The Project Gutenberg eBook of The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, Volume 2 (of 5) This ebook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this ebook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United States, you will have to check the laws of the country where you are located before using this eBook. Title: The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, Volume 2 (of 5) Author: Thomas Hobbes Editor: Sir William Molesworth Release date: June 24, 2024 [eBook #73906] Language: English Original publication: London: John Bohn, 1839 Credits: Emmanuel Ackerman, KD Weeks and the Online Distributed Proofreading Team at https://www.pgdp.net (This book was produced from images made available by the HathiTrust Digital Library.) *** START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE ENGLISH WORKS OF THOMAS HOBBES, VOLUME 2 (OF 5) *** ------------------------------------------------------------------------ Transcriber’s Note: This version of the text cannot represent certain typographical effects. Italics are delimited with the ‘_’ character as _italic_. Footnotes have been moved to follow the paragraphs in which they are referenced. Minor errors, attributable to the printer, have been corrected. Please see the transcriber’s note at the end of this text for details regarding the handling of any textual issues encountered during its preparation. THE ENGLISH WORKS OF THOMAS HOBBES. LONDON: C RICHARDS, PRINTER, ST. MARTIN’S LANE. THE ENGLISH WORKS OF THOMAS HOBBES OF MALMESBURY; NOW FIRST COLLECTED AND EDITED BY SIR WILLIAM MOLESWORTH, BART. --- VOL. II. --- LONDON: JOHN BOHN, HENRIETTA STREET, COVENT GARDEN. --- MDCCCXLI. PHILOSOPHICAL RUDIMENTS CONCERNING GOVERNMENT AND SOCIETY. BY THOMAS HOBBES OF MALMESBURY. TO THE RIGHT HONOURABLE WILLIAM EARL OF DEVONSHIRE, MY MOST HONOURED LORD. --- MAY IT PLEASE YOUR LORDSHIP, It was the speech of the Roman people, to whom the name of _king_ had been rendered odious, as well by the tyranny of the Tarquins as by the genius and decretals of that city; it was the speech, I say, of the public, however pronounced from a private mouth, (if yet Cato the censor were no more than such): _that all kings are to be reckoned amongst ravenous beasts_. But what a beast of prey was the Roman people; whilst with its conquering eagles it erected its proud trophies so far and wide over the world, bringing the Africans, the Asiatics, the Macedonians, and the Achæans, with many other despoiled nations, into a specious bondage, with the pretence of preferring them to be denizens of Rome! So that if Cato’s saying were a wise one, it was every whit as wise, that of Pontius Telesinus; who flying about with open mouth through all the companies of his army in that famous encounter which he had with Sylla, cried out: that _Rome herself as well as Sylla, was to be razed; for that there would always be wolves and depredators of their liberty, unless the forest that lodged them were grubbed up by the roots_. To speak impartially, both sayings are very true: that _man to man is a kind of God_; and that _man to man is an arrant wolf_. The first is true, if we compare citizens amongst themselves; and the second, if we compare cities. In the one, there is some analogy of similitude with the Deity; to wit, justice and charity, the twin sisters of peace. But in the other, good men must defend themselves by taking to them for a sanctuary the two daughters of war, deceit and violence: that is, in plain terms, a mere brutal rapacity. Which although men object to one another as a reproach, by an inbred custom which they have of beholding their own actions in the persons of other men, wherein, as in a mirror, all things on the left side appear to be on the right, and all things on the right side to be as plainly on the left; yet the natural right of preservation, which we all receive from the uncontrolable dictates of necessity, will not admit it to be a vice, though it confess it to be an unhappiness. Now that with Cato himself, a person of so great a renown for wisdom, animosity should so prevail instead of judgment, and partiality instead of reason, that the very same thing which he thought just in his popular state, he should censure as unjust in a monarchical; other men perhaps may have leisure to admire. But I have been long since of this opinion; that there was never yet any more than vulgar prudence, that had the luck of being acceptable to the giddy people; but either it hath not been understood, or else having been so hath been levelled and cried down. The more eminent actions and apothegms, both of the Greeks and Romans, have been indebted for their eulogies not so much to the _reason_, as to the _greatness_ of them; and very many times to that prosperous usurpation, (with which our histories do so mutually upbraid each other), which as a conquering torrent carries all before it, as well public agents as public actions, in the stream of time. Wisdom, properly so called, is nothing else but this: _the perfect knowledge of the truth in all matters whatsoever_. Which being derived from the registers and records of _things_; and that as it were through the conduit of certain definite appellations; cannot possibly be the work of a sudden acuteness, but of a well-balanced reason; which by the compendium of a word, we call _philosophy_. For by this it is that a way is opened to us, in which we travel from the contemplation of particular things to the inference or result of universal actions. Now look, how many sorts of things there are, which properly fall within the cognizance of human reason; into so many branches does the tree of philosophy divide itself. And from the diversity of the matter about which they are conversant, there hath been given to those branches a