole organization becomes in some degree plastic. But the variability,
which we almost universally meet with in our domestic production, is
not directly produced, as Hooker and Asa Gray have well remarked, by
man; he can neither originate varieties, nor prevent their occurrence;
he can only preserve and accumulate such as do occur. Unintentionally
he exposes organic beings to new and changing conditions of life, and
variability ensues; but similar changes of conditions might and do
occur under nature. Let it also be borne in mind how infinitely complex
and close-fitting are the mutual relations of all organic beings to
each other and to their physical conditions of life; and consequently
what infinitely varied diversities of structure might be of use to
each being under changing conditions of life. Can it then be thought
improbable, seeing that variations useful to man have undoubtedly
occurred, that other variations useful in some way to each being in the
great and complex battle of life, should occur in the course of many
successive generations? If such do occur, can we doubt (remembering
that many more individuals are born than can possibly survive) that
individuals having any advantage, however slight, over others, would
have the best chance of surviving and of procreating their kind? On the
other hand, we may feel sure that any variation in the least degree
injurious would be rigidly destroyed. This preservation of favourable
individual differences and variations, and the destruction of those
which are injurious, I have called Natural Selection, or the Survival
of the Fittest. Variations neither useful nor injurious would not be
affected by natural selection, and would be left either a fluctuating
element, as perhaps we see in certain polymorphic species, or would
ultimately become fixed, owing to the nature of the organism and the
nature of the conditions.

Several writers have misapprehended or objected to the term Natural
Selection. Some have even imagined that natural selection induces
variability, whereas it implies only the preservation of such
variations as arise and are beneficial to the being under its
conditions of life. No one objects to agriculturists speaking of the
potent effects of man’s selection; and in this case the individual
differences given by nature, which man for some object selects, must of
necessity first occur. Others have objected that the term selection
implies conscious choice in the animals which become modified; and it
has even been urged that, as plants have no volition, natural selection
is not applicable to them! In the literal sense of the word, no doubt,
natural selection is a false term; but who ever objected to chemists
speaking of the elective affinities of the various elements?--and yet
an acid cannot strictly be said to elect the base with which it in
preference combines. It has been said that I speak of natural selection
as an active power or Deity; but who objects to an author speaking
of the attraction of gravity as ruling the movements of the planets?
Everyone knows what is meant and is implied by such metaphorical
expressions; and they are almost necessary for brevity. So again it is
difficult to avoid personifying the word Nature; but I mean by Nature,
only the aggregate action and product of many natural laws, and by laws
the sequence of events as ascertained by us. With a little familiarity
such superficial objections will be forgotten.

We shall best understand the probable course of natural selection by
taking the case of a country undergoing some slight physical change,
for instance, of climate. The proportional numbers of its inhabitants
will almost immediately undergo a change, and some species will
probably become extinct. We may conclude, from what we have seen of the
intimate and complex manner in which the inhabitants of each country
are bound together, that any change in the numerical proportions of
the inhabitants, independently of the change of climate itself, would
seriously affect the others. If the country were open on its borders,
new forms would certainly immigrate, and this would likewise seriously
disturb the relations of some of the former inhabitants. Let it be
remembered how powerful the influence of a single introduced tree
or mammal has been shown to be. But in the case of an island, or of
a country partly surrounded by barriers, into which new and better
adapted forms could not freely enter, we should then have places in the
economy of nature which would assuredly be better filled up, if some
of the original inhabitants were in some manner modified; for, had the
area been open to immigration, these same places would have been seized
on by intruders. In such cases, slight modifications, which in any
way favoured the individuals of any species, by better adapting them
to their altered conditions, would tend to be preserved; and natural
selection would have free scope for the work of improvement.

We have good reason to believe, as shown in the first chapter, that
changes in the conditions of life give a tendency to increased
variability; and in the foregoing cases the conditions have changed,
and this would manifestly be favourable to natural selection, by
affording a better chance of the occurrence of profitable variations.
Unless such occur, natural selection can do nothing. Under the term
of “variations,” it must never be forgotten that mere individual
differences are included. As man can produce a great result with
his domestic animals and plants by adding up in any given direction
individual differences, so could natural selection, but far more easily
from having incomparably longer time for action. Nor do I believe
that any great physical change, as of climate, or any unusual degree
of isolation to check immigration, is necessary in order that new and
unoccupied places should be left for natural selection to fill up by
improving some of the varying inhabitants. For as all the inhabitants
of each country are struggling together with nicely balanced forces,
extremely slight modifications in the structure or habits of one
species would often give it an advantage over others; and still further
modifications of the same kind would often still further increase the
advantage, as long as the species continued under the same conditions
of life and profited by similar means of subsistence and defense. No
country can be named in which all the native inhabitants are now so
perfectly adapted to each other and to the physical conditions under
which they live, that none of them could be still better adapted or
improved; for in all countries, the natives have been so far conquered
by naturalized productions, that they have allowed some foreigners to
take firm possession of the land. And as foreigners have thus in every
country beaten some of the natives, we may safely conclude that the
natives might have been modified with advantage, so as to have better
resisted the intruders.

As man can produce, and certainly has produced, a great result by his
methodical and unconscious means of selection, what may not natural
selection effect? Man can act only on external and visible characters:
Nature, if I may be allowed to personify the natural preservation or
survival of the fittest, cares nothing for appearances, except in so
far as they are useful to any being. She can act on every internal
organ, on every shade of constitutional difference, on the whole
machinery of life. Man selects only for his own good: Nature only for
that of the being which she tends. Every selected character is fully
exercised by her, as is implied by the fact of their selection. Man
keeps the natives of many climates in the same country; he seldom
exercises each selected character in some peculiar and fitting manner;
he feeds a long and a short-beaked pigeon on the same food; he does
not exercise a long-backed or long-legged quadruped in any peculiar
manner; he exposes sheep with long and short wool to the same climate.
He does not allow the most vigorous males to struggle for the females.
He does not rigidly destroy all inferior animals, but protects during
each varying season, as far as lies in his power, all his productions.
He often begins his selection by some half-monstrous form; or at
least by some modification prominent enough to catch the eye or to
be plainly useful to him. Under nature, the slightest differences of
structure or constitution may well turn the nicely-balanced scale in
the struggle for life, and so be preserved. How fleeting are the wishes
and efforts of man! how short his time! and consequently how poor will
be his results, compared with those accumulated by Nature during whole
geological periods! Can we wonder, then, that Nature’s productions
should be far “truer” in character than man’s productions; that they
should be infinitely better adapted to the most complex conditions of
life, and should plainly bear the stamp of far higher workmanship?

It may metaphorically be said that natural selection is daily and
hourly scrutinizing, throughout the world, the slightest variations;
rejecting those that are bad, preserving and adding up all that are
good; silently and sensibly working, whenever and wherever opportunity
offers, at the improvement of each organic being in relation to its
organic and inorganic conditions of life. We see nothing of these slow
changes in progress, until the hand of time has marked the lapse of
ages, and then so imperfect is our view into long-past geological ages,
that we see only that the forms of life are now different from what
they formerly were.

In order that any great amount of modification should be effected in
a species, a variety when once formed must again, perhaps after a
long interval of time, vary or present individual differences of the
same favourable nature as before; and these must be again preserved,
and so onwards step by step. Seeing that individual differences of
the same kind perpetually recur, this can hardly be considered as an
unwarrantable assumption. But whether it is true, we can judge only by
seeing how far the hypothesis accords with and explains the general
phenomena of nature. On the other hand, the ordinary belief that the
amount of possible variation is a strictly limited quantity is likewise
a simple assumption.

Although natural selection can act only through and for the good of
each being, yet characters and structures, which we are apt to consider
as of very trifling importance, may thus be acted on. When we see
leaf-eating insects green, and bark-feeders mottled gray; the Alpine
ptarmigan white in winter, the red-grouse the colour of heather,
we must believe that these tints are of service to these birds and
insects in preserving them from danger. Grouse, if not destroyed at
some period of their lives, would increase in countless numbers;
they are known to suffer largely from birds of prey; and hawks are
guided by eyesight to their prey--so much so, that on parts of the
Continent persons are warned not to keep white pigeons, as being the
most liable to destruction. Hence natural selection might be effective
in giving the proper colour to each kind of grouse, and in keeping
that colour, when once acquired, true and constant. Nor ought we to
think that the occasional destruction of an animal of any particular
colour would produce little effect: we should remember how essential
it is in a flock of white sheep to destroy a lamb with the faintest
trace of black. We have seen how the colour of the hogs, which feed on
the “paint-root” in Virginia, determines whether they shall live or
die. In plants, the down on the fruit and the colour of the flesh are
considered by botanists as characters of the most trifling importance:
yet we hear from an excellent horticulturist, Downing, that in the
United States smooth-skinned fruits suffer far more from a beetle, a
Curculio, than those with down; that purple plums suffer far more from
a certain disease than yellow plums; whereas another disease attacks
yellow-fleshed peaches far more than those with other coloured flesh.
If, with all the aids of arts, these slight differences make a great
difference in cultivating the several varieties, assuredly, in a state
of nature, where the trees would have to struggle with other trees and
with a host of enemies, such differences would effectually settle which
variety, whether a smooth or downy, a yellow or purple-fleshed fruit,
should succeed.

In looking at many small points of difference between species, which,
as far as our ignorance permits us to judge, seem quite unimportant,
we must not forget that climate, food, etc., have no doubt produced
some direct effect. It is also necessary to bear in mind that, owing to
the law of correlation, when one part varies, and the variations are
accumulated through natural selection, other modifications, often of
the most unexpected nature, will ensue.

As we see that those variations which, under domestication, appear at
any particular period of life, tend to reappear in the offspring at the
same period; for instance, in the shape, size, and flavour of the seeds
of the many varieties of our culinary and agricultural plants; in the
caterpillar and cocoon stages of the varieties of the silkworm; in the
eggs of poultry, and in the colour of the down of their chickens; in
the horns of our sheep and cattle when nearly adult; so in a state of
nature natural selection will be enabled to act on and modify organic
beings at any age, by the accumulation of variations profitable at that
age, and by their inheritance at a corresponding age. If it profit
a plant to have its seeds more and more widely disseminated by the
wind, I can see no greater difficulty in this being effected through
natural selection, than in the cotton planter increasing and improving
by selection the down in the pods on his cotton trees. Natural
selection may modify and adapt the larva of an insect to a score of
contingencies, wholly different from those which concern the mature
insect; and these modifications may effect, through correlation, the
structure of the adult. So, conversely, modifications in the adult may
affect the structure of the larva; but in all cases natural selection
will insure that they shall not be injurious: for if they were so, the
species would become extinct.

Natural selection will modify the structure of the young in relation
to the parent, and of the parent in relation to the young. In social
animals it will adapt the structure of each individual for the benefit
of the whole community; if the community profits by the selected
change. What natural selection cannot do, is to modify the structure
of one species; without giving it any advantage, for the good of
another species; and though statements to this effect may be found
in works of natural history, I cannot find one case which will bear
investigation. A structure used only once in an animal’s life, if
of high importance to it, might be modified to any extent by natural
selection; for instance, the great jaws possessed by certain insects,
used exclusively for opening the cocoon--or the hard tip of the beak of
unhatched birds, used for breaking the egg. It has been asserted, that
of the best short-beaked tumbler-pigeons a greater number perish in the
egg than are able to get out of it; so that fanciers assist in the act
of hatching. Now if nature had to make the beak of a full-grown pigeon
very short for the bird’s own advantage, the process of modification
would be very slow, and there would be simultaneously the most rigorous
selection of all the young birds within the egg, which had the most
powerful and hardest beaks, for all with weak beaks would inevitably
perish; or, more delicate and more easily broken shells might be
selected, the thickness of the shell being known to vary like every
other structure.

It may be well here to remark that with all beings there must be much
fortuitous destruction, which can have little or no influence on
the course of natural selection. For instance a vast number of eggs
or seeds are annually devoured, and these could be modified through
natural selection only if they varied in some manner which protected
them from their enemies. Yet many of these eggs or seeds would perhaps,
if not destroyed, have yielded individuals better adapted to their
conditions of life than any of those which happened to survive. So
again a vast number of mature animals and plants, whether or not they
be the best adapted to their conditions, must be annually destroyed by
accidental causes, which would not be in the least degree mitigated
by certain changes of structure or constitution which would in other
ways be beneficial to the species. But let the destruction of the
adults be ever so heavy, if the number which can exist in any district
be not wholly kept down by such causes,--or again let the destruction
of eggs or seeds be so great that only a hundredth or a thousandth
part are developed,--yet of those which do survive, the best adapted
individuals, supposing that there is any variability in a favourable
direction, will tend to propagate their kind in larger numbers than the
less well adapted. If the numbers be wholly kept down by the causes
just indicated, as will often have been the case, natural selection
will be powerless in certain beneficial directions; but this is no
valid objection to its efficiency at other times and in other ways; for
we are far from having any reason to suppose that many species ever
undergo modification and improvement at the same time in the same area.


                           SEXUAL SELECTION

Inasmuch as peculiarities often appear under domestication in one sex
and become hereditarily attached to that sex, so no doubt it will be
under nature. Thus it is rendered possible for the two sexes to be
modified through natural selection in relation to different habits
of life, as is sometimes the case; or for one sex to be modified in
relation to the other sex, as commonly occurs. This leads me to say
a few words on what I have called Sexual Selection. This form of
selection depends, not on a struggle for existence in relation to other
organic beings or to external conditions, but on a struggle between the
individuals of one sex, generally the males, for the possession of the
other sex. The result is not death to the unsuccessful competitor, but
few or no offspring. Sexual selection is, therefore, less rigorous than
natural selection. Generally, the most vigorous males, those which are
best fitted for their places in nature, will leave most progeny. But in
many cases, victory depends not so much on general vigour, as on having
special weapons, confined to the male sex. A hornless stag or spurless
cock would have a poor chance of leaving numerous offspring. Sexual
selection, by always allowing the victor to breed, might surely give
indomitable courage, length to the spur, and strength to the wing to
strike in the spurred leg, in nearly the same manner as does the brutal
cockfighter by the careful selection of his best cocks. How low in the
scale of nature the law of battle descends, I know not; male alligators
have been described as fighting, bellowing, and whirling round, like
Indians in a war-dance, for the possession of the females; male
salmons have been observed fighting all day long; male stag-beetles
sometimes bear wounds from the huge mandibles of other males; the
males of certain hymenopterous insects have been frequently seen by
that inimitable observer, M. Fabre, fighting for a particular female
who sits by, an apparently unconcerned beholder of the struggle, and
then retires with the conquerer. The war is, perhaps, severest between
the males of polygamous animals, and these seem oftenest provided with
special weapons. The males of carnivorous animals are already well
armed; though to them and to others, special means of defence may be
given through means of sexual selection, as the mane of the lion, and
the hooked jaw to the male salmon; for the shield may be as important
for victory as the sword or spear.

Amongst birds, the contest is often of a more peaceful character.
All those who have attended to the subject believe that there is the
severest rivalry between the males of many species to attract, by
singing, the females. The rock-thrush of Guiana, birds of paradise,
and some others, congregate; and successive males display with the
most elaborate care, and show off in the best manner, their gorgeous
plumage; they likewise perform strange antics before the females,
which, standing by as spectators, at last choose the most attractive
partner. Those who have closely attended to birds in confinement well
know that they often take individual preferences and dislikes: thus
Sir R. Heron has described how a pied peacock was eminently attractive
to all his hen birds. I cannot here enter on the necessary details;
but if man can in a short time give beauty and an elegant carriage to
his bantams, according to his standard of beauty, I can see no good
reason to doubt that female birds, by selecting, during thousands
of generations, the most melodious or beautiful males, according
to their standard of beauty, might produce a marked effect. Some
well-known laws, with respect to the plumage of male and female birds,
in comparison with the plumage of the young, can partly be explained
through the action of sexual selection on variations occuring at
different ages, and transmitted to the males alone or to both sexes at
corresponding ages; but I have not space here to enter on this subject.

Thus it is, as I believe, that when the males and females of any
animal have the same general habits of life, but differ in structure,
colour, or ornament, such differences have been mainly caused by sexual
selection: that is, by individual males having had, in successive
generations, some slight advantage over other males, in their weapons,
means of defence, or charms, which they have transmitted to their
male offspring alone. Yet, I would not wish to attribute all sexual
differences to this agency: for we see in our domestic animals
peculiarities arising and becoming attached to the male sex, which
apparently have not been augmented through selection by man. The tuft
of hair on the breast of the wild turkey-cock cannot be of any use, and
it is doubtful whether it can be ornamental in the eyes of the female
bird;--indeed, had the tuft appeared under domestication, it would have
been called a monstrosity.


         ON THE DEGREE TO WHICH ORGANISATION TENDS TO ADVANCE

Natural Selection acts exclusively by the preservation and accumulation
of variations, which are beneficial under the organic and inorganic
conditions to which each nature is exposed at all periods of life. The
ultimate result is that each creature tends to become more and more
improved in relation to its conditions. This improvement inevitably
leads to the gradual advancement of the organisation of the greater
number of living beings throughout the world. But here we enter on
a very intricate subject, for naturalists have not defined to each
other’s satisfaction what is meant by an advance in organisation.
Amongst the vertebrata the degree of intellect and an approach in
structure to man clearly come into play. It might be thought that
the amount of change which the various parts and organs pass through
in their development from the embryo to maturity would suffice as a
standard of comparison; but there are cases, as with certain parasitic
crustaceans, in which several parts of the structure become less
perfect, so that the mature animal cannot be called higher than its
larva. Von Bar’s standard seems the most widely applicable and the
best, namely, the amount of differentiation of the parts of the same
organic being, in the adult state as I should be inclined to add, and
their specialisation for different functions; or, as Milne Edwards
would express it, the completeness of the division of physiological
labour. But we shall see how obscure this subject is if we look,
for instance, to fishes, amongst which some naturalists rank those
as highest which, like the sharks, approach nearest to amphibians;
whilst other naturalists rank the common bony or teleostean fishes as
the highest, inasmuch as they are most strictly fishlike, and differ
most from the other vertebrate classes. We see still more plainly
the obscurity of the subject by turning to plants, amongst which the
standard of intellect is of course quite excluded; and here some
botanists rank those plants as highest which have every organ, as
sepals, petals, stamens, and pistils, fully developed in each flower;
whereas other botanists, probably with more truth, look at the plants
which have their several organs much modified and reduced in number as
the highest.

If we take as the standard of high organisation, the amount of
differentiation and specialisation of the several organs in each
being when adult (and this will include the advancement of the brain
for intellectual purposes), natural selection clearly leads towards
this standard; for all physiologists admit that the specialisation
of organs, inasmuch as in this state they perform their functions
better, is an advantage to each being; and hence the accumulation
of variations tending towards specialisation is within the scope of
natural selection. On the other hand, we can see, bearing in mind that
all organic beings are striving to increase at a high ratio and to
seize on every unoccupied or less well occupied place in the economy of
nature, that it is quite possible for natural selection gradually to
fit a being to a situation in which several organs would be superfluous
or useless: in such cases there would be retrogression in the scale of
organisation. Whether organisation on the whole has actually advanced
from the remotest geological periods to the present day will be more
conveniently discussed in our chapter on Geological Succession.

But it may be objected that if all organic beings thus tend to rise
in the scale, how is it that throughout the world a multitude of the
lowest forms still exist; and how is it that in each great class some
forms are far more highly developed than others? Why have not the
more highly developed forms everywhere supplanted and exterminated
the lower? Lamarck, who believed in an innate and inevitable tendency
towards perfection in all organic beings, seems to have felt this
difficulty so strongly, that he was led to suppose that new and simple
forms are continually being produced by spontaneous generation. Science
has not as yet proved the truth of this belief, whatever the future
may reveal. On our theory the continued existence of lowly organisms
offers no difficulty; for natural selection, or the survival of the
fittest, does not necessarily include progressive development--it only
takes advantage of such variations as arise and are beneficial to each
creature under its complex relations of life. And it may be asked
what advantage, as far as we can see, would it be to an infusorian
animalcule--to an intestinal worm--or even to an earth-worm, to be
highly organised. If it were no advantage, these forms would be left,
by natural selection, unimproved or but little improved, and might
remain for indefinite ages in their present lowly condition. And
geology tells us that some of the lowest forms, as the infusoria and
rhizopods, have remained for an enormous period in nearly their present
state. But to suppose that most of the many now existing low forms
have not in the least advanced since the first dawn of life would be
extremely rash; for every naturalist who has dissected some of the
beings now ranked as very low in the scale, must have been struck with
their really wondrous and beautiful organisation.

Nearly the same remarks are applicable if we look to the different
grades of organisation within the same great group; for instance,
in the vertebrata, to the co-existence of mammals and fish--amongst
mammalia, to the co-existence of man and the ornithorhynchus--amongst
fishes, to the co-existence of the shark and the lancelet
(_Amphioxus_), which latter fish in the extreme simplicity of
its structure approaches the invertebrate classes. But mammals and
fish hardly come into competition with each other; the advancement
of the whole class of mammals, or of certain members in this class,
to the highest grade would not lead to their taking the place of
fishes. Physiologists believe that the brain must be bathed by warm
blood to be highly active, and this requires aërial respiration;
so that warm-blooded mammals when inhabiting the water lie under a
disadvantage in having to come continually to the surface to breathe.
With fishes, members of the shark family would not tend to supplant the
lancelet; for the lancelet, as I hear from Fritz Müller, has as sole
companion and competitor on the barren, sandy shore of South Brazil,
an anomalous annelid. The three lowest orders of mammals, namely,
marsupials, edentata, and rodents, co-exist in South America in the
same region with numerous monkeys, and probably interfere little with
each other. Although organisation, on the whole, may have advanced and
be still advancing throughout the world, yet the scale will always
present many degrees of perfection; for the high advancement of certain
whole classes, or of certain members of each class, does not at all
necessarily lead to the extinction of those groups with which they do
not enter into close competition. In some cases, as we shall hereafter
see, lowly organised forms appear to have been preserved to the present
day, from inhabiting confined or peculiar stations, where they have
been subjected to less severe competition, and where their scanty
numbers have retarded the chance of favourable variations arising.

Finally, I believe that many lowly organised forms now exist
throughout the world, from various causes. In some cases variations or
individual differences of a favourable nature may never have arisen
for natural selection to act on and accumulate. In no case, probably,
has time sufficed for the utmost possible amount of development.
In some few cases there has been what we must call retrogression
of organisation. But the main cause lies in the fact that under
very simple conditions of life a high organisation would be of no
service,--possibly would be of actual disservice, as being of a more
delicate nature, and more liable to be put out of order and injured.

Looking to the first dawn of life, when all organic beings, as we may
believe, presented the simplest structure, how, it has been asked,
could the first steps in the advancement of differentiation of parts
have arisen? Mr. Herbert Spencer would probably answer that, as soon as
simple unicellular organism came by growth or division to be compounded
of several cells, or became attached to any supporting surface, his law
“that homologous units of any order become differentiated in proportion
as their relations to incident forces become different” would come into
action. But as we have no facts to guide us, speculation on the subject
is almost useless. It is, however, an error to suppose that there would
be no struggle for existence, and, consequently, no natural selection,
until many forms had been produced; variations in a single species
inhabiting an isolated station might be beneficial, and thus the whole
mass of individuals might be modified, or two distinct forms might
arise. But, as I remarked towards the close of the Introduction, no
one ought to feel surprise at much remaining as yet unexplained on the
origin of species, if we make due allowance for our profound ignorance
on the mutual relations of the inhabitants of the world at the present
time, and still more so during past ages.


                       CONVERGENCE OF CHARACTER

Mr. H. C. Watson thinks that I have overrated the importance of
divergence of character (in which, however, he apparently believes),
and that convergence, as it may be called, has likewise played a
part. If two species, belonging to two distinct though allied genera,
had both produced a large number of new and divergent forms, it is
conceivable that these might approach each other so closely that they
would have all to be classed under the same genus; and thus the
descendants of two distinct genera would converge into one. But it
would in most cases be extremely rash to attribute to convergence a
close and general similarity of structure in the modified descendants
of widely distinct forms. The shape of a crystal is determined solely
by the molecular forces, and it is not surprising that dissimilar
substances should sometimes assume the same form; but with organic
beings we should bear in mind that the form of each depends on an
infinitude of complex relations, namely, on the variations which have
arisen, those being due to causes far too intricate to be followed
out,--on the nature of the variations which have been preserved or
selected, and this depends on the surrounding physical conditions, and
in a still higher degree on the surrounding organisms with which each
being has come into competition,--and lastly, on inheritance (in itself
a fluctuating element) from innumerable progenitors, all of which have
had their forms determined through equally complex relations. It is
incredible that the descendants of two organisms, which had originally
differed in a marked manner, should ever afterwards converge so closely
as to lead to a near approach to identity throughout their whole
organisation. If this had occurred, we should meet with the same form,
independently of genetic connection, recurring in widely separated
geological formations; and the balance of evidence is opposed to any
such an admission.

Mr. Watson has also objected that the continued action of natural
selection, together with divergence of character, would tend to make
an indefinite number of specific forms. As far as mere inorganic
conditions are concerned, it seems probable that a sufficient number
of species would soon become adapted to all considerable diversities
of heat, moisture, &c.; but I fully admit that the mutual relations
of organic beings are more important; and as the number of species in
any country goes on increasing, the organic conditions of life must
become more and more complex. Consequently there seems at first sight
no limit to the amount of profitable diversification of structure, and
therefore no limit to the number of species which might be produced.
We do not know that even the most prolific area is fully stocked with
specific forms: at the Cape of Good Hope and in Australia, which
support such an astonishing number of species, many European plants
have become naturalised. But geology shows us, that from an early part
of the tertiary period the number of species of shells, and that from
the middle part of this same period the number of mammals, has not
greatly or at all increased. What then checks an indefinite increase
in the number of species? The amount of life (I do not mean the number
of specific forms) supported on an area must have a limit, depending
so largely as it does on physical conditions; therefore, if an area
be inhabited by very many species, each or nearly each species will
be represented by few individuals; and such species will be liable to
exterminate from accidental fluctuations in the nature of the seasons
or in the number of their enemies. The process of extermination in
such cases would be rapid, whereas the production of new species
must always be slow. Imagine the extreme case of as many species as
individuals in England, and the first severe winter or very dry summer
would exterminate thousands on thousands of species. Rare species, and
each species will become rare if the number of species in any country
becomes indefinitely increased, will, on the principle often explained,
present within a given period few favourable variations; consequently,
the process of giving birth to new specific forms would thus be
retarded. When any species becomes very rare, close interbreeding will
help to exterminate it; authors have thought that this comes into play
in accounting for the deterioration of the Aurochs in Lithuania, of Red
Deer in Scotland, and of Bears in Norway, &c. Lastly, and this I am
inclined to think is the most important element, a dominant species,
which has already beaten many competitors in its own home, will tend to
spread and supplant many others. Alph. de Candolle has shown that those
species which spread widely, tend generally to spread very widely;
consequently, they will tend to supplant and exterminate several
species in several areas, and thus check the inordinate increase of
specific forms throughout the world. Dr. Hooker has recently shown that
in the S. E. corner of Australia, where, apparently, there are many
invaders from different quarters of the globe, the endemic Australian
species have been greatly reduced in number. How much weight to
attribute to these several considerations I will not pretend to say;
but conjointly they must limit in each country the tendency to an
indefinite augmentation of specific forms.


                          SUMMARY OF CHAPTER

If under changing conditions of life organic beings present individual
differences in almost every part of their structure, and this cannot
be disputed; if there be, owing to their geometrical rate of increase,
a severe struggle for life at some age, season, or year, and this
certainly cannot be disputed; then, considering the infinite complexity
of the relations of all organic beings to each other and to their
conditions of life, causing an infinite diversity in structure,
constitution, and habits, to be advantageous to them, it would be a
most extraordinary fact if no variations had ever occurred useful to
each being’s own welfare, in the same manner as so many variations
have occurred useful to man. But if variations useful to any organic
being ever do occur, assuredly individuals thus characterised will
have the best chance of being preserved in the struggle for life; and
from the strong principle of inheritance, these will tend to produce
offspring similarly characterised. This principle of preservation,
or the survival of the fittest, I have called Natural Selection. It
leads to the improvement of each creature in relation to its organic
and inorganic conditions of life; and consequently, in most cases, to
what must be regarded as an advance in organisation. Nevertheless,
low and simple forms will long endure if well fitted for their simple
conditions of life.

Natural selection, on the principle of qualities being inherited at
corresponding ages, can modify the egg, seed, or young, as easily as
the adult. Amongst many animals, sexual selection will have given its
aid to ordinary selection, by assuring to the most vigorous and best
adapted males the greatest number of offspring. Sexual selection will
also give characters useful to the males alone, in their struggles or
rivalry with other males; and these characters will be transmitted to
one sex or to both sexes, according to the form of inheritance which
prevails.

Whether natural selection has really thus acted in adapting the
various forms of life to their several conditions and stations, must
be judged by the general tenor and balance of evidence given in the
following chapters. But we have already seen how it entails extinction;
and how largely extinction has acted in the world’s history, geology
plainly declares. Natural selection, also, leads to divergence of
character; for the more organic beings diverge in structure, habits,
and constitution, by so much the more can a large number be supported
on the area,--of which we see proof by looking to the inhabitants of
any small spot, and to the productions naturalised in foreign lands.
Therefore, during the modification of the descendants of any one
species, and during the incessant struggle of all species to increase
in numbers, the more diversified the descendants become, the better
will be their chance of success in the battle for life. Thus the small
differences distinguishing varieties of the same species, steadily tend
to increase, till they equal the greater differences between species of
the same genus, or even of distinct genera.

We have seen that it is the common, the widely diffused and widely
ranging species, belonging to the larger genera within each class,
which vary most; and these tend to transmit to their modified offspring
that superiority which now makes them dominant in their own countries.
Natural selection, as has just been remarked, leads to divergence of
character and to much extinction of the less improved and intermediate
forms of life. On these principles, the nature of the affinities, and
the generally well-defined distinctions between the innumerable organic
beings in each class throughout the world, may be explained. It is
a truly wonderful fact--the wonder of which we are apt to overlook
from familiarity--that all animals and all plants throughout all time
and space should be related to each other in groups, subordinate to
groups, in the manner which we everywhere behold--namely, varieties of
the same species most closely related, species of the same genus less
closely and unequally related, forming sections and sub-genera, species
of distinct genera much less closely related, and genera related in
different degrees, forming sub-families, families, orders, sub-classes
and classes. The several subordinate groups in any class cannot be
ranked in a single file, but seem clustered round points, and these
round other points, and so on in almost endless cycles. If species had
been independently created, no explanation would have been possible of
this kind of classification; but it is explained through inheritance
and the complex action of natural selection, entailing extinction and
divergence of character....

The affinities of all the beings of the same class have sometimes been
represented by a great tree. I believe this simile largely speaks the
truth. The green and budding twigs may represent existing species; and
those produced during former years may represent the long succession
of extinct species. At each period of growth all the growing twigs
have tried to branch out on all sides, and to overtop and kill the
surrounding twigs and branches, in the same manner as species and
groups of species have at all times overmastered other species in the
great battle for life. The limbs divided into great branches, and these
into lesser and lesser branches, were themselves once, when the tree
was young, budding twigs; and this connection of the former and present
buds by ramifying branches may well represent the classification of
all extinct and living species in groups subordinate to groups. Of the
many twigs which flourished when the tree was a mere bush, only two or
three, now grown into great branches, yet survive and bear the other
branches; so with the species which lived during long-past geological
periods, very few have left living and modified descendants. From
the first growth of the tree, many a limb and branch has decayed and
dropped off; and these fallen branches of various sizes may represent
those whole orders, families, and genera which have now no living
representatives, and which are known to us only in a fossil state. As
we here and there see a thin straggling branch springing from a fork
low down in a tree, and which by some chance has been favoured and is
still alive on its summit, so we occasionally see an animal like the
Ornithorhynchus or Lepidosiren, which in some small degree connects by
its affinities two large branches of life, and which has apparently
been saved from fatal competition by having inhabited a protected
station. As buds give rise by growth to fresh buds, and these, if
vigorous, branch out and overtop on all sides many a feebler branch, so
by generation I believe it has been with the great Tree of Life, which
fills with its dead and broken branches the crust of the earth, and
covers the surface with its ever-branching and beautiful ramifications.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 32: From the _Origin of Species_. Ch. IV.]




                                  XXX

                            THEODOR SCHWANN

                               1810-1882


 _Theodor Schwann, the son of a Prussian printer, was born at Neuss,
 Prussia, December 7, 1810. He first studied medicine, but was persuaded
 to devote himself to science by Johannes Mueller, who appointed him
 assistant in the anatomical museum. In 1838 he was called to the
 Catholic University of Louvain, and later removed to Liège. One of
 the first to suggest the chemical explanation of life, he discovered
 the presence and function of pepsin as a ferment in digestion. In
 1839 he established his great theory that all life is composed of
 inter-connected cellular units--a conception which revolutionized
 biology. He died at Liège on January 11, 1882._


                            CELL THEORY[33]

The various opinions entertained with respect to the fundamental powers
of an organized body may be reduced to two, which are essentially
different from one another. The first is, that every organism
originates with an inherent power, which models it into conformity
with a predominant idea, arranging the molecules in the relation
necessary for accomplishing certain purposes held forth by this idea.
Here, therefore, that which arranges and combines the molecules is a
power acting with a definite purpose. A power of this kind would be
essentially different from all the powers of inorganic nature, because
action goes on in the latter quite blindly. A certain impression is
followed of necessity by a certain change of quality and quantity,
without regard to any purpose. In this view, however, the fundamental
power of the organism (or the soul, in the sense employed by Stahl)
would, inasmuch as it works with a definite individual purpose, be
much more nearly allied to the immaterial principle, endued with
consciousness which we must admit operates in man.

The other view is, that the fundamental powers of organized bodies
agree essentially with those of inorganic nature, that they work
altogether blindly according to laws of necessity and irrespective
of any purpose, that they are powers which are as much established
with the existence of matter as the physical powers are. It might be
assumed that the powers which form organized bodies do not appear at
all in inorganic nature, because this or that particular combination
of molecules, by which the powers are elicited, does not occur in
inorganic nature, and yet they might not be essentially distinct
from physical and chemical powers. It cannot, indeed, be denied that
adaptation to a particular purpose, in some individuals even in a
high degree, is characteristic of every organism; but, according to
this view, the source of this adaptation does not depend upon each
organism being developed by the operation of its own power in obedience
to that purpose, but it originates as in inorganic nature, in the
creation of the matter with its blind powers by a rational Being. We
know, for instance, the powers which operate in our planetary system.
They operate, like all physical powers, in accordance with blind laws
of necessity, and yet is the planetary system remarkable for its
adaptation to a purpose. The ground of this adaptation does not lie in
the powers, but in Him, who has so constituted matter with its powers,
that in blindly obeying its laws it produces a whole suited to fulfil
an intended purpose. We may even assume that the planetary system
has an individual adaptation to a purpose. Some external influence,
such as a comet, may occasion disturbances of motion, without thereby
bringing the whole into collision; derangements may occur on single
planets, such as a high tide, &c., which are yet balanced entirely by
physical laws. As respects their adaptation to a purpose, organized
bodies differ from these in degree only; and by this second view we are
just as little compelled to conclude that the fundamental powers of
organization operate according to laws of adaptation to a purpose, as
we are in inorganic nature.