diversity of names too. For treating of figures, it is called _geometry_; of motion, _physic_; of natural right, _morals_; put altogether, and they make up _philosophy_. Just as the British, the Atlantic, and the Indian seas, being diversely christened from the diversity of their shores, do notwithstanding all together make up _the ocean_. And truly the geometricians have very admirably performed their part. For whatsoever assistance doth accrue to the life of man, whether from the observation of the heavens or from the description of the earth, from the notation of times, or from the remotest experiments of navigation; finally, whatsoever things they are in which this present age doth differ from the rude simpleness of antiquity, we must acknowledge to be a debt which we owe merely to geometry. If the moral philosophers had as happily discharged their duty, I know not what could have been added by human industry to the completion of that happiness, which is consistent with human life. For were the nature of human actions as distinctly known as the nature of _quantity_ in geometrical figures, the strength of _avarice_ and _ambition_, which is sustained by the erroneous opinions of the vulgar as touching the nature of _right_ and _wrong_, would presently faint and languish; and mankind should enjoy such an immortal peace, that unless it were for habitation, on supposition that the earth should grow too narrow for her inhabitants, there would hardly be left any pretence for war. But now on the contrary, that neither the sword nor the pen should be allowed any cessation; that the knowledge of the law of nature should lose its growth, not advancing a whit beyond its ancient stature; that there should still be such siding with the several factions of philosophers, that the very same action should be decried by some, and as much elevated by others; that the very same man should at several times embrace his several opinions, and esteem his own actions far otherwise in himself than he does in others: these, I say, are so many signs, so many manifest arguments, that what hath hitherto been written by moral philosophers, hath not made any progress in the knowledge of the truth; but yet hath took with the world, not so much by giving any light to the understanding as entertainment to the affections, whilst by the successful rhetorications of their speech they have confirmed them in their rashly received opinions. So that this part of philosophy hath suffered the same destiny with the _public ways_, which lie open to all passengers to traverse up and down: or the same lot _with highways and open streets_, some for divertisement, and some for business; so that what with the impertinences of some and the altercations of others, those ways have never a seed time, and therefore yield never a harvest. The only reason of which unluckiness should seem to be this; that amongst all the writers of that part of philosophy there is not one that hath used an idoneous principle of tractation. For we may not, as in a circle, begin the handling of a science from what point we please. There is a certain clue of reason, whose beginning is in the dark; but by the benefit of whose conduct, we are led as it were by the hand into the clearest light. So that the principle of tractation is to be taken from that darkness; and then the light to be carried thither for irradiating the doubts. As often therefore as any writer doth either weakly forsake that clue, or wilfully cut it asunder; he describes the footsteps, not of his progress in science, but of his wanderings from it. And from this it was, that when I applied my thoughts to the investigation of natural _justice_, I was presently advertised from the very word justice, (which signifies a steady will of giving every one his _own_), that my first enquiry was to be, from whence it proceeded that any man should call anything rather his _own_, than _another man’s_. And when I found that this proceeded not from nature, but consent; (for what nature at first laid forth in common, men did afterwards distribute into several _impropriations_); I was conducted from thence to another inquiry; namely, to what end and upon what impulsives, when all was equally every man’s in common, men did rather think it fitting that every man should have his inclosure. And I found the reason was, that from a community of goods there must needs arise contention, whose enjoyment should be greatest. And from that contention all kind of calamities must unavoidably ensue, which by the instinct of nature every man is taught to shun. Having therefore thus arrived at two maxims of human nature; the one arising from the _concupiscible_ part, which desires to appropriate to itself the use of those things in which all others have a joint interest; the other proceeding from the _rational_, which teaches every man to fly a contra-natural dissolution, as the greatest mischief that can arrive to nature: which principles being laid down, I seem from them to have demonstrated by a most evident connexion, in this little work of mine, first, the absolute necessity of leagues and contracts, and thence the rudiments both of moral and of civil prudence. That appendage which is added concerning the regiment of God, hath been done with this intent; that the dictates of God Almighty in the law of nature, might not seem repugnant to the written law, revealed to us in his word. I have also been very wary in the whole tenour of my discourse, not to meddle with the civil laws of any particular nation whatsoever: that is to say, I have avoided coming ashore, which those times have so infested both with shelves and tempests. At what expense of time and industry I have been in this scrutiny after truth, I am not ignorant; but to what purpose, I know not. For being partial judges of ourselves, we lay a partial estimate upon our own productions. I therefore offer up this book to your Lordship’s, not favour, but censure first; as having found by many experiments, that it is not the credit of the author, nor the newness of the work, nor yet the ornament of the style, but only the weight of reason, which recommends any _opinion_ to your Lordship’s favour and approbation. If it fortune to please, that is to say, if it be sound, if it be useful, if it be not vulgar; I humbly offer it to your Lordship, as both my glory and my protection. But if in anything I have erred, your Lordship will yet accept it as a testimony of my gratitude; that the means of study, which I enjoyed by your Lordship’s goodness, I have employed to the procurement of your Lordship’s favour. The God of heaven crown your Lordship with length of days, in this earthly station; and in the heavenly Jerusalem with a crown of glory. Your Honour’s most humble, and most devoted Servant, THOMAS HOBBES. ------- THE AUTHOR’S PREFACE TO THE READER. Reader, I promise thee here such things, which ordinarily promised do seem to challenge the greatest attention, (whether thou regard the dignity or profit of the matter treated, or the right method of handling it, or the honest motive and good advice to undertake it, or lastly the moderation of the author,) and I lay them here before thine eyes. In this book thou shalt find briefly described the duties of men: first, as men; then as subjects; lastly, as Christians. Under which duties are contained, not only the elements of the laws of nature and of nations, together with the true original and power of justice; but also the very essence of Christian religion itself, so far forth as the measure of this my purpose could well bear it. Which kind of doctrine, excepting what relates to Christian religion, the most ancient sages did judge fittest to be delivered to posterity, either curiously adorned with verse, or clouded with allegories, as a most beautiful and hallowed mystery of royal authority; lest by the disputations of private men it might be defiled. Other philosophers in the mean time, to the advantage of mankind, did contemplate the faces and motions of things; others, without disadvantage, their natures and causes. But in after times, Socrates is said to have been the first who truly loved this civil science; although hitherto not thoroughly understood, yet glimmering forth as through a cloud in the government of the commonweal: and that he set so great a value on this, that utterly abandoning and despising all other parts of philosophy, he wholly embraced this, as judging it only worthy the labour of his mind. After him comes Plato, Aristotle, Cicero, and other philosophers, as well Greek as Latin. And now at length all men of all nations, not only philosophers but even the vulgar, have and do still deal with this as a matter of ease, exposed and prostitute to every mother-wit, and to be attained without any great care or study. And, which makes mainly for its dignity, those who suppose themselves to have it, or are in such employment as they ought to have it, do so wonderfully please themselves in its _idea_, as they easily brook the followers of other arts to be esteemed and styled ingenuous, learned, skilful, and what you will, except prudent: for this name, in regard of civil knowledge, they presume to be due to themselves only. Whether therefore the worth of arts is to be weighed by the worthiness of the persons who entertain them, or by the number of those who have written of them, or by the judgment of the wisest; certainly this must carry it, which so nearly relates to princes, and others engaged in the government of mankind; in whose adulterate species also the most part of men do delight themselves, and in which the most excellent wits of philosophers have been conversant. The benefit of it, when rightly delivered, that is, when derived from true principles by evident connection, we shall then best discern, when we shall but well have considered the mischiefs that have befallen mankind from its counterfeit and babbling form. For in matters wherein we speculate for the exercise of our wits, if any error escape us, it is without hurt; neither is there any loss, but of time only. But in those things which every man ought to meditate for the steerage of his life, it necessarily happens that not only from errors, but even from ignorance itself, there arise offences, contentions, nay, even slaughter itself. Look now, how great a prejudice these are; such and so great is the benefit arising from this doctrine of morality truly declared. How many kings, and those good men too, hath this one error, that a tyrant king might lawfully be put to death, been the slaughter of! How many throats hath this false position cut, that a prince for some causes may by some certain men be deposed! And what bloodshed hath not this erroneous doctrine caused, that kings are not superiors to, but administrators for the multitude! Lastly, how many rebellions hath this opinion been the cause of, which teacheth that the knowledge whether the commands of kings be just or unjust, belongs to private men; and that before they yield obedience, they not only may, but ought to dispute them! Besides, in the moral philosophy now commonly received, there are many things no less dangerous than those, which it matters not now to recite. I suppose those ancients foresaw this, who rather chose to have the science of justice wrapped up in fables, than openly exposed to disputations. For before such questions began to be moved, princes did not sue for, but already exercised the supreme power. They kept their empire entire, not by arguments, but by punishing the wicked and protecting the good. Likewise