The first view of the fundamental powers of organized bodies may be
called the teleological, the second the physical view. An example will
show at once, how important for physiology is the solution of the
question as to which is to be followed. If, for instance, we define
inflammation and suppuration to be the effort of the organism to remove
a foreign body that has been introduced into it; or fever to be the
effort of the organism to eliminate diseased matter, and both as the
result of the “autocracy of the organism,” then these explanations
accord with the teleological view. For, since by these processes the
obnoxious matter is actually removed, the process which effects them
is one adapted to an end; and as the fundamental power of the organism
operates in accordance with definite purposes, it may either set these
processes in action primarily, or may also summon further powers of
matter to its aid, always, however, remaining itself the “primum
movens.” On the other hand, according to the physical view, this is
just as little an explanation as it would be to say, that the motion of
the earth around the sun is an effort of the fundamental power of the
planetary system to produce a change of seasons on the planets, or to
say, that ebb and flood are the reaction of the organism of the earth
upon the moon.

In physics, all those explanations which were suggested by a
teleological view of nature, as “horror vacui,” and the like, have
long been discarded. But in animated nature, adaptation--individual
adaptation--to a purpose is so prominently marked, that it is
difficult to reject all teleological explanations. Meanwhile it must
be remembered that those explanations, which explain at once all
and nothing, can be but the last resources, when no other view can
possibly be adopted; and there is no such necessity for admitting the
teleological view in the case of organized bodies. The adaptation of
a purpose which is characteristic of organized bodies differs only in
degree from what is apparent also in the inorganic part of nature;
and the explanation that organized bodies are developed, like all the
phenomena of inorganic nature, by the operation of blind laws framed
with the matter, cannot be rejected as impossible. Reason certainly
requires some ground for such adaptation, but for her it is sufficient
to assume that matter with the powers inherent in it owes its existence
to a rational Being. Once established and preserved in their integrity,
these powers may, in accordance with their immutable laws of blind
necessity, very well produce combinations, which manifest, even in
a high degree, individual adaptation to a purpose. If, however,
rational power interpose after creation merely to sustain, and not
as an immediately active agent, it may, so far as natural science is
concerned, be entirely excluded from the consideration of the creation.

But the teleological view leads to further difficulties in the
explanation, and especially with respect to generation. If we assume
each organism to be formed by a power which acts according to a certain
predominant idea, a portion of this power may certainly reside in the
ovum during generation; but then we must ascribe to this subdivision
of the original power, at the separation of the ovum from the body of
the mother, the capability of producing an organism similar to that
which the power, of which it is but a portion, produced: that is, we
must assume that this power is infinitely divisible, and yet that each
part may perform the same actions as the whole power. If, on the other
hand, the power of organized bodies reside, like the physical powers,
in matter as such, and be set free only by a certain combination of the
molecules, as, for instance, electricity is set free by the combination
of a zinc and copper plate, then also by the conjunction of molecules
to form an ovum the power may be set free, by which the ovum is capable
of appropriating to itself fresh molecules, and these newly-conjoined
molecules again by this very mode of combination acquire the same
power to assimilate fresh molecules. The first development of the
many forms of organized bodies--the progressive formation of organic
nature indicated by geology--is also much more difficult to understand
according to the teleological than the physical view.

Another objection to the teleological view may be drawn from the
foregoing investigation. The molecules, as we have seen, are not
immediately combined in various ways, as the purpose of the organism
requires, but the formation of the elementary parts of organic
bodies is regulated by laws which are essentially the same for all
elementary parts. One can see no reason why this should be the case,
if each organism be endued with a special power to frame the parts
according to the purpose which they have to fulfil: it might much
rather be expected that the formative principle, although identical
for organs physiologically the same, would yet in different tissues
be correspondingly varied. This resemblance of the elementary parts
has, in the instance of plants, already led to the conjecture that
the cells are really the organisms, and that the whole plant is an
aggregrate of these organisms arranged according to certain laws.
But since the elementary parts of animals bear exactly similar
relations, the individuality of an entire animal would thus be lost;
and yet precisely upon the individuality of the whole animal does the
assumption rest, that it possesses a single fundamental power operating
in accordance with a definite idea.

Meanwhile, we cannot altogether lay aside teleological views if all
phenomena are not clearly explicable by the physical view. It is,
however, unnecessary to do so, because an explanation, according to
the teleological view, is only admissible when the physical can be
shown to be impossible. In any case it conduces much more to the object
of science to strive, at least, to adopt the physical explanation.
And I would repeat that, when speaking of a physical explanation of
organic phenomena, it is not necessary to understand an explanation by
known physical powers, such, for instance, as that universal refuge
electricity, and the like; but an explanation by means of powers which
operate like the physical powers, in accordance with strict laws of
blind necessity, whether they be also to be found in inorganic nature
or not.

We set out, therefore, with the supposition that an organized body
is not produced by a fundamental power which is guided in its
operation by a definite idea, but is developed, according to blind
laws of necessity, by powers which, like those of inorganic nature,
are established by the very existence of matter. As the elementary
materials of organic nature are not different from those of the
inorganic kingdom, the source of the organic phenomena can only
reside in another combination of these materials, whether it be in a
peculiar mode of union of the elementary atoms to form atoms of the
second order, or in the arrangement of these conglomerate molecules
when forming either the separate morphological elementary parts of
organisms, or an entire organism. We have here to do with the latter
question solely, whether the cause of organic phenomena lies in the
whole organism, or in its separate elementary parts. If this question
can be answered, a further inquiry still remains as to whether the
organism or its elementary parts possess this power through the
peculiar mode of combination of the conglomerate molecules, or through
the mode in which the elementary atoms are united into conglomerate
molecules.

We may, then, form the two following ideas of the cause of organic
phenomena, such as growth, &c. First, that the cause resides in the
totality of the organism. By the combination of the molecules into
a systematic whole, such as the organism is in every stage of its
development, a power is engendered, which enables such an organism to
take up fresh material from without, and appropriate it either to the
formation of new elementary parts, or to the growth of those already
present. Here, therefore, the cause of the growth of the elementary
parts resides in the totality of the organism. The other mode of
explanation is, that growth does not ensue from a power resident in the
entire organism, but that each separate elementary part is possessed of
an independent power, an independent life, so to speak; in other words,
the molecules in each separate elementary part are so combined as to
set free a power by which it is capable of attracting new molecules,
and so increasing, and the whole organism subsists only by means of
the reciprocal action of the single elementary parts. So that here the
single elementary parts only exert an active influence on nutrition,
and totality of the organism may indeed be a condition, but is not in
this view a cause.

In order to determine which of these two views is the correct one,
we must summon to our aid the results of the previous investigation.
We have seen that all organized bodies are composed of essentially
similar parts, namely, of cells; that these cells are formed and grow
in accordance with essentially similar laws; and, therefore, that these
processes must, in every instance, be produced by the same powers. Now,
if we find that some of these elementary parts, not differing from the
others, are capable of separating themselves from the organism, and
pursuing an independent growth, we may thence conclude that each of
the other elementary parts, each cell, is already possessed of power
to take up fresh molecules and growth; and that, therefore, every
elementary part possesses a power of its own, an independent life, by
means of which it would be enabled to develop itself independently,
if the relations which it bore to external parts were but similar to
those in which it stands in the organism. The ova of animals afford us
example of such independent cells, growing apart from the organism.
It may, indeed, be said of the ova of higher animals, that after
impregnation the ovum is essentially different from the other cells of
the organism; that by impregnation there is a something conveyed to the
ovum, which is more to it than an external condition for vitality, more
than nutrient matter; and that it might thereby have first received
its peculiar vitality, and therefore that nothing can be inferred from
it with respect to the other cells. But this fails in application to
those classes which consist only of female individuals, as well as
with the spores of the lower plants; and, besides, in the inferior
plants any given cell may be separated from the plant, and then grow
alone. So that here are whole plants consisting of cells, which can
be positively proved to have independent vitality. Now, as all cells
grow according to the same laws, and consequently the cause of growth
cannot in one case lie in the cell, and in another in the whole
organism; and since it may be further proved that some cells, which
do not differ from the rest in their mode of growth, are developed
independently, we must ascribe to all cells an independent vitality,
that is, such combinations of molecules as occur in any single cell,
are capable of setting free the power by which it is enabled to take
up fresh molecules. The cause of nutrition and growth resides not in
the organism as a whole, but in the separate elementary parts--the
cells. The failure of growth in the case of any particular cell, when
separated from an organized body, is as slight an objection to this
theory as it is an objection against the independent vitality of a bee,
that it cannot continue long in existence after being separated from
its swarm. The manifestation of the power which resides in the cell
depends upon conditions to which it is subject only when in connexion
with the whole (organism).

The question, then, as to the fundamental power of organized bodies
resolves itself into that of the fundamental powers of the individual
cells. We must now consider the general phenomena attending the
formation of cells, in order to discover what powers may be presumed
to exist in the cells to explain them. These phenomena may be arranged
in two natural groups: first, those which relate to the combination of
the molecules to form a cell, and which may be denominated the plastic
phenomena of the cells; secondly, those which result from chemical
changes either in the component particles of the cell itself, or in the
surrounding cytoblastema, and which may be called metabolic phenomena
(_to metabolikon_, implying that which is liable to occasion or to
suffer change).

The general plastic appearances in the cells are, as we have seen,
the following: at first a minute corpuscle is formed (the nucleolus);
a layer of substance (the nucleus) is then precipitated around it,
which becomes more thickened and expanded by the continual deposition
of fresh molecules between those already present. Deposition goes on
more vigorously at the outer part of this layer than at the inner.
Frequently the entire layer, or in other instances the outer part of
it only, becomes condensed to a membrane, which may continue to take
up new molecules in such a manner that it increases more rapidly in
superficial extent than in thickness, and thus an intervening cavity is
necessarily formed between it and the nucleolus. A second layer (cell)
is next precipitated around this first, in which precisely the same
phenomena are repeated, with merely the difference that in this case
the processes, especially the growth of the layer and the formation of
the space intervening between it and the first layer (the cell-cavity),
go on more rapidly and more completely. Such were the phenomena in
the formation of most cells; in some, however, there appeared to be
only a single layer formed, while in others (those especially in which
the nucleolus was hollow) there were three. The other varieties in
the development of the elementary parts were (as we saw) reduced to
these--that if two neighbouring cells commence their formation so near
to one another that the boundaries of the layers forming around each
of them meet at any spot, a common layer may be formed enclosing the
two incipient cells. So at least the origin of nuclei, with two or
more nucleoli, seemed explicable, by a coalescence of the first layers
(corresponding to the nucleus), and the union of many primary cells
into one secondary cell by a similar coalescence of the second layers
(which correspond to the cell). But the further development of these
common layers proceeds as though they were only an ordinary single
layer. Lastly, there were some varieties in the progressive development
of the cells, which were referable to an unequal deposition of the new
molecules between those already present in the separate layers. In this
way modifications of form and division of the cells were explained.
And among the number of the plastic phenomena in the cells we may
mention, lastly, the formation of secondary deposits; for instances
occur in which one or more new layers, each on the inner surface of
the previous one, are deposited on the inner surface of a simple or of
a secondary cell.

These are the most important phenomena observed in the formation and
development of cells. The unknown cause, presumed to be capable of
explaining these processes in the cells, may be called the plastic
power of the cells. We will, in the next place, proceed to determine
how far a more accurate definition of this power may be deduced from
these phenomena.

In the first place, there is a power of attraction exerted in the
very commencement of the cell, in the nucleolus, which occasions the
addition of new molecules to those already present. We may imagine
the nucleolus itself to be first formed by a sort of crystallization
from out of a concentrated fluid. For if a fluid be so concentrated
that the molecules of the substance in solution exert a more powerful
mutual attraction than is exerted between them and the molecules of
the fluid in which they are dissolved, a part of the solid substance
must be precipitated. One can readily understand that the fluid must be
more concentrated when new cells are being formed in it than when those
already present have merely to grow. For if the cell is already partly
formed, it exerts an attractive force upon the substance still in
solution. There is then a cause for the deposition of this substance,
which does not co-operate when no part of the cell is yet formed.
Therefore, the greater the attractive force of the cell is, the less
concentration of the fluid is required; while, at the commencement of
the formation of a cell, the fluid must be more than concentrated. But
the conclusion which may be thus directly drawn, as to the attractive
power of the cell, may also be verified by observation. Wherever the
nutrient fluid is not equally distributed in a tissue, the new cells
are formed in that part into which the fluid penetrates first, and
where, consequently, it is most concentrated. Upon this fact, as we
have seen, depended the difference between the growth of organized and
unorganized tissues. And this confirmation of the foregoing conclusion
by experience speaks also for the correctness of the reasoning itself.

The attractive power of the cells operates so as to effect the addition
of new molecules in two ways,--first, in layers, and secondly, in such
a manner in each layer that the new molecules are deposited between
those already present. This is only an expression of the fact; the
more simple law, by which several layers are formed and the molecules
are not all deposited between those already present, cannot yet be
explained. The formation of layers may be repeated once, twice, or
thrice. The growth of the separate layers is regulated by a law,
that the deposition of new molecules should be greatest at the part
where the nutrient fluid is most concentrated. Hence the outer part
particularly becomes condensed into a membrance both in the layer
corresponding to the nucleus and in that answering to the cell, because
the nutrient fluid penetrates from without, and consequently is more
concentrated at the outer than at the inner part of each layer. For
the same reason the nucleus grows rapidly, so long as the layer of the
cell is not formed around it, but it either stops growing altogether,
or at least grows much more slowly as soon as the cell-layer has
surrounded it; because then the latter receives the nutrient matter
first, and, therefore, in a more concentrated form. And hence the cell
becomes, in a general sense, much more completely developed, while
the nucleus-layer usually remains at a stage of development, in which
the cell-layer had been in its earlier period. The addition of new
molecules is so arranged that the layers increase more considerably in
superficial extent than in thickness; and thus an intervening space
is formed between each layer and the one preceding it, by which cells
and nuclei are formed into actual hollow vesicles. From this it may be
inferred that the deposition of new molecules is more active between
those which lie side by side along the surface of the membrane, than
between those which lie one upon the other in its thickness. Were it
otherwise, each layer would increase in thickness, but there would be
no intervening cavity between it and the previous one, there would be
no vesicles, but a solid body composed of layers.

Attractive power is exerted in all the solid parts of the cell. This
follows, not only from the fact that new molecules may be deposited
everywhere between those already present, but also from the formation
of secondary deposits. When the cavity of a cell is once formed,
material may be also attracted from its contents and deposited in
layers; and as this deposition takes place upon the inner surface
of the membrane of the cell, it is probably that which exerts the
attractive influence. This formation of layers on the inner surface of
the cell-membrane is, perhaps, merely a repetition of the same process
by which, at an earlier period, nucleus and cell were precipitated as
layers around the nucleolus. It must, however, be remarked that the
identity of these two processes cannot be so clearly proved as that of
the processes by which nucleus and cell are formed; more especially
as there is a variety in the phenomena, for the secondary deposits in
plants occur in spiral forms, while this has at least not yet been
demonstrated in the formation of the cell-membrane and the nucleus,
although by some botanical writers the cell-membrane itself is supposed
to consist of spirals.

The power of attraction may be uniform throughout the whole cell,
but it may also be confined to single spots; the deposition of new
molecules is then more vigorous at these spots, and the consequence of
this uneven growth of the cell-membrane is a change in the form of the
cell.

The attractive power of the cells manifest a certain form of election
in its operation. It does not take up all the substances contained in
the surrounding cytoblastema, but only particular ones, either those
which are analogous with the substance already present in the cell
(assimilation), or such as differ from it in chemical properties. The
several layers grow by assimilation, but when a new layer is being
formed, different material from that of the previously-formed layer
is attracted: for the nucleolus, the nucleus and cell-membrane are
composed of materials which differ in their chemical properties.

Such are the peculiarities of the plastic power of the cells, so far as
they can as yet be drawn from observation. But the manifestations of
this power presuppose another faculty of the cells. The cytoblastema,
in which the cells are formed, contains the elements of the materials
of which the cell is composed, but in other combinations; it is
not a mere solution of cell-material, but it contains only certain
organic substances in solution. The cells, therefore, not only attract
materials from out of the cytoblastema, but they must have the faculty
of producing chemical changes in its constituent particles. Besides
which, all the parts of the cell itself may be chemically altered
during the process of its vegetation. The unknown cause of all these
phenomena, which we comprise under the term metabolic phenomena of the
cells, we will denominate the metabolic power.

The next point which can be proved is, that this power is an attribute
of the cells themselves, and that the cytoblastema is passive under
it. We may mention vinous fermentation as an instance of this. A
decoction of malt will remain for a long time unchanged; but as soon as
some yeast is added to it, which consists partly of entire fungi and
partly of a number of single cells, the chemical change immediately
ensues. Here the decoction of malt is the cytoblastema; the cells
clearly exhibit activity, the cytoblastema, in this instance even a
boiled fluid, being quite passive during the change. The same occurs
when any simple cells, as the spores of the lower plants, are sown in
boiled substances.

In the cells themselves again, it appears to be the solid parts, the
cell-membrane and the nucleus, which produce the change. The contents
of the cell undergo similar and even more various changes than the
external the cytoblastema, and it is at least probable that these
changes originate with the solid parts composing the cells, especially
the cell-membrane, because the secondary deposits are formed on
the inner surface of the cell-membrane, and other precipitates are
generally formed in the first instance around the nucleus. It may
therefore, on the whole, be said that the solid component particles of
the cells possess the power of chemically altering the substances in
contact with them.

The substances which result from the transformation of the contents
of the cell are different from those which are produced by change
in the external cytoblastema. What is the cause of this difference,
if the metamorphosing power of the cell-membrane be limited to its
immediate neighbourhood merely? Might we not much rather expect that
converted substance would be found without distinction on the inner
as on the outer surface of the cell-membrane? It might be said that
the cell-membrane converts the substance in contact with it without
distinction, and that the variety in the products of this conversion
depends only upon a difference between the convertible substance
contained in the cell and the external cytoblastema. But the question
then arises, as to how it happens that the contents of the cell differ
from the external cytoblastema. If it be true that the cell-membrane,
which at first closely surrounds the nucleus, expands in the course of
its growth, so as to leave an interspace between it and the cell, and
that the contents of the cell consist of fluid which has entered this
space merely by imbibition, they cannot differ essentially from the
external cytoblastema. I think therefore that, in order to explain the
distinction between the cell-contents and the external cytoblastema,
we must ascribe to the cell-membrane not only the power in general of
chemically altering the substances which it is either in contact with,
or has imbibed, but also of so separating them that certain substances
appear on its inner, and others on its outer surface. The secretion of
substances already present in the blood, as, for instance, of urea, by
the cells with which the urinary tubes are lined, cannot be explained
without such a faculty of the cells. There is, however, nothing so
very hazardous in it, since it is a fact that different substances are
separated in the decompositions produced by the galvanic pile. It might
perhaps be conjectured from this peculiarity of the metabolic phenomena
in the cells, that a particular position of the axes of the atoms
composing the cell-membrane is essential for the production of these
appearances.

Chemical changes occur, however, not only in the cytoblastema and the
cell-contents, but also in the solid parts of which the cells are
composed, particularly the cell-membrane. Without wishing to assert
that there is any intimate connexion between the metabolic power
of the cells and galvanism, I may yet, for the sake of making the
representation of the process more clear, remark that the chemical
changes produced by a galvanic pile are accompanied by corresponding
changes in the pile itself.

The more obscure the cause of the metabolic phenomena in the cells
is, the more accurately we must mark the circumstances and phenomena
under which they occur. One condition to them is a certain temperature,
which has a maximum and a minimum. The phenomena are not produced in
a temperature below 0° or above 80° R.; boiling heat destroys this
faculty of the cells permanently; but the most favorable temperature is
one between 10° and 32° R. Heat is evolved by the process itself.

Oxygen, or carbonic acid, in a gaseous form or lightly confined, is
essentially necessary to the metabolic phenomena of the cells. The
oxygen disappears and carbonic acid is formed, or _vice versa_,
carbonic acid disappears, and oxygen is formed. The universality of
respiration is based entirely upon this fundamental condition to the
metabolic phenomena of the cells. It is so important that, as we shall
see further on, even the principal varieties of form in organized
bodies are occasioned by this peculiarity of the metabolic process in
the cells.

Each cell is not capable of producing chemical changes in every organic
substance contained in solution, but only in particular ones. The fungi
of fermentation, for instance, effect no changes in any other solutions
than sugar; and the spores of certain plants do not become developed in
all substances. In the same manner it is probable that each cell in the
animal body converts only particular constituents of the blood.

The metabolic power of the cells is arrested not only by powerful
chemical actions, such as destroy organic substances in general, but
also by matters which chemically are less uncongenial; for instance,
concentrated solutions of neutral salts. Other substances, as arsenic,
do so in less quantity. The metabolic phenomena may be altered in
quality by other substances, both organic and inorganic, and a change
of this kind may result even from mechanical impressions on the cells.

Such are the most essential characteristics of the fundamental powers
of the cell, so far as they can as yet be deduced from the phenomena.
And now, in order to comprehend distinctly in what the peculiarity of
the formative process of a cell, and therefore in what the peculiarity
of the essential phenomenon in the formation of organized bodies
consist, we will compare this process with a phenomenon of inorganic
nature as nearly as possible similar to it. Disregarding all that
is specially peculiar to the formation of cells, in order to find a
more general definition in which it may be included with a process
occurring in inorganic nature, we may view it as a process in which a
solid body of definite and regular shape is formed in a fluid at the
expense of a substance held in solution by that fluid. The process of
crystallization in inorganic nature comes also within this definition,
and is, therefore, the nearest analogue to the formation of cells.

Let us now compare the two processes, that the difference of the
organic process may be clearly manifest. First, with reference to the
plastic phenomena, the forms of cells and crystals are very different.
The primary forms of crystals are simple, always angular, and bounded
by plane surfaces; they are regular, or at least symmetrical, and
even the very varied secondary forms of crystals are almost, without
exception, bounded by plane surfaces. But manifold as is the form of
cells, they have very little resemblance to crystals; round surfaces
predominate, and where angles occur, they are never quite sharp, and
the polyhedral crystal-like form of many cells results only from
mechanical causes. The structure too of cells and of crystals is
different. Crystals are solid bodies, composed merely of layers placed
one upon another; cells are hollow vesicles, either single, or several
inclosed one within another. And if we regard the membranes of these
vesicles as layers, there will still remain marks of difference between
them and crystals; these layers are not in contact, but contain fluid
between them, which is not the case with crystals; the layers in the
cells are few, from one to three only; and they differ from each
other in chemical properties, while those of crystals consist of the
same chemical substance. Lastly, there is also a great difference
between crystals and cells in their mode of growth. Crystals grow by
apposition, the new molecules are set only upon the surface of those
already deposited, but cells increase also by intussusception, that
is to say, the new molecules are deposited also between those already
present.

But greatly as these plastic phenomena differ in cells and in crystals,
the metabolic are yet more different, or rather they are quite peculiar
to cells. For a crystal to grow, it must be already present as such in
the solution, and some extraneous cause must interpose to diminish its
solubility. Cells, on the contrary, are capable of producing a chemical
change in the surrounding fluid, of generating matters which had not
previously existed in it as such, but of which only the elements were
present in another combination. They therefore require no extraneous
influence to effect a change of solubility; for if they can produce
chemical changes in the surrounding fluid, they may also produce
such substances as could not be held in solution under the existing
circumstances, and therefore need no external cause of growth. If a
crystal be laid in a pretty strong solution, of a substance similar
even to itself, nothing ensues without our interference, or the crystal
dissolves completely: the fluid must be evaporated for the crystal
to increase. If a cell be laid in a solution of a substance, even
different from itself, it grows and converts this substance without
our aid. And this it is from which the process going on in the cells
(so long as we do not separate it into its several acts) obtains that
magical character, to which attaches the idea of Life.

From this we perceive how very different are the phenomena in the
formation of cells and of crystals. Meanwhile, however, the points
of resemblance between them should not be overlooked. They agree in
this important point, that solid bodies of a certain regular shape are
formed in obedience to definite laws at the expense of a substance
contained in solution in a fluid; and the crystal, like the cell, is
so far an active and positive agent as to cause the substances which
are precipitated to be deposited on itself, and nowhere else. We
must, therefore, attribute to it as well as to the cell a power to
attract the substance held in solution in the surrounding fluid. It
does not indeed follow that these two attractive powers, the power of
crystallization--to give it a brief title--and the plastic power of the
cells, are essentially the same. This could only be admitted, if it
were proved that both powers acted according to the same laws. But this
is seen at the first glance to be by no means the case: the phenomena
in the formation of cells and crystals, are, as we have observed, very
different, even if we regard merely the plastic phenomena of the cells,
and leave their metabolic power (which may possibly arise from some
other peculiarity of organic substance) for a time entirely out of the
question.

Is it, however, possible that these distinctions are only secondary,
that the power of crystallization and the plastic power of the cells
are identical, and that an original difference can be demonstrated
between the substance of cells and that of crystals, by which we
may perceive that the substance of cells must crystallize as cells
according to the laws by which crystals are formed, rather than in the
shape of the ordinary crystals? It may be worth while to institute such
an inquiry.

In seeking such a distinction between the substance of cells and that
of crystals, we may say at once that it cannot consist in anything
which the substance of cells has in common with those organic
substances which crystallize in the ordinary form. Accordingly, the
more complicated arrangement of the atoms of the second order in
organic bodies cannot give rise to this difference; for we see in
sugar, for instance, that the mode of crystallization is not altered by
this chemical composition.

Another point of difference by which inorganic bodies are distinguished
from at least some of the organic bodies, is the faculty of imbibition.
Most organic bodies are capable of being infiltrated by water, and
in such a manner that it penetrates not so much into the interspaces
between the elementary tissues of the body, as into the simple
structureless tissues, such as areolar tissue, &c.; so that they form
an homogeneous mixture, and we can neither distinguish particles
of organic matter, nor interspaces filled with water. The water
occupies the infiltrated organic substances, just as it is present in
a solution, and there is as much difference between the capacity for
imbibition and capillary permeation, as there is between a solution and
the phenomena of capillary permeation. When water soaks through a layer
of glue, we do not imagine it to pass through pores, in the common
sense of the term; and this is just the condition of all substances
capable of imbibition. They possess, therefore, a double nature,
they have a definite form like solid bodies; but like fluids, on the
other hand, they are also permeable by anything held in solution. As
a specifically lighter fluid poured on one specifically heavier so
carefully as not to mix with it, yet gradually penetrates it, so also,
every solution, when brought into contact with a membrane already
infiltrated with water, bears the same relations to the membrane, as
though it were a solution. And crystallization being the transition
from the fluid to the solid state, we may conceive it possible, or
even probable, that if bodies, capable of existing in an intermediate
state between solid and fluid could be made to crystallize, a
considerable difference would be exhibited from the ordinary mode of
crystallization. In fact, there is nothing, which we call a crystal,
composed of substance capable of imbibition; and even among organized
substances, crystallization takes place only in those which are capable
of imbibition, as fat, sugar, tartaric acid, &c. The bodies capable of
imbibition, therefore, either do not crystallize at all, or they do so
under a form so different from the crystal that they are not recognized
as such.

Let us inquire what would most probably ensue if material capable of
imbibition crystallized according to the ordinary laws, what varieties
from the common crystals would be most likely to show themselves,
assuming only that the solution has permeated through the parts of
the crystal already formed, and that new molecules can therefore
be deposited between them. The ordinary crystals increase only by
apposition; but there may be an important difference in the mode of
this apposition. If the molecules were all deposited symmetrically
one upon another, we might indeed have a body of a certain external
form like a crystal; but it would not have the structure of one,
it would not consist of layers. The existence of this laminated
structure in crystals presupposes a double kind of apposition of their
molecules; for in each layer the newly-deposited molecules coalesce,
and become continuous with those of the same layer already present;
but those molecules which form the adjacent surfaces of two layers
do not coalesce. This is a remarkable peculiarity in the formation
of crystals, and we are quite ignorant of its cause. We cannot yet
perceive why the new molecules, which are being deposited on the
surface of a crystal (already formed up to a certain point), do not
coalesce and become continuous with those already deposited, like the
molecules in each separate layer, instead of forming, as they do, a
new layer; and why this new layer does not constantly increase in
thickness, instead of producing a second layer around the crystal, and
so on. In the meantime we can do no more than express the fact in the
form of a law, that the coalescing molecules are deposited rather along
the surface beside each other, than in the thickness upon one another,
and thus, as the breadth of the layer depends upon the size of the
crystal, so also the layer can attain only a certain thickness, and
beyond this, the molecules which are being deposited cannot coalesce
with it, but must form a new layer.

If we now assume that bodies capable of imbibition could also
crystallize, the two modes of junction of the molecules should be
shown also by them. Their structure should also be laminated, at least
there is no perceptible reason for a difference in this particular,
as the very fact of layers being formed in common crystals shows that
the molecules need not be all joined together in the most exact manner
possible. The closest possible conjunction of the molecules takes place
only in the separate layers. In the common crystals this occurs by
apposition of the new molecules on the surface of those present and
coalescence with them. In bodies capable of imbibition, a much closer
union is possible, because in them the new molecules may be deposited
by intussusception between those already present. It is scarcely,
therefore, too bold an hypothesis to assume, that when bodies capable
of imbibition crystallize, their separate layers would increase by
intussusception; and that this does not happen in ordinary crystals,
simply because it is impossible.

Let us then imagine a portion of the crystal to be formed: new
molecules continue to be deposited, but do not coalesce with the
portion of the crystal already formed; they unite with one another
only, and form a new layer, which, according to analogy with the common
crystals, may invest either the whole or a part of the crystal. We
will assume that it invests the entire crystal. Now, although this
layer be formed by the deposition of new molecules between those
already present instead of by apposition, yet this does not involve
any change in the law, in obedience to which the deposition of the
coalescing molecules goes on more vigorously in two directions,
that is, along the surface, than it does in the third direction
corresponding to the thickness of the layer; that is to say, the
molecules which are deposited by intussusception between those already
present, must be deposited much more vigorously between those lying
together along the surface of the layer than between those which lie
over one another in its thickness. This deposition of molecules side
by side is limited in common crystals by the size of the crystal, or
by that of the surface on which the layer is formed; the coalescence
of molecules therefore ceases as regards that layer, and a new one
begins. But if the layers grow by intussusception in crystals capable
of imbibition, there is nothing to prevent the deposition of more
molecules between those which lie side by side upon the surface, even
after the lamina has invested the whole crystal; it may continue to
grow without the law by which the new molecules coalesce requiring to
be altered. But the consequence is, that the layer becomes, in the
first instance more condensed, that is, more solid substance is taken
into the same space; and afterwards it will expand and separate from
the completed part of the crystal so as to leave a hollow space between
itself and the crystal; this space fills with fluid by imbibition,
and the first-formed portion of the crystal adheres to a spot on its
inner surface. Thus, in bodies capable of imbibition, instead of a new
layer attached to the part of the crystal already formed, we obtain a
hollow vesicle. At first this must have the shape of the body of the
crystal around which it is formed, and must, therefore, be angular,
if the crystal is angular. If, however, we imagine this layer to be
composed of soft substance capable of imbibition, we may readily
comprehend how such a vesicle must very soon become round or oval. But
the first-formed part of the crystal also consists of substance capable
of imbibition, so that it is very doubtful whether it must have an
angular form at all. In common crystals atoms of some one particular
substance are deposited together, and we can understand how a certain
angular form of the crystal may result if these atoms have a certain
form, or if in certain axes they attract each other differently. But in
bodies capable of imbibition, an atom of one substance is not set upon
another atom of the same substance, but atoms of water come between;
atoms of water, which are not united with an atom of solid substance,
so as to form a compound atom, as in the water of crystallization, but
which exist in some other unknown manner between the atoms of solid
substance. It is not possible, therefore, to determine whether that
part of the crystal which is first formed must have an angular figure
or not.

An ordinary crystal consists of a number of laminæ; when so small as
to be but just discernible, it has the form which the whole crystal
afterwards exhibits, at least as far as regards the angles; we must
therefore suppose that the first layer is formed around a very small
corpuscle, which is of the same shape as the subsequent crystal. We
will call this the primitive corpuscle. It is doubtful what may be
the shape of this corpuscle in the crystals which are capable of
imbibition. The first layer, then, is formed around the corpuscle
in the way mentioned; it grows by intussusception, and thus forms
a hollow, round or oval vesicle, to the inner surface of which the
primitive corpuscle adheres. As all the new molecules that are being
deposited may be placed in this layer without any alteration being
required in the law which regulates the coalescence of the molecules
during crystallization, we must conclude that it remains the only
layer, and becomes greatly expanded, so as to represent all the
layers of an ordinary crystal. It is, however, a question whether
there may not exist some reasons why several layers can be formed.
We can certainly conceive such to be the case. The quantity of the
solid substance that must crystallize in a given time, depends upon
the concentration of the fluid; the number of molecules that may,
in accordance with the law already mentioned, be deposited in the
layer in a given time depends upon the quantity of the solution
which can penetrate the membrane by imbibition during that time. If
in consequence of the concentration of the fluid there must be more
precipitated in the time than can penetrate the membrane, it can only
be deposited as a new layer on the outer surface of the vesicle. When
this second layer is formed, the new molecules are deposited in it, and
it rapidly becomes expanded into a vesicle, on the inner surface of
which the first vesicle lies with its primitive corpuscle. The first
vesicle now either does not grow at all, or at any rate much more
slowly, and then only when the endosmosis into the cavity of the second
vesicle proceeds so rapidly that all that might be precipitated while
passing through it, is not deposited. The second vesicle, when it is
developed at all, must needs be developed relatively with more rapidity
than the first; for as the solution is in the most concentrated state
at the beginning, the necessity for the formation of a second layer
then occurs sooner; but when it is formed, the concentration of the
fluid is diminished, and this necessity occurs either later or not at
all. It is possible, however, that even a third, or fourth, and more,
may be formed; but the outermost layer must always be relatively the
most vigorously developed; for when the concentration of the solution
is only so strong, that all that must be deposited in a certain time,
can be deposited in the outermost layer, it is all applied to the
increase of this layer.

Such, then, would be the phenomena under which substances capable of
imbibition would probably crystallize, if they did so at all. I say
probably, for our incomplete knowledge of crystallization and the
faculty of imbibition, does not as yet admit of our saying anything
positively _a priori_. It is, however, obvious that these are the
principal phenomena attending the formation of cells. They consist
always of substance capable of imbibition; the first part formed is
a small corpuscle, not angular (nucleolus), around this a lamina is
deposited (nucleus), which advances rapidly in its growth, until a
second lamina (cell) is formed around it. This second now grows more
quickly and expands into a vesicle, as indeed often happens with
the first layer. In some rarer instances only one layer is formed;
in others, again, there are three. The only other difference in the
formation of cells is, that the separate layers do not consist of the
same chemical substance, while a common crystal is always composed
of one material. In instituting a comparison, therefore, between the
formation of cells and crystallization, the above-mentioned differences
in form, structure, and mode of growth fall altogether to the ground.
If crystals were formed from the same substance as cells, they would
probably, in these respects, be subject to the same conditions as the
cells. Meanwhile the metabolic phenomena, which are entirely absent in
crystals, still indicate essential distinctions.