subjects did not measure what was just by the sayings and judgments of private men, but by the laws of the realm; nor were they kept in peace by disputations, but by power and authority. Yea, they reverenced the supreme power, whether residing in one man or in a council, as a certain visible divinity. Therefore they little used, as in our days, to join themselves with ambitious and hellish spirits, to the utter ruin of their state. For they could not entertain so strange a fancy, as not to desire the preservation of that by which they were preserved. In truth, the simplicity of those times was not yet capable of so learned a piece of folly. Wherefore it was peace and a golden age, which ended not before that, Saturn being expelled, it was taught lawful to take up arms against kings. This, I say, the ancients not only themselves saw, but in one of their fables they seem very aptly to have signified it to us. For they say, that when Ixion was invited by Jupiter to a banquet, he fell in love, and began to court Juno herself. Offering to embrace her, he clasped a cloud; from whence the Centaurs proceeded, by nature half men, half horses, a fierce, a fighting, and unquiet generation. Which changing the names only, is as much as if they should have said, that private men being called to councils of state, desired to prostitute justice, the only sister and wife of the supreme, to their own judgments and apprehensions; but embracing a false and empty shadow instead of it, they have begotten those hermaphrodite opinions of moral philosophers, partly right and comely, partly brutal and wild; the causes of all contentions and bloodsheds. Since therefore such opinions are daily seen to arise, if any man now shall dispel those clouds, and by most firm reasons demonstrate that there are no authentical doctrines concerning right and wrong, good and evil, besides the constituted laws in each realm and government; and that the question whether any future action will prove just or unjust, good or ill, is to be demanded of none but those to whom the supreme hath committed the interpretation of his laws: surely he will not only show us the highway to peace, but will also teach us how to avoid the close, dark, and dangerous by-paths of faction and sedition; than which I know not what can be thought more profitable. Concerning my method, I thought it not sufficient to use a plain and evident style in what I have to deliver, except I took my beginning from the very matter of civil government, and thence proceeded to its generation and form, and the first beginning of justice. For everything is best understood by its constitutive causes. For as in a watch, or some such small engine, the matter, figure, and motion of the wheels cannot well be known, except it be taken insunder and viewed in parts; so to make a more curious search into the rights of states and duties of subjects, it is necessary, I say, not to take them insunder, but yet that they be so considered as if they were dissolved; that is, that we rightly understand what the quality of human nature is, in what matters it is, in what not, fit to make up a civil government, and how men must be agreed amongst themselves that intend to grow up into a well-grounded state. Having therefore followed this kind of method, in the first place I set down for a principle, by experience known to all men and denied by none, to wit, that the dispositions of men are naturally such, that except they be restrained through fear of some coercive power, every man will distrust and dread each other; and as by natural right he may, so by necessity he will be forced to make use of the strength he hath, toward the preservation of himself. You will object perhaps, that there are some who deny this. Truly so it happens, that very many do deny it. But shall I therefore seem to fight against myself, because I affirm that the same men confess and deny the same thing? In truth I do not; but they do, whose actions disavow what their discourses approve of. We see all countries, though they be at peace with their neighbours, yet guarding their frontiers with armed men, their towns with walls and ports, and keeping constant watches. To what purpose is all this, if there be no fear of the neighbouring power? We see even in well-governed states, where there are laws and punishments appointed for offenders, yet particular men travel not without their sword by their sides for their defences; neither sleep they without shutting not only their doors against their fellow subjects, but also their trunks and coffers for fear of domestics. Can men give a clearer testimony of the distrust they have each of other, and all of all? Now, since they do thus, and even countries as well as men, they publicly profess their mutual fear and diffidence. But in disputing they deny it; that is as much as to say, that out of a desire they have to contradict others, they gainsay themselves. Some object that this principle being admitted, it would needs follow, not only that all men were wicked, (which perhaps though it seem hard, yet we must yield to, since it is so clearly declared by holy writ), but also wicked by nature, which cannot be granted without impiety. But this, that men are evil by nature, follows not from this principle. For though the wicked were fewer than the righteous, yet because we cannot distinguish them, there is a necessity of suspecting, heeding, anticipating, subjugating, self-defending, ever incident to the most honest and fairest conditioned. Much less does it follow, that those who are wicked, are so by nature. For though from nature, that is, from their first birth, as they are merely sensible creatures, they have this disposition, that immediately as much as in them lies they desire and do whatsoever is best pleasing to them, and that either through fear they fly from, or through hardness repel those dangers which approach them; yet are they not for this reason to be accounted wicked. For the affections of the mind, which arise only from the lower parts of the soul, are not wicked themselves; but the actions thence proceeding may be so sometimes, as when they are either offensive or against duty. Unless you give children all they ask for, they are peevish and cry, aye, and strike their parents sometimes; and all this they have from nature. Yet are they free from guilt, neither may we properly call them wicked; first, because they cannot hurt; next, because wanting the free use of reason they are exempted from all duty. These when they come to riper years, having acquired power whereby they may do hurt, if they shall continue to do the same things, then truly they both begin to be, and are properly accounted wicked. Insomuch as a wicked man is almost the same thing with a child grown strong and sturdy, or a man of a childish disposition; and malice the same with a defect of reason in that age when nature ought to be better governed through good education and experience. Unless therefore we will say that men are naturally evil, because they receive not their education and use of reason from nature, we must needs acknowledge that men may derive desire, fear, anger, and other passions from nature, and yet not impute the evil effects of those unto nature. The foundation therefore which I have laid, standing firm, I demonstrate, in the first place, that the state of men without civil society, which state we may properly call the state of nature, is nothing else but a mere war of all against all; and in that war all men have equal right unto all things. Next, that all men as soon as they arrive to understanding of this hateful condition, do desire, even nature itself compelling them, to be freed from this misery. But that this cannot be done, except by compact, they all quit that right they have to all things. Furthermore, I declare and confirm what the nature of compact is; how and by what means the right of one might be transferred unto another to make their compacts valid; also what rights, and to whom they must necessarily be granted, for the establishing of peace; I mean, what those dictates of reason are, which may properly be termed the laws of nature. And all these are contained in that part of this book which I entitle _Liberty_. These grounds thus laid, I show further what civil government, and the supreme power in it, and the divers kinds of it are; by what means it becomes so; and what rights particular men, who intend to constitute this civil government, must so necessarily transfer from themselves on the supreme power, whether it be one man or an assembly of men, that, except they do so, it will evidently appear to be no civil government, but the rights which all men have to all things, that is, the rights of war will still remain. Next I distinguish the divers kinds of it, to wit, monarchy, aristocracy, democracy; and paternal dominion, and that of masters over their servants. I declare how they are constituted, and I compare their several conveniences and inconveniences, each with other. Furthermore, I unfold what those things are which destroy it, and what his or their duty is, who rule in chief. Last of all, I explicate the natures of law and of sin; and I distinguish law from counsel, from compact, from that which I call right. All which I comprehend under the title of _Dominion_. In the last part of it, which is entitled _Religion_, lest that right, which by strong reason, in the preceding discourse, I had confirmed the sovereign powers to have over their subjects, might seem to be repugnant to the sacred Scriptures; I show, in the first place, how it repugns not the divine right, for as much as God overrules all rulers by nature, that is, by the dictates of natural reason. In the second, forasmuch as God himself had a peculiar dominion over the Jews, by virtue of that ancient covenant of circumcision. In the third, because God doth now rule over us Christians, by virtue of our covenant of baptism. And therefore the authority of rulers in chief, or of civil government, is not at all, we see, contrary to religion. In the last place, I declare what duties are necessarily required from us, to enter into the _kingdom of heaven_. And of those I plainly demonstrate, and conclude out of evident testimonies of holy writ according to the interpretation made by all, that the obedience, which I have affirmed to be due from particular Christian subjects unto their Christian princes, cannot possibly in the least sort be repugnant unto Christian religion. You have seen my method: receive now the reason which moved me to write this. I was studying philosophy for my mind sake, and I had gathered together its first elements in all kinds; and having digested them into three sections by degrees, I thought to have written them, so as in the first I would have treated of _body_ and its general properties; in the second of _man_ and his special faculties and affections; in the third, of _civil government_ and the duties of subjects. Wherefore the first section would have contained _the first philosophy_, and certain elements of physic; in it we would have considered the reasons of _time_, _place_, _cause_, _power_, _relation_, _proportion_, _quantity_, _figure_, and _motion_. In the second, we would have been conversant about _imagination_, _memory_, _intellect_, _ratiocination_, _appetite_, _will_, _good_ and _evil_, _honest_ and _dishonest_, and the like. What this last section handles, I have now already showed you. Whilst I contrive, order, pensively and slowly compose these matters; (for I only do reason, I dispute