Should this important difference between the mode of formation of
cells and crystals lead us to deny all intimate connexion of the two
processes, the comparison of the two may serve at least to give a clear
representation of the cell-life. The following may be conceived to be
the state of the matter: the material of which the cells are composed
is capable of producing chemical changes in the substance with which it
is in contact, just as the well-known preparation of platinum converts
alcohol into acetic acid. This power is possessed by every part of the
cell. Now, if the cytoblastema be so changed by a cell already formed,
that a substance is produced which cannot become attached to that cell,
it immediately crystallizes as the central nucleolus of a new cell. And
then this converts the cytoblastema in the same manner. A portion of
that which is converted may remain in the cytoblastema in solution,
or may crystallize as the commencement of new cells; another portion,
the cell-substance, crystallizes around the central corpuscle. The
cell-substance is either soluble in the cytoblastema, and crystallizes
from it, so soon as the latter becomes saturated with it; or else it is
insoluble, and crystallizes at the time of its formation, according to
the laws of crystallization of bodies capable of imbibition mentioned
above, forming in this manner one or more layers around the central
corpuscle, and so on. If we conceive the above to represent the mode
of formation of cells, we regard the plastic power of the cells as
identical with the power by which crystals grow. According to the
foregoing description of the crystallization of bodies capable of
imbibition, the most important plastic phenomena of the cells are
certainly satisfactorily explained. But let us see if this comparison
agrees with all the characteristics of the plastic power of the cells.

The attractive power of the cells does not always operate
symmetrically; the deposition of new molecules may be more vigorous in
particular spots, and thus produce a change in the form of the cell.
This is quite analogous to what happens in crystals; for although
in them an angle is never altered, there may be much more material
deposited on some surfaces than on others; and thus, for instance,
a quadrilateral prism may be formed out of a cube. In this case new
layers are deposited on one, or on two opposite sides of a cube. Now,
if one layer in cells represent a number of layers in a common crystal,
it may be easily perceived that instead of several new layers being
formed on two opposite surfaces of a cell, the one layer would grow
more at those spots, and thus a round cell would be elongated into a
fibre; and so with the other changes of form. Division of the cells
can have no analogue in common crystals, because that which is once
deposited is incapable of any further change. But this phenomenon
may be made to accord with the representation of crystals capable
of imbibition.... And if we ascribe to a layer of a crystal capable
of imbibition the power of producing chemical changes in organic
substances, we can very well understand also the origin of secondary
deposits on its inner surface as they occur in cells. For if, in
accordance with the laws of crystallization, the lamina has become
expanded into a vesicle, and its cavity has become filled by imbibition
with a solution of organic substance, there may be materials formed
by means of the converting influence of the lamina, which cannot any
longer be held in solution. These may, then, either crystallize within
the vesicle, as new crystals capable of imbibition under the form of
cells; or if they are allied to the substance of the vesicle, they may
so crystallize as to form part of the system of the vesicle itself:
the latter may occur in two ways, the new matters may be applied to
the increase of the vesicle, or they may form new layers on its inner
surface from the same cause which led to the first formation of the
vesicle itself as a layer. In the cells of plants these secondary
deposits have a spiral arrangement. This is a very important fact,
though the laws of crystallization do not seem to account for the
absolute necessity of it. If, however, it could be mathematically
proved from the laws of the crystallization of inorganic bodies, that
under the altered circumstances in which bodies capable of imbibition
are placed, these deposits must be arranged in spiral forms, it might
be asserted without hesitation that the plastic power of cells and the
fundamental powers of crystals are identical.

We come now, however, to some peculiarities in the plastic power of
cells, to which we might, at first sight, scarcely expect to find
anything analogous in crystals. The attractive power of the cells
manifests a certain degree of election in its operation; it does
not attract every substance present in the cytoblastema, but only
particular ones; and here a muscle-cell, there a fat-cell, is generated
from the same fluid, the blood. Yet crystals afford us an example
of a precisely similar phenomenon, and one which has already been
frequently adduced as analogous to assimilation. If a crystal of nitre
be placed in a solution of nitre and sulphate of soda, only the nitre
crystallizes; when a crystal of sulphate of soda is put in, only the
sulphate of soda crystallizes. Here, therefore, there occurs just the
same selection of the substance to be attracted.

We observed another law attending the development of the plastic
phenomena in the cells, viz. that a more concentrated solution is
requisite for the first formation of a cell than for its growth when
already formed, a law upon which the difference between organized and
unorganized tissues is based. In ordinary crystallization the solution
must be more than saturated for the process to begin. But when it is
over, there remains a mother lye, according to Thénard, which is no
longer saturated at the same temperature. This phenomenon accords
precisely with the cells; it shows that a more concentrated solution is
requisite for the commencement of crystallization than for the increase
of a crystal already formed. The fact has indeed been disputed by
Thomson; but if, in the undisputed experiment quoted above, the crystal
of sulphate of soda attracts the dissolved sulphate of soda rather
than the dissolved nitre, and _vice versa_, the crystal of nitre
attracts the dissolved nitre more than the dissolved sulphate of soda,
it follows that a crystal does attract a salt held in solution, because
the experiment proves that there are degrees of this attraction. But if
there be such an attraction exerted by a crystal, then the introduction
of a crystal into a solution of a salt, affords an efficient cause for
the deposition of this salt, which does not exist when no crystal is
introduced. The solution must therefore be more concentrated in the
latter case than in the former, though the difference be so slight
as not to be demonstrable by experiment. It would not, however, be
superfluous to repeat the experiments. In the instance of crystals
capable of imbibition, this difference may be considerably augmented,
since the attraction of molecules may increase perhaps considerably by
the penetrating of the solution between those already deposited.

We see then how all the plastic phenomena in the cells may be compared
with phenomena which, in accordance with the ordinary laws of
crystallization, would probably appear if bodies capable of imbibition
could be brought to crystallize. So long as the object of such a
comparison were merely to render the representation of the process
by which cells are formed more clear, there could not be much urged
against it; it involves nothing hypothetical, since it contains no
explanation; no assertion is made that the fundamental power of the
cells really has something in common with the power by which crystals
are formed. We have, indeed, compared the growth of organisms with
crystallization, in so far as in both cases solid substances are
deposited from a fluid, but we have not therefore asserted the
identity of the fundamental powers. So far we have not advanced beyond
the data, beyond a certain simple mode of representing the facts.

The question is, however, whether the exact accordance of the phenomena
would not authorize us to go further. If the formation and growth of
the elementary particles of organisms have nothing more in common with
crystallization than merely the deposition of solid substances from out
of a fluid, there is certainly no reason for assuming any more intimate
connexion of the two processes. But we have seen, first, that the laws
which regulate the deposition of the molecules forming the elementary
particles of organisms are the same for all elementary parts; that
there is a common principle in the development of all elementary parts,
namely, that of the formation of cells; it was then shown that the
power which induced the attachment of the new molecules did not reside
in the entire organism, but in the separated elementary particles (this
we called the plastic power of the cells); lastly, it was shown that
the laws, according to which the new molecules combine to form cells,
are (so far as our incomplete knowledge of the laws of crystallization
admits of our anticipating their probability) the same as those by
which substances capable of imbibition would crystallize. Now the
cells do, in fact, consist only of material capable of imbibition;
should we not then be justified in putting forth the proposition, that
the formation of the elementary parts of organisms is nothing but a
crystallization of substance, capable of imbibition, and the organism
nothing but an aggregate of such crystals capable of imbibition?

To advance so important a point as absolutely true, would certainly
need the clearest proof; but it cannot be said that even the premises
which have been set forth have in all points the requisite force. For
too little is still known of the cause of crystallization to predict
with safety (as was attempted above) what would follow if a substance
capable of imbibition were to crystallize. And if these premises were
allowed, there are two other points which must be proved in order to
establish the proposition in question: 1. That the metabolic phenomena
of the cells, which have not been referred to in the foregoing
argument, are as much the necessary consequence of the faculty of
imbibition, or of some other peculiarity of the substance of cells, as
the plastic phenomena are. 2. That if a number of crystals capable of
imbibition are formed, they must combine according to certain laws
so as to form a systematic whole, similar to an organism. Both these
points must be clearly proved, in order to establish the truth of the
foregoing view. But it is otherwise if this view be adduced merely as
an hypothesis, which may serve as a guide for new investigations. In
such case the inferences are sufficiently probable to justify such
an hypothesis, if only the two points just mentioned can be shown to
accord with it.

With reference to the first of these points, it would certainly be
impossible, in our ignorance as to the cause of chemical phenomena in
general, to prove that a crystal capable of imbibition must produce
chemical changes in substances surrounding it; but then we could not
infer, from the manner in which spongy platinum is formed, that it
would act so peculiarly upon oxygen and hydrogen. But in order to
render this view tenable as a possible hypothesis, it is only necessary
to see that it may be a consequence. It cannot be denied that it may:
there are several reasons for it, though they certainly are but weak.
For instance, since all cells possess this metabolic power, it is more
likely to depend on a certain position of the molecules, which in all
probability is essentially the same in all cells, than on the chemical
combination of the molecules, which is very different in different
cells. The presence, too, of different substances on the inner and
outer surface of the cell-membrane in some measure implies that a
certain direction of the axes of the atoms may be essential to the
metabolic phenomena of the cells. I think, therefore, that the cause of
the metabolic phenomena resides in that definite mode of arrangement
of the molecules which occurs in crystals, combined with the capacity
which the solution has to penetrate between these regularly deposited
molecules (by means of which, presuming the molecules to possess
polarity, a sort of galvanic pile will be formed), and that the same
phenomena would be observed in an ordinary crystal, if it could be
rendered capable of imbibition. And then perhaps the differences
of quality in the metabolic phenomena depend upon their chemical
composition.

In order to render tenable the hypothesis contained in the second
point, it is merely necessary to show that crystals capable of
imbibition can unite with one another according to certain laws. If
at their first formation all crystals were isolated, if they held
no relation whatever to each other, the view would leave entirely
unexplained how the elementary parts of organisms, that is, the
crystals in question, become united to form a whole. It is therefore
necessary to show that crystals do unite with each other according
to certain laws, in order to perceive, at least, the possibility
of their uniting also to form an organism, without the need of any
further combining power. But there are many crystals in which a union
of this kind, according to certain laws, is indisputable; indeed they
often form a whole, so like an organism in its entire form, that
groups of crystals are known in common life by the names of flowers,
trees, etc. I need only refer to the ice-flowers on the windows, or
to the lead-tree, etc. In such instances a number of crystals arrange
themselves in groups around others, which form an axis. If we consider
the contact of each crystal with the surrounding fluid to be an
indispensable condition to the growth of crystals which are not capable
of imbibition, but that those which are capable of imbibition, in which
the solution can penetrate whole layers of crystals, do not require
this condition, we perceive that the similarity between organisms and
these aggregations of crystals is as great as could be expected with
such difference of substance. As most cells require for the production
of their metabolic phenomena, not only their peculiar nutrient fluid,
but also the access of oxygen and the power of exhaling carbonic acid,
or _vice versa_; so, on the other hand, organisms in which there
is no circulation of respiratory fluid, or in which at least it is not
sufficient, must be developed in such a way as to present as extensive
a surface as possible to the atmospheric air. This is the condition of
plants, which require for their growth that the individual cells should
come into contact with the surrounding medium in a similar manner,
if not in the same degree as occurs in a crystal tree, and in them
indeed the cells unite into a whole organism in a form much resembling
a crystal tree. But in animals the circulation renders the contact of
the individual cells with the surrounding medium superfluous, and they
may have more compact forms, even though the laws by which the cells
arrange themselves are essentially the same.

The view then that organisms are nothing but the form under which
substances capable of imbibition crystallize, appears to be compatible
with the most important phenomena of organic life, and may be so
far admitted, that it is a possible hypothesis; or attempt towards
an explanation of these phenomena. It involves very much that is
uncertain and paradoxical, but I have developed it in detail, because
it may serve as a guide for new investigations. For even if no relation
between crystallization and the growth of organisms be admitted
in principle, this view has the advantage of affording a distinct
representation of the organic processes; an indispensable requisite for
the institution of new inquiries in a systematic manner, or for testing
by the discovery of new facts a mode of explanation which harmonizes
with phenomena already known.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 33: Translated from _Mikroskopische Untersuchungen über die
Wachstum der Tiere und der Pflanzen_ (Berlin, 1839) by Henry Smith
in the _Publications of the Sydenham Society_ (1847).]




                                 XXXI

                         HERMANN VON HELMHOLTZ

                               1821-1894


 _Hermann von Helmholtz, born at Potsdam, Prussia, August 31, 1821,
 studied medicine at the University of Berlin, from which he received
 his degree in 1842. He then entered the German Army as surgeon and
 in 1847 published his paper on “The Conservation of Energy,” which
 summarized historically the development of the idea. In 1849 he was
 appointed professor of physiology and general pathology at Königsberg.
 In 1855 he was called to Bonn, and in 1858 was elected to the chair of
 physiology at Heidelberg._

 _In 1851 he invented the ophthalmoscope and later at Heidelberg he
 continued his researches in the subject of sight, and also cleared up
 the problem of the mechanical causes of sound. In 1871 he was appointed
 professor of physics at the University of Berlin, where he remained
 until his death, September 8, 1894._


                    THE CONSERVATION OF ENERGY[34]

A new conquest of very general interest has been recently made by
natural philosophy. In the following pages I will endeavour to give a
notion of the nature of this conquest. It has reference to a new and
universal natural law, which rules the action of natural forces in
their mutual relations towards each other, and is as influential on
our theoretic views of natural processes as it is important in their
technical applications.

Among the practical arts which owe their progress to the development of
the natural sciences, from the conclusion of the middle ages downwards,
practical mechanics, aided by the mathematical science which bears the
same name, was one of the most prominent. The character of the art
was, at the time referred to, naturally very different from its present
one. Surprised and stimulated by its own success, it thought no problem
beyond its power, and immediately attacked some of the most difficult
and complicated. Thus it was attempted to build automaton figures which
should perform the functions of men and animals. The wonder of the last
century was Vaucanson’s duck, which fed and digested its food; the
flute player of the same artist, which moved all its fingers correctly;
the writing boy of the older, and the pianoforte player of the younger
Droz: which latter, when performing, followed its hands with its eyes,
and at the conclusion of the piece bowed courteously to the audience.
That men like those mentioned, whose talent might bear comparison with
the most inventive heads of the present age, should spend so much
time in the construction of these figures, which we at present regard
as the merest trifles, would be incomprehensible, if they had not
hoped in solemn earnest to solve a great problem. The writing boy of
the elder Droz was publicly exhibited in Germany some years ago. Its
wheel-work is so complicated, that no ordinary head would be sufficient
to decipher its manner of action. When, however, we are informed that
this boy and its constructor, being suspected of the black art, lay
for a time in the Spanish Inquisition, and with difficulty obtained
their freedom, we may infer that in those days even such a toy appeared
great enough to excite doubts as to its natural origin. And though
these artists may not have hoped to breathe into the creature of
their ingenuity a soul gifted with moral completeness, still there
were many who would be willing to dispense with the moral qualities
of their servants if, at the same time, their immoral qualities could
also be got rid of; and accept, instead of the mutability of flesh
and bones, services which should combine the regularity of a machine
with the durability of brass and steel. The object, therefore, which
the inventive genius of the past century placed before it with the
fullest earnestness, and not as a piece of amusement merely, was boldly
chosen, and was followed up with an expenditure of sagacity which has
contributed not a little to enrich the mechanical experience which a
later time knew how to take advantage of. We no longer seek to build
machines which shall fulfil the thousand services required of one man,
but desire, on the contrary, that a machine shall perform one service,
but shall occupy in doing it the place of a thousand men.

From these efforts to imitate living creatures, another idea, also by
a misunderstanding, seems to have developed itself, which, as it were,
formed the new philosopher’s stone of the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries. It was now the endeavour to construct a perpetual motion
machine. Under this term was understood a machine which, without being
wound up, without consuming in the working of it, falling water, wind
or any other natural force, should still continue in motion, the motive
power being perpetually supplied by the machine itself. Beasts and
human beings seemed to correspond to the idea of such an apparatus, for
they moved themselves energetically and incessantly as long as they
lived, were never wound up, and nobody set them in motion. A connection
between the taking in of nourishment and the development of force did
not make itself apparent. The nourishment seemed only necessary to
grease, as it were, the wheel-work of the animal machine, to replace
what was used up, and to renew the old. The development of force out of
itself seemed to be the essential peculiarity, the real quintessence of
organic life. If, therefore, men were to be constructed, a perpetual
motion must first be found.

Another hope also seemed to take up incidentally the second place,
which, in our wiser age, would certainly have claimed the first rank
in the thoughts of men. The perpetual motion was to produce work
inexhaustibly without corresponding consumption, that is to say, out
of nothing. Work, however, is money. Here, therefore, the practical
problem which the cunning heads of all centuries have followed in the
most diverse ways, namely, to fabricate money out of nothing, invited
solution. The similarity with the philosopher’s stone sought by the
ancient chemists was complete. That also was thought to contain the
quintessence of organic life, and to be capable of producing gold.

The spur which drove men to inquiry was sharp, and the talent of some
of the seekers must not be estimated as small. The nature of the
problem was quite calculated to entice poring brains, to lead them
round a circle for years, deceiving ever with new expectations, which
vanished upon nearer approach, and finally reducing these dupes of
hope to open insanity. The phantom could not be grasped. It would be
impossible to give a history of these efforts, as the clearer heads,
among whom the elder Droz must be ranked, convinced themselves of the
futility of their experiments, and were naturally not inclined to
speak much about them. Bewildered intellects, however, proclaimed
often enough that they had discovered the grand secret; and as the
incorrectness of their proceedings was always speedily manifest, the
matter fell into bad repute, and the opinion strengthened itself more
and more that the problem was not capable of solution; one difficulty
after another was brought under the dominion of mathematical mechanics,
and finally a point was reached where it could be proved that, at least
by the use of pure mechanical forces, no perpetual motion could be
generated.

We have here arrived at the idea of the driving force or power of
a machine, and shall have much to do with it in future. I must,
therefore, give an explanation of it. The idea of work is evidently
transferred to machines by comparing their arrangements with those of
men and animals to replace which they were applied. We still reckon
the work of steam engines according to horse-power. The value of
manual labor is determined partly by the force which is expended in
it (a strong laborer is valued more highly than a weak one), partly,
however, by the skill which is brought into action. A machine, on the
contrary, which executes work skilfully, can always be multiplied to
any extent; hence its skill has not the high value of human skill in
domains where the latter cannot be supplied by machines. Thus the idea
of the quantity of work in the case of machines has been limited to the
consideration of the expenditure of force; this was the more important,
as indeed most machines are constructed for the express purpose of
exceeding, by the magnitude of their effects, the powers of men and
animals. Hence, in a mechanical sense, the idea of work is become
identical with that of the expenditure of force, and in this way I will
apply it.

How, then, can we measure this expenditure, and compare it in the case
of different machines?

I must here conduct you a portion of the way--as short a portion
as possible--over the uninviting field of mathematico-mechanical
ideas, in order to bring you to a point of view from which a more
rewarding prospect will open. And though the example which I shall
here choose, namely, that of a water-mill with iron hammer, appears
to be tolerably romantic, still, alas, I must leave the dark forest
valley, the spark-emitting anvil, and the black Cyclops wholly out of
sight, and beg a moment’s attention to the less poetic side of the
question, namely, the machinery. This is driven by a water-wheel, which
in its turn is set in motion by the falling water. The axle of the
water-wheel has at certain places small projections, thumbs, which,
during the rotation, lift the heavy hammer and permit it to fall again.
The falling hammer belabors the mass of metal, which is introduced
beneath it. The work therefore done by the machine consists, in this
case, in the lifting of the hammer, to do which the gravity of the
latter must be overcome. The expenditure of force will, in the first
place, other circumstances being equal, be proportioned to the weight
of the hammer; it will, for example, be double when the weight of the
hammer is doubled. But the action of the hammer depends not upon its
weight alone, but also upon the height from which it falls. If it falls
through two feet, it will produce a greater effect than if it falls
through only one foot. It is, however, clear that if the machine, with
a certain expenditure of force, lifts the hammer a foot in height, the
same amount of force must be expended to raise it a second foot in
height. The work is therefore not only doubled when the weight of the
hammer is increased twofold, but also when the space through which it
falls is doubled. From this it is easy to see that the work must be
measured by the product of the weight into the space through which it
ascends. And in this way, indeed, do we measure in mechanics.

The unit of work is a foot-pound, that is, a pound weight, raised to
the height of one foot.

While the work in this case consists in the raising of the heavy
hammer-head, the driving force which sets the latter in motion is
generated by falling water. It is not necessary that the water should
fall vertically, it can also flow in a moderately inclined bed; but
it must always, where it has water-mills to set in motion, move from
a higher to a lower position. Experiment and theory coincided in
teaching, that when a hammer of a hundred weight is to be raised one
foot, to accomplish this at least a hundred weight of water must fall
through the space of one foot; or what is equivalent to this, two
hundred weight must fall full half a foot, or four hundred weight a
quarter of a foot, etc. In short, if we multiply the weight of the
falling water by the height through which it falls, and regard, as
before, the product as the measure of the work, then the work performed
by the machine in raising the hammer can, in the most favourable case,
be only equal to the number of foot-pounds of water which have fallen
in the same time. In practice, indeed, this ratio is by no means
attained; a great portion of the work of the falling water escapes
unused, inasmuch as part of the force is unwillingly sacrificed for the
sake of obtaining greater speed.

I will further remark, that this relation remains unchanged whether
the hammer is driven immediately by the axle of the wheel, or
whether--by the intervention of wheel-work, endless screws, pulleys,
ropes--the motion is transferred to the hammer. We may, indeed, by
such arrangements, succeed in raising a hammer of ten hundred weight,
when by the first simple arrangement, the elevation of a hammer of one
hundred weight might alone be possible; but either this heavier hammer
is raised to only one-tenth of the height, or tenfold the time is
required to raise it to the same height; so that, however we may alter,
by the interposition of machinery, the intensity of the acting force,
still in a certain time, during which the mill-stream furnishes us with
a definite quantity of water, a certain definite quantity of work, and
no more, can be performed.

Our machinery, therefore, has, in the first place, done nothing more
than make use of the gravity of the falling water in order to overpower
the gravity of the hammer, and to raise the latter. When it has lifted
the hammer to the necessary height, it again liberates it, and the
hammer falls upon the metal mass which is pushed beneath it. But why
does the falling hammer here exercise a greater force than when it is
permitted simply to press with its own weight on the mass of metal? Why
is its power greater as the height from which it falls is increased?
We find, in fact, that the work performed by the hammer is determined
by its velocity. In other cases, also, the velocity of moving masses
is a means of producing great effects. I only remind you of the
destructive effects of musket-bullets, which, in a state of rest, are
the most harmless things in the world. I remind you of the windmill,
which derives its force from the moving air. It may appear surprising
that motion, which we are accustomed to regard as a non-essential and
transitory endowment of bodies, can produce such great effects. But
the fact is, that motion appears to us, under ordinary circumstances,
transitory, because the movement of all terrestrial bodies is resisted
perpetually by other forces, friction, resistance of the air, etc.,
so that motion is incessantly weakened and finally neutralized. A
body, however, which is opposed by no resisting force, when once set
in motion, moves onward eternally with undiminished velocity. Thus
we know that the planetary bodies have moved without change, through
space, for thousands of years. Only by resisting forces can motion
be diminished or destroyed. A moving body, such as the hammer or the
musket-ball, when it strikes against another, presses the latter
together, or penetrates it, until the sum of the resisting forces which
the body struck presents to its pressure, or to the separation of its
particles, is sufficiently great to destroy the motion of the hammer
or of the bullet. The motion of a mass regarded as taking the place of
working force is called the living force (_vis viva_) of the mass.
The word “living” has of course here no reference whatever to living
beings, but is intended to represent solely the force of the motion as
distinguished from the state of unchanged rest--from the gravity of
a motionless body, for example, which produces an incessant pressure
against the surface which supports it, but does not produce any motion.

In the case before us, therefore, we had first power in the form of
a falling mass of water, then in the form of a lifted hammer, and,
thirdly, in the form of the living force of the fallen hammer. We
should transform the third form into the second, if we, for example,
permitted the hammer to fall upon a highly elastic steel beam strong
enough to resist the shock. The hammer would rebound, and in the most
favourable case would reach a height equal to that from which it
fell, but would never rise higher. In this way its mass would ascend:
and at the moment when its highest point has been attained, it would
represent the same number of raised foot-pounds as before it fell,
never a greater number; that is to say, living force can generate the
same amount of work as that expended in its production. It is therefore
equivalent to this quantity of work.

Our clocks are driven by means of sinking weights, and our watches by
means of the tension of springs. A weight which lies on the ground, an
elastic spring which is without tension, can produce no effects; to
obtain such we must first raise the weight or impart tension to the
spring, which is accomplished when we wind up our clocks and watches.
The man who winds the clock or watch communicates to the weight or
to the spring a certain amount of power, and exactly so much as is
thus communicated is gradually given out again during the following
twenty-four hours, the original force being thus slowly consumed
to overcome the friction of the wheels and the resistance which the
pendulum encounters from the air. The wheel-work of the clock therefore
exhibits no working force which was not previously communicated to it,
but simply distributes the force given to it uniformly over a longer
time.

Into the chamber of an air-gun we squeeze, by means of a condensing
air-pump, a great quantity of air. When we afterwards open the cock of
a gun and admit the compressed air into the barrel, the ball is driven
out of the latter with a force similar to that exerted by ignited
powder. Now we may determine the work consumed in the pumping-in of the
air, and the living force which, upon firing, is communicated to the
ball, but we shall never find the latter greater than the former. The
compressed air has generated no working force, but simply gives to the
bullet that which has been previously communicated to it. And while we
have pumped for perhaps a quarter of an hour to charge the gun, the
force is expended in a few seconds when the bullet is discharged; but
because the action is compressed into so short a time, a much greater
velocity is imparted to the ball than would be possible to communicate
to it by the unaided effort of the arm in throwing it.

From these examples you observe, and the mathematical theory has
corroborated this for all purely mechanical, that is to say, for
moving forces, that all our machinery and apparatus generate no
force, but simply yield up the power communicated to them by
natural forces--falling water, moving wind, or by the muscles of
men and animals. After this law had been established by the great
mathematicians of the last century, a perpetual motion, which should
make only use of pure mechanical forces, such as gravity, elasticity,
pressure of liquids and gases, could only be sought after by bewildered
and ill-instructed people. But there are still other natural forces
which are not reckoned among the purely moving forces--heat,
electricity, magnetism, light, chemical forces, all of which
nevertheless stand in manifold relation to mechanical processes. There
is hardly a natural process to be found which is not accompanied by
mechanical actions, or from which mechanical work may not be derived.
Here the question of a perpetual motion remained open; the decision of
this question marks the progress of modern physics.

In the case of the air-gun, the work to be accomplished in the
propulsion of the ball was given by the arm of the man who pumped in
the air. In ordinary firearms, the condensed mass of air which propels
the bullet is obtained in a totally different manner, namely, by the
combustion of the powder. Gunpowder is transformed by combustion for
the most part into gaseous products, which endeavor to occupy a much
larger space than that previously taken by the volume of the powder.
Thus, you see, that, by the use of gunpowder, the work which the human
arm must accomplish in the case of the air-gun is spared.

In the mightiest of our machines, the steam engine, it is a strongly
compressed aeriform body, water, vapour, which, by its effort to
expand, sets the machine in motion. Here, also, we do not condense the
steam by means of an external mechanical force, but by communicating
heat to a mass of water in a closed boiler, we change this water
into steam, which, in consequence of the limits of the space, is
developed under strong pressure. In this case, therefore, it is the
heat communicated which generates the mechanical force. The heat thus
necessary for the machine we might obtain in many ways; the ordinary
method is to procure it from the combustion of coal.

Combustion is a chemical process. A particular constituent of our
atmosphere, oxygen, possesses a strong force of attraction, or, as
it is named in chemistry, a strong affinity for the constituents of
the combustible body, which affinity, however, in most cases, can
only exert itself at high temperatures. As soon as a portion of the
combustible body, for example, the coal, is sufficiently heated,
the carbon unites itself with great violence to the oxygen of the
atmosphere and forms a peculiar gas, carbonic acid, the same which we
see foaming from beer and champagne. By this combination, light and
heat are generated; heat is generally developed by any combination
of two bodies of strong affinity for each other; and when the heat
is intense enough, light appears. Hence, in the steam engine, it is
chemical processes and chemical forces which produce the astonishing
work of these machines. In like manner the combustion of gunpowder is a
chemical process which, in the barrel of the gun, communicates living
force to the bullet.

While now the steam engine develops for us mechanical work out of
heat, we can conversely generate heat by mechanical forces. A skilful
blacksmith can render an iron wedge red hot by hammering. The axes of
our carriages must be protected, by careful greasing, from ignition
through friction. Even lately this property has been applied on a large
scale. In some factories, where a surplus of water power is at hand,
this surplus is applied to cause a strong iron plate to rotate swiftly
upon another, so that they become strongly heated by friction. The heat
so obtained warms the room, and thus a stove without fuel is provided.
Now, could not the heat generated by the plates be applied to a small
steam engine, which in its turn should be able to keep the rubbing
plates in motion? The perpetual motion would thus be at length found.
This question might be asked, and could not be decided by the older
mathematico-mechanical investigations. I will remark, beforehand, that
the general law which I will lay before you answers the question in the
negative.

By a similar plan, however, a speculative American set some time ago
the industrial world of Europe in excitement. The magneto-electric
machines often made use of in the case of rheumatic disorders are well
known to the public. By imparting a swift rotation to the magnet of
such a machine, we obtain powerful currents of electricity. If those
be conducted through water, the latter will be reduced into its two
components, oxygen and hydrogen. By the combustion of hydrogen, water
is again generated. If this combustion takes place, not in atmospheric
air, of which oxygen only constitutes a fifth part, but in pure oxygen,
and if a bit of chalk be placed in the flame, the chalk will be raised
to a white heat, and give us the sun-like Drummond’s light. At the same
time, the flame develops a considerable quantity of heat. Our American
proposed to utilize in this way the gases obtained from electrolytic
decomposition, and asserted that by the combustion a sufficient amount
of heat was generated to keep a small steam engine in action, which
again drove his magneto-electric machine, decomposed the water, and
thus continually prepared its own fuel. This would certainly have been
the most splendid of all discoveries; a perpetual motion which, besides
the force which kept it going, generated light like the sun, and
warmed all around it. The matter was by no means badly cogitated. Each
practical step in the affair was known to be possible; but those who at
that time were acquainted with the physical investigations which bear
upon this subject could have affirmed, on first hearing the report,
that the matter was to be numbered among the numerous stories of the
fable-rich America; and indeed a fable it remained.

It is not necessary to multiply examples further. You will infer from
those given, in what immediate connection heat, electricity, magnetism,
light, and chemical affinity, stand with mechanical forces.

Starting from each of these different manifestations of natural forces
we can set every other in motion, for the most part not in one way
merely, but in many ways. It is here as with the weaver’s web--

    Where a step stirs a thousand threads
    The shuttles shoot from side to side,
    The fibres flow unseen,
    And one shock strikes a thousand combinations.

Now it is clear that if by any means we could succeed, as the above
American professed to have done, by mechanical forces, to excite
chemical, electrical, or other natural processes, which, by any circuit
whatever, and without altering permanently the active masses in the
machine, could produce mechanical force in greater quantity than that
at first applied, a portion of the work thus gained might be made use
of to keep the machine in motion, while the rest of the work might be
applied to any other purpose whatever. The problem was, to find in
the complicated net of reciprocal actions, a track through chemical,
electrical, magnetical, and thermic processes, back to mechanical
actions, which might be followed with a final gain of mechanical work;
thus would the perpetual motion be found.

But, warned by the futility of former experiments, the public had
become wiser. On the whole, people did not seek much after combinations
which promised to furnish a perpetual motion, but the question was
inverted. It was no more asked, how can I make use of the known and
unknown relations of natural forces so as to construct a perpetual
motion? but it was asked, if a perpetual motion be impossible, what are
the relations which must subsist between natural forces? Everything
was gained by this inversion of the question. The relations of natural
forces rendered necessary by the above assumption, might be easily
and completely stated. It was found that all known relations of force
harmonize with the consequences of that assumption, and a series of
unknown relations were discovered at the same time, the correctness of
which remained to be proved. If a single one of them could be proved
false, then a perpetual motion would be possible.

The first who endeavoured to travel this way was a Frenchman, named
Carnot, in the year 1824. In spite of a too limited conception of
his subject, and an incorrect view as to the nature of heat, which
led him to some erroneous conclusions, his experiment was not quite
unsuccessful. He discovered a law which now bears his name, and to
which I will return further on.

His labors remained for a long time without notice, and it was not
till eighteen years afterwards, that is, in 1842, that different
investigators in different countries, and independent of Carnot, laid
hold of the same thought.

The first who saw truly the general law here referred to, and expressed
it correctly, was a German physician, J. R. Mayer, of Heilbronn,
in the year 1842. A little later, in 1843, a Dane, named Colding,
presented a memoir to the Academy of Copenhagen, in which the same law
found utterance, and some experiments were described for its further
corroboration. In England, Joule began about the same time to make
experiments having reference to the same subject. We often find, in the
case of questions to the solution of which the development of science
points, that several heads, quite independent of each other, generate
exactly the same series of reflections.

I myself, without being acquainted with either Mayer or Colding, and
having first made the acquaintance of Joule’s experiments at the end of
my investigation, followed the same path. I endeavoured to ascertain
all the relations between the different natural processes, which
followed from our regarding them from the above point of view. My
inquiry was made public in 1847, in a small pamphlet bearing the title,
“On the Conservation of Force.”

Since that time the interest of the scientific public for this subject
has gradually augmented. A great number of the essential consequences
of the above manner of viewing the subject, the proof of which was
wanting when the first theoretic notions were published, have since
been confirmed by experiment, particularly by those of Joule; and
during the last year the most eminent physicist of France, Regnault,
has adopted the new mode regarding the question, and by fresh
investigations on the specific heat of gases has contributed much to
its support. For some important consequences the experimental proof
is still wanting, but the number of confirmations is so predominant,
that I have not deemed it too early to bring the subject before even a
non-scientific audience.

How the question has been decided you may already infer from what has
been stated. In the series of natural processes there is no circuit
to be found, by which mechanical force can be gained without a
corresponding consumption. The perpetual motion remains impossible. Our
reflections, however, gain thereby a higher interest.

We have thus far regarded the development of force by natural
processes, only in its relation to its usefulness to man, as mechanical
force. You now see that we have arrived at a general law, which holds
good wholly independent of the application which man makes of natural
forces; we must therefore make the expression of our new law correspond
to this more general significance. It is in the first place clear, that
the work which, by any natural process whatever, is performed under
favourable conditions by a machine, and which may be measured in the
way already indicated, may be used as a measure of force common to
all. Further, the important question arises, “If the quantity of force
cannot be augmented except by corresponding consumption, can it be
diminished or lost?” For the purpose of our machines it certainly can,
if we neglect the opportunity to convert natural processes to use, but
as investigation has proved, not for a nature as a whole.