not); it so happened in the interim, that my country, some few years before the civil wars did rage, was boiling hot with questions concerning the rights of dominion and the obedience due from subjects, the true forerunners of an approaching war; and was the cause which, all those other matters deferred, ripened and plucked from me this third part. Therefore it happens, that what was last in order, is yet come forth first in time. And the rather, because I saw that, grounded on its own principles sufficiently known by experience, it would not stand in need of the former sections. Yet I have not made it out of a desire of praise: although if I had, I might have defended myself with this fair excuse, that very few do things laudably, who are not affected with commendation: but for your sakes, readers, who I persuaded myself, when you should rightly apprehend and thoroughly understand this doctrine I here present you with, would rather choose to brook with patience some inconveniences under government, (because human affairs cannot possibly be without some), than self-opiniatedly disturb the quiet of the public; that, weighing the justice of those things you are about, not by the persuasion and advice of private men, but by the laws of the realm, you will no longer suffer ambitious men through the streams of your blood to wade to their own power; that you will esteem it better to enjoy yourselves in the present state, though perhaps not the best, than by waging war endeavour to procure a reformation for other men in another age, yourselves in the meanwhile either killed or consumed with age. Furthermore, for those who will not acknowledge themselves subject to the civil magistrate, and will be exempt from all public burthens, and yet will live under his jurisdiction, and look for protection from the violence and injuries of others, that you would not look on them as fellow-subjects, but esteem them for enemies and spies; and that ye rashly admit not for God’s word all which, either openly or privately, they shall pretend to be so. I say more plainly, if any preacher, confessor, or casuist, shall but say that this doctrine is agreeable with God’s word, namely, that the chief ruler, nay, any private man may lawfully be put to death without the chief’s command, or that subjects may resist, conspire, or covenant against the supreme power; that ye by no means believe them, but instantly declare their names. He who approves of these reasons, will also like my intentions in writing this book. Last of all, I have propounded to myself this rule through this whole discourse. First, not to define aught which concerns the justice of single actions, but leave them to be determined by the laws. Next, not to dispute the laws of any government in special, that is, not to point which are the laws of any country, but to declare what the laws of all countries are. Thirdly, not to seem of opinion, that there is a less proportion of obedience due to an _aristocracy_ or _democracy_ than a _monarchy_. For though I have endeavoured, by arguments in my tenth chapter, to gain a belief in men, that monarchy is the most commodious government; which one thing alone I confess in this whole book not to be demonstrated, but only probably stated; yet every where I expressly say, that in all kind of government whatsoever there ought to be a supreme and equal power. Fourthly, not in anywise to dispute the positions of divines, except those which strip subjects of their obedience, and shake the foundations of civil government. Lastly, lest I might imprudently set forth somewhat of which there would be no need, what I had thus written I would not presently expose to the public. Wherefore I got some few copies privately dispersed among some of my friends; that discrying the opinions of others, if any things appeared erroneous, hard, or obscure, I might correct, soften and explain them. These things I found most bitterly excepted against. That I had made the civil powers too large; but this by ecclesiastical persons. That I had utterly taken away liberty of conscience; but this by sectaries. That I had set princes above the civil laws; but this by lawyers. Wherefore I was not much moved by these men’s reprehensions, as who in doing this, did but do their own business; except it were to tie those knots somewhat faster. But for their sakes who have a little been staggered at the principles themselves, to wit, the nature of men, the authority or right of nature, the nature of compacts and contracts, and the original of civil government; because in finding fault they have not so much followed their passions, as their common-sense, I have therefore in some places added some annotations, whereby I presumed I might give some satisfaction to their differing thoughts. Lastly, I have endeavoured to offend none, beside those whose principles these contradict, and whose tender minds are lightly offended by every difference of opinions. Wherefore, if ye shall meet with some things which have more of sharpness, and less of certainty than they ought to have, since they are not so much spoken for the maintenance of parties as the establishment of peace, and by one whose just grief for the present calamities of his country may very charitably be allowed some liberty; it is his only request to ye, Readers, ye will deign to receive them with an equal mind. ------- ------------------------------------------------------------------------ THE INDEX. --- OF LIBERTY. CHAP. PAGE 1. Of the state of men without civil society 1 2. Of the law of nature concerning contracts 14 3. Of the other laws of nature 29 4. That the law of nature is a divine law 59 OF DOMINION. 