In the collision and friction of bodies against each other, the
mechanics of former years assumed simply that living force was lost.
But I have already stated that each collision and each act of friction
generates heat; and, moreover, Joule has established by experiment
the important law that for every foot-pound of force which is lost a
definite quantity of heat is always generated, and that when work is
performed by the consumption of heat, for each foot-pound thus gained
a definite quantity of heat disappears. The quantity of heat necessary
to raise the temperature of a pound of water a degree of the centigrade
thermometer, corresponds to a mechanical force by which a pound weight
would be raised to the height of 1350 feet; we name this quantity the
mechanical equivalent of heat. I may mention here that these facts
conduct of necessity to the conclusion, that the heat is not, as was
formerly imagined, a fine imponderable substance, but that, like
light, it is a peculiar shivering motion of the ultimate particles of
bodies. In collision and friction, according to this manner of viewing
the subject, the motion of the mass of a body which is apparently lost
is converted into a motion of the ultimate particles of the body; and
conversely, when mechanical force is generated by heat, the motion of
the ultimate particles is converted into a motion of the mass.

Chemical combinations generate heat, and the quantity of this heat is
totally independent of the time and steps through which the combination
has been effected, provided that other actions are not at the same
time brought into play. If, however, mechanical work is at the same
time accomplished, as in the case of the steam engine, we obtain as
much less heat as is equivalent to this work. The quantity of work
produced by chemical force is in general very great. A pound of the
purest coal gives when burnt, sufficient heat to raise the temperature
of 8086 pounds of water one degree of the centigrade thermometer; from
this we can calculate that the magnitude of the chemical force of
attraction between the particles of a pound of coal and the quantity
of oxygen that corresponds to it is capable of lifting a weight of one
hundred pounds to a height of twenty miles. Unfortunately, in our steam
engines, we have hitherto been able to gain only the smallest portion
of this work; the greater part is lost in the shape of heat. The best
expansive engines give back as mechanical work only eighteen per cent.
of the heat generated by the fuel.

From a similar investigation of all the other known physical and
chemical processes, we arrive at the conclusion that Nature as a whole
possesses a store of force which cannot in any way be either increased
or diminished. And that, therefore, the quantity of force in Nature is
just as eternal and unalterable as the quantity of matter. Expressed
in this form, I have named the general law “The Principle of the
Conservation of Force.”

We cannot create mechanical force, but we may help ourselves from the
general store-house of Nature. The brook and the wind, which drive our
mills, the forest and the coal-bed, which supply our steam engines and
warm our rooms, are to us the bearers of a small portion of the great
natural supply which we draw upon for our purposes, and the actions of
which we can apply as we think fit. The possessor of a mill claims the
gravity of the descending rivulet, or the living force of the moving
wind, as his possession. These portions of the store of Nature are what
give his property its chief value.

Further, from the fact that no portion of force can be absolutely lost,
it does not follow that a portion may not be inapplicable to human
purposes. In this respect the inferences drawn by William Thomson from
the law of Carnot are of importance. This law, which was discovered
by Carnot during his endeavours to ascertain the relations between
heat and mechanical force, which, however, by no means belongs to the
necessary consequences of the conservation of force, and which Clausius
was the first to modify in such a manner that it no longer contradicted
the above general law, expresses a certain relation between the
compressibility, the capacity for heat, and the expansion by heat of
all bodies. It is not yet considered as actually proved, but some
remarkable deductions having been drawn from it, and afterwards proved
to be facts by experiment, it has attained thereby a great degree
of probability. Besides the mathematical form in which the law was
first expressed by Carnot, we can give it the following more general
expression:--“Only, when heat passes from a warmer to a colder body,
and even then only partially, can it be converted into mechanical work.”

The heat of a body which we cannot cool further, cannot be changed
into another form of force; into the electric or chemical force, for
example. Thus, in our steam engines, we convert a portion of the heat
of the glowing coal into work, by permitting it to pass to the less
warm water of the boiler. If, however, all the bodies in nature had
the same temperature, it would be impossible to convert any portion of
their heat into mechanical work. According to this, we can divide the
total force store of the universe into two parts, one of which is heat,
and must continue to be such; the other, to which a portion of the heat
of the warmer bodies, and the total supply of chemical, mechanical,
electrical, and magnetical forces belong, is capable of the most varied
changes of form, and constitutes the whole wealth of change which takes
place in nature.

But the heat of the warmer bodies strives perpetually to pass to
bodies less warm by radiation and conduction, and thus to establish
an equilibrium of temperature. At each motion of a terrestrial body,
a portion of mechanical force passes by friction or collision into
heat, of which only a part can be converted back again into mechanical
force. This is also generally the case in every electrical and chemical
process. From this, it follows that the first portion of the store of
force, the unchangeable heat, is augmented by every natural process,
while the second portion, mechanical, electrical, and chemical force,
must be diminished; so that if the universe be delivered over to
the undisturbed action of its physical processes, all force will
finally pass into the form of heat, and all heat come into a state of
equilibrium. Then all possibility of a further change would be at an
end, and the complete cessation of all natural processes must set in.
The life of men, animals, and plants, could not of course continue if
the sun had lost its high temperature, and with it his light,--if all
the components of the earth’s surface had closed those combinations
which their affinities demand. In short, the universe from that time
forward would be condemned to a state of eternal rest.

These consequences of the law of Carnot are, of course, only valid,
provided that the law, when sufficiently tested, proves to be
universally correct. In the mean time there is little prospect of the
law being proved incorrect. At all events we must admire the sagacity
of Thomson, who, in the letters of a long known little mathematical
formula, which only speaks of the heat, volume, and pressure of bodies,
was able to discern consequences which threatened the universe, though
certainly after an infinite period of time, with eternal death.

I have already given you notice that our path lay through a thorny and
unrefreshing field of mathematico-mechanical developments. We have
now left this portion of our road behind us. The general principle
which I have sought to lay before you has conducted us to a point from
which our view is a wide one, and aided by this principle, we can now
at pleasure regard this or the other side of the surrounding world,
according as our interest in the matter leads us. A glance into the
narrow laboratory of the physicist, with its small appliances and
complicated abstractions, will not be so attractive as a glance at the
wide heaven above us, the clouds, the rivers, the woods, and the living
beings around us. While regarding the laws which have been deduced
from the physical processes of terrestrial bodies, as applicable also
to the heavenly bodies, let me remind you that the same force which,
acting at the earth’s surface, we call gravity (_Schwere_), acts
as gravitation in the celestial spaces, and also manifests its power in
the motion of the immeasurably distant double stars which are governed
by exactly the same laws as those subsisting between the earth and
moon; that, therefore, the light and heat of terrestrial bodies do not
in any way differ essentially from those of the sun, or of the most
distant fixed star; that the meteoric stones which sometimes fall from
external space upon the earth are composed of exactly the same simple
chemical substances as those with which we are acquainted. We need,
therefore, feel no scruple in granting that general laws to which all
terrestrial natural processes are subject, are also valid for other
bodies than the earth. We will, therefore, make use of our law to
glance over the household of the universe with respect to the store of
force, capable of action, which it possesses.

A number of singular peculiarities in the structure of our planetary
system indicate that it was once a connected mass with a uniform
motion of rotation. Without such an assumption, it is impossible to
explain why all the planets move in the same direction round the sun,
why they all rotate in the same direction round their axes, why the
planes of their orbits, and those of their satellites and rings all
nearly coincide, why all their orbits differ but little from circles;
and much besides. From these remaining indications of a former state,
astronomers have shaped an hypothesis regarding the formation of our
planetary system, which, although from the nature of the case it must
ever remain an hypothesis, still in its special traits is so well
supported by analogy, that it certainly deserves our attention. It
was Kant who, feeling great interest in the physical description of
the earth and the planetary system, undertook the labour of studying
the works of Newton, and as an evidence of the depth to which he had
penetrated into the fundamental ideas of Newton, seized the notion
that the same attractive force of all ponderable matter which now
supports the motion of the planets, must also aforetime have been able
to form from matter loosely scattered in space the planetary system.
Afterwards, and independent of Kant, Laplace, the great author of the
_Mecanique Celeste_, laid hold of the same thought, and introduced
it among astronomers.

The commencement of our planetary system, including the sun, must,
according to this, be regarded as an immense nebulous mass which filled
the portion of space which is now occupied by our system, far beyond
the limits of Neptune, our most distant planet. Even now we perhaps
see similar masses in the distant regions of the firmament, as patches
of nebulæ, and nebulous stars; within our system also, comets, the
zodiacal light, the corona of the sun during a total eclipse, exhibit
remnants of a nebulous substance, which is so thin that the light
of the stars passes through it unenfeebled and unrefracted. If we
calculate the density of the mass of our planetary system, according to
the above assumption, for the time when it was a nebulous sphere, which
reached to the path of the outmost planet, we should find that it would
require several cubic miles of such matter to weigh a single grain.

The general attractive force of all matter must, however, impel these
masses to each other, and to condense, so that the nebulous sphere
became incessantly smaller, by which, according to mechanical laws, a
motion of rotation originally slow, and the existence of which must be
assumed, would gradually become quicker and quicker. By the centrifugal
force which must act most energetically in the neighbourhood of the
equator of the nebulous sphere, masses could from time to time be torn
away, which afterwards would continue their courses separate from the
main mass, forming themselves into single planets, or, similar to the
great original sphere, into planets with satellites and rings, until
finally the principal mass condensed itself into the sun. With regard
to the origin of heat and light, this view gives us no information.

When the nebulous chaos first separated itself from other fixed star
masses, it must not only have contained all kinds of matter which was
to constitute the future planetary system, but also, in accordance
with our new law, the whole store of force which at one time must
unfold therein its wealth of actions. Indeed in this respect an immense
dower was bestowed in the shape of the general attraction of all the
particles for each other. This force, which on the earth exerts itself
as gravity, acts in the heavenly spaces as gravitation. As terrestrial
gravity when it draws a weight downwards performs work and generates
_vis viva_, so also the heavenly bodies do the same when they draw
two portions of matter from distant regions of space towards each other.

The chemical forces must have been also present, ready to act; but as
these forces can only come into operation by the most intimate contact
of the different masses, condensation must have taken place before the
play of chemical forces began.

Whether a still further supply of force in the shape of heat was
present at the commencement we do not know. At all events, by aid of
the law of the equivalence of heat and work, we find in the mechanical
forces, existing at the time to which we refer, such a rich source of
heat and light, that there is no necessity whatever to take refuge in
the idea of a store of these forces originally existing. When through
condensation of the masses their particles came into collision,
and clung to each other, the _vis viva_ of their motion would
be thereby annihilated, and must reappear as heat. Already in old
theories, it has been calculated that cosmical masses must generate
heat by their collision, but it was far from anybody’s thought to make
even a guess at the amount of heat to be generated in this way. At
present we can give definite numerical values with certainty.

Let us make this addition to our assumption; that, at the commencement,
the density of the nebulous matter was a vanishing quantity, as
compared with the present density of the sun and planets; we can then
calculate how much work has been performed by the condensation; we can
further calculate how much of this work still exists in the form of
mechanical force, as attraction of the planets towards the sun, and as
_vis viva_ of their motion, and find by this how much of the force
has been converted into heat.

The result of this calculation is, that only about the 454th part
of the original mechanical force remains as such, and that the
remainder, converted into heat, would be sufficient to raise a mass
of water equal to the sun and planets taken together, not less than
twenty-eight millions of degrees of the centigrade scale. For the
sake of comparison, I will mention that the highest temperature which
we can produce by the oxyhydrogen blowpipe, which is sufficient to
fuse and vaporize even platina, and which but few bodies can endure,
is estimated at about two thousand centigrade degrees. Of the action
of a temperature of twenty-eight millions of such degrees we can
form no notion. If the mass of our entire system were pure coal,
by the combustion of the whole of it only the 3500th part of the
above quantity would be generated. This is also clear, that such a
development of heat must have presented the greatest obstacle to the
speedy union of the masses, that the larger part of the heat must have
been diffused by radiation into space, before the masses could form
bodies possessing the present density of the sun and planets, and that
these bodies must once have been in a state of fiery fluidity. This
notion is corroborated by the geological phenomena of our planet; and
with regard to the other planetary bodies, the flattened form of the
sphere, which is the form of equilibrium of a fluid mass, is indicative
of a former state of fluidity. If I thus permit an immense quantity of
heat to disappear without compensation from our system, the principle
of the conservation of force is not thereby invaded. Certainly for our
planet it is lost, but not for the universe. It has proceeded outwards,
and daily proceeds outwards into infinite space; and we know not
whether the medium which transmits the undulations of light and heat
possesses an end where the rays must return, or whether they eternally
pursue their way through infinitude.

The store of force at present possessed by our system, is also
equivalent to immense quantities of heat. If our earth were by a sudden
shock brought to rest on her orbit--which is not to be feared in the
existing arrangements of our system--by such a shock a quantity of heat
would be generated equal to that produced by the combustion of fourteen
such earths of solid coal. Making the most unfavourable assumption as
to its capacity for heat, that is, placing it equal to that of water,
the mass of the earth would thereby be heated 11,200 degrees; it would
therefore be quite fused and for the most part reduced to vapour. If,
then, the earth, after having been thus brought to rest, should fall
into the sun, which of course would be the case, the quantity of heat
developed by the shock would be four hundred times greater.

Even now, from time to time, such a process is repeated on a small
scale. There can hardly be a doubt that meteors, fire-balls, and
meteoric stones are masses which belong to the universe, and before
coming into the domain of our earth, moved like the planets round the
sun. Only when they enter our atmosphere do they become visible and
fall sometimes to the earth. In order to explain the emission of light
by these bodies, and the fact that for some time after their descent
they are very hot, the friction was long ago thought of which they
experience in passing through the air. We can now calculate that a
velocity of 3,000 feet a second, supposing the whole of the friction
to be expended in heating the solid mass, would raise a piece of
meteoric iron 1,000° C. in temperature, or, in other words, to a vivid
red heat. Now the average velocity of the meteors seems to be thirty or
forty times the above amount. To compensate this, however, the greater
portion of the heat is, doubtless, carried away by the condensed mass
of air which the meteor drives before it. It is known that bright
meteors generally leave a luminous trail behind them, which probably
consists of several portions of the red-hot surfaces. Meteoric masses
which fall to the earth often burst with a violent explosion, which
may be regarded as a result of the quick heating. The newly-fallen
pieces have been for the most part found hot, but not red-hot, which
is easily explainable by the circumstances, that during the short time
occupied by the meteor in passing through the atmosphere, only a thin,
superficial layer is heated to redness, while but a small quantity of
heat has been able to penetrate to the interior of the mass. For this
reason the red heat can speedily disappear.

Thus has the falling of the meteoric stone, the minute remnant of
processes which seems to have played an important part in the formation
of the heavenly bodies, conducted us to the present time, where we
pass from the darkness of hypothetical views to the brightness of
knowledge. In what we have said, however, all that is hypothetical is
the assumption of Kant and Laplace, that the masses of our system were
once distributed as nebulæ in space.

On account of the rarity of the case, we will still further remark,
in what close coincidence the results of science here stand with the
earlier legends of the human family, and the forebodings of poetic
fancy. The cosmogony of ancient nations generally commences with chaos
and darkness.

Neither is the Mosaic tradition very divergent, particularly when we
remember that that which Moses names heaven is different from the blue
dome above us, and is synonymous with space, and that the unformed
earth, and the waters of the great deep, which were afterwards divided
into waters above the firmament, and waters below the firmament,
resembled the chaotic components of the world.

Our earth bears still the unmistakable traces of its old fiery fluid
condition. The granite formations of her mountains exhibit a structure,
which can only be produced by the crystallization of fused masses.
Investigation still shows that the temperature in mines, and borings,
increases as we descend; and if this increase is uniform, at the depth
of fifty miles, a heat exists sufficient to fuse all our minerals. Even
now our volcanoes project, from time to time, mighty masses of fused
rocks from their interior, as a testimony of the heat which exists
there. But the cooled crust of the earth has already become so thick,
that, as may be shown by calculations of its conductive power, the heat
coming to the surface from within, in comparison with that reaching the
earth from the sun, is exceedingly small, and increases the temperature
of the surface only about one-thirtieth of a degree centigrade; so that
the remnant of the old store of force which is enclosed as heat within
the bowels of the earth, has a sensible influence upon the processes
at the earth’s surface, only through the instrumentality of volcanic
phenomena. These processes owe their power almost wholly to the action
of other heavenly bodies, particularly to the light and heat of the
sun, and partly also, in the case of the tides, to the attraction of
the sun and moon.

Most varied and numerous are the changes which we owe to the light
and heat of the sun. The sun heats our atmosphere irregularly, the
warm rarefied air ascends, while fresh cool air flows from the sides
to supply its place: in this way winds are generated. This action is
most powerful at the equator, the warm air of which incessantly flows
in the upper regions of the atmosphere towards the poles: while just
as persistently, at the earth’s surface, the trade wind carries new
and cool air to the equator. Without the heat of the sun all winds
must, of necessity, cease. Similar currents are produced by the same
cause in the waters of the sea. Their power may be inferred from the
influence which in some cases they exert upon climate. By them the warm
water of the Antilles is carried to the British Isles, and confers upon
them a mild, uniform warmth and rich moisture; while, through similar
causes, the floating ice of the North Pole is carried to the coast
of Newfoundland, and produces cold. Further, by the heat of the sun,
a portion of the water is converted into vapour which rises in the
atmosphere, is condensed to clouds, or falls in rain and snow upon the
earth, collects in the form of springs, brooks, and rivers, and finally
reaches the sea again, after having gnawed the rocks, carried away the
light earth, and thus performed its part in the geologic changes of the
earth; perhaps, besides all this it has driven our water-mill upon its
way. If the heat of the sun were withdrawn, there would remain only a
single motion of water, namely, the tides, which are produced by the
attraction of the sun and moon.

How is it now, with the motions and the work of organic beings? To
the builders of the automata of the last century, men and animals
appeared as clockwork which was never wound up, and created the force
which they exerted out of nothing. They did not know how to establish
a connection between the nutriment consumed and the work generated.
Since, however, we have learned to discern in the steam-engine this
origin of mechanical force, we must inquire whether something similar
does not hold good with regard to men. Indeed, the continuation of
life is dependent on the consumption of nutritive materials: these
are combustible substances, which, after digestion and being passed
into the blood, actually undergo a slow combustion, and finally enter
into almost the same combinations with the oxygen of the atmosphere
that are produced in an open fire. As the quantity of heat generated
by combustion is independent of the duration of the combustion and
the steps in which it occurs, we can calculate from the mass of the
consumed material how much heat, or its equivalent work is thereby
generated in an animal body. Unfortunately, the difficulty of the
experiments is still very great; but within those limits of accuracy
which have been as yet attainable, the experiments show that the heat
generated in the animal body corresponds to the amount which would be
generated by the chemical processes. The animal body therefore does not
differ from the steam-engine, as regards the manner in which it obtains
heat and force, but does differ from it in the manner in which the
force gained is to be made use of. The body is, besides, more limited
than the machine in the choice of its fuel; the latter could be heated
with sugar, with starch-flour, and butter, just as well as with coal
or wood; the animal body must dissolve its materials artificially, and
distribute them through its system; it must, further, perpetually renew
the used-up materials of its organs, and as it cannot itself create
the matter necessary for this, the matter must come from without.
Liebig was the first to point out these various uses of the consumed
nutriment. As material for the perpetual renewal of the body, it seems
that certain definite albuminous substances which appear in plants, and
form the chief mass of the animal body, can alone be used. They form
only a portion of the mass of nutriment taken daily; the remainder,
sugar, starch, fat, are really only materials for warming, and are
perhaps not to be superseded by coal, simply because the latter does
not permit itself to be dissolved.

If, then, the processes in the animal body are not in this respect to
be distinguished from inorganic processes, the question arises, whence
comes the nutriment which constitutes the source of the body’s force?
The answer is, from the vegetable kingdom; for only the material of
plants, or the flesh of plant-eating animals, can be made use of for
food. The animals which live on plants occupy a mean position between
carnivorous animals, in which we reckon man, and vegetables, which
the former could not make use of immediately as nutriment. In hay and
grass the same nutritive substances are present as in meal and flour,
but in less quantity. As, however, the digestive organs of man are not
in a condition to extract the small quantity of the useful from the
great excess of the insoluble, we submit, in the first place, these
substances to the powerful digestion of the ox, permit the nourishment
to store itself in the animal’s body, in order in the end to gain it
for ourselves in a more agreeable and useful form. In answer to our
question, therefore, we are referred to the vegetable world. Now when
what plants take in and what they give out are made the subjects of
investigation, we find that the principal part of the former consists
in the products of combustion which are generated by the animal.
They take the consumed carbon given off in respiration, as carbonic
acid, from the air, the consumed hydrogen as water, the nitrogen in
its simplest and closest combinations as ammonia; and from these
materials, with the assistance of small ingredients which they take
from the soil, they generate anew the compound combustible substances,
albumen, sugar, oil, on which the animal subsists. Here, therefore,
is a circuit which appears to be a perpetual store of force. Plants
prepare fuel and nutriment, animals consume these, burn them slowly
in their lungs, and from the products of combustion the plants again
derive their nutriment. The latter is an eternal source of chemical,
the former of mechanical forces. Would not the combination of both
organic kingdoms produce the perpetual motion? We must not conclude
hastily: further inquiry shows, that plants are capable of producing
combustible substances only when they are under the influence of the
sun. A portion of the sun’s rays exhibits a remarkable relation to
chemical forces,--it can produce and destroy chemical combinations;
and these rays, which for the most part are blue or violet, are called
therefore chemical rays. We make use of their action in the production
of photographs. Here compounds of silver are decomposed at the place
where the sun’s rays strike them. The same rays overpower in the green
leaves of plants the strong chemical affinity of the carbon of the
carbonic acid for oxygen, give back the latter free to the atmosphere,
and accumulate the other, in combination with other bodies, as woody
fibre, starch, oil, or resin. These chemically active rays of the sun
disappear completely as soon as they encounter the green portions of
the plants, and hence it is that in daguerreotype images the green
leaves of plants appear uniformly black. Inasmuch as the light coming
from them does not contain the chemical rays, it is unable to act upon
the silver compounds.

Hence a certain portion of force disappears from the sunlight, while
combustible substances are generated and accumulated in plants; and
we can assume it as very probable, that the former is the cause of
the latter. I must indeed remark, that we are in possession of no
experiments from which we might determine whether the vis viva of the
sun’s rays which have disappeared, corresponds to the chemical forces
accumulated during the same time; and as long as these experiments are
wanting, we cannot regard the stated relation as a certainty. If this
view should prove correct, we derive from it the flattering result,
that all force, by means of which our bodies live and move, finds
its source in the purest sunlight; and hence we are all, in point
of nobility, not behind the race of the great monarch of China, who
heretofore alone called himself Son of the Sun. But it must also be
conceded that our lower fellow-beings, the frog and leech, share the
same ethereal origin, as also the whole vegetable world, and even the
fuel which comes to us from the ages past, as well as the youngest
offspring of the forest with which we heat our stoves and set our
machines in motion.

You see, then, that the immense wealth of ever-changing meteorological,
climatic, geological, and organic processes of our earth are almost
wholly preserved in action by the light and heat-giving rays of the
sun; and you see in this a remarkable example, how Proteus-like the
effects of a single cause, under altered external conditions, may
exhibit itself in nature. Besides these, the earth experiences an
action of another kind from its central luminary, as well as from its
satellite the moon, which exhibits itself in the remarkable phenomenon
of the ebb and flow of the tide.

Each of these bodies excites, by its attraction upon the waters of the
sea, two gigantic waves, which flow in the same direction round the
world, as the attracting bodies themselves apparently do. The two waves
of the moon, on account of her greater nearness, are about three and a
half times as large as those excited by the sun. One of these waves has
its crest on the quarter of the earth’s surface which is turned towards
the moon, the other is at the opposite side. Both these quarters
possess the flow of the tide, while the regions which lie between have
the ebb. Although in the open sea the height of the tide amounts to
only about three feet, and only in certain narrow channels, where the
moving water is squeezed together, rises to thirty feet, the might of
the phenomena is nevertheless manifest from the calculation of Bessel,
according to which a quarter of the earth covered by the sea possesses,
during the flow of the tide, about 25,000 cubic miles of water more
than during the ebb, and that therefore such a mass of water must, in
six and a quarter hours, flow from one quarter of the earth to the
other.

The phenomena of the ebb and flow, as already recognized by Mayer,
combined with the law of the conservation of force, stand in remarkable
connection with the question of the stability of our planetary system.
The mechanical theory of the planetary motions discovered by Newton
teaches, that if a solid body in absolute vacuo, attracted by the sun,
move around him in the same manner as the planets, this motion will
endure unchanged through all eternity.

Now we have actually not only one, but several such planets, which
move around the sun, and by their mutual attraction create little
changes and disturbances in each other’s paths. Nevertheless Laplace,
in his great work, the _Mecanique Celeste_, has proved that in
our planetary system all these disturbances increase and diminish
periodically, and can never exceed certain limits, so that by this
cause the external existence of the planetary system is unendangered.

But I have already named two assumptions which must be made: first,
that the celestial spaces must be absolutely empty; and secondly, that
the sun and planets must be solid bodies. The first is at least the
case as far as astronomical observations reach, for they have never
been able to detect any retardation of the planets, such as would
occur if they moved in a resisting medium. But on a body of less mass,
the comet of Encke, changes are observed of such a nature: this comet
describes ellipses round the sun which are becoming gradually smaller.
If this kind of motion, which certainly corresponds to that through a
resisting medium, be actually due to the existence of such a medium,
a time will come when the comet will strike the sun; and a similar
end threatens all the planets, although after a time, the length of
which baffles our imagination to conceive of it. But even should the
existence of a resisting medium appear doubtful to us, there is no
doubt that the planets are not wholly composed of solid materials which
are inseparably bound together. Signs of the existence of an atmosphere
are observed on the Sun, on Venus, Mars, Jupiter, and Saturn. Signs
of water and ice upon Mars; and our earth has undoubtedly a fluid
portion on its surface, and perhaps a still greater portion of fluid
within it. The motions of the tides, however, produce friction, all
friction destroys _vis viva_, and the loss in this case can only
affect the _vis viva_ of the planetary system. We come thereby to
the unavoidable conclusion, that every tide, although with infinite
slowness, still with certainty, diminishes the store of mechanical
force of the system; and as a consequence of this, the rotation of
the planets in question round their axes must become more slow; they
must therefore approach the sun, or their satellites must approach
them. What length of time must pass before the length of our day is
diminished one second by the action of the tide cannot be calculated,
until the height and time of the tide in all portions of the ocean are
known. This alteration, however, takes place with extreme slowness,
as is known by the consequences which Laplace has deduced from the
observations of Hipparchus, according to which, during a period of
2000 years, the duration of the day has not been shortened by the
one-three-hundredth part of a second. The final consequence would be,
but after millions of years, if in the mean time the ocean did not
become frozen, that one side of the earth would be constantly turned
towards the sun, and enjoy a perpetual day, whereas the opposite side
would be involved in eternal night. Such a position we observe in our
moon with regard to the earth, and also in the case of the satellites
as regards their planets; it is, perhaps, due to the action of the
mighty ebb and flow to which these bodies, in the time of their fiery
fluid condition, were subjected.

I would not have brought forward these conclusions, which again
plunge us in the most distant future, if they were not unavoidable.
Physico-mechanical laws are, as it were, the telescopes of our
spiritual eye, which can penetrate into the deepest night of time, past
and to come.

Another essential question as regards the future of our planetary
system has reference to its future temperature and illumination.
As the internal heat of the earth has but little influence on the
temperature of the surface, the heat of the sun is the only thing which
essentially affects the question. The quantity of heat falling from the
sun during a given time upon a given portion of the earth’s surface
may be measured, and from this it can be calculated how much heat in a
given time is sent out from the entire sun. Such measurements have been
made by the French physicist Pouillet, and it has been found that the
sun gives out a quantity of heat per hour equal to that which a layer
of the densest coal ten feet thick would give out by its combustion;
and hence in a year a quantity equal to the combustion of a layer of
seventeen miles. If this heat were drawn uniformly from the entire mass
of the sun, its temperature would only be diminished thereby one and
one-third of a degree centigrade per year, assuming its capacity for
heat to be equal to that of water. These results can give us an idea of
the magnitude of the emission, in relation to the surface and mass of
the sun; but they cannot inform us whether the sun radiates heat as a
glowing body, which since its formation has its heat accumulated within
it, or whether a new generation of heat by chemical processes takes
place at the sun’s surface. At all events the law of the conservation
of force teaches us that no process analogous to those known at the
surface of the earth, can supply for eternity an inexhaustible amount
of light and heat to the sun. But the same law also teaches that the
store of force at present existing, as heat, or as what may become
heat, is sufficient for an immeasurable time. With regard to the store
of chemical force in the sun, we can form no conjecture, and the
store of heat there existing can only be determined by very uncertain
estimations. If, however, we adopt the very probable view, that the
remarkably small density of so large a body is caused by its high
temperature, and may become greater in time, it may be calculated that
if the diameter of the sun were diminished only the ten-thousandth
part of its present length, by this act a sufficient quantity of heat
would be generated to cover the total emission for 2100 years. Such a
small change besides it would be difficult to detect even by the finest
astronomical observations.

Indeed, from the commencement of the period during which we possess
historic accounts, that is, for a period of about 4000 years, the
temperature of the earth has not sensibly diminished. From these old
ages we have certainly no thermometric observations, but we have
information regarding the distribution of certain cultivated plants,
the vine, the olive tree, which are very sensitive to changes of the
mean annual temperature, and we find that these plants at the present
moment have the same limits of distribution that they had in the times
of Abraham and Homer; from which we may infer backwards the constancy
of the climate.

In opposition to this it has been urged, that here in Prussia the
German knights in former times cultivated the vine, cellared their
own wine and drank it, which is no longer possible. From this the
conclusion has been drawn, that the heat of our climate has diminished
since the time referred to. Against this, however, Dove has cited the
reports of ancient chroniclers, according to which, in some peculiarly
hot years, the Prussian grape possessed somewhat less than its usual
quantity of acid. The fact also speaks not so much for the climate of
the country as for the throats of the German drinkers.

But even though the force store of our planetary system is so immensely
great, that by the incessant emission which has occurred during the
period of human history it has not been sensibly diminished, even
though the length of the time which must flow by, before a sensible
change in the state of our planetary system occurs, is totally
incapable of measurement, still the inexorable laws of mechanics
indicate that this store of force, which can only suffer loss and not
gain, must be finally exhausted. Shall we terrify ourselves by this
thought? Men are in the habit of measuring the greatness and the wisdom
of the universe by the duration and the profit which it promises to
their own race; but the past history of the earth already shows what
an insignificant moment the duration of the existence of our race
upon it constitutes. A Nineveh vessel, a Roman sword awakes in us the
conception of grey antiquity. What the museums of Europe show us of the
remains of Egypt and Assyria we gaze upon with silent astonishment, and
despair of being able to carry our thoughts back to a period so remote.
Still must the human race have existed for ages, and multiplied itself
before the pyramids of Nineveh could have been erected. We estimate the
duration of human history at 6000 years; but immeasurable as this time
may appear to us, what is it in comparison with the time during which
the earth carried successive series of rank plants and mighty animals,
and no men; during which in our neighbourhood the amber-tree bloomed,
and dropped its costly gum on the earth and in the sea; when in
Siberia, Europe and North America groves of tropical palms flourished;
where gigantic lizards, and after them elephants, whose mighty remains
we still find buried in the earth, found a home? Different geologists,
proceeding from different premises, have sought to estimate the
duration of the above creative period, and vary from a million to nine
million years. And the time during which the earth generated organic
beings is again small when we compare it with the ages during which the
world was a ball of fused rocks. For the duration of its cooling from
2000° to 200° centigrade, the experiments of Bishop upon basalt show
that about 350 millions of years would be necessary. And with regard
to the time during which the first nebulous mass condensed into our
planetary system, our most daring conjectures must cease. The history
of man, therefore, is but a short ripple in the ocean of time. For a
much longer series of years than that during which man has already
occupied this world, the existence of the present state of inorganic
nature favourable to the duration of man seems to be secured, so that
for ourselves and for long generations after us, we have nothing
to fear. But the same forces of air and water, and of the volcanic
interior, which produced former geological revolutions, and buried one
series of living forms after another, act still upon the earth’s crust.
They more probably will bring about the last day of the human race than
those distant cosmical alterations of which we have spoken, and perhaps
force us to make way for new and more complete living forms, as the
lizards and the mammoth have given place to us and our fellow-creatures
which now exist.

Thus the thread which was spun in darkness by those who sought a
perpetual motion has conducted us to a universal law of nature, which
radiates light into the distant nights of the beginning and of the
end of the history of the universe. To our own race it permits a long
but not an endless existence; it threatens it with a day of judgment,
the dawn of which is still happily obscured. As each of us singly
must endure the thought of his death, the race must endure the same.
But above the forms of life gone by, the human race has higher moral
problems before it, the bearer of which it is, and in the completion of
which it fulfils its destiny.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 34: Translated from _Über die Erhaltung der Kraft_
(Berlin, 1847).]




                                 XXXII

                             LOUIS PASTEUR

                               1822-1895


 _Louis Pasteur was born at Dôle, France, December 27, 1822, the son
 of a tanner. Educated at Arbois, Besançon, and the École Normale,
 he was appointed assistant professor of chemistry at the last-named
 institution. His first important work was in demonstrating the
 asymmetry of molecules. In 1863 he investigated fermentation and showed
 that it was caused by the growth of bacteria and later proved that it
 was also the cause of putrefaction, a suggestion which Lister employed
 in developing antiseptic surgery. In 1865 Pasteur discovered the
 bacillus which caused the silkworm disease. Taking up the principle of
 inoculation he applied it to small-pox and later extended it to other
 infectious diseases. He died September 28, 1895._


                    INOCULATION FOR HYDROPHOBIA[35]

Gentlemen:--Your Congress meetings are the place for the discussion
of the gravest problems of medicine; they serve also to point out the
great landmarks of the future. Three years ago, on the eve of the
London Congress, the doctrine of micro-organisms, the ætiological cause
of transmissible maladies, was still the subject of sharp criticisms.
Certain refractory minds continued to uphold the idea that “disease is
in us, from us, by us.”

It was expected that the decided supporters of the theory of the
spontaneity of diseases would make a bold stand in London; but no
opposition was made to the doctrine of “exteriority,” or external
causes, the first cause of contagious diseases, and those questions
were not discussed at all.

It was there seen, once again, that when all is ready for the final
triumph of truth, the united conscience of a great assembly feels it
instinctively and recognises it.

All clear-sighted minds had already foreseen that the theory of the
spontaneity of diseases received its death-blow on the day when it
became possible reasonably to consider the spontaneous generation of
microscopic organisms as a myth, and when, on the other hand, the
life-activity of those same beings was shown to be the main cause of
organic decomposition and of all fermentation.

From the London Congress, also, dates the recognition of another very
hopeful progress; we refer to the attenuation of different viruses,
to the production of varying degrees of virulence for each virus, and
their preservation by suitable methods of cultivation; to the practical
application, finally, of those new facts in animal medicine.

New microbic prophylactic viruses have been added to those of
fowl-cholera and of splenic fever. The animals saved from death by
contagious diseases are now counted by hundreds of thousands, and the
sharp opposition which those scientific novelties met with at the
beginning was soon swept away by the rapidity of their onward progress.

Will the circle of practical applications of those new notions be
limited in future to the prophylaxis of animal distempers? We must
never think little of a new discovery, nor despair of its fecundity;
but more than that, in the present instance, it may be asserted that
the question is already solved in principle. Thus, splenic fever is
common to animals and man, and we make bold to declare that, were it
necessary to do so, nothing could be easier than to render man also
proof against that affection. The process which is employed for animals
might, almost without a change, be applied to him also. It would simply
become advisable to act with an amount of prudence which the value of
the life of an ox or a sheep does not call for. Thus, we should use
three or four vaccine-viruses instead of two, of progressive intensity
of virulence, and choose the first ones so weak that the patient
should never be exposed to the slightest morbid complication, however
susceptible to the disease he might be by his constitution.

The difficulty, then, in the case of human diseases, does not lie in
the application of the new method of prophylaxis, but rather in the
knowledge of the physiological properties of their viruses. All our
experiments must tend to discover the proper degree of attenuation
for each virus. But experimentation, if allowable on animals, is
criminal on man. Such is the principal cause of the complication of
researches bearing on diseases exclusively human. Let us keep in mind,
nevertheless, that the studies of which we are speaking were born
yesterday only, that they have already yielded valuable results, and
that new ones may be fairly expected when we shall have gone deeper
into the knowledge of animal maladies, and of those in particular which
affect animals in common with man.

The desire to penetrate farther forward in that double study led me to
choose rabies as the subject of my researches, in spite of the darkness
in which it was veiled.

The study of rabies was begun in my laboratory four years ago, and
pursued since then without other interruption than what was inherent
to the nature of the researches themselves, which present certain
unfavourable conditions. The incubation of the disease is always
protracted, the space disposed of is never sufficient, and it thus
becomes impossible at a given moment to multiply the experiments as
one would like. Notwithstanding those material obstacles, lessened by
the interest taken by the French Government in all questions of great
scientific interest, we now no longer count the experiments which we
have made, my fellow workers and myself. I shall limit myself to-day to
an exposition of our latest acquisitions.

The name alone of a disease, and of rabies above all others, at once
suggests to the mind the notion of a remedy.

But it will, in the majority of cases, be labour lost to aim in the
first instance at discovering a mode of cure. It is, in a manner,
leaving all progress to chance. Far better to endeavour to acquaint
oneself, first of all, with the nature, the cause, and the evolution of
the disease, with a glimmering hope, perhaps, of finally arriving at
its prophylaxis.

To this last method we are indebted for the result that rabies is no
longer to-day to be considered as an insoluble riddle.

We have found that the virus of rabies develops itself invariably in
the nervous system, brain, and spinal cord, in the nerves, and in the
salivary glands; but it is not present at the same moment in every
one of those parts. It may, for example, develop itself at the lower
extremity of the spinal cord, and only after a time reach the brain.
It may be met with at one or at several points of the encephalon whilst
being absent at certain other points of the same region.

If an animal is killed whilst in the power of rabies, it may require
a pretty long search to discover the presence here or there in the
nervous system, or in the glands, of the virus of rabies. We have been
fortunate enough to ascertain that in all cases, when death has been
allowed to supervene naturally, the swelled-out portion, or bulb, of
the medulla oblongata nearest to the brain, and uniting the spinal
cord with it, is always rabid. When an animal has died of rabies (and
the disease always ends in death), rabid matter can with certainty be
obtained from its bulb, capable of reproducing the disease in other
animals when inoculated into them, after trephining, in the arachnoid
space of the cerebral meninges.

Any street dog whatsoever, inoculated in the manner described with
portions of the bulb of an animal which has died of rabies, will
certainly develop the same disease. We have thus inoculated several
hundreds of dogs brought without any choice from the pound. Never once
was the inoculation a failure. Similarly also, with uniform success,
several hundred guinea-pigs, and rabbits more numerous still.

Those two great results, the constant presence of the virus in the
bulb at the time of death, and the certainty of the reproduction
of the disease by inoculation into the arachnoid space, stand out
like experimental axioms, and their importance is paramount. Thanks
to the precision of their application, and to the well-known daily
repetition of those two criteria of our experiments, we have been
able to move forward steadily and surely in that arduous study. But,
however solid those experimental bases, they were, nevertheless,
incapable in themselves of giving us the faintest notion as to some
method of vaccination against rabies. In the present state of science
the discovery of a method of vaccination against some virulent malady
presupposes:

1. That we have to deal with a virus capable of assuming diverse
intensities, of which the weaker ones can be put to vaccinal or
protective uses.

2. That we are in possession of a method enabling us to reproduce those
diverse degrees of virulence at will.

At the present time, however, science is acquainted with one sort of
rabies only--viz., dog rabies.

Rabies, whether in dog, man, horse, ox, wolf, fox, etc., comes
originally from the bite of a mad dog. It is never spontaneous,
neither in the dog nor in any other animal. There are none seriously
authenticated among the alleged cases of so-called spontaneous rabies,
and I add that it is idle to argue that the first case of rabies of
all must have been spontaneous. Such an argument does not solve the
difficulty, and wantonly calls into question the as yet inscrutable
problem of the origin of life. It would be quite as well, against the
assertion that an oak tree always proceeded from another oak tree, to
argue that the first of all oak trees that ever grew must have been
produced spontaneously. Science, which knows itself, is well aware that
it would be useless for her to discuss about the origin of things;
she is aware that, for the present at any rate, that origin is placed
beyond the ken of her investigations.

In fine, then, the first question to be solved on our way towards the
prophylaxis of rabies is that of knowing whether the virus of that
malady is susceptible of taking on varying intensities, after the
manner of the virus of fowl-cholera or of splenic fever.

But in what way shall we ascertain the possible existence of varying
intensities in the virus of rabies? By what standard shall we measure
the strength of a virus which either fails completely or kills? Shall
we have recourse to the visible symptoms of rabies? But those symptoms
are extremely variable, and depend essentially on the particular point
of the encephalon or of the spinal cord where the virus has in the
first instance fixed and developed itself. The most caressing rabies,
for such do exist, when inoculated into another animal of the same
species, give rise to furious rabies of the intensest type.

Might we then perhaps make use of the duration of incubation as a
means of estimating the intensity of our virus? But what can be more
changeful than the incubative period? Suppose a mad dog were to bite
several sound dogs: one of them will take rabies in one month or six
weeks, another after two or three months or more. Nothing, too, is more
changeful than the length of incubation according to the different
modes of inoculation. Thus, other circumstances the same, after bites
or hypodermic inoculation rabies occasionally develops itself, and at
other times aborts completely; but inoculations on the brain are never
sterile, and give the disease after a relatively short incubation.

It is possible, nevertheless, to gauge with sufficient accuracy the
degree of intensity of our virus by means of the time of incubation,
on condition that we make use exclusively of the intra-cranial mode
of inoculation; and secondly, that we do away with one of the great
disturbing influences inherent to the results of inoculation made
by bites, under the skin or in the veins, by injecting the right
proportion of material.

The duration of incubation, as a matter of fact, may depend largely
on the quantity of efficient virus--that is to say, on the quantity
of virus which reaches the nervous system without diminution or
modification. Although the quantity of virus capable of giving rabies
may be, so to speak, infinitely small, as seen in the common fact of
the disease developing itself after rabid bites which, as a rule,
introduce into the system a barely appreciable weight of virus, it
is easy to double the length of incubation by simply changing the
proportion of those very small quantities of inoculated matter. I may
quote the following examples:--

On May 10, 1882, we injected into the popliteal vein of a dog ten drops
of a liquid prepared by crushing a portion of the bulb of a dog, which
had died of ordinary canine madness, in three or four times its volume
of sterilised broth.

Into a second dog we injected 1/100th of that quantity, into a third
1/200th. Rabies showed itself in the first dog on the eighteenth day
after the injection, on the thirty-fifth day in the second dog, whilst
the third one did not take the disease at all, which means that, for
the last animal, with the particular mode of inoculation employed, the
quantity of virus injected was not sufficient to give rabies. And yet
that dog, like all dogs, was susceptible of taking the disease, for it
actually took it twenty-two days after a second inoculation, performed
on September 3, 1882.

I now take another example bearing on rabbits, and by a different mode
of inoculation. This time, after trephining, the bulb of a rabbit
which had died of rabies after inoculation of an extremely powerful
virus is triturated and mixed with two or three times its volume of
sterilised broth. The mixture is allowed to stand a little, and then
two drops of the supernatant liquid are injected after trephining into
a first rabbit, into a second rabbit one-fourth of that quantity, and
in succession into other rabbits, 1/16th, 1/64th, 1/128th, and 1/152nd
of that same quantity. All those rabbits died of rabies, the incubation
having been eight days, nine and ten days for the third and fourth,
twelve and sixteen days for the last ones.

Those variations in the length of incubation were not the result of
any weakening or diminution of the intrinsic virulence of the virus
brought on possibly by its dilution, for the incubation of eight days
was at once recovered when the nervous matter of all those rabbits was
inoculated into new animals.

Those examples show that, whenever rabies follows upon bites or
hypodermic inoculations, the differences in respect of length of
incubation must be chiefly ascribed to the variations, at times within
considerable limits, of the ever-undeterminate proportions of the
inoculated viruses which reach the central nervous system.

If, therefore, we desire to make use of the length of incubation as a
measure of the intensity of the virulence, it will be indispensable
to have recourse to inoculation on the surface of the brain, after
trephining, a process the action of which is absolutely certain,
coupled with the use of a larger quantity of virus than what is
strictly sufficient to give rise to rabies. By those means the
irregularities in the length of incubation for the same virus tend to
disappear completely, because we always have the maximum effect which
that virus can produce; that maximum coincides with a minimum length of
incubation.

We have thus, finally, become possessed of a method enabling us to
investigate the possible existence of different degrees of virulence,
and to compare them with one another. The whole secret of the method,
I repeat, consists in inoculating on the brain, after trephining, a
quantity of virus which, although small in itself, is still greater
than what is simply necessary to reproduce rabies. We thus disengage
the incubation from all disturbing influences and render its duration
dependent exclusively on the activity of the particular virus used,
that activity being in each case estimated by the minimum incubation
determined by it.

This method was applied in the first instance to the study of canine
madness, and in particular to the question of knowing whether
dog-madness was always one and the same, with perhaps the slight
variations which might be due to the differences of race in diverse
dogs.

We accordingly got hold of a number of dogs affected with ordinary
street rabies, at all times of the year, at all seasons of the same
year or of different years, and belonging to the most dissimilar canine
races. In each case the bulbar portion of the medulla oblongata was
taken out from the recently dead animal, triturated and suspended in
two or three times its volume of sterilised liquid, making use all
along of every precaution to keep our materials pure, and two drops
of this liquid injected after trephining into one or two rabbits.
The inoculation is made with a Pravaz syringe, the needle of which,
slightly curved at its extremity, is inserted through the dura-mater
into the arachnoid space. The results were as follows: all the rabbits,
from whatever sort of dog inoculated, showed a period of incubation
which ranged between twelve and fifteen days, without almost a single
exception. Never did they show an incubation of eleven, ten, nine, or
eight days, never an incubation of several weeks or of several months.

Dog-rabies, the ordinary rabies, the only known rabies, is thus
sensibly one in its virulence, and its modifications, which are very
limited, appear to depend solely on the varying aptitude for rabies
of the different known races. But we are going now to witness a deep
change in the virulence of dog-rabies.

Let us take one, any one, of our numerous rabbits, inoculated with the
virus of an ordinary mad dog, and, after it has died, extract its bulb,
prepare it just as described, and inject two drops of the bulb-emulsion
into the arachnoid space of a second rabbit, whose bulb will in turn
and in time be injected into a third rabbit, the bulb of which again
will serve for a fourth rabbit, and so on.

There will be evidence, even from the first few passages, of a marked
tendency towards a lessening of the period of incubation in the
succeeding rabbits. Just one example:

Towards the end of the year 1882 fifteen cows and one bull died of
rabies on a farm situated in the neighbourhood of the town of Melun.
They had been bitten on October 2 by the farm dog, which had become
mad. The head of one of the cows, which had died on November 15, was
sent to my laboratory by M. Rossignol, a veterinary surgeon in Melun.
A number of experiments were made on dogs and rabbits, and showed that
the following parts, the only encephalic (or those pertaining to the
brain) ones tested, were rabid: the bulb, the cerebellum, the frontal
lobe, the sphenoidal lobe. The rabbits trephined and inoculated with
those different parts showed the first symptoms of rabies on the
seventeenth and eighteenth days after inoculation. With the bulb of
one of those rabbits two more were inoculated, of which one took rabies
on the fifteenth day, the other on the twenty-third day.

We may notice, once for all, that when rabies is transferred from one
animal to another of a different species, the period of incubation is
always very irregular at first in the individuals of the second species
if the virus had not yet become fixed in its maximum virulence for the
first species. We have just seen an example of that phenomenon, since
one of the rabbits had an incubation of fifteen days, the other of
twenty-three days, both having received the same virus and all other
circumstances remaining apparently the same for them.

The bulb of the first one of those last rabbits which died was
injected into two more rabbits, still after trephining. One of them
took rabies on the tenth day, the other on the fourteenth day. The
bulb of the first one that died was again injected into a couple of
new rabbits, which developed the disease in ten days and twelve days
respectively. A fifth time two new animals were inoculated from the
first one that died, and they both took the disease on the eleventh day
after inoculation: similarly, a sixth passage was made, and gave an
incubation of eleven days, twelve days for the seventh passage, ten and
eleven for the eighth, ten days for the ninth and tenth passages, nine
days for the eleventh, eight and nine days for the twelfth, and so on,
with differences of twenty-four hours at the most, until we got to the
twenty-first passage, when rabies declared itself in eight days, and
subsequently to that always in eight days up to the fiftieth passage,
which was only effected a few days ago. That long experimental series
which is still going on was begun on November 15, 1882, and will be
kept up for the purpose of preserving in our rabies virus that maximum
virulence which it has come to now for some considerable time, as it is
easy to calculate.

Allow me to call your attention to the ease and safety of the
operations for trephining and then inoculating the virus. Throughout
the last twenty months we have been able without a single interruption
in the course of the series to carry the one initial virus through a
succession of rabbits which were all trephined and inoculated every
twelfth day or so.

Guinea-pigs reach more rapidly the maximum virulence of which they are
susceptible. The period of incubation is in them also variable and
irregular at the beginning of the series of successive passages, but
it soon enough fixes itself at a minimum of five days. The maximum
virulence in guinea-pigs is reached after seven or eight passages only.
It is worth noting that the number of passages required before reaching
the maximum virulence, both in guinea-pigs and in rabbits, varies with
the origin of the first virus with which the series is begun.

If now this rabies with maximum virulence be transferred again into the
dog from guinea-pig or rabbit, there is produced a dog-virus which in
point of virulence goes far beyond that of ordinary canine madness.

But, a natural query--of what use can be that discovery as to the
existence and artificial production of diverse varieties of rabies,
every one of them more violent and more rapidly fatal than the habitual
madness of the dog? The man of science is thankful for the smallest
find he can make in the field of pure science, but the many, terrified
at the very name of hydrophobia, claim something more than mere
scientific curiosities. How much more interesting it would be to become
acquainted with a set of rabies viruses which should, on the contrary,
be possessed of attenuated degrees of virulence! Then, indeed, might
there be some hope of creating a number of vaccinal rabies viruses
such as we have done for the virus of fowl-cholera, of the microbe of
saliva, of the red evil of swine (swine-plague), and even of acute
septicæmia. Unfortunately, however, the methods which had served for
those different viruses showed themselves to be either inapplicable
or inefficient in the case of rabies. It therefore became necessary
to find out new and independent methods, such, for example, as the
cultivation _in vitro_ of the mortal rabies virus.

Jenner was the first to introduce into current science the opinion that
the virus which he called the grease of the horse, and which we call
now more exactly horse-pox, probably softened its virulence, so to
speak, in passing through the cow and before it could be transferred
to man without danger. It was therefore natural to think of a possible
diminution of the virulence of rabies by a number of passages through
the organisms of some animal or other, and the experiment was worth
trying. A large number of attempts were made, but the majority of the
animal species experimented on exalted the virulence after the manner
of rabbits and guinea-pigs; fortunately, however, it was not so with
monkey.

On December 6, 1883, a monkey was trephined and inoculated with the
bulb of a dog, which had itself been similarly inoculated from a child
who had died of rabies. The monkey took rabies eleven days later, and
when dead served for inoculation into a second monkey, which also took
the disease on the eleventh day. A third monkey, similarly inoculated
from the second one, showed the first symptoms on the twenty-third
day, etc. The bulb of each one of the monkeys was inoculated, after
trephining, into two rabbits each time. The rabbits inoculated from the
first monkey developed rabies between thirteen and sixteen days, those
from the second monkey between fourteen and twenty days, those from
the third monkey between twenty-six and thirty days, those from the
fourth monkey both of them after the twenty-eighth day, those from the
fifth monkey after twenty-seven days, those from the sixth monkey after
thirty days.

It cannot be doubted after that, that successive passages through
monkeys, and from the several monkeys to rabbits, do diminish the
virulence of the virus for the latter animals; they diminish it for
dogs also. The dog inoculated with the bulb of the fifth monkey gave
an incubation of no less than fifty-eight days, although it had been
inoculated in the arachnoid space.

The experiments were renewed with fresh sets of monkeys and led
to similar results. We were therefore actually in possession of a
method by means of which we could attenuate the virulence of rabies.
Successive inoculations from monkey to monkey elaborate viruses which,
when transferred to rabbits, reproduce rabies in them, but with a
progressively lengthening period of incubation. Nevertheless, if one of
those rabbits be taken as the first for inoculations through a series
of rabbits, the rabies thus cultivated obeys the law which we have seen
before, and has its virulence increased at each passage.

The practical application of those facts gives us a method for the
vaccination of dogs against rabies. As a starting point, make use of
one of the rabbits inoculated from a monkey sufficiently removed from
the first animal of the monkey series for the inoculation--hypodermic
or intra-venous--of that rabbit’s bulb not to be mortal for a new
rabbit. The next vaccinal inoculations are made with the bulbs of
rabbits derived by successive passages from that first rabbit.

In the course of our experiments we made use, as a rule, for
inoculation, of the virus of rabbits which had died after an incubation
of four weeks, repeating three or four times each the vaccinal
inoculations made with the bulbs of rabbits derived in succession
from one another and from the first one of the series, itself coming
directly from the monkey. I abstain from giving more details, because
certain experiments which are actually going on allow me to expect that
the process will be greatly simplified.

You must be feeling, gentlemen, that there is a great blank in my
communication; I do not speak of the micro-organism of rabies. We have
not got it. The process for isolating it is still imperfect, and the
difficulties of its cultivation outside the bodies of animals have not
yet been got rid of, even by the use, as pabulum, of fresh nervous
matter. The methods which we employed in our study of rabies ought all
the more perhaps, on that account, to fix attention. Long still will
the art of preventing diseases have to grapple with virulent maladies
the micro-organic germs of which will escape our investigations. It is,
therefore, a capital scientific fact that we should be able, after all,
to discover the vaccination process for a virulent disease without yet
having at our disposal its special virus and whilst yet ignorant of how
to isolate or to cultivate its microbe.

As soon as the method for the vaccination of dogs was firmly
established, and we had in our possession a large number of dogs which
had been rendered refractory to rabies, I had the idea of submitting
to a competent committee those of the facts which appeared destined in
future to serve as a basis for the vaccination of dogs against rabies.
That course was suggested to me in prevision of the later practical
application of the method, by the recollection of the opposition with
which Jenner’s discovery met at its beginning.

I spoke of my project to M. Fallières, the Minister of Public
Instruction, who was pleased to approve of it and gave commission to
the following gentlemen to control the facts which I had summarily
communicated to the Academy of Sciences in its sitting of May 19 last:
Messrs. Béclard, Paul Bert, Bouley, Aimeraud, Villemin, Vulpian. M.
Bouley was appointed president, Dr. Villemin, secretary, and the
commission at once set to work. I have the pleasure of informing
you that it has just sent in a first report to the Minister. I was
acquainted with it here, and the following are in a few words, the
facts related in that first report on rabies. I had given to the
commission nineteen vaccinated dogs in succession--that is to say,
dogs which had been rendered refractory by preventive inoculations.
Thirteen only of them had after their vaccination been already
submitted to the test-inoculation on the brain.

The nineteen dogs were, for the sake of comparison, divided into
sets along with nineteen more control dogs brought from the pound
without any sort of selection. To begin with, two refractory dogs
and two control dogs were on June 1 trephined and inoculated under
the dura-mater, on the surface of the brain, with the bulb of a dog
affected with ordinary street rabies.

On June 3 another refractory dog and another control dog were bitten by
a furious street mad dog.

The same furious mad dog was on June 4 made to bite still another
refractory and another control dog. On June 6 the furious dog which
had been utilised on June 3 and 4 died. The bulb was taken out and
inoculated, after trephining, into three refractory dogs and three
control dogs. On June 10 another street mad dog, having been secured,
was, by the commission, made to bite one refractory and one control
dog. On June 16 the commission had two new dogs, a refractory one and
a control one, bitten by one of the control dogs of June 1, which had
been seized with rabies on June 14 in consequence of the inoculation
after trephining which it had received on June 1.

On June 19 the commission got three refractory and three control dogs
inoculated before their own eyes in the popliteal vein with the bulb
of an ordinary street mad dog. On June 20 they had inoculated in
their presence, and still in a vein, ten dogs altogether, six of them
refractory and four just brought from the pound.

On June 28, the Commission hearing that M. Paul Simon, a veterinary
surgeon, had a furious biting mad dog, had four of their dogs, two
refractory and two control dogs, taken to his place and bitten by the
mad dog.

The Rabies Commission have, therefore, experimented on thirty-eight
dogs altogether--namely, nineteen refractory dogs and nineteen control
dogs susceptible of taking the disease. Those of the dogs which have
not died in consequence of the operations themselves are still under
observation, and will long continue to be. The commission, reporting
up to the present moment on their observations as to the state of the
animals tried and tested by them, find that out of the nineteen control
dogs six were bitten, of which six three have taken rabies. Seven
received intra-venous inoculations, of which five have died of rabies.
Five were trephined and inoculated on the brain; the five have died of
rabies.

On the other hand, not one of the nineteen vaccinated dogs has taken
rabies.

In the course of the experiments, on July 13, one of the refractory
dogs died in consequence of a black diarrhœa which had begun in the
first days of July. In order to ascertain whether rabies had anything
to do with it as the cause of death, its bulb was at once inoculated,
after trephining, into three rabbits and one guinea-pig. All four
animals are still to-day in perfect health, a certain proof that the
dog died of some common malady, and not of rabies.

The second report of the Commission will be concerned with the
experiments made as to the refractoriness to rabies of twenty dogs to
be vaccinated by the Commission themselves.

(_M. Pasteur then announced that he had just received that same
morning the first report addressed to M. Fallières by the Official
Commission on Rabies. It states that twenty-three refractory dogs were
bitten by ordinary mad dogs, and that not one of them had taken rabies.
On the other hand, within two months after the bites, 66 per cent. of
the normal dogs similarly bitten had already taken the disease._)


_November 1, 1886.--New Communication on Rabies._--On October 26,
1885, I acquainted the Academy with a method of prophylaxis of rabies
after bites. Numerous applications on dogs had justified me in trying
it on man. As early as March 1, 350 persons bitten by dogs undoubtedly
mad, and several more by dogs simply suspected of rabies, had already
been treated at my laboratory by Dr. Grancher. And in consideration
of the happy results obtained it appeared to me that it had become
necessary to found an establishment for anti-rabic vaccinations.

To-day, October 31, 1886, 2,490 persons have received the preventive
inoculations in Paris alone. The treatment was in the first instance
uniform for the great majority of the patients, notwithstanding the
different conditions presented by them as to age, sex, the number of
bites received, their seat, their depth, and the time which had elapsed
since the occurrence of the accident. It lasted ten days, the patient
receiving every day an injection prepared from the spinal marrow of a
rabbit, beginning with that of fourteen days’ and ending with that of
five days’ desiccation.

Those 2,490 cases are subdivided according to nationality in the
following manner:

                       Russia                191
                       Italy                 165
                       Spain                 107
                       England                80
                       Belgium                57
                       Austria                52
                       Portugal               25
                       Roumania               22
                       United States          18
                       Holland                14
                       Greece                 10
                       Germany                 9
                       Turkey                  7
                       Brazil                  3
                       India                   2
                       Switzerland             2
                       France and Algeria  1,726

The number of French persons has been considerable, amounting to 1,726,
and it will be enough to confine ourselves to the category formed by
them as a basis for discussing the degree of efficacy of the method.

Out of the total 1,726 cases treated, the treatment has failed ten
times--namely, in the following cases:

The children: Lagut, Peytel, Clédière, Moulis, Astier, Videau.

The woman: Leduc, seventy years old.

The men: Marius Bouvier (thirty years), Clergot (thirty), and Norbert
Magnevon (eighteen).

I leave out of count two other persons, Louise Pelletier and Moermann,
whose deaths must be attributed to their tardy arrival at the
laboratory, Louise Pelletier thirty-six days, and Moermann forty-three
days after they had been bitten.

We have therefore ten deaths for 1,726 cases, or 1 in 170; such are,
for France and Algeria, the results of the first year’s application of
the method.

Those statistics, taken as a whole, demonstrate the efficacy of the
treatment, as proved further by the relatively large number of deaths
which occurred amongst bitten persons who had not been vaccinated.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 35: From Address delivered August 10, 1884 at the Copenhagen
meeting of the International Medical Congress.]




                                XXXIII

                          JAMES CLERK MAXWELL

                               1831-1879


 _James Clerk Maxwell, born November 13, 1831, attended Edinburgh
 University 1847-1850. Entering Cambridge, he graduated second wrangler
 in 1854. He then taught for four years in Marischal College, Aberdeen,
 and in 1860 was called to King’s College, London, where he remained for
 the following eight years. He early revealed his mathematical genius
 and before he was nineteen had the honor of reading several pages
 before the Royal Society of Edinburgh. He developed by mathematics the
 theory that electricity was a condition of stress or strain in the
 ether, a wave moving in the same medium as light and traveling at the
 same rate of speed. The theory was substantiated by the experiments of
 Hertz, a pupil of Helmholtz, who in 1887 proved the existence of the
 waves which now bear his name. Maxwell died at Cambridge, November 5,
 1879._


       THE MAXWELL AND HERTZ THEORY OF ELECTRICITY AND LIGHT[36]

It was at the moment when the experiments of Fresnel were forcing
the scientific world to admit that light consists of the vibrations
of a highly attenuated fluid filling interplanetary spaces that the
researches of Ampère were making known the laws of the mutual action
of currents and were so enunciating the fundamental principles of
electro-dynamics.

It needed but one step to the supposition that that same fluid, the
ether, which is the medium of luminous phenomena, is at the same
time the vehicle of electrical action. In imagination Ampère made
this stride; but the illustrious physicist could not foresee that the
seducing hypothesis with which he was toying, a mere dream for him, was
ere long to take a precise form and become one of the vital concerns of
exact science.

A dream it remained for many years, till one day, after electrical
measurements had become extremely exact, some physicist, turning over
the numerical data, much as a resting pedestrian might idly turn over
a stone, brought to light an odd coincidence. It was that the factor
of transformation between the system of electro-statical units and the
system of electro-dynamical units was equal to the velocity of light.
Soon the observations directed to this strange coincidence became so
exact that no sane head could longer hold it a mere coincidence. No
longer could it be doubted that some occult affinity existed between
optical and electrical phenomena. Perhaps, however, we might be
wondering to this day what this affinity could be were it not for the
genius of Clerk Maxwell.


                         DISPLACEMENT CURRENTS

The reader is aware that solid bodies are divided into two classes,
conductors through which electricity can move in the form of a galvanic
current, and nonconductors, or dielectrics. The electricians of former
days regarded dielectrics as quite inert, having no part to play but
that of obstinately refusing passage to electricity. Had that been so,
any one non-conductor might be replaced by any other without making
any difference in the phenomena; but Faraday found that that was not
the case. Two condensers of the same form and dimensions put into
connection with the same source of electricity do not take the same
charge, though the thickness of the isolating plate be the same, unless
the matter of that plate be chemically the same. Now Clerk Maxwell had
too deeply studied the researches of Faraday not to comprehend the
importance of dielectrics and the imperative obligation to recognize
their active part.

Besides, if light is but an electric phenomenon, when it traverses a
thickness of glass electrical events must take place in that glass. And
what can be the nature of those events? Maxwell boldly answers, they
are, and must be, currents.

All the experience of his day seemed to contradict this. Never had
currents been observed except in conductors. How was Maxwell to
reconcile his audacious hypothesis with a fact so well established
as that? Why is it that under certain circumstances those supposed
currents produce manifest effects, while under ordinary conditions they
can not be observed at all?

The answer was that dielectrics resist the passage of electricity not
so much more than conductors do, but in a different manner. Maxwell’s
idea will best be understood by a comparison.

If we bend a spring, we meet a resistance which increases the more
the spring is bended. So, if we can only dispose of a finite force, a
moment will come when the motion will cease, equilibrium being reached.
Finally, when the force ceases the spring will in flying back restore
the whole of the energy which has been expended in bending it.

Suppose, on the other hand, that we wish to displace a body plunged
into water. Here again a resistance will be experienced, but it will
not go on increasing in proportion as the body advances, supposing it
to be maintained at a constant velocity. So long as the motive force
acts, equilibrium will never, then, be attained; nor when the force
is removed will the body in the least tend to return, nor can any
portion of the energy expended be restored. It will, in fact, have been
converted into heat by the viscosity of the water.

The contrast is plain; and we ought to distinguish elastic resistance
from viscous resistance. Using these terms, we may express Maxwell’s
idea by saying that dielectrics offer an elastic resistance, conductors
a viscous resistance, to the movements of electricity. Hence, there
are two kinds of currents; currents of displacement which traverse
dielectrics and ordinary currents of conduction which circulate in
conductors.

Currents of the first kind, having to overcome an elastic resistance
which continually increases, naturally can last but a very short time,
since a state of equilibrium will quickly be reached.

Currents of conduction, on the other hand, having only a viscous
resistance to overcome, must continue so long as there is any
electromotive force.

Let us return to the simile used by M. Cornu in his notice in the
Annuaire du Bureau des Longitudes for 1893. Suppose we have in a
reservoir water under pressure. Lead a tube plumb downward into the
reservoir. The water will rise in the tube, but the rise will stop
when hydrostatic equilibrium is attained--that is, when the downward
pressure of the water in the tube above the point of application of the
first pressure on the reservoir, and due to the weight of the water,
balances that first pressure. If the pipe is large, there will be no
friction or loss of head, and the water so raised can be used to do
work. That represents a current of displacement.

If, on the other hand, the water flows out of the reservoir by a
horizontal pipe, the motion will go on till the reservoir is emptied;
but if the tube is small and long there will be a great loss of energy
and considerable production of heat by friction. That represents a
current of conduction.

Though it would be vain, not to say idle, to attempt to represent all
details, it may be said that everything happens just as if the currents
of displacement were acting to bend a multitude of little springs.
When the currents cease, electrostatic equilibrium is established,
and the springs are bent the more, the more intense is the electric
field. The accumulated work of the springs--that is, the electrostatic
energy--can be entirely restored as soon as they can unbend, and so it
is that we obtain mechanical work when we leave the conductors to obey
the electrostatic attractions. Those attractions must be due to the
pressure exercised on the conductors by the bent springs. Finally, to
pursue the image to the death, the disruptive discharge may be compared
to the breaking of the springs when they are bent too much.

On the other hand, the energy employed to produce conduction currents
is lost, being wholly converted into heat, like that spent in
overcoming the viscosity of fluids. Hence it is that the conducting
wires become heated.

From Maxwell’s point of view it seems that all currents are in closed
circuits. The older electricians did not so opine. They regarded the
current circulating in a wire joining the two poles of a pile as
closed; but if in place of directly uniting the two poles we place them
in communication with the two armatures of a condenser, the momentary
current which lasts while the condenser is getting charged was not
considered as a current round a closed circuit. It went, they thought,
from one armature through the wire, the battery, the other wire, to
the other armature, and there it stopped. Maxwell, on the contrary,
supposed that in the form of a current of displacement it passes
through the nonconducting plate of the condenser, and that precisely
what brings it to cessation is the opposite electromotive force set up
by the displacement of electricity in this dielectric.

Currents become sensible in three ways--by their heating effects, by
their actions on other currents and on magnets, and by the induced
currents to which they give rise. We have seen why currents of
conduction develop heat and why currents of displacement do not.
But Maxwell’s hypothetical currents ought at any rate to produce
electro-magnetic and inductive effects. Why do these effects not
appear? The answer is, that it is because a current of displacement
can not last long enough. That is to say, they can not last long in
one direction. Consequently in a dielectric no current can long exist
without alteration. But the effects ought to and will become observable
if the current is continually reversed at sufficiently short intervals.


                          THE NATURE OF LIGHT

Such, according to Maxwell, is the origin of light. A luminiferous wave
is a series of alternating currents produced in dielectrics, in air, or
even in the interplanetary void, and reversed in direction a million
of million of times per second. The enormous induction due to these
frequent alternations sets up other currents in the neighboring parts
of the dielectric, and so the waves are propagated.

Calculation shows that the velocity of propagation would be equal to
the ratio of the units, which we know is the velocity of light.

Those alternative currents are a sort of electrical oscillation. Are
they longitudinal, like those of sound, or are they transversal, like
those of Fresnal’s ether? In the case of sound the air undergoes
alternative condensations and rarefactions. The ether of Fresnal, on
the other hand, behaves as if it were composed of incompressible layers
capable only of slipping over one another. Were these currents in open
paths, the electricity carried from one end to the other would become
accumulated at one extremity. It would thus be condensed and rarefied
like air, and its vibrations would be longitudinal. But Maxwell only
admits currents in closed circuits; accumulation is impossible, and
electricity behaves like the incomprehensible ether of Fresnel, with
its transversal vibrations.


                       EXPERIMENTAL VERIFICATION

We thus obtain all the results of the theory of waves. Yet this was not
enough to decide the physicists to adopt the ideas of Maxwell. It was a
seductive hypothesis; but physicists consider hypotheses which lead to
no distinct observational consequences as beyond the borders of their
province. That province, so defined, no experimental confirmation of
Maxwell’s theory invaded for twenty-five years.

What was wanted was some issue between the two theories not too
delicate for our coarse methods of observation to decide. There was but
one line of research along which any _experimentum crucis_ was to
be met with.

The old electro-dynamics makes electro-magnetic induction take place
instantaneously; but according to Maxwell’s doctrine it propagates
itself with the velocity of light.

The point was then to measure, or at least to make certain, a velocity
of propagation of inductive effects. This is what the illustrious
German physicist Hertz has done by the method of interferences.

The method is well known in its application to optical phenomena. Two
luminous rays from one identical center interfere when they reach the
same point after pursuing paths of different lengths. If the difference
is one, two, or any whole number of wave lengths, the two lights
re-enforce one another so that if their intensities are equal, that of
their combination is four times as great. But if the difference is an
odd number of half wave lengths, the two lights extinguish one another.

Luminiferous waves are not peculiar in showing this phenomenon;
it belongs to every periodic change which is propagated with
definite velocity. Sound interferes just as light does, and so must
electro-dynamic induction if it is strictly periodic and has a definite
velocity of propagation. But if the propagation is instantaneous there
can be no interference, since in that case there is no finite wave
length.

The phenomenon, however, could not be observed were the wave length
greater than the distance within which induction is sensible. It is
therefore requisite to make the period of alternation as short as
possible.


                          ELECTRICAL EXCITERS

We can obtain such currents by means of an apparatus which constitutes
a veritable electrical pendulum. Let two conductors be united by a
wire. If they have not the same electric potential the electrical
equilibrium is disturbed and tends to restore itself, just as the molar
equilibrium is disturbed when a pendulum is carried away from the
position of repose.

A current is set up in the wire, tending to equalize the potential,
just as the pendulum begins to move so as to be carried back to the
position of repose. But the pendulum does not stop when it reaches that
position. Its inertia carries it farther. Nor, when the two electrical
conductors reach the same potential, does the current in the wire
cease. The equilibrium instantaneously existing is at once destroyed by
a cause analogous to inertia, namely self-induction. We know that when
a current is interrupted it gives rise in parallel wires to an induced
current in the same direction. The same effect is produced in the
circuit itself, if that is not broken. In other words, a current will
persist after the cessation of its causes, just as a moving body does
not stop the instant it is no longer driven forward.

When, then, the two potentials become equal, the current will go on and
give the two conductors relative charges opposite to those they had
at first. In this case, as in that of the pendulum, the position of
equilibrium is passed, and a return motion is inevitable. Equilibrium,
again instantaneously attained, is at once again broken for the same
reason; and so the oscillations pursue one another unceasingly.

Calculation shows that the period depends on the capacity of the
conductors in such a way that it is only necessary to diminish that
capacity sufficiently (which is easily done) to have an electric
pendulum capable of producing an alternating current of extremely short
period.

All that was well enough known by the theoretical researches of Lord
Kelvin and by the experimentation of Federson on the oscillatory
discharge of the Leyden jar. It was not that which constituted the
originality of Hertz.

But it is not enough to construct a pendulum; it is further requisite
to set it into oscillation. For that, it is necessary to carry it off
from equilibrium and to let it go suddenly, that is to say, to release
it in a time short as compared to the period of its oscillation.

For if, having pulled a pendulum to one side by a string, we were to
let go of the string more slowly than the pendulum would have descended
of itself, it would reach the vertical without momentum, and no
oscillation would be set up.

In like manner, with an electric pendulum whose natural period is, say,
a hundred-millionth of a second, no mechanical mode of release would
answer the purpose at all, sudden as it might seem to us with our more
than sluggish conceptions of promptitude. How, then, did Hertz solve
the problem?

To return to our electric pendulum, a gap of a few millimeters is
made in the wire which joins the two conductors. This gap divides our
apparatus into two symmetrical parts, which are connected to the two
poles of a Ruhmkorff coil. The induced current begins to charge the
two conductors, and the difference of their potential increases with
relative slowness.

At first the gap prevents a discharge from the conductors; the air in
it plays the rôle of insulator and maintains our pendulum in a position
diverted from that of equilibrium.

But when the difference of potential becomes great enough, a spark will
jump across. If the self-induction is great enough and the capacity
and resistance small enough, there will be an oscillatory discharge
whose period can be brought down to a hundred-millionth of a second.
The oscillatory discharge would not, it is true, last long by itself;
but it is kept up by the Ruhmkorff coil, whose current is itself
oscillatory with a period of about a hundred-thousandth of a second,
and thus the pendulum gets a new impulse as often as that.

The instrument just described is called a resonance exciter. It
produces oscillations which are reversed from a hundred million to a
thousand million times per second. Thanks to this extreme frequency,
they can produce inductive effects at great distances. To make these
effects sensible another electric pendulum is used, called a resonator.
In this the coil is suppressed. It consists simply of two little
metallic spheres very near to one another, with a long wire connecting
them in a roundabout way.

The induction due to the exciter will set the resonator in vibration
the more intensely the more nearly the natural periods of vibration
are the same. At certain phases of the vibration the difference of
potential of the two spheres will be just great enough to cause the
sparks to leap across.


                    PRODUCTION OF THE INTERFERENCES

Thus we have an instrument which reveals the inductive waves which
radiate from the exciter. We can study them in two ways. We may either
expose the resonator to the direct induction of the exciter at a great
distance, or else make this induction act at a small distance on a long
conducting wire which the electric wave will follow and which in its
turn will act at a small distance on the resonator.

Whether the wave is propagated along a wire or across the air,
interferences can be produced by reflection. In the first case it
will be reflected at the extremity of the wire, which it will again
pass through in the opposite direction. In the second case it can be
reflected on a metallic leaf which will act as a mirror. In either case
the reflected ray will interfere with the direct ray, and positions
will be found in which the spark of the resonator will be extinguished.

Experiments with a long wire are the easier and furnish much valuable
information, but they cannot furnish an _experimentum crucis_,
since in the old theory, as in the new, the velocity of the electric
wave in a wire should be equal to that of light. But experiments on
direct induction at great distances are decisive. They not only show
that the velocity of propagation of induction across air is finite,
but also that it is equal to the velocity of the wave propagated along
a wire, conformably to the ideas of Maxwell.


                          SYNTHESIS OF LIGHT

I shall insist less on other experiments of Hertz, more brilliant
but less instructive. Concentrating with a parabolic mirror the wave
of induction that emanates from the exciter, the German physicist
obtained a true pencil of rays of electric force, susceptible of
regular reflection and refraction. These rays, were the period but
one-millionth of what it is, would not differ from rays of light.
We know that the sun sends us several varieties of radiations, some
luminiferous, since they act on the retina, others dark, infra-red, or
ultraviolet, which reveal themselves in chemical and calorific effects.
The first owe the qualities which render them sensible to us to a
physiological chance. For the physicist, the infra-red differs from red
only as red differs from green; it simply has a greater wave length.
That of the Hertzian radiations is far greater still, but they are mere
differences of degree, and if the ideas of Clerk Maxwell are true, the
illustrious professor of Bonn has effected a genuine synthesis of light.


                              CONCLUSION

Nevertheless, our admiration for such unhoped-for successes must not
let us forget what remains to be accomplished. Let us endeavor to take
exact account of the results definitely acquired.

In the first place, the velocity of direct induction through air is
finite; for otherwise interferences could not exist. Thus the old
electro-dynamics is condemned. But what is to be set up in its place?
Is it to be the doctrine of Maxwell, or rather some approximation to
that, for it would be too much to suppose that he had foreseen the
truth in all its details? Though the probabilities are accumulating, no
complete demonstration of that doctrine has ever attained.

We can measure the wave length of the Hertzian oscillations. That
length is the product of the period into the velocity of propagation.
We should know the velocity if we knew the period; but this last is
so minute that we cannot measure it; we can only calculate it by a
formula due to Lord Kelvin. That calculation leads to figures agreeable
to the theory of Maxwell; but the last doubts will only be dissipated
when the velocity of propagation has been directly measured. (See Note
I.)

But this is not all. Matters are far from being as simple as this
brief account of the matter would lead one to think. There are various
complications.

In the first place, there is around the exciter a true radiation of
induction. The energy of the apparatus radiates abroad, and if no
source feeds it, it quickly dissipates itself and the oscillations
are rapidly extinguished. Hence arises the phenomenon of multiple
resonance, discovered by Messrs. Sarasin and De la Rive, which at first
seemed irreconcilable with the theory.

On the other hand, we know that light does not exactly follow the
laws of geometrical optics, and the discrepancy, due to diffraction,
increases proportionately to the wave length. With the great waves
of the Hertzian undulations these phenomena must assume enormous
importance and derange everything. It is doubtless fortunate, for the
moment at least, that our means of observation are as coarse as they
are, for otherwise the simplicity which struck us would give place to
a dedalian complexity in which we should lose our way. No doubt a good
many perplexing anomalies have been due to this. For the same reason
the experiments to prove a refraction of the electrical waves can
hardly be considered as demonstrative.

It remains to speak of a difficulty still more grave, though doubtless
not insurmountable. According to Maxwell, the coefficient of
electrostatic induction of a transparent body ought to be equal to the
square of its index of refraction. Now this is not so. The few bodies
which follow Maxwell’s law are exceptions. The phenomena are plainly
far more complex than was at first thought. But we have not yet been
able to make out how matters stand, and the experiments conflict with
one another.

Much, then, remains to be done. The identity of light with a vibratory
motion in electricity is henceforth something more than a seductive
hypothesis; it is a probable truth. But it is not yet quite proved.

NOTE I.--Since the above was written another great step
has been taken. M. Blondlot has virtually succeeded, by ingenious
experimental contrivances, in directly measuring the velocity of a
disturbance along a wire. The number found differs little from the
ratio of the units; that is, from the velocity of light, which is
300,000 kilometers per second. Since the interference experiments made
at Geneva by Messrs. Sarasin and De la Rive have shown, as I said
above, that induction is propagated in air with the same velocity as an
electric disturbance which follows a conducting wire, we must conclude
that the velocity of the induction is the same as that of light, which
is a confirmation of the ideas of Maxwell.

M. Fizeau had formerly found for the velocity of electricity a number
far smaller, about 180,000 kilometers. But there is no contradiction.
The currents used by M. Fizeau, though intermittent, were of small
frequency and penetrated to the axis of the wire, while the currents of
M. Blondlot, oscillatory and of very short period, remained superficial
and were confined to a layer of less than a hundredth of a millimeter
in thickness. One may readily suppose the laws of propagation are not
the same in the two cases.

NOTE II.--I have endeavored above to render the explanation
of the electrostatic attractions and of the phenomena of induction
comprehensible by means of a simile. Now let us see what Maxwell’s idea
is of the cause which produces the mutual attractions of currents.

While the electrostatic attractions are taken to be due to a multitude
of little springs--that is to say, to the elasticity of the ether--it
is supposed to be the living force and inertia of the same fluid which
produce the phenomena of induction and electro-dynamical effects.

The complete calculation is far too extended for these pages, and I
shall again content myself with a simile. I shall borrow it from a well
known instrument--the centrifugal governor.

The living force of this apparatus is proportional to the square of the
angular velocity and to the square of the distance of the balls.

According to the hypothesis of Maxwell, the ether is in motion in
galvanic currents, and its living force is proportional to the square
of the intensity of the current, which thus correspond, in the parallel
I am endeavoring to establish, to the angular velocity of rotation.

If we consider two currents in the same direction, the living force,
with equal intensity, will be greater the nearer the currents are to
one another. If the currents have opposite directions, the living force
will be greater the farther they are apart.

In order to increase the angular velocity of the regulator and
consequently its living force, it is necessary to supply it with
energy and consequently to overcome a resistance which we call its
inertia.

In the same way, in order to increase the intensity of a current, we
must augment the living force of the ether, and it will be necessary to
supply it with energy and to overcome a resistance which is nothing but
the inertia of the ether and which we call the induction.

The living force will be greater if the currents are in the same
direction and near together. The energy to be furnished the counter
electromotive force of induction will be greater. This is what we
express when we say that the mutual action of two currents is to be
added to their self-induction. The contrary is the case when their
directions are opposite.

If we separate the balls of the regulator, it will be necessary, in
order to maintain the angular velocity, to furnish energy, because with
equal angular velocity the living force is greater the more the balls
are separated.

In the same way, if two currents have the same direction and are
brought toward one another, it will be necessary, in order to maintain
the intensity to supply energy, because the living force will be
augmented. We shall, therefore, have to overcome an electromotive
force of induction which will tend to diminish the intensity of the
currents. It would tend on the contrary to augment it, if the currents
had the same direction and were carried apart, or if they had opposite
directions and were brought together.

Finally, the centrifugal force tends to increase the distance between
the balls, which would augment the living force were the angular
velocity to be maintained.

In like manner, when the currents have the same direction, they attract
each other--that is to say, they tend to approach each other, which
would increase the living force if the intensity were maintained.
If their directions are opposed they repel one another and tend to
separate, which would again tend to increase the living force were the
intensity kept constant.

Thus the electrostatic effects would be due to the elasticity of the
ether and the electro-dynamical phenomena to the living force. Now,
ought this elasticity itself to be explained, as Lord Kelvin thinks, by
rotations of small parts of the fluid? Different reasons may render
this hypothesis attractive; but it plays no essential part in the
theory of Maxwell, which is quite independent of it.

In the same way, I have made comparisons with divers mechanisms. But
they are only similes, and pretty rough ones. A complete mechanical
explanation of electrical phenomena is not to be sought in the volumes
of Maxwell, but only a statement of the conditions which any such
explanation has to satisfy. Precisely what will confer long life on the
work of Maxwell is its being unentangled with any special mechanical
hypothesis.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 36: Translated from a paper by M. Henri Poincaré.]




                                 XXXIV

                            AUGUST WEISMANN

                               1834-1914


 _August Weismann was born at Frankfort-on-Main, January 17, 1834,
 and studied medicine at Göttingen, 1852-1856. He was physician to the
 Austrian Archduke for two years (1860-62), but was compelled to retire
 because of his poor eyesight. He was called to the chair of zoology
 at Freiburg University. After a close study of Darwin’s theory, he
 published in 1876 his “Studies in the Theories of Descent,” a book
 which at once attracted much attention among scientists, for it
 proposed the theory of the germ-plasm as the basis of heredity, and
 denied the theory of the transmissibility of acquired characteristics.
 He died at Freiburg-in-Baden, November 6, 1914._


   THE CONTINUITY OF THE GERM-PLASM AS THE FOUNDATION OF A THEORY OF
                             HEREDITY[37]

                             INTRODUCTION

When we see that, in the higher organisms, the smallest structural
details, and the most minute peculiarities of bodily and mental
disposition, are transmitted from one generation to another; when we
find in all species of plants and animals a thousand characteristic
peculiarities of structure continued unchanged through long series of
generations; when we even see them in many cases unchanged throughout
whole geological periods; we very naturally ask for the causes of
such a striking phenomenon: and inquire how it is that such facts
become possible, how it is that the individual is able to transmit its
structural features to its offspring with such precision. And the
immediate answer to such a question must be given in the following
terms:--“A single cell out of the millions of diversely differentiated
cells which compose the body, becomes specialized as a sexual cell; it
is thrown off from the organism and is capable of reproducing all the
peculiarities of the parent body, in the new individual which springs
from it by cell-division and the complex process of differentiation.”
Then the more precise question follows: “How is it that such a single
cell can reproduce the _tout ensemble_ of the parent with all the
faithfulness of a portrait?”

The answer is extremely difficult; and no one of the many attempts
to solve the problem can be looked upon as satisfactory; no one of
them can be regarded as even the beginning of a solution or as a
secure foundation from which a complete solution may be expected in
the future. Neither Häeckel’s “Perigenesis of the Plastidule,” nor
Darwin’s “Pangenesis,” can be regarded as such a beginning. The former
hypothesis does not really treat of that part of the problem which
is here placed in the foreground, viz., the explanation of the fact
that the tendencies of heredity are present in single cells, but it
is rather concerned with the question as to the manner in which it
is possible to conceive the transmission of a certain tendency of
development into the sexual cell, and ultimately into the organism
arising from it. The same may be said of the hypothesis of His, who,
like Häeckel regards heredity as the transmission of certain kinds of
motion. On the other hand, it must be conceded that Darwin’s hypothesis
goes to the very root of the question, but he is content to give, as
it were, a provisional or purely formal solution, which, as he himself
says, does not claim to afford insight into the real phenomena, but
only to give us the opportunity of looking at all the facts of heredity
from a common standpoint. It has achieved this end, and I believe it
has unconsciously done more, in that the thoroughly logical application
of its principles has shown that the real causes of heredity cannot
lie in the formation of gemmules or in any allied phenomena. The
improbabilities to which any such theory would lead are so great that
we can affirm with certainty that its details cannot accord with
existing facts. Furthermore, Brooks’ well-considered and brilliant
attempt to modify the theory of Pangenesis cannot escape the reproach
that it is based upon possibilities, which one might certainly describe
as improbabilities. But although I am of the opinion that the whole
foundation of the theory of Pangenesis, however it may be modified,
must be abandoned, I think, nevertheless, its author deserves great
credit, and that its production has been one of those indirect roads
along which science has been compelled to travel in order to arrive
at the truth. Pangenesis is a modern revival of the oldest theory of
heredity, that of Democritus, according to which the sperm is secreted
from all parts of the body of both sexes during copulation, and is
animated by a bodily force; according to this theory also, the sperm
from each part of the body reproduces the same part.

If, according to the received physiological and morphological ideas
of the day, it is impossible to imagine that gemmules produced by
each cell of the organism are at all times to be found in all parts
of the body, and furthermore that these gemmules are collected in the
sexual cells, which are then able to reproduce again in a certain
order each separate cell of the organism, so that each sexual cell is
capable of developing into the likeness of the parent body; if all
this is inconceivable, we must inquire for some other way in which we
can arrive at a foundation for the true understanding of heredity. My
present task is not to deal with the whole question of heredity, but
only with the single although fundamental question--“How is it that a
single cell of the body can contain within itself all the hereditary
tendencies of the whole organism?” I am here leaving out of account
the further question as to the forces and the mechanism by which these
tendencies are developed in the building-up of the organism. On this
account I abstain from considering at present the views of Nägeli, for
as will be shown later on, they only slightly touch this fundamental
question, although they may certainly claim to be of the highest
importance with respect to the further question alluded to above.

Now if it is impossible for the germ-cell to be, as it were, an extract
of the whole body, and for all the cells of the organism to dispatch
small particles to the germ-cells, from which the latter derive their
power of heredity; then there remain, as it seems to me, only two other
possible, physiologically conceivable, theories as to the origin of
germ-cells, manifesting such powers as we know they possess. Either
the substance of the parent germ-cell is capable of undergoing a
series of changes which, after the building-up of a new individual
leads back again to identical germ-cells; or the germ-cells are not
derived at all, as far as their essential and characteristic substance
is concerned, from the body of the individual, but they are derived
directly from the parent germ-cell.

I believe that the latter view is the true one: I have expounded it
for a number of years, and have attempted to defend it, and to work
out its further details in various publications. I propose to call it
the theory of “The Continuity of the Germ-plasm,” for it is founded
upon the idea that heredity is brought about by the transference from
one generation to another of a substance with a definite chemical,
and above all, molecular constitution. I have called this substance
“germ-plasm,” and have assumed that it possesses a highly complex
structure, conferring upon it the power of developing into a complex
organism. I have attempted to explain heredity by supposing that in
each ontogeny a part of the specific germ-plasm contained in the
parent egg-cell is not used up in the construction of the body of
the offspring, but is reserved unchanged for the formation of the
germ-cells of the following generation.

It is clear that this view of the origin of germ-cells explains the
phenomena of heredity very simply, inasmuch as heredity becomes thus
a question of growth and of assimilation,--the most fundamental of
all vital phenomena. If the germ-cells of successive generations are
directly continuous, and thus only form, as it were, different parts
of the same substance, it follows that these cells must, or at any
rate may, possess the same molecular constitution, and that they
would therefore pass through exactly the same stages under certain
conditions of development, and would form the same final product. The
hypothesis of the continuity of the germ-plasm gives an identical
starting point to each successive generation, and thus explains how it
is that an identical product arises from all of them. In other words,
the hypothesis explains heredity as part of the underlying problems
of assimilation and of the causes which act directly during ontogeny;
it therefore builds a foundation from which the explanation of these
phenomena can be attempted.

It is true that this theory also meets with difficulties, for it seems
to be unable to do justice to a certain class of phenomena, viz.,
the transmission of so-called acquired characters. I therefore gave
immediate and special attention to this point in my first publication
on heredity, and I believe that I have shown that the hypothesis of
the transmission of acquired characters--up to that time generally
accepted--is, to say the least, very far from being proved, and
that entire classes of facts which have been interpreted under this
hypothesis may be quite as well interpreted otherwise, while in many
cases they must be explained differently. I have shown that there is
no ascertained fact which, at least up to the present time, remains
in irrevocable conflict with the hypothesis of the continuity of
the germ-plasm; and I do not know any reason why I should modify
this opinion to-day, for I have not heard of any objection which
appears to be feasible. E. Roth has objected that in pathology we
everywhere meet with the fact that acquired local disease may be
transmitted to the offspring as a predisposition; but all such cases
are exposed to the serious criticism that the very point that first
needs to be placed on a secure footing is incapable of proof, viz.,
the hypothesis that the causes which in each particular case led to
the predisposition were really acquired. It is not my intention, on
the present occasion, to enter fully into the question of acquired
characters; I hope to be able to consider the subject in greater detail
at a future date. But in the meantime I should wish to point out that
we ought, above all, to be clear as to what we really mean by the
expression “acquired character.” An organism cannot acquire anything
unless it already possesses the predisposition to acquire it: acquired
characters are therefore no more than local or sometimes general
variations which arise under the stimulus provided by certain external
influences. If by the long-continued handling of a rifle, the so-called
“_Exercierknochen_” (a bony growth caused by the pressure of
the weapon in drilling) is developed, such a result depends upon
the fact that the bone in question, like every other bone, contains
within itself a predisposition to react upon certain mechanical
stimuli, by growth in a certain direction and to a certain extent. The
predisposition towards an “_Exercierknochen_” is therefore already
present, or else the growth could not be formed; and the same reasoning
applies to all other “acquired characters.”

Nothing can arise in an organism unless the predisposition to it is
pre-existent, for every acquired character is simply the reaction
of the organism upon a certain stimulus. Hence I should never have
thought of asserting that predispositions cannot be transmitted, as
E. Roth appears to believe. For instance, I freely admit that the
predisposition to an “_Exercierknochen_” varies, and that a
strongly marked predisposition may be transmitted from father to son,
in the form of bony tissue with a more susceptible constitution. But
I should deny that the son could develop an “_Exercierknochen_”
without having drilled, or that, after having drilled, he could
develop it more easily than his father, on account of the drilling
through which the latter first acquired it. I believe that this is as
impossible as that the leaf of an oak should produce a gall without
having been pierced by a gall-producing insect, as a result of the
thousands of antecedent generations of oaks which have been pierced by
such insects, and have thus “acquired” the power of producing galls. I
am also far from asserting that the germ-plasm--which, as I hold, is
transmitted as the basis of heredity from one generation to another--is
absolutely unchangeable or totally uninfluenced by forces residing in
the organism within which it is transformed into germ-cells. I am also
compelled to admit that it is conceivable that organisms may exert a
modifying influence upon their germ-cells, and even that such a process
is to a certain extent inevitable. The nutrition and growth of the
individual must exercise some influence upon its germ-cells; but in the
first place this influence must be extremely slight, and in the second
place it cannot act in the manner in which it is usually assumed that
it takes place. A change of growth at the periphery of an organism,
as in the case of an “_Exercierknochen_,” can never cause such a
change in the molecular structure of the germ-plasm as would augment
the predisposition to an “_Exercierknochen_,” so that the son
would inherit an increased susceptibility of the bony tissue or even of
the particular bone in question. But any change produced will result
from the reaction of the germ-cell upon changes of nutrition caused by
alteration in growth at the periphery, leading to some change in the
size, number, or arrangement of its molecular units. In the present
state of our knowledge there is reason for doubting whether such
reaction can occur at all; but, if it can take place, at all events
the quality of the change in the germ-plasm can have nothing to do
with the quality of the acquired character, but only with the way in
which the general nutrition is influenced by the latter. In the case of
the “_Exercierknochen_” there would be practically no change in
the general nutrition, but if such a bony growth could reach the size
of a carcinoma, it is conceivable that a disturbance of the general
nutrition of the body might ensue. Certain experiments on plants--on
which Nägeli showed that they can be submitted to strongly varied
conditions of nutrition for several generations, without the production
of any visible hereditary change--show that the influence of nutrition
upon the germ-cells must be very slight, and that it may possibly leave
the molecular structure of the germ-plasm altogether untouched. This
conclusion is also supported by comparing the uncertainty of these
results with the remarkable precision with which heredity acts in the
case of those characters which are known to be transmitted. In fact,
up to the present time, it has never been proved that any changes in
general nutrition can modify the molecular structure of the germ-plasm,
and far less has it been rendered by any means probable that the
germ-cells can be affected by acquired changes which have no influence
on general nutrition. If we consider that each so-called predisposition
(that is, a power of reacting upon a certain stimulus in a certain way,
possessed by any organism or by one of its parts) must be innate, and
further that each acquired character is only the predisposed reaction
of some part of an organism upon some external influence; then we must
admit that only one of the causes which produce any acquired character
can be transmitted, the one which was present before the character
itself appeared, viz., the predisposition; and we must further
admit that the latter arises from the germ, and that it is quite
immaterial to the following generation whether such predisposition
comes into operation or not. The continuity of the germ-plasm is amply
sufficient to account for such a phenomenon, and I do not believe that
any objection to my hypothesis, founded upon the actually observed
phenomena of heredity, will be found to hold. If it be accepted, many
facts will appear in a light different from that which has been cast
upon them by the hypothesis which has been hitherto received,--a
hypothesis which assumes that the organism produces germ-cells afresh,
again and again, and that it produces them entirely from its own
substance. Under the former theory the germ-cells are no longer looked
upon as the product of the parent’s body, at least as far as their
essential part--the specific germ-plasm--is concerned: they are rather
considered as something which is to be placed in contrast with the
_tout ensemble_ of the cells which make up the parent’s body, and
the germ-cells of succeeding generations stand in a similar relation
to one another as a series of generations of unicellular organisms,
arising by a continued process of cell-division. It is true that in
most cases the generations of germ-cells do not arise immediately
from one another as complete cells, but only as minute particles of
germ-plasm. This latter substance, however forms the foundation of the
germ-cells of the next generation, and stamps them with their specific
character. Previous to the publication of my theory, C. Jäger, and
later M. Nussbaum, have expressed ideas upon heredity which come very
near to my own. Both of these writers started with the hypothesis that
there must be a direct connection between the germ-cells of succeeding
generations, and they tried to establish such a continuity by supposing
that the germ-cells of the offspring are separated from the parent
germ-cell before the beginning of embryonic development, or at least
before any histological differentiation has taken place. In this form
their suggestion cannot be maintained, for it is in conflict with
numerous facts. A continuity of the germ-cells does not now take place,
except in very rare instances; but this fact does not prevent us from
adopting a theory of the continuity of the germ-plasm, in favour of
which much weighty evidence can be brought forward. In the following
pages I shall attempt to develop further the theory of which I have
just given a short account, to defend it against any objections which
have been brought forward, and to draw from it new conclusions which
may perhaps enable us more thoroughly to appreciate facts which are
known, but imperfectly understood. It seems to me that this theory of
continuity of the germ-plasm deserves at least to be examined in all
its details, for it is the simplest theory upon the subject, and the
one which is most obviously suggested by the facts of the case, and we
shall not be justified in forsaking it for a more complex theory until
proof that it can be no longer maintained is forthcoming. It does not
presuppose anything except facts which can be observed at any moment,
although they may not be understood,--such as assimilation, or the
development of like organisms from like germs; while every other theory
of heredity is founded on hypotheses which cannot be proved. It is
nevertheless possible that continuity of the germ-plasm does not exist
in the manner in which I imagine that it takes place, for no one can at
present decide whether all the ascertained facts agree with and can be
explained by it. Moreover, the ceaseless activity of research brings to
light new facts every day, and I am far from maintaining that my theory
may not be disproved by some of these. But even if it should have to
be abandoned at a later period, it seems to me that, at the present
time, it is a necessary stage in the advancement of our knowledge, and
one which must be brought forward and passed through, whether it prove
right or wrong, in the future. In this spirit I offer the following
considerations, and it is in this spirit that I should wish them to be
received.


                            THE GERM-PLASM

I entirely agree with Strasburger when he says, “The specific qualities
of organisms are based upon nuclei”; and I further agree with him in
many of his ideas as to the relation between the nucleus and cell-body:
“Molecular stimuli proceed from the nucleus into the surrounding
cytoplasm; stimuli which, on the one hand, control the phenomena of
assimilation in the cell, and, on the other hand, give to the growth
of the cytoplasm, which depends upon nutrition, a certain character
peculiar to the species.” “The nutritive cytoplasm assimilates, while
the nucleus controls the assimilation, and hence the substances
assimilated possess a certain constitution and nourish in a certain
manner the cyto-idioplasm and the nuclear idioplasm. In this way the
cytoplasm takes part in the phenomena of construction, upon which the
specific form of the organism depends. This constructive activity
of the cyto-idioplasm depends upon the regulative influence of the
nuclei.” The nuclei therefore “determine the specific direction in
which an organism develops.”

The opinion--derived from the recent study of the phenomena of
fertilization--that the nucleus impresses its specific character
upon the cell, has received conclusive and important confirmation
in the experiments upon the regeneration of Infusoria, conducted
simultaneously by M. Nussbaum at Bonn, and by A. Gruber at Freiburg.
Nussbaum’s statement that an artificially separated portion of a
_Paramaecium_, which does not contain any nuclear substance,
immediately dies, must not be accepted as of general application, for
Gruber has kept similar fragments of other Infusoria alive for several
days. Moreover, Gruber had previously shown that individual Protozoa
occur, which live in a normal manner, and are yet without a nucleus,
although this structure is present in other individuals of the same
species. But the meaning of the nucleus is made clear by the fact,
published by Gruber, that such artificially separated fragments of
Infusoria are incapable of regeneration, while on the other hand those
fragments which contain nuclei always regenerate. It is therefore only
under the influence of the nucleus that the cell substance re-develops
into the full type of the species. In adopting the view that the
nucleus is the factor which determines the specific nature of the cell,
we stand on a firm foundation upon which we can build with security.

If therefore the first segmentation nucleus contains, in its molecular
structure, the whole of the inherited tendencies of development, it
must follow that during segmentation and subsequent cell-division, the
nucleoplasm will enter upon definite and varied changes which must
cause the differences appearing in the cells which are produced; for
identical cell-bodies depend, _ceteris paribus_, upon identical
nucleoplasm, and conversely different cells depend upon differences
in the nucleoplasm. The fact that the embryo grows more strongly in
one direction than in another, that its cell-layers are of different
nature and are ultimately differentiated into various organs and
tissues,--forces us to accept the conclusion that the nuclear substance
has also been changed in nature, and that such changes take place
during ontogenetic development in a regular and definite manner.
This view is also held by Strasburger, and it must be the opinion of
all who seek to derive the development of inherited tendencies from
the molecular structure of the germ-plasm, instead of from preformed
gemmules.

We are thus led to the important question as to the forces by which the
determining substance or nucleoplasm is changed, and as to the manner
in which it changes during the course of ontogeny, and on the answer
to this question our further conclusions must depend. The simplest
hypothesis would be to suppose that, at each division of the nucleus,
its specific substance divides into two halves of unequal quality, so
that the cell-bodies would also be transformed; for we have seen that
the character of a cell is determined by that of its nucleus. Thus in
any Metazoon the first two segmentation spheres would be transformed in
such a manner that one only contained the hereditary tendencies of the
endoderm and the other those of the ectoderm, and therefore, at a later
stage, the cells of the endoderm would arise from the one and those of
the ectoderm from the other; and this is actually known to occur. In
the course of further division the nucleoplasm of the first ectoderm
cell would again divide unequally, _e. g._, into the nucleoplasm
containing the hereditary tendencies of the nervous system, and into
that containing the tendencies of the external skin. But even then,
the end of the unequal division of nuclei would not have been nearly
reached; for, in the formation of the nervous system, the nuclear
substance which contains the hereditary tendencies of the sense-organs
would, in the course of further cell-division, be separated from that
which contains the tendencies of the central organs, and the same
process would continue in the formation of all single organs, and in
the final development of the most minute histological elements. This
process would take place in a definitely ordered course, exactly as
it has taken place throughout a very long series of ancestors; and
the determining and directing factor is simply and solely the nuclear
substance, the nucleoplasm, which possesses such a molecular structure
in the germ-cell that all such succeeding stages of its molecular
structure in future nuclei must necessarily arise from it, as soon as
the requisite external conditions are present. This is almost the same
conception of ontogenetic development as that which has been held by
embryologists who have not accepted the doctrine of evolution: for we
have only to transfer the primary cause of development, from an unknown
source within the organism, into the nuclear substance, in order to
make the views identical.


I believe I have shown that theoretically hardly any objection can be
raised against the view that the nuclear substance of somatic cells
may contain unchanged germ-plasm, or that this germ-plasm may be
transmitted along certain lines. It is true that we might imagine _a
priori_ that all somatic nuclei contain a small amount of unchanged
germ-plasm. In Hydroids such an assumption cannot be made, because only
certain cells in a certain succession possess the power of developing
into germ-cells; but it might well be imagined that in some organisms
it would be a great advantage if every part possessed the power of
growing up into the whole organism and of producing sexual cells under
appropriate circumstances. Such cases might exist if it were possible
for all somatic nuclei to contain a minute fraction of unchanged
germ-plasm. For this reason, Strasburger’s other objection against my
theory also fails to hold; viz., that certain plants can be propagated
by pieces of rhizomes, roots, or even by means of leaves, and that
plants produced in this manner may finally give rise to flowers, fruit
and seeds, from which new plants arise. “It is easy to grow new plants
from the leaves of begonia which have been cut off and merely laid upon
moist sand, and yet in the normal course of ontogeny the molecules of
germ-plasm would not have been compelled to pass through the leaf; and
they ought therefore to be absent from its tissue. Since it is possible
to raise from the leaf a plant which produces flower and fruit, it is
perfectly certain that special cells containing the germ-substance
cannot exist in the plant.” But I think that this fact only proves
that in begonia and similar plants all the cells of the leaves or
perhaps only certain cells contain a small amount of germ-plasm, and
that consequently these plants are specially adapted for propagation
by leaves. How is it then that all plants cannot be reproduced in this
way? No one has ever grown a tree from the leaf of the lime or oak,
or a flowering plant from the leaf of the tulip or convolvulus. It
is insufficient to reply that in the last mentioned cases the leaves
are more strongly specialized, and have thus become unable to produce
germ-substance; for the leaf-cells in these different plants have
hardly undergone histological differentiation in different degrees.
If, notwithstanding, the one can produce a flowering plant, while the
others have not this power, it is of course clear that reasons other
than the degree of histological differentiation must exist; and,
according to my opinion, such a reason is to be found in the admixture
of a minute quantity of unchanged germ-plasm with some of their nuclei.

In Sach’s excellent lectures on the physiology of plants, we read on
page 723--“In the true mosses almost any cell of the roots, leaves and
shoot-axes, and even of the immature sporogonium, may grow out under
favourable conditions, become rooted, form new shoots, and give rise to
an independent living plant.” Since such plants produce germ-cells at
a later period, we have here a case which requires the assumption that
all or nearly all cells must contain germ-plasm.

The theory of the continuity of the germ-plasm seems to me to be
still less disproved or even rendered improbable by the facts of the
alternation of generations. If the germ-plasm may pass on from the egg
into certain somatic cells of an individual, and if it can be further
transmitted along certain lines, there is no difficulty in supposing
that it may be transmitted through a second, third, or through any
number of individuals produced from the former by budding. In fact, in
the Hydroids, on which my theory of the continuity of the germ-plasm
has been chiefly based, alternation of generations is the most
important means of propagation.


                 THE SIGNIFICANCE OF THE POLAR BODIES

We have already seen that the specific nature of a cell depends upon
the molecular structure of its nucleus; and it follows from this
conclusion that my theory is further, and as I believe strongly,
supported, by the phenomenon of the expulsion of polar bodies, which
has remained inexplicable for so long a time.

For if the specific molecular structure of a cell-body is caused
and determined by the structure of the nucleoplasm, every kind of
cell which is histologically differentiated must have a specific
nucleoplasm. But the egg-cell of most animals, at any rate during
the period of growth, is by no means an indifferent cell of the most
primitive type. At such a period its cell-body has to perform quite
peculiar and specific functions; it has to secrete nutritive substances
of a certain chemical nature and physical constitution, and to store
up this food material in such a manner that it may be at the disposal
of the embryo during its development. In most cases the egg-cell
also forms membranes which are often characteristic of particular
species of animals. The growing egg-cell is therefore histologically
differentiated: and in this respect resembles a somatic cell. It
may perhaps be compared to a gland-cell, which does not expel its
secretion, but deposits it within its own substance. To perform such
specific functions it requires a specific cell-body, and the latter
depends upon a specific nucleus. It therefore follows that the growing
egg-cell must possess nucleoplasm of specific molecular structure,
which directs the above mentioned secretory functions of the cell.
The nucleoplasm of histologically differentiated cells may be called
histogenetic nucleoplasm, and the growing egg-cell must contain such
a substance, and even a certain specific modification of it. This
nucleoplasm cannot possibly be the same as that which, at a later
period, causes embryonic development. Such development can only be
produced by the true germ-plasm of immensely complex constitution, such
as I have previously attempted to describe. It therefore follows that
the nucleus of the egg-cell contains two kinds of nucleoplasm:--germ
and a peculiar modification of histogenetic nucleoplasm, which
may be called ovogenetic nucleoplasm. This substance must greatly
preponderate in the young egg-cell, for, as we have already seen, it
controls the growth of the latter. The germ-plasm, on the other hand,
can only be present in minute quantity at first, but it must undergo
considerable increase during the growth of the cell. But in order
that the germ-plasm may control the cell-body, or, in other words, in
order that embryonic development may begin, the still preponderating
ovogenetic nucleoplasm must be removed from the cell. This removal
takes place in the same manner as that in which differing nuclear
substances are separated during the ontogeny of the embryo: viz., by
nuclear division, leading to cell-division. The expulsion of the polar
bodies is nothing more than the removal of ovogenetic nucleoplasm from
the egg-cell. That the ovogenetic nucleoplasm continues greatly to
preponderate in the nucleus up to the very last, may be concluded from
the fact that two successive divisions of the latter and the expulsion
of two polar bodies appear to be the rule. If in this way a small part
of the cell-body is expelled from the egg, the extrusion must in all
probability be considered as an inevitable loss, without which the
removal of the ovogenetic nucleoplasm cannot be effected.


                   ON THE NATURE OF PARTHENOGENESIS

It is well known that the formation of polar bodies has been repeatedly
connected with the sexuality of germ-cells, and that it has been
employed to explain the phenomena of parthenogenesis. I may now perhaps
be allowed to develop the views as to the nature of parthenogenesis at
which I have arrived under the influence of my explanation of polar
bodies.

The theory of parthenogenesis adopted by Minot and Balfour is
distinguished by its simplicity and clearness, among all other
interpretations which had been hitherto offered. Indeed, their
explanation follows naturally and almost as a matter of course, if the
assumption made by these observers be correct, that the polar body is
the male part of the hermaphrodite egg-cell. An egg which has lost its
male part cannot develop into an embryo until it has received a new
male part in fertilization. On the other hand, an egg which does not
expel its male part may develop without fertilization, and thus we are
led to the obvious conclusion that parthenogenesis is based upon the
non-expulsion of polar bodies. Balfour distinctly states “that the
function of forming polar cells has been acquired by the ovum for the
express purpose of preventing parthenogenesis.”

It is obvious that I cannot share this opinion, for I regard the
expulsion of polar bodies as merely the removal of the ovogenetic
nucleoplasm, on which depended the development of the specific
histological structure of the egg-cell. I must assume that the
phenomena of maturation in the parthenogenetic egg and in the sexual
egg are precisely identical, and that in both, the ovogenetic
nucleoplasm must in some way be removed before embryonic development
can begin.

Unfortunately the actual proof of this assumption is not so complete
as might be desired. In the first place, we are as yet uncertain
whether polar bodies are or are not expelled by parthenogenetic eggs;
for in no single instance has such expulsion been established beyond
doubt. It is true that this deficiency does not afford any support
to the explanation of Minot and Balfour, for in all cases in which
polar bodies have not been found in parthenogenetic eggs, these
structures are also absent from the eggs which require fertilization
in the same species. But although the expulsion of polar bodies in
parthenogenesis has not yet been proved to occur, we must assume it to
be nearly certain that the phenomena of maturation, whether connected
or unconnected with the expulsion of polar bodies, are the same in the
eggs which develop parthenogenetically and in those which are capable
of fertilization, in one and the same species. This conclusion depends,
above all, upon the phenomena of reproduction in bees, in which,
as a matter of fact, the same egg may be fertilized or may develop
parthenogenetically, as I shall have occasion to describe in greater
detail at a later period.

Hence when we see that the eggs of many animals are capable of
developing without fertilization, while in other animals such
development is impossible, the difference between the two kinds of eggs
must rest upon something more than the mode of transformation of the
nucleus of the germ-cell into the first segmentation nucleus. There
are, indeed, facts which distinctly point to the conclusion that the
difference is based upon quantitative and not qualitative relations.
A large number of insects are exceptionally reproduced by the
parthenogenetic method, _e. g._, in Lepidoptera. Such development
does not take place in all the eggs laid by an unfertilized female,
but only in part, and generally a small fraction of the whole, while
the rest die. But among the latter there are some which enter upon
embryonic development without being able to complete it, and the
stage at which development may cease also varies. It is also known
that the eggs of higher animals may pass through the first stages of
segmentation without having been fertilized. This was shown to be
the case in the egg of the frog by Leuckart, in that of the fowl by
Oellacher, and even in the egg of mammals by Hensen.

Hence in such cases it is not the impulse to development, but the power
to complete it, which is absent. We know that force is always bound up
with matter, and it seems to me that such instances are best explained
by the supposition that too small an amount of that form of matter
is present, which, by its controlling agency, effects the building
up of the embryo by the transformation of mere nutritive material.
This substance is the germ-plasm of the segmentation nucleus, and I
have assumed above that it is altered in the course of ontogeny by
changes which arise from within, so that when sufficient nourishment
is afforded by the cell-body, each succeeding stage necessarily
results from the preceding one. I believe that changes arise in the
constitution of the nucleoplasm at each cell-division which takes place
during the building up of the embryo, changes which either correspond
or differ in the two halves of each nucleus. If, for the present, we
neglect the minute amount of unchanged germ-plasm which is reserved
for the formation of the germ-cells, it is clear that a great many
different stages in the development of somatic nucleoplasm are thus
formed, which may be denominated as stages 1, 2, 3, 4, etc., up to
_n_. In each of these stages the cells differ more as development
proceeds, and as the number by which the stage is denominated becomes
higher. Thus, for instance, the two first segmentation spheres would
represent the first stage of somatic nucleoplasm, a stage which may
be considered as but slightly different in its molecular structure
from the nucleoplasm of the segmentation nucleus; the first four
segmentation spheres would represent the second stage; the succeeding
eight spheres the third, and so on. It is clear that at each successive
stage the molecular structure of the nucleoplasm must be further
removed from that of the germ-plasm, and that, at the same time, the
cells of each successive stage must also diverge more widely among
themselves in the molecular structure of their nucleoplasm. Early in
development each cell must possess its own peculiar nucleoplasm, for
the further course of development is peculiar to each cell. It is
only in the later stages that equivalent or nearly equivalent cells
are formed in large numbers, cells in which we must also suppose the
existence of equivalent nucleoplasm.

If we may assume that a certain amount of germ-plasm must be contained
in the segmentation nucleus in order to complete the whole process of
the ontogenetic differentiation of this substance; if we may further
assume that the quantity of germ-plasm in the segmentation nucleus
varies in different cases; then we should be able to understand why
one egg can only develop after fertilization, while another can
begin its development without fertilization, but cannot finish it,
and why a third is even able to complete its development. We should
also understand why one egg only passes through the first stages of
segmentation and is then arrested, while another reaches a few more
stages in advance, and a third develops so far that the embryo is
nearly completely formed. These differences would depend upon the
extent to which the germ-plasm, originally present in the egg, was
sufficient for the development of the latter; development will be
arrested as soon as the nucleoplasm is no longer capable of producing
the succeeding stage, and is thus unable to enter upon the following
nuclear division.

From a general point of view such a theory would explain many
difficulties, and it would render possible an explanation of the
phyletic origin of parthenogenesis, and an adequate understanding
of the strange and often apparently abrupt and arbitrary manner
of its occurrence. In my works on Daphnidae I have already laid
especial stress upon the proposition that parthenogenesis in insects
and Crustacea certainly cannot be an ancestral condition which has
been transmitted by heredity, but that it has been derived from a
sexual condition. In what other way can we explain the fact that
parthenogenesis is present in certain species or genera, but absent
in others closely allied to them; or the fact that males are entirely
wanting in species of which the females possess a complete apparatus
for fertilization? I will not repeat all the arguments with which I
attempted to support this conclusion. Such a conclusion may be almost
certainly accepted for the Daphnidae, because parthenogenesis does not
occur in their still living ancestors, the Phyllopods, and especially
the Estheridae. In Daphnidae the cause and object of the phyletic
development of parthenogenesis may be traced more clearly than in any
other group of animals. In Daphnidae we can accept the conclusion with
greater certainty than in all other groups, except perhaps the Aphidae,
that parthenogenesis is extremely advantageous to species in certain
conditions of life; and that it has only been adopted when, and as far
as, it has been beneficial; and further, that at least in this group
parthenogenesis became possible and was adopted in each species as soon
as it became useful. Such a result can be easily understood if it is
only the presence of more or less germ-plasm which decides whether an
egg is or is not capable of development without fertilization.

If we now examine the foundations of this hypothesis we shall find that
we may at once accept one of its assumptions, viz., that fluctuations
occur in the quantity of germ-plasm in the segmentation nucleus; for
there can never be absolute equality in any single part of different
individuals. As soon therefore as these fluctuations become so great
that parthenogenesis is produced, it may become, by the operation of
natural selection, the chief mode of reproduction of the species or
of certain generations of the species. In order to place this theory
upon a firm basis, we have simply to decide whether the quantity of
germ-plasm contained in the segmentation nucleus is the factor which
determines development; although for the present it will be sufficient
if we can render this view to some extent probable, and show that it is
not a contradiction of established facts.

At first sight this hypothesis seems to encounter serious difficulties.
It will be objected that neither the beginning nor the end of embryonic
development can possibly depend upon the quantity of nucleoplasm in the
segmentation nucleus, since the amount may be continually increased
by growth; for it is well known that during embryonic development
the nuclear substance increases with astonishing rapidity. By an
approximate calculation I found that in the egg of a Cynips the
quantity of nuclear substance present at the time when the blastoderm
was about to be formed, and when there were twenty-six nuclei, was even
then seven times as great as the quantity which had been contained
in the segmentation nucleus. How then can we imagine that embryonic
development would ever be arrested from want of nuclear substance, and
if such deficiency really acted as an arresting force, how then could
development begin at all? We might suppose that when germ-plasm is
present in sufficient quantity to start segmentation, it must also be
sufficient to complete the development; for it grows continuously, and
must presumably always possess a power equal to that which it possessed
at the beginning, and which was just sufficient to start the process of
segmentation. If at each ontogenetic stage the quantity of nucleoplasm
is just sufficient to produce the following stage, we might well
imagine that the whole ontogeny would necessarily be completed.

The flaw in this argument lies in the erroneous assumption that the
growth of nuclear substance is, when the quality of the nucleus and
the conditions of nutrition are equal, unlimited and uncontrolled. The
intensity of growth must depend upon the quantity of nuclear substance
with which growth and the phenomena of segmentation commenced. There
must be an optimum quantity of nucleoplasm with which the growth of
the nucleus proceeds most favourably and rapidly, and this optimum
will be represented in the normal size of the segmentation nucleus.
Such a size is just sufficient to produce, in a certain time and
under certain external conditions, the nuclear substance necessary
for the construction of the embryo, and to start the long series
of cell-divisions. When the segmentation nucleus is smaller, but
large enough to enter upon segmentation, the nuclei of the two first
embryonic cells will fall rather more below the normal size, because
the growth of the segmentation nucleus, during and after division will
be less rapid on account of its unusually small size. The succeeding
generations of nuclei will depart more and more from the normal size in
each respective stage, because they do not pass into a resting stage
during embryonic development, but divide again immediately after their
formation. Hence nuclear growth would become less vigorous as the
nuclei fell more and more below the optimum size, and at last a moment
would arrive when they would be unable to divide, or would be at least
unable to control the cell-body in such a manner as to lead to its
division.

The first event of importance for embryonic development is the
maturation of the egg, _i. e._, the transformation of the
nucleus of the germ-cell into a nuclear spindle and the removal of
the ovogenetic nucleoplasm by the separation of polar bodies, or by
some analogous process. There must be some cause for this separation,
and I have already tried to show that it may lie in the quantitative
relations which obtain between the two kinds of nucleoplasm contained
in the nucleus of the egg. I have suggested that the germ-plasm, at
first small in quantity, undergoes a gradual increase, so that it
can finally oppose the ovogenetic nucleoplasm. I will not further
elaborate this suggestion, for the ascertained facts are insufficient
for the purpose. But the appearances witnessed in nuclear division
indicate that there are opposing forces, and that such a contest is
the motive cause of division; and Roux may be right in referring the
opposition to electrical forces. However this may be, it is perfectly
certain that the development of this opposition is based upon internal
conditions arising during growth in the nucleus itself. The quantity
of nuclear thread cannot by itself determine whether the nucleus can
or cannot enter upon division; if so, it would be impossible for two
divisions to follow each other in rapid succession, as is actually
the case in the separation of the two polar bodies, and also in their
subsequent division. In addition to the effects of quantity, the
internal conditions of the nucleus must also play an important part in
these phenomena. Quantity alone does not necessarily produce nuclear
division, or the nucleus of the egg would divide long before maturation
is complete, for it contains much more nucleoplasm than the female
pronucleus, which remains in the egg after the expulsion of the polar
bodies, and which is in most cases capable of further division. But
the fact that segmentation begins immediately after the conjugation of
male and female pronuclei, also shows that quantity is an essential
requisite. The effect of fertilization has been represented as
analogous to that of the spark which kindles the gunpowder. In the
latter case an explosion ensues, in the former segmentation begins.
Even now many authorities are inclined to refer the polar repulsion
manifested in the nuclear division which immediately follows
fertilization, to the antagonism between male and female elements. But,
according to the important discoveries of Flemming and van Beneden, the
polar repulsion in each nuclear division is not based on the antagonism
between male and female loops, but depends upon the antagonism and
mutual repulsion between the two halves of the same loop. The loops of
the father and those of the mother remain together and divide together
throughout the whole ontogeny.

What can be the explanation of the fact that nuclear division follows
immediately after fertilization, but that without fertilization it
does not occur in most cases? There is only one possible explanation,
viz., the fact that the quantity of the nucleus has been suddenly
doubled, as the result of conjugation. The difference between the male
and female pronuclei cannot serve as an explanation, even though the
nature of this difference is entirely unknown, because polar repulsion
is not developed between the male and female halves of the nucleus, but
within each male and each female half. We are thus forced to conclude
that increase in the quantity of the nucleus affords an impulse for
division, the disposition towards it being already present. It seems
to me that this view does not encounter any theoretical difficulties,
and that it is an entirely feasible hypothesis to suppose that, besides
the internal conditions of the nucleus, its quantitative relation to
the cell-body must be taken into especial account. It is imaginable, or
perhaps even probable, that the nucleus enters upon division as soon
as its idioplasm has attained a certain strength, quite apart from the
supposition that certain internal conditions are necessary for this
end. As above stated, such conditions may be present, but division may
not occur because the right quantitative relation between nucleus and
cell-body, or between the different kinds of nuclear idioplasm has not
been established. I imagine that such a quantitative deficiency exists
in an egg which, after the expulsion of the ovogenetic nucleoplasm
in the polar bodies, requires fertilization in order to begin
segmentation. The fact that the polar bodies were expelled proves that
the quantity of the nucleus was sufficient to cause division, while
afterwards it was no longer sufficient to produce such a result.

This suggestion will be made still clearer by an example. In _Ascaris
megalocephala_ the nuclear substance of the female pronucleus
forms two loops, and the male pronucleus does the same; hence the
segmentation nucleus contains four loops, and this is also the case
with the first segmentation spheres. If we suppose that in embryonic
development the first nuclear division requires such an amount of
nuclear substance as is necessary for the formation of four loops,--it
follows that an egg, which can only form two or three loops from its
nuclear reticulum, would not be able to develop parthenogenetically,
and that not even the first division would take place. If we further
suppose that, while four loops are sufficient to start nuclear
division, these loops must be of a certain size and quantity in order
to complete the whole ontogeny (in a certain species), it follows
that eggs possessing a reticulum which contains barely enough nuclear
substance to divide into four segments, would be able to produce
the first division and perhaps also the second and third, or some
later division, but that at a certain point during ontogeny, the
nuclear substance would become insufficient, and development would be
arrested. This will occur in eggs which enter upon development without
fertilization, but are arrested before its completion. One might
compare this retardation leading to the final arrest of development,
to a railway train which is intended to meet a number of other trains
at various junctions, and which can only travel slowly because of some
defect in the engine. It will be a little behind time at the first
junction, but it may just catch the train, and it may also catch the
second or even the third; but it will be later at each successive
junction, and will finally arrive too late for a certain train; and
after that it will miss all the trains at the remaining junctions. The
nuclear substance grows continuously during development, but the rate
at which it increases depends upon the nutritive conditions together
with its initial quantity. The nutritive changes during the development
of an egg depend upon the quantity of the cell-body which was present
at the outset, and which cannot be increased. If the quantity of
the nuclear substance is rather too small at the beginning, it will
become more and more insufficient in succeeding stages, as its growth
becomes less vigorous, and differs more from the standard it would
have reached if the original quantity had been normal. Consequently it
will gradually fall more and more short of the normal quantity, like
the train which arrives later and later at each successive junction,
because its engine, although with the full pressure of steam, is unable
to attain the normal speed.

It will be objected that four loops cannot be necessary for nuclear
division in _Ascaris_, since such division takes place in the
formation of the polar bodies, resulting in the appearance of the
female pronucleus with only two loops. But this fact only shows that
the quantity of nuclear substance necessary for the formation of four
loops is not necessary for all nuclear divisions; it does not disprove
the assumption that such a quantity is required for the division of
the segmentation nucleus. In addition to these considerations we must
not leave the substance of the cell-body altogether out of account,
for, although it is not the bearer of the tendencies of heredity, it
must be necessary for every change undergone by the nucleus, and it
surely also possesses the power of influencing changes to a large
extent. There must be some reason for the fact that in all animal eggs
with which we are acquainted, the nucleus moves to the surface of the
egg at the time of maturation, and there passes through its well known
transformation. It is obvious that it is there subjected to different
influences from those which would have acted upon it in the center of
the cell-body, and it is clear that such an unequal cell-division as
takes place in the separation of the polar bodies could not occur if
the nucleus remained in the center of the egg.

This explanation of the necessity for fertilization does not exclude
the possibility that, under certain circumstances, the substance of the
egg-nucleus may be larger, so that it is capable of forming four loops.
Eggs which thus possess sufficient nucleoplasm, viz., germ-plasm, for
the formation of the requisite four loops of normal size (namely, of
the size which would have been produced by fertilization), can and must
develop by the parthenogenetic method.

Of course the assumption that four loops must be formed has only
been made for the sake of illustration. We do not yet know whether
there are always exactly four loops in the segmentation nucleus. I
may add that, although the details by which these considerations are
illustrated are based on arbitrary assumptions, the fundamental view
that the development of the egg depends, _ceteris paribus_, upon
the quantity of nuclear substance, is certainly right, and follows as
a necessary conclusion from the ascertained facts. It is not unlikely
that such a view may receive direct proof in the results of future
investigations. Such proof might, for instance, be forthcoming if we
were to ascertain, in the same species, the number of loops present
in the segmentation nucleus of fertilization, as compared with those
present in the segmentation nucleus of parthenogenesis.

The reproductive process in bees will perhaps be used as an argument
against my theory. In these insects the same egg will develop into a
female or male individual, according as fertilization has or has not
taken place, respectively. Hence one and the same egg is capable of
fertilization, and also of parthenogenetic development, if it does
not receive a spermatozoon. It is in the power of the queen-bee to
produce male or female individuals: by an act of will she decides
whether the egg she is laying is to be fertilized or unfertilized.
She “knows beforehand” whether an egg will develop into a male or a
female animal, and deposits the latter kind in the cells of queens and
workers, the former in the cells of drones. It has been shown by the
discoveries of Leuckart and von Siebold that all the eggs are capable
of developing into male individuals, and that they are only transformed
into “female eggs” by fertilization. This fact seems to be incompatible
with my theory as to the cause of parthenogenesis, for if the same
egg, possessing exactly the same contents, and above all the same
segmentation nucleus, may develop sexually or parthenogenetically, it
appears that the power of parthenogenetic development must depend on
some factor other than the quantity of germ-plasm.

Although this appears to be the case, I believe that my theory
encounters no real difficulty. I have no doubt whatever that the same
egg may develop with or without fertilization. From a careful study of
the numerous excellent investigations upon this point which have been
conducted in a particularly striking manner by Bessels (in addition
to the observers quoted above), I have come to the conclusion that
the fact is absolutely certain. It must be candidly admitted that
the same egg will develop into a drone when not fertilized, or into
a worker or queen when fertilized. One of Bessels’ experiments is
sufficient to prove this assertion. He cut off the wings of a young
queen and thus rendered her incapable of taking “the nuptial flight.”
He then observed that all the eggs which she laid developed into
male individuals. This experiment was made in order to prove that
drones are produced by unfertilized eggs; but it also proves that the
assertion mentioned above is correct, for the eggs which ripen first
and are therefore first laid, would have been fertilized had the queen
been impregnated. The supposition that, at certain times, the queen
produces eggs requiring fertilization, while at other times her eggs
develop parthenogenetically, is quite excluded by this experiment; for
it follows from it that the eggs must all be of precisely the same
kind, and that there is no difference between the eggs which require
fertilization and those which do not.

But does it therefore follow that the quantity of germ-plasm in
the segmentation nucleus is not the factor which determines the
beginning of embryonic development? I believe not. It can be very
well imagined that the nucleus of the egg, having expelled the
ovogenetic nucleoplasm, may be increased to the size requisite for the
segmentation nucleus in one of two ways: either by conjugation with
a sperm-nucleus, or by simply growing to double its size. There is
nothing improbable in this latter assumption, and one is even inclined
to inquire why such growth does not take place in all unfertilized
eggs. The true answer to this question must be that nature pursues
the sexual method of reproduction, and that the only way in which the
general occurrence of parthenogenesis could be prevented was by the
production of eggs which remained sterile unless they were fertilized.
This was effected by a loss of the capability of growth on the part of
the egg-nucleus after it had expelled the ovogenetic nucleoplasm.

The case of the bee proves in a very striking manner that the
difference between eggs which require fertilization, and those which
do not, is not produced until after the maturation of the egg and the
removal of the ovogenetic nucleoplasm. The increase in the quantity of
the germ-plasm cannot have taken place at any earlier period, or else
the nucleus of the egg would always start embryonic development by
itself, and the egg would probably be incapable of fertilization. For
the relation between egg-nucleus and sperm-nucleus is obviously based
upon the fact that each of them is insufficient by itself, and requires
completion. If such completion had taken place at an early stage the
egg-nucleus would either cease to exercise any attractive force upon
the sperm-nucleus, or else conjugation would be effected, as in Fol’s
interesting experiments upon fertilization by many spermatozoa; and,
as in these experiments, malformation of the embryo would result. In
Daphnidae I believe I have shown that the summer eggs are not only
developed parthenogenetically, but also that they are never fertilized;
and the explanation of this incapacity for fertilization may perhaps be
found in the fact that their segmentation nucleus is already formed.

We may therefore conclude that, in bees, the nucleus of the egg, formed
during maturation, may either conjugate with the sperm-nucleus, or
else if no spermatozoon reaches it the egg may, under the stimulus of
internal causes, grow to double its size, thus attaining the dimensions
of the segmentation nucleus. For our present purpose we may leave
out of consideration the fact that in the latter case the individual
produced is a male, and in the former case a female.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 37: From _Essays upon Heredity and Kindred Biological
Problems_, Vol. I (1889).]




                                 XXXV

                          SIR NORMAN LOCKYER

                               1836-1920


 _Sir Joseph Norman Lockyer, born at Rugby, England, May 17, 1836,
 entered the War Office in 1857. Through his own exertions he educated
 himself in science and was one of the first to suggest the hypothesis
 that the earth and other spheres were the result of the aggregation
 of meteorites. He was also the first to apply the spectroscope to
 the corona of the sun, revealing the chemical composition of solar
 prominences as chiefly hydrogen, calcium, and helium. He died at
 Sidmouth, Devonshire, August 16, 1920._


                    THE CHEMISTRY OF THE STARS[38]

The importance of practical work, the educational value of the seeking
after truth by experiment and observation on the part of even young
students, are now generally recognized. That battle has been fought
and won. But there is a tendency in the official direction of seats of
learning to consider what is known to be useful, because it is used,
in the first place. The fact that the unknown, that is, the unstudied,
is the mine from which all scientific knowledge with its million
applications has been won is too often forgotten.

Bacon, who was the first to point out the importance of experiment in
the physical sciences, and who predicted the applications to which I
have referred, warns us that “_lucifera experimenta non fructifera
quaerenda_”; and surely we should highly prize those results which
enlarge the domain of human thought and help us to understand the
mechanism of the wonderful universe in which our lot is cast, as well
as those which add to the comfort and the convenience of our lives.

It would be also easy to show by many instances how researches,
considered ideally useless at the time they were made, have been the
origin of the most tremendous applications. One instance suffices.
Faraday’s trifling with wires and magnets has already landed us in one
of the greatest revolutions which civilization has witnessed; and where
the triumphs of electrical science will stop no man can say.

This is a case in which the useless has been rapidly sublimed into
utility so far as our material wants are concerned.

I propose to bring to your notice another “useless” observation
suggesting a line of inquiry which I believe sooner or later is
destined profoundly to influence human thought along many lines.

Fraunhofer at the beginning of this century examined sunlight and
starlight through a prism. He found that the light received from the
sun differed from that of the stars. So useless did his work appear
that we had to wait for half a century till any considerable advance
was made. It was found at last that the strange “lines” seen and named
by Fraunhofer were precious indications of the chemical substances
present in worlds immeasurably remote. We had, after half a century’s
neglect, the foundation of solar and stellar chemistry, an advance in
knowledge equaling any other in its importance.

In dealing with my subject I shall first refer to the work which
has been done in more recent years with regard to this chemical
conditioning of the atmospheres of stars, and afterwards very briefly
show how this work carries us into still other new and wider fields of
thought.

The first important matter which lies on the surface of such a general
inquiry as this is that if we deal with the chemical elements as judged
by the lines in their spectra we know for certain of the existence of
oxygen, of nitrogen, of argon, representing one class of gases, in no
celestial body whatever; whereas, representing other gases, we have a
tremendous demonstration of the existence of all the known lines of
hydrogen and helium.

We see, then, that the celestial sorting out of gases is quite
different from the terrestrial one.

Taking the substances classed by the chemist as non-metals, we find
carbon and silicium--I prefer, on account of its stellar behavior, to
call it silicium, though it is old fashioned--present in celestial
phenomena. We have evidence of this in the fact that we have a
considerable development of carbon in some stars and an indication
of silicium in others. But these are the only non-metals observed.
Now, with regard to the metallic substances which we find, we deal
chiefly with calcium, strontium, iron, and magnesium. Others are not
absolutely absent, but their percentage quantity is so small that they
are negligible in a general statement.

Now do these chemical elements exist indiscriminately in all the
celestial bodies, so that practically, from a chemical point of view,
the bodies appear to us of similar chemical constitution? No; it is not
so.

From the spectra of those stars which resemble the sun, in that they
consist of an interior nucleus surrounded by an atmosphere which
absorbs the light of the nucleus, and which, therefore, we study by
means of this absorption, it is to be gathered that the atmospheres
of some stars are chiefly gaseous--i. e., consisting of elements we
recognize as gases here--of others chiefly metallic, of others again
mainly composed of carbon or compounds of carbon.

Here, then, we have spectroscopically revealed the fact that there is
considerable variation in the chemical constituents which build up the
stellar atmospheres.

This, though a general, is still an isolated statement. Can we connect
it with another? One of the laws formulated by Kirchhoff in the infancy
of spectroscopic inquiry has to do with the kind of radiation given
out by bodies at different temperatures. A poker placed in a fire
first becomes red, and, as it gets hotter, white hot. Examined in a
spectroscope, we find that the red condition comes from the absence of
blue light; that the white condition comes from the gradual addition of
blue as the temperature increases.

The law affirms that the hotter a mass of matter is the farther its
spectrum extends into the ultraviolet.

Hence the hotter a star is the farther does its complete or continuous
spectrum lengthen out toward the ultraviolet and the less it is
absorbed by cooler vapors in its atmosphere.

Now, to deal with three of the main groups of stars, we find the
following very general result:

Gaseous stars        Longest spectrum.
Metallic stars       Medium spectrum.
Carbon stars         Shortest spectrum.

We have now associated two different series of phenomena, and we are
enabled to make the following statement:

Gaseous stars        Highest temperature.
Metallic stars       Medium temperature.
Carbon stars         Lowest temperature.

Hence the differences in apparent chemical constitutions are associated
with differences of temperature.

Can we associate with the two to which I have already called attention
still a third class of facts? Laboratory work enables us to do this.
When I began my inquiries the idea was, one gas or vapor, one spectrum.
We now know that this is not true; the systems of bright lines given
out by radiating substances change with the temperature.

We can get the spectrum of a well known compound substance--say
carbonic oxide; it is one special to the compound; we increase the
temperature so as to break up the compound, and we then get the spectra
of its constituents, carbon and oxygen.

But the important thing in the present connection is that the spectra
of the chemical elements behave exactly in the same way as the spectra
of known compounds do when we employ temperatures far higher than those
which break up the compounds; and indeed in some cases the changes
are more marked. For brevity I will take for purposes of illustration
three substances, and deal with one increase of temperature only, a
considerable one and obtainable by rendering a substance incandescent,
first by a direct current of electricity, as happens in the so-called
“arc lamps” employed in electric lighting, and next by the employment
of a powerful induction coil and battery of Leyden jars. In laboratory
parlance we pass thus from the arc to the jar-spark. In the case of
magnesium, iron, and calcium, the changes observed on passing from
the temperature of the arc to that of the spark have been minutely
observed. In each, new lines are added or old ones are intensified at
the higher temperature. Such lines have been termed “enhanced lines.”

These enhanced lines are not seen alone; outside the region of high
temperature in which they are produced, the cooling vapors give us the
cool lines. Still we can conceive the enhanced lines to be seen alone
at the highest temperature in a space sufficiently shielded from the
action of all lower temperatures, but such a shielding is beyond our
laboratory expedients.

In watching the appearance of these special enhanced lines in stellar
spectra we have a third series of phenomena available, and we find that
the results are absolutely in harmony with what has gone before. Thus:

Gaseous stars   Highest temperature  Strong helium and faint
                                       enhanced lines.

Metallic stars                       Feeble helium and strong
                Medium temperature     enhanced lines.

Carbon stars                         No helium and strong arc lines.
                Lowest temperature   Faint arc lines.

It is clear now, not only that the spectral changes in stars are
associated with, or produced by, changes of temperature, but that
the study of the enhanced spark and the arc lines lands us in the
possibility of a rigorous stellar thermometry, such lines being more
easy to observe than the relative lengths of spectrum.

Accepting this, we can take a long stride forward and, by carefully
studying the chemical revelations of the spectrum, classify the stars
along a line of temperature. But which line? Were all the stars in
popular phraseology created hot? If so, we should simply deal with
the running down of temperature, and because all the hottest stars
are chemically alike, all cooler stars would be alike. But there are
two very distinct groups of coolest stars; and since there are two
different kinds of coolest stars, and only one kind of hottest stars,
it cannot be merely a question either of a running up or a running down
of temperature.

Many years of very detailed inquiry have convinced me that all stars
save the hottest must be sorted out into two series--those getting
hotter and those, like our sun, getting cooler, and that the hottest
stage in the history of a star is reached near the middle of its life.

The method of inquiry adopted has been to compare large-scale
photographs of the spectra of the different stars taken by my
assistants at South Kensington; the complete harmony of the results
obtained along various lines of other work carries conviction with it.

We find ourselves here in the presence of minute details exhibiting the
workings of a chemical law, associated distinctly with temperature;
and more than this, we are also in the presence of high temperature
furnaces, entirely shielded by their vastness from the presence of
those distracting phenomena which we are never free from in the most
perfect conditions of experiment we can get here.

What, then, is the chemical law? It is this: In the very hottest
stars we deal with the gases hydrogen, helium, and doubtless others
still unknown, almost exclusively. At the next lowest temperatures we
find these gases being replaced by metals in the state in which they
are observed in our laboratories when the most powerful jar-spark is
employed. At a lower temperature still the gases almost disappear
entirely, and the metals exist in the state produced by the electric
arc. Certain typical stars showing these chemical changes may be
arranged as follows:

This, then, is the result of our first inquiry into the existence of
the various chemical elements in the atmospheres of stars generally.
We get a great diversity, and we know that this diversity accompanies
changes of temperature. We have also found that the sun, which we
independently know to be a cooling star, and Arcturus are identical
chemically.

We have now dealt with the presence of the various chemical elements
generally in the atmospheres of stars. The next point we have to
consider is, whether the absorption which the spectrum indicates for
us takes place from top to bottom of the atmosphere or only in certain
levels.

In many of these stars the atmosphere may be millions of miles high. In
each the chemical substances in the hottest and coldest portions may be
vastly different. The region, therefore, in which this absorption takes
place, which spectroscopically enables us to discriminate star from
star, must be accurately known before we can obtain the greatest amount
of information from our inquiries.

Our next duty then, clearly, is to study the sun--a star so near us
that we can examine the different parts of its atmosphere, which we
cannot do in the case of the more distant stars. By doing this we
may secure facts which will enable us to ascertain in what parts of
the atmosphere the absorption takes place which produces the various
phenomena on which the chemical classification has been based.

It is obvious that the general spectrum of the sun, like that of stars
generally, is built up of all the absorptions which can make themselves
felt in every layer of its atmosphere from bottom to top; that is, from
the photosphere to the outermost part of the corona. Let me remind you
that this spectrum is changeless from year to year.

Now, sun-spots are disturbances produced in the photosphere; and the
chromosphere, with its disturbances, called prominences, lies directly
above it. Here, then, we are dealing with the lowest part of the sun’s
atmosphere. We find first of all that, in opposition to the changeless
general spectrum, great changes occur with the sun-spot period, both in
the spots and chromosphere.

The spot spectrum is indicated, as was found in 1866, by the widening
of certain lines; the chromospheric spectrum, as was found in 1868, by
the appearance at the sun’s limb of certain bright lines. In both cases
the lines affected, seen at any one time, are relatively few in number.

In the spot spectrum, at a sun-spot minimum, we find iron lines chiefly
affected; at a maximum they are chiefly of unknown or unfamiliar
origin. At the present moment the affected lines are those recorded
in the spectra of vanadium and scandium, with others never seen in
a laboratory. That we are here far away from terrestrial chemical
conditions is evidenced by the fact that there is not a gram of
scandium available for laboratory use in the world at the present time.

Then we have the spectrum of the prominences and the chromosphere. That
spectrum we are enabled to observe every day when the sun shines, as
conveniently as we can observe that of sun spots. The chromosphere is
full of marvels. At first, when our knowledge of spectra was very much
more restricted than now, almost all the lines observed were unknown.
In 1868 I saw a line in the yellow, which I found behaved very much
like hydrogen, though I could prove that it was not due to hydrogen;
for laboratory use the substance which gave rise to it I called helium.
Next year I saw a line in the green at 1474 of Kirchhoff’s scale. That
was an unknown line, but in some subsequent researches I traced it to
iron. From that day to this we have observed a large number of lines.
They have gradually been dragged out from the region of the unknown,
and many are now recognized as enhanced lines, to which I have already
called attention as appearing in the spectra of metals at a very high
temperature.

But useful as the method of observing the chromosphere without an
eclipse, which enables us

    “... to feel from world to world,”

as Tennyson has put it, has proved, we want an eclipse to see it face
to face.

A tremendous flood of light has been thrown upon it by the use of large
instruments constructed on a plan devised by Respighi and myself in
1871. These give us an image of the chromosphere painted in each one
of its radiations, so that the exact locus of each chemical layer is
revealed. One of the instruments employed during the Indian eclipse of
this year is that used in photographing the spectra of stars, so that
it is now easy to place photographs of the spectra of the chromosphere
obtained during a total eclipse and of the various stars side by side.

I have already pointed out that the chemical classification indicated
that the stars next above the sun in temperature are represented by γ
Cygni and Procyon, one on the ascending, the other on the descending
branch of the temperature curve.

Studying the spectra photographed during the eclipse of this year we
see that practically the lower part of the sun’s atmosphere, if present
by itself, would give us the lines which specialize the spectra of γ
Cygni or Procyon.

I recognize in this result a veritable Rosetta stone, which will enable
us to read the celestial hieroglyphics presented to us in stellar
spectra, and help us to study the spectra and to get at results much
more distinctly and certainly than ever before.

One of the most important conclusions we draw from the Indian eclipse
is that, for some reason or other, the lowest, hottest part of the
sun’s atmosphere does not write its record among the lines which build
up the general spectrum so effectively as does a higher one.

There was another point especially important on which we hoped for
information, and that was this: Up to the employment of the prismatic
camera insufficient attention had been directed to the fact that in
observations made by an ordinary spectroscope no true measure of the
height to which the vapors or gases extended above the sun could be
obtained; early observations, in fact, showed the existence of glare
between the observer and the dark moon; hence it must exist between us
and the sun’s surroundings.

The prismatic camera gets rid of the effects of this glare, and its
results indicate that the effective absorbing layer--that, namely,
which gives rise to the Fraunhofer lines--is much more restricted in
thickness than was to be gathered from the early observations.

We are justified in extending these general conclusions to all the
stars that shine in the heavens.

So much, then, in brief, for solar teachings in relation to the record
of the absorption of the lower parts of stellar atmospheres.

Let us next turn to the higher portions of the solar surroundings, to
see if we can get any effective help from them.

In this matter we are dependent absolutely upon eclipses, and I shall
fulfill my task very badly if I do not show you that the phenomena
then observable when the so-called corona is visible, full of awe and
grandeur to all, are also full of precious teaching to the student
of science. This also varies like the spots and prominences with the
sun-spot period.

It happened that I was the only person that saw both the eclipse of
1871 at the maximum of the sun-spot period and that of 1878 at minimum;
the corona of 1871 was as distinct from the corona of 1878 as anything
could be. In 1871 we got nothing but bright lines, indicating the
presence of gases; namely, hydrogen and another, since provisionally
called coronium. In 1878 we got no bright lines at all, so I stated
that probably the changes in the chemistry and appearance of the corona
would be found to be dependent upon the sun-spot period, and recent
work has borne out that suggestion.

I have now specially to refer to the corona as observed and
photographed this year in India by means of the prismatic camera,
remarking that an important point in the use of the prismatic camera is
that it enables us to separate the spectrum of the corona from that of
the prominences.

One of the chief results obtained is the determination of the position
of several lines of probably more than one new gas, which, so far, have
not been recognized as existing on the earth.

Like the lowest hottest layer, for some reason or other, this upper
layer does not write its record among the lines which build up the
general spectrum.


GENERAL RESULTS REGARDING THE LOCUS OF ABSORPTION IN STELLAR ATMOSPHERES

We learn from the sun, then, that the absorption which defines the
spectrum of a star is the absorption of a middle region, one shielded
both from the highest temperature of the lowest reaches of the
atmosphere, where most tremendous changes are continually going on and
the external region where the temperature must be low, and where the
metallic vapors must condense.

If this is true for the sun it must be equally true for Arcturus,
which exactly resembles it. I go further than this, and say that in
the presence of such definite results as those I have brought before
you it is not philosophical to assume that the absorption may take
place at the bottom of the atmosphere of one star or at the top of the
atmosphere of another. The _onus probandi_ rests upon those who
hold such views.

So far I have only dealt in detail with the hotter stars, but I have
pointed out that we have two distinct kinds of coolest ones, the
evidence of their much lower temperature being the shortness of their
spectra. In one of these groups we deal with absorption alone, as in
those already considered; we find an important break in the phenomena
observed; helium, hydrogen, and metals have practically disappeared,
and we deal with carbon absorption alone.

But the other group of coolest stars presents us with quite new
phenomena. We no longer deal with absorption alone, but accompanying
it we have radiation, so that the spectra contain both dark lines and
bright ones. Now, since such spectra are visible in the case of new
stars, the ephemera of the skies, which may be said to exist only for
an instant relatively, and when the disturbance which gives rise to
their sudden appearance has ceased, we find their places occupied by
nebulæ, we cannot be dealing here with stars like the sun, which has
already taken some millions of years to slowly cool, and requires more
millions to complete the process into invisibility.

The bright lines seen in the large number of permanent stars which
resemble these fleeting ones--new stars, as they are called--are those
discerned in the once mysterious nebulæ which, so far from being stars,
were supposed not many years ago to represent a special order of
created things.

Now the nebulæ differ from stars generally in the fact that in their
spectra we have practically to deal with radiation alone; we study them
by their bright lines; the conditions which produce the absorption by
which we study the chemistry of the hottest stars are absent.


                          A NEW VIEW OF STARS

Here, then, we are driven to the perfectly new idea that some of the
cooler bodies in the heavens, the temperature of which is increasing
and which appear to us as stars, are really disturbed nebulæ.

What, then, is the chemistry of the nebulæ? It is mainly gaseous;
the lines of helium and hydrogen and the flutings of carbon, already
studied by their absorption in the groups of stars to which I have
already referred, are present as bright ones.

The presence of the lines of the metals iron, calcium, and probably
magnesium, shows us that we are not dealing with gases merely.

Of the enhanced metallic lines there are none; only the low temperature
lines are present, so far as we yet know. The temperature, then, is
low, and lowest of all in those nebulæ where carbon flutings are seen
almost alone.


                         A NEW VIEW OF NEBULÆ

Passing over the old views, among them one that the nebulæ were holes
in something dark which enabled us to see something bright beyond, and
another that they were composed of a fiery fluid, I may say that not
long ago, they were supposed to be masses of gases only, existing at a
very high temperature.

Now, since gases may glow at a low temperature as well as at a high
one, the temperature evidence must depend upon the presence of cool
metallic lines and the absence of the enhanced ones.

The nebulæ, then, are relatively cool collections of some of the
permanent gases and of some cool metallic vapors, and both gases and
metals are precisely those I have referred to as writing their records
most visibly in stellar atmosphere.

Now, can we get more information concerning this association of certain
gases and metals? In laboratory work it is abundantly recognized that
all meteorites (and many minerals) when slightly heated give out
permanent gases, and under certain conditions the spectrum of the
nebulæ may in this way be closely approximated to. I have not time to
labor this point, but I may say that a discussion of all the available
observations to my mind demonstrates the truth of the suggestion, made
many years ago by Professor Tait before any spectroscopic facts were
available, that the nebulæ are masses of meteorites rendered hot by
collisions.

Surely human knowledge is all the richer for this indication of the
connection between the nebulæ, hitherto the most mysterious bodies in
the skies, and the “stones that fall from heaven.”


                          CELESTIAL EVOLUTION

But this is, after all, only a stepping stone, important though it be.
It leads us to a vast generalization. If the nebulæ are thus composed,
they are bound to condense to centers, however vast their initial
proportions, however irregular the first distribution of the cosmic
clouds which compose them. Each pair of meteorites in collision puts us
in mental possession of what the final stage must be. We begin with a
feeble absorption of metallic vapors round each meteorite in collision;
the space between the meteorites is filled with the permanent gases
driven out farther afield and having no power to condense. Hence
dark metallic and bright gas lines. As time goes on the former must
predominate, for the whole swarm of meteorites will then form a gaseous
sphere with a strongly heated center, the light of which will be
absorbed by the exterior vapor.

The temperature order of the group of stars with bright lines as well
as dark ones in their spectra has been traced, and typical stars
indicating the chemical changes have been as carefully studied as those
in which absorption phenomena are visible alone, so that now there are
no breaks in the line connecting the nebulæ with the stars on the verge
of extinction.

Here we are brought to another tremendous outcome--that of the
evolution of all cosmical bodies from meteorites, the various stages
recorded by the spectra being brought about by the various conditions
which follow from the conditions.

These are, shortly, that at first collisions produce luminosity among
the colliding particles of the swarm, and the permanent gases are given
off and fill the interspaces. As condensation goes on, the temperature
at the center of condensation always increasing, all the meteorites
in time are driven into a state of gas. The meteoritic bombardment
practically now ceases for lack of material, and the future history
of the mass of gas is that of a cooling body, the violent motions in
the atmosphere while condensation was going on now being replaced by a
relative calm.

The absorption phenomena in stellar spectra are not identical at
the same mean temperature on the ascending and descending sides of
the curve, on account of the tremendous difference in the physical
conditions.

In a condensing swarm, the center of which is undergoing meteoritic
bombardment from all sides, there cannot be the equivalent of the
solar chromosphere; the whole mass is made up of heterogeneous vapor
at different temperatures and moving with different velocities in
different regions.

In a condensed swarm, of which we can take the sun as a type, all
action produced from without has practically ceased; we get relatively
a quiet atmosphere and an orderly assortment of the vapors from top to
bottom, disturbed only by the fall of condensed metallic vapors. But
still, on the view that the differences in the spectra of the heavenly
bodies chiefly represent differences in degree of condensation and
temperature, there can be _au fond_, no great chemical difference
between bodies of increasing and bodies of decreasing temperature.
Hence we find at equal mean temperatures on opposite sides of the
temperature curve this chemical similarity of the absorbing vapors
proved by many points of resemblance in the spectra, especially the
identical behavior of the enhanced metallic and cleveite lines.


                        CELESTIAL DISSOCIATION

The time you were good enough to put at my disposal is now exhausted,
but I cannot conclude without stating that I have not yet exhausted
all the conceptions of a high order to which Fraunhofer’s apparently
useless observation has led us.

The work which to my mind has demonstrated the evolution of the cosmos
as we know it from swarms of meteorites, has also suggested a chemical
evolution equally majestic in its simplicity.

A quarter of a century ago I pointed out that all the facts then
available suggested the hypothesis that in the atmospheres of the sun
and stars various degrees of “celestial dissociation” were at work,
a “dissociation” which prevented the coming together of the finest
particles of matter which at the temperature of the earth and at all
artificial temperature yet attained here compose the metals, the
metalloids and compounds.

On this hypothesis the so-called atoms of the chemist represent not the
origins of things, but only early stages of the evolutionary process.

At the present time we have tens of thousands of facts which were not
available twenty-five years ago. All these go to the support of the
hypothesis, and among them I must indicate the results obtained at the
last eclipse, dealing with the atmosphere of the sun in relation to
that of the various stars of higher temperature to which I called your
attention. In this way we can easily explain the enhanced lines of iron
existing practically alone in Alpha Cygni. I have yet to learn any
other explanation.

I have nothing to take back, either from what I then said or what I
have said since on this subject, and although the view is not yet
accepted, I am glad to know that many other lines of work which are now
being prosecuted tend to favor it.

I have no hesitation in expressing my conviction that in a not distant
future the inorganic evolution to which we have been finally led by
following up Fraunhofer’s useless experiment will take its natural
place side by side with that organic evolution, the demonstration of
which has been one of the glories of the nineteenth century.

And finally now comes the moral of my address. If I have helped to show
that observations having no immediate practical bearing may yet help
on the thought of mankind, and that this is a thing worth the doing,
let me express a hope that such work shall find no small place in the
future University of Birmingham.


FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 38: From an address delivered at the University of Birmingham
(1900).]




                                 XXXVI

                              ROBERT KOCH

                               1843-1910


 _Robert Koch, born at Klausthal, Hanover, Germany, December 11,
 1843, graduated from Göttingen in 1866. After a short period as
 assistant surgeon in the General Hospital in Hamburg, he practised
 medicine at Langenhagen, Kackwitz, and Wollstein from 1872 to 1880,
 during which time he began his researches in bacteriology. By 1878 he
 had placed bacteriology on a scientific basis. In 1880 he was called
 to Berlin as chief of the Sanitary Institute, where he continued his
 studies of tuberculosis and cholera. After inventing new microscopical
 appliances and a new technique, in 1882 he stated his discovery of
 the tubercle bacillus. In 1883, after publishing a method for the
 prevention of anthrax by inoculation, he was sent by his government
 to Egypt and India to investigate cholera. During that work he
 discovered the cholera bacillus. In 1884 he returned to Germany and
 in the following year went to France as cholera commissioner. In 1888
 he published a paper on the prophylaxis of infectious diseases in the
 army. In later years he investigated the bubonic plague, malaria, and
 sleeping-sickness. He died at Baden-Baden, May 28, 1910._


                        THEORY OF BACTERIA[39]

I am well aware that the investigations above described are very
imperfect. It was necessary, in order to have time for those parts
of the investigation which seemed the most important and essential,
to omit the examination of many organs, such as the brain, heart,
retina, etc., which ought not to pass unnoticed in researches on
infective diseases. For the same reason no record was kept of the
temperature, although this would undoubtedly have yielded most
interesting results. I have intentionally refrained from entering into
details of morbid anatomy, as only the etiology interested me, and as
I did not feel qualified to undertake a study of the morbid anatomy of
traumatic infective diseases. I must therefore leave this part of the
investigation to those who are better able to undertake it.

Nevertheless I consider that the results of my researches are
sufficiently definite to enable me to deduce from them some well
founded conclusions.

In this summary I shall, however, confine myself to the most obvious
conclusions. It has indeed of late become too common to draw the most
sweeping conclusions as to infective diseases in general from the
most unimportant observations on bacteria. I shall not follow this
custom, although the material at my command would furnish rich food
for meditation. For the longer I study infective diseases the more am
I convinced that generalisations of new facts are here a mistake, and
that every individual infective disease or group of closely allied
diseases must be investigated for itself.

As regards the artificial traumatic infective diseases observed by me,
the conditions which must be established before their parasitic nature
can be proved, we completely fulfilled in the case of the first five,
but only partially in that of the sixth. For the infection was produced
by such small quantities of fluid (blood, serum, pus, etc.) that the
result cannot be attributed to a merely chemical poison.

In the materials used for inoculation bacteria were without exception
present, and in each disease a different and well marked form of
organism could be demonstrated.

At the same time, the bodies of those animals which died of the
artificial traumatic infective diseases contained bacteria in
such numbers that the symptoms and the death of the animals were
sufficiently explained. Further, the bacteria found were identical
with those which were present in the fluid used for inoculation, and a
definite form of organisms corresponded in every instance to a distinct
disease.

These artificial traumatic infective diseases bear the greatest
resemblance to human traumatic infective diseases, both as regards
their origin from putrid substances, their course, and the result of
post-mortem examination. Further, in the first case, just as in the
last, the parasitic organisms could be only imperfectly demonstrated
by the earlier methods of investigation; not till an improved method of
procedure was introduced was it possible to obtain complete proof that
they were parasitic diseases. We are therefore justified in assuming
that human traumatic infective diseases will in all probability be
proved to be parasitic when investigated by these improved methods.

On the other hand, it follows from the fact that a definite pathogenic
bacterium, e. g., the septicæmic bacillus, cannot be inoculated on
every variety of animal (a similar fact is also true with regard to the
bacillus anthracis); that the septicæmia of mice, rabbits, and man are
not under all circumstances produced by the same bacterial form. It is
of course possible that one or other of the bacteric forms found in
animals also play a part in such diseases in the human subject. That,
however, must be especially demonstrated for each case; _a priori_
one need only expect that bacteria are present; as regards form, size
and conditions of growth, they may be similar, but not always the same,
even in what appear to be similar diseases in different animals.

Besides the pathogenic bacteria already found in animals there are no
doubt many others. My experiments refer only to those diseases which
ended fatally. Even these are in all probability not exhausted in the
six forms mentioned. Further experiments on many different species
of animals, with the most putrid substances and with every possible
modification in the method of application, will doubtless bring to
light a number of other infective diseases, which will lead to further
conclusions regarding infective diseases and pathogenic bacteria.

But even in the small series of experiments which I was able to carry
out, one fact was so prominent that I must regard it as constant,
and, as it helps to remove most of the obstacles to the admission of
the existence of a centagium vivum for traumatic infective diseases,
I look on it as the most important result of my work. I refer to
the differences which exist between pathogenic bacteria and to the
constancy of their characters. A distinct bacteric form corresponds, as
we have seen, to each disease, and this form always remains the same,
however often the disease is transmitted from one animal to another.
Further, when we succeed in reproducing the same disease _de novo_
by the injection of putrid substances, only the same bacteric form
occurs which was before found to be specific for that disease.

Further, the differences between these bacteria are as great as could
be expected between particles which border on the invisible. With
regard to these differences, I refer not only to the size and form
of the bacteria, but also to the conditions of their growth, which
can be best recognized by observing their situation and grouping. I
therefore study not only the individual alone, but the whole group of
bacteria, and would, for example, consider a micrococcus which in one
species of animal occurred only in masses (i. e., in a zooglæa form),
as different from another which in the same variety of animal, under
the same conditions of life, was only met with as isolated individuals.
Attention must also be paid to the physiological effect, of which I
scarcely know a more striking example than the case of the bacillus
and the chain-like micrococcus growing together in the cellular tissue
of the ear; the one passing into the blood and penetrating into the
white blood corpuscles, the other spreading out slowly into the tissues
in its vicinity and destroying everything around about; or again, the
case of the septicæmic and pyæmic micrococci of the rabbit in their
different relations to the blood; or lastly, the bacilli only extending
over the surface of the aural cartilage in the erysipetalous disease,
as contrasted with the bacillus anthracis, likewise inoculated on the
rabbit’s ear, but quickly passing into the blood.

As, however, there corresponds to each of the diseases investigated a
form of bacterium distinctly characterized by its physiological action,
by its conditions of growth, size, and form, which, however often the
disease be transmitted from one animal to another, always remains the
same and never passes over into another form, e. g., from the spherical
to the rod shaped, we must in the meantime regard these different forms
of pathogenic bacteria as distinct and constant species.

This is, however, an assertion that will be much disputed by botanists,
to whose special province this subject really belongs.

Amongst those botanists who have written against the subdivision of
bacteria into species, is Nägeli, who says, “I have for ten years
examined thousands of different forms of bacteria, and I have not yet
seen any absolute necessity for dividing them even into two distinct
species.”

Brefeld also states that he can only admit the existence of specific
forms justifying the formation of distinct species when the whole
history of development has been traced by cultivation from spore to
spore in the most nutritive fluids.

Although Brefeld’s demand is undoubtedly theoretically correct it
cannot be made a _sine qua non_ in every investigation on
pathogenic bacteria. We should otherwise be compelled to cease our
investigations into the etiology of infective diseases till botanists
have succeeded in finding out the different species of bacteria by
cultivation and development from spore to spore. It might then very
easily happen that the endless trouble of pure cultivation would be
expended on some form of bacterium which would finally turn out to be
scarcely worthy of attention. In practice only the opposite method can
work. In the first place certain peculiarities of a particular form of
bacterium different from those of other forms, and in the second place
its constancy, compel us to separate it from other less known and less
interesting, and provisionally to regard it as a species. And now, to
verify this provisional supposition, the cultivation from spore to
spore may be undertaken. If this succeeds under conditions which cut
out all sources of fallacy, and if it furnishes a result corresponding
to that obtained by the previous observations, then the conclusions
which were drawn from these observations and which led to its being
ranked as a distinct species must be regarded as valid.

On this, which as it seems to me is the only correct practical method,
I take my stand, and, till the cultivation of bacteria from spore to
spore shows that I am wrong, I shall look on pathogenic bacteria as
consisting of different species.

In order, however, to show that I do not stand alone in this view, I
shall here mention the opinion of some botanists who have already come
to a similar conclusion.

Cohn states that, in spite of the fact that many dispute the necessity
of separating bacteria into genera or species, he must nevertheless
adhere to the method as yet followed by him, and separate bacteria
of a different form and fermenting power from each other, so long as
complete proof of their identity is not given.

From his investigations on the effects of different temperatures and
of desiccation on the development of bacterium termo, Eidam came to
the conclusion that different forms of bacteria require different
conditions of nutriment, and that they behave differently towards
physical and chemical influences. He regards these facts as a further
proof of the necessity of dividing organisms into distinct species.

I shall bring forward another reason to show the necessity of looking
on the pathogenic bacteria which I have described as distinct species.
The greatest stress, in investigations on bacteria, is justly laid on
the so-called pure cultivations, in which only one definite form of
bacterium is present. This evidently arises from the view that if, in a
series of cultivations, the same form of bacterium is always obtained,
a special significance must attach to this form: it must indeed be
accepted as a constant form, or in a word as a species. Can, then,
a series of pure cultivations be carried out without admixture of
other bacteria? It can in truth be done, but only under very limited
conditions. Only such bacteria can be cultivated pure, with the aids
at present at command, which can always be known to be pure, either by
their size and easily recognizable form, as the bacillus anthracis, or
by the production of a characteristic coloring matter as the pigment
bacteria. When, during a series of cultivations, a strange species of
bacteria has by chance got in, as may occasionally happen under any
circumstances, it will in these cases be at once observed, and the
unsuccessful experiment will be thrown out of the series without the
progress of investigation being thereby necessarily interfered with.

But the case is quite different when attempts are made to carry
out cultivations of very small bacteria, which, perhaps, cannot be
distinguished at all without staining; how are we then to discover the
occurrence of contamination? It is impossible to do so, and therefore
all attempts at pure cultivation in apparatus, however skilfully
planned and executed, must, as soon as small bacteria with but little
characteristic appearances are dealt with, be considered as subject to
unavoidable sources of fallacy, and in themselves inconclusive.

But nevertheless a pure cultivation is possible, even in the case
of the bacteria which are smallest and most difficult to recognise.
This, however, is not conducted in cultivation apparatus, but in
the animal body. My experiments demonstrate this. In all the cases
of a distinct disease, e. g., of septicæmia of mice, only the small
bacilli were present, and no other form of bacterium was ever found
with it, unless in the case where that causing the tissue gangrene was
intentionally inoculated at the same time. In fact, there exists no
better cultivation apparatus for pathogenic bacteria than the animal
body itself. Only a very limited number of bacteria can grow in the
body, and the penetration of organisms into it is so difficult that
the uninjured living body may be regarded as completely isolated
with respect to other forms of bacteria than those intentionally
introduced. It is quite evident, from a careful consideration of
the two diseases produced in mice--septicæmia and gangrene of the
tissue--that I have succeeded in my experiments in obtaining a pure
cultivation. In the putrefying blood, which was the cause of these two
diseases, the most different forms of bacteria were present, and yet
only two of these found in the living mouse the conditions necessary
for their existence. All the others died, and these two alone, a small
bacillus and a chain-like micrococcus, remained and grew. These could
be transferred from one animal to another as often as was desired,
without suffering any alteration in their characteristic form, in
their specific physiological action and without any other variety of
bacteria at any time appearing. And further, as I have demonstrated, it
is quite in the power of the experimenter to separate these two forms
of bacteria from each other. When the blood in which only the bacilli
are present is used, these alone are transmitted, and thenceforth are
obtained quite pure; while on the other hand, when a field mouse is
inoculated with both forms of bacteria, the bacilli disappear, and
the micrococcus can be then cultivated pure. Doubtless an attempt to
unite these two forms again in the same animal by inoculation would
have been successful. In short, one has it completely in one’s power
to cultivate several varieties of bacteria together, to separate them
from each other, and eventually to combine them again. Greater demands
can hardly be made on a pure cultivation, and I must therefore regard
the successive transmission of artificial infective diseases as the
best and surest method of pure cultivation. And it can further claim
the same power of demonstrating the existence of specific forms of
bacteria, as must be conceded to any faultless cultivation experiments.

From the fact that the animal body is such an excellent apparatus for
pure cultivation, and that, as we have seen, when the experiments are
properly arranged and sufficient optical aids used, only one specific
form of bacterium can be found in each distinct case of artificial
traumatic infective disease, we may now further conclude that when, in
examining a traumatic infective disease, several different varieties
of bacteria are found, as e. g., chains of small granules, rods, and
long, oscillating threads--such as were seen together by Coze and Feltz
in the artificial septicæmia of rabbits--we have to do either with a
combined infective disease,--that is, not a pure one,--or, what in the
case cited is more probable, an inexact and inaccurate observation.
When, therefore, several species of bacteria occur together in any
morbid process, before definite conclusions are drawn as to the
relations of the disease in question to the organisms, either proof
must be furnished that they are all concerned in the morbid process,
or an attempt must be made to isolate them and to obtain a true
pure cultivation. Otherwise we cannot avoid the objection that the
cultivation was not pure, and therefore not conclusive. I shall only
briefly refer to a further necessary consequence of the admission of
the existence of different species of pathogenic bacteria. The number
of the species of these bacteria is limited; for, of the numerous
diverse forms present in putrid fluids, one or but few can in the most
favorable cases develop in the animal body. Those which disappear
are, for that species of animal at least, not pathogenic bacteria.
If, however, as follows from the foregoing, there exist hurtful and
harmless bacteria, experiments performed on animals with the latter,
e. g., with bacterium termo, prove absolutely nothing for or against
the behavior of the former--the pathogenic--forms. But almost all the
experiments of this nature have been carried out with the first mixture
of different species of bacteria which came to hand without there being
any certainty that pathogenic bacteria were in reality present in the
mixture. It is therefore evident that none of these experiments can
be regarded as furnishing evidence of any value for or against the
parasitic nature of infective diseases.

In all my experiments, not only have the form and size of the bacteria
been constant, but the greatest uniformity in their actions on the
animal organisms has been observed, though no increase of virulence, as
described by Coze and Feltz, Davaine, and others. This leads me to make
some remarks on the supposed law of the increasing virulence of blood
when transmitted through successive animals, discovered or confirmed by
the investigators just named.

The discovery of this law has, as is well known, been received with
great enthusiasm, and it has excited no little interest owing to its
intimate bearing on the doctrine of natural selection (Anpassung and
Vererbung). Some investigators, who are in other things very exact,
have allowed themselves to be blinded by the seductive theory that
the insignificant action of a single putrefactive bacterium may, by
continued natural selection in passing from animal to animal, be
increased in virulence till it becomes deadly though a drop of the
infective liquid be diluted in a quadrillion times. They have founded
thereon the most beautiful practical applications, not suspecting that
the bacteria in question have never been certainly demonstrated.

The original works of Coze and Feltz, as also that of Davaine, are
not at my disposal for reference; and I cannot therefore enter into
a complete criticism of them. So far, however, as I can gather from
the references accessible to me, especially from the detailed notices
in Virchow and Hirch’s “Jahnesbericht,” no complete proof that the
virulence of septicæmic blood increases from generation to generation
seems to have been furnished. Apparently blood more and more diluted
was injected, and astonishment was felt when this always acted, the
effect being then ascribed to its increasing virulence. But controlling
experiments to ascertain whether the septicæmic blood were not already
as virulent in the second and third generations as in the twenty-fifth,
do not seem to have been made. My experiments so far support and are in
accordance with those of Coze, Feltz, and Davaine in that for the first
infection of an animal relatively large quantities of putrid fluid are
necessary; but in the second generation, or at the latest in the third,
the full virulence was attained, and afterwards remained constant.

Of my artificial infective diseases the septicæmia of the mouse has
the greatest correspondence with the artificial septicæmia described
by Davaine. If we were to experiment with this disease in the same
manner as Davaine experimented, we would, if no controlling experiments
were employed, find the same increase in virulence of the disease. It
would only be necessary to use blood in slowly decreasing quantities in
order to obtain in this way any progressive increase of the virulence
that might be desired. I, however, took from the second or third
animal the smallest possible quantity of material for inoculation, and
thus arrived more quickly at the greatest degree of virulence. Till,
therefore, I am assured that, in the septicæmia observed by Davaine,
such controlling experiments were made, I can only look on an increase
in virulence as holding good for the earlier generations. In order
to explain this we do not, however, require to have recourse to the
magical wand of natural selection; a feasible explanation can be very
naturally furnished. Let us take again the septicæmia of mice, as being
the most suitable example.

If two drops of putrefying blood be injected into such an animal
there is introduced not only a number of totally distinct species
of bacteria, but also a certain amount of dissolved putrid poison
(sepsin), not sufficient to produce a fatal effect, but yet certainly
not without influence on the health of the animal. Different factors
must therefore be considered as affecting the health of the animal. On
the one hand there is the dissolved poison, on the other the different
species of bacteria, of which, however, perhaps only two, as in the
example before us, can multiply in the body of the mouse and there
exert a continuous noxious influence. Only one of these two species can
penetrate into the blood, and if the blood alone be used for further
inoculations, only this one variety will come victorious out of the
battle for existence. The further development of the experiment depends
entirely on the quantity of the putrid poison, and on the relation
of the two forms of bacteria to each other in point of numbers. If
one injects a large amount of septic poison and a large number of
that variety of bacteria which increase locally (in this case the
chain-like micrococci causing the gangrene of the tissue), but only a
very small number of the bacteria which pass into the blood (here the
bacilli), the first animal experimented on will die, as a result of the
preponderation influence of the first two factors before many bacilli
can have got into the blood and multiplied there. Of the blood of this
first animal, containing, as it does, proportionately very few bacilli,
one-fifth to one-tenth of a drop must be inoculated in order to convey
the disease with certainty. In the second animal, however, only the
bacilli are introduced, and these develop undisturbed in the blood. For
the infection of the third animal the smallest quantity of this blood
which can produce an effect is then sufficient, and after this third
generation the virulence of the blood remains uniform.

We may also imagine another case in which the increase of the virulence
may go on through more than two generations without any modification
resulting from natural selection and transmission from animal to
animal. This would take place if several species of bacteria capable
of passing into the blood were introduced into the animal at the first
injection. Let us suppose, for example, that in the same putrefying
blood which served for the foregoing experiment, the bacilli of
anthrax were also present, there would then be contained in the blood
of the first animal not only the septicæmic bacillus, but also
bacillus anthracis, and of each only a small number; of the anthrax
bacilli there would be even fewer than of the other, because in mice
they are deposited chiefly in the spleen, lungs, etc.; while in the
blood of the heart they are, even in the most favorable cases, only
sparsely distributed. On the other hand, the anthrax bacilli have
this advantage, that, provided they be inoculated in considerable
numbers, they kill even within twenty hours, while the septicæmic
bacilli only destroy life after fifty hours. In the blood of the second
animal, therefore, both species of bacilli would be present in larger
numbers than in the first, although not yet so numerous as if either
organism had been inoculated singly. Hence a larger quantity of blood
is necessary to ensure transmission to a third animal. Perhaps this
might be the case even in the fourth generation, till finally one or
other variety of bacillus would alone be present in the blood injected.
Probably this would be the septicæmic bacillus.

In this way the experiments of Coze, Feltz, and Davaine may admit of
simple explanation and be brought into harmony with my results.



FOOTNOTES:

[Footnote 39: From the English translation (1880) of _Untersuchungen
über die Aetiologie der Wundinfectionskrankheiten_ (1878).]




                         =TRANSCRIBER’S NOTES=

Simple typographical errors have been silently corrected; unbalanced
quotation marks were remedied when the change was obvious, and
otherwise left unbalanced.

Punctuation, hyphenation, and spelling were made consistent when a
predominant preference was found in the original book; otherwise they
were not changed.





*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK CLASSICS OF MODERN SCIENCE ***


    

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S. copyright
law means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works,
so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United
States without permission and without paying copyright
royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part
of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™
concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark,
and may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following
the terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use
of the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for
copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very
easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as creation
of derivative works, reports, performances and research. Project
Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given away—you may
do practically ANYTHING in the United States with eBooks not protected
by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject to the trademark
license, especially commercial redistribution.


START: FULL LICENSE

THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE

PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free
distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
(or any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at
www.gutenberg.org/license.

Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works

1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your
possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be bound
by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person
or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be
used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this
agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg™
electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.

1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection
of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the individual
works in the collection are in the public domain in the United
States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in the
United States and you are located in the United States, we do not
claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing,
displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as
all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope
that you will support the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting
free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg™
works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the
Project Gutenberg™ name associated with the work. You can easily
comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the
same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when
you share it without charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are
in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States,
check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this
agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing,
distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any
other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes no
representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any
country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other
immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must appear
prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™ work (any work
on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or with which the
phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is accessed, displayed,
performed, viewed, copied or distributed:

    This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and most
    other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions
    whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms
    of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online
    at www.gutenberg.org. If you
    are not located in the United States, you will have to check the laws
    of the country where you are located before using this eBook.
  
1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is
derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not
contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the
copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in
the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply
either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or
obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg™
trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted
with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works
posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the
beginning of this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg™
License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg™.

1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.

1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including
any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access
to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work in a format
other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in the official
version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain
Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the
full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:

    • You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
        the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the method
        you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed
        to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, but he has
        agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project
        Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid
        within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are
        legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty
        payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project
        Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in
        Section 4, “Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg
        Literary Archive Foundation.”
    
    • You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
        you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
        does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
        License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
        copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue
        all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg™
        works.
    
    • You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of
        any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
        electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of
        receipt of the work.
    
    • You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
        distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.
    

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project
Gutenberg™ electronic work or group of works on different terms than
are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing
from the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating the Project
Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg™
electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may
contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate
or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other
intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or
other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or
cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the “Right
of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
Gutenberg™ electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium
with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you
with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in
lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person
or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second
opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If
the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing
without further opportunities to fix the problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT
LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of
damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement
violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the
agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or
limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or
unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the
remaining provisions.

1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
providing copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in
accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the
production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses,
including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of
the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this
or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b) alteration, modification, or
additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any
Defect you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg™

Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It
exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations
from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see
Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation

The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by
U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,
Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation

Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without widespread
public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the widest
array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND
DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular state
visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To
donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg™ electronic works

Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed
editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,
including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.