5. Of the causes and first original of civil 63 government 6. Of the right, whether we consider it in an 71 assembly or in one person, which he hath who is endued with supreme authority 7. Of the three kinds of government, Democracy, 92 Aristocracy, and Monarchy 8. Of the right which lords and masters have over 108 their servants 9. Of the right which parents have over their 114 children, and of a kingdom paternal 10. A comparison of the three kinds of government, 126 each with other, according to the inconveniences of each one 11. The places and examples of Scripture concerning 143 the right of government, which make for proof of the foresaid doctrines 12. Of the inward causes which dissolve all civil 149 government 13. Of the duties of those men who sit at the helm of 165 state 14. Of laws and sins 182 OF RELIGION. 15. Of God’s government by nature 201 16. Of his government by the old covenant 226 17. Of his government by the new covenant 250 18. Of those things which are necessary for our 298 entrance into the kingdom of heaven PHILOSOPHICAL ELEMENTS OF A TRUE CITIZEN. --- LIBERTY. --- CHAPTER I. OF THE STATE OF MEN WITHOUT CIVIL SOCIETY. 1. The Introduction. 2. That the beginning of civil society is from mutual fear. 3. That men by nature are all equal. 4. Whence the will of mischieving each other ariseth. 5. The discord arising from comparison of wits. 6. From the appetite many have to the same thing. 7. The definition of _right_. 8. A right to the end, gives a right to the means necessary to that end. 9. By the right of nature, every man is judge of the means which tend to his own preservation. 10. By nature all men have equal right to all things. 11. This right which all men have to all things, is unprofitable. 12. The state of men without civil society, is a mere state of war: the definitions of _peace_ and _war_. 13. War is an adversary to man’s preservation. 14. It is lawful for any man, by natural right, to compel another whom he hath gotten in his power, to give caution of his future obedience. 15. Nature dictates the seeking after peace. [Sidenote: Introduction.] The faculties of human nature may be reduced unto four kinds; bodily strength, experience, reason, passion. Taking the beginning of this following doctrine from these, we will declare, in the first place, what manner of inclinations men who are endued with these faculties bear towards each other, and whether, and by what faculty they are born apt for society, and to preserve themselves against mutual violence; then proceeding, we will shew what advice was necessary to be taken for this business, and what are the conditions of society, or of human peace; that is to say, (changing the words only), what are the fundamental _laws of nature_. [Sidenote: That the beginning of mutual society is from fear.] 2. The greatest part of those men who have written aught concerning commonwealths, either suppose, or require us or beg of us to believe, that man is a creature born fit[1] for society. The Greeks call him πολιτικον; and on this foundation they so build up the doctrine of civil society, as if for the preservation of peace, and the government of mankind, there were nothing else necessary than that men should agree to make certain covenants and conditions together, which themselves should then call laws. Which axiom, though received by most, is yet certainly false; and an error proceeding from our too slight contemplation of human nature. For they who shall more narrowly look into the causes for which men come together, and delight in each other’s company, shall easily find that this happens not because naturally it could happen no otherwise, but by accident. For if by nature one man should love another, that is, as man, there could no reason be returned why every man should not equally love every man, as being equally man; or why he should rather frequent those, whose society affords him honour or profit. We do not therefore by nature seek society for its own sake, but that we may receive some honour or profit from it; these we desire primarily, that secondarily. How, by what advice, men do meet, will be best known by observing those things which they do when they are met. For if they meet for traffic, it is plain every man regards not his fellow, but his business; if to discharge some office, a certain market-friendship is begotten, which hath more of jealousy in it than true love, and whence factions sometimes may arise, but good will never; if for pleasure and recreation of mind, every man is wont to please himself most with those things which stir up laughter, whence he may, according to the nature of that which is ridiculous, by comparison of another man’s defects and infirmities, pass the more current in his own opinion. And although this be sometimes innocent and without offence, yet it is manifest they are not so much delighted with the society, as their own vain glory. But for the most part, in these kinds of meeting we wound the absent; their whole life, sayings, actions are examined, judged, condemned. Nay, it is very rare but some present receive a fling as soon as they part; so as his reason was not ill, who was wont always at parting to go out last. And these are indeed the true delights of society, unto which we are carried by nature, that is, by those passions which are incident to all creatures, until either by sad experience or good precepts it so fall out, which in many it never happens, that the appetite of present matters be dulled with the memory of things past: without which the discourse of most quick and nimble men on this subject, is but cold and hungry. Footnote 1: _Born fit._] Since we now see actually a constituted society among men, and none living out of it, since we discern all desirous of congress and mutual correspondence, it may seem a wonderful kind of stupidity, to lay in the very threshold of this doctrine such a stumbling block before the reader, as to deny _man to be born fit for society_. Therefore I must more plainly say, that it is true indeed, that to man by nature, or as man, that is, as soon as he is born, solitude is an enemy; for infants have need of others to help them to live, and those of riper years to help them to live well. Wherefore I deny not that men (even nature compelling) desire to come together. But civil societies are not mere meetings, but bonds, to the making whereof faith and compacts are necessary; the virtue whereof to children and fools, and the profit whereof to those who have not yet tasted the miseries which accompany its defects, is altogether unknown; whence it happens, that those, because they know not what society is, cannot enter into it; these, because ignorant of the benefit it brings, care not for it. Manifest therefore it is, that all men, because they are born in infancy, are born unapt for society. Many also, perhaps most men, either through defect of mind or want of education, remain unfit during the whole course of their lives; yet have they, infants as well as those of riper years, a human nature. Wherefore man is made fit for society not by nature, but by education. Furthermore, although man were born in such a condition as to desire it, it follows not, that he therefore were born fit to enter into it. For it is one thing to desire, another to be in capacity fit for what we desire; for even they, who through their pride, will not stoop to equal conditions, without which there can be no society, do yet desire it. But if it so happen, that being met they pass their time in relating some stories, and one of them begins to tell one which concerns himself; instantly every one of the rest most greedily desires to speak of himself too; if one relate some wonder, the rest will tell you miracles, if they have them; if not, they will feign them. Lastly, that I may say somewhat of them who pretend to be wiser than others: if they meet to talk of philosophy, look, how many men, so many would be esteemed masters, or else they not only love not their fellows, but even persecute them with hatred. So clear is it by experience to all men who a little more narrowly consider human affairs, that all free congress ariseth either from mutual poverty, or from vain glory, whence the parties met endeavour to carry with them either some benefit, or to leave behind them that same εὐδοκιμεῖν, some esteem and honour with those, with whom they have been conversant. The same is also collected by reason out of the definitions themselves of _will_, _good_, _honour_, _profitable_. For when we voluntarily contract society, in all manner of society we look after the object of the will, that is, that which every one of those who gather together, propounds to himself for good. Now whatsoever seems good, is pleasant, and relates either to the senses, or the mind. But all the mind’s pleasure is either glory, (or to have a good opinion of one’s self), or refers to glory in the end; the rest are sensual, or conducing to sensuality, which may be all comprehended under the word _conveniences_. All society therefore is either for gain, or for glory; that is, not so much for love of our fellows, as for the love of ourselves. But no society can be great or lasting, which begins from vain glory. Because that glory is like honour; if all men have it no man hath it, for they consist in comparison and precellence. Neither doth the society of others advance any whit the cause of my glorying in myself; for every man must account himself, such as he can make himself without the help of others. But though the benefits of this life may be much furthered by mutual help; since yet those may be better attained to by dominion than by the society of others, I hope no body will doubt, but that men would much more greedily be carried by nature, if all fear were removed, to obtain dominion, than to gain society. We must therefore resolve, that the original of all great and lasting societies consisted not in the mutual good will men had towards each other, but in the mutual fear[2] they had of each other. Footnote 2: _The mutual fear._] It is objected: it is so improbable that men should grow into civil societies out of fear, that if they had been afraid, they would not have endured each others looks. They presume, I believe, that to fear is nothing else than to be affrighted. I comprehend in this word _fear_, a certain foresight of future evil; neither do I conceive flight the sole property of fear, but to distrust, suspect, take heed, provide so that they may not fear, is also incident to the fearful. They who go to sleep, shut their doors; they who travel, carry their swords with them, because they fear thieves. Kingdoms guard their coasts and frontiers with forts and castles; cities are compact with walls; and all for fear of neighbouring kingdoms and towns. Even the strongest armies, and most accomplished for fight, yet sometimes parley for peace, as fearing each others power, and lest they might be overcome. It is through fear that men secure themselves by flight indeed, and in corners, if they think they cannot escape otherwise; but for the most part, by arms and defensive weapons; whence it happens, that daring to come forth they know each other’s spirits. But then if they fight, civil society ariseth from the victory; if they agree, from their agreement. [Sidenote: That men by nature are all equal.] 3. The cause of mutual fear consists partly in the natural equality of men, partly in their mutual will of hurting: whence it comes to pass, that we can neither expect from others, nor promise to ourselves the least security. For if we look on men full-grown, and consider how brittle the frame of our human body is, which perishing, all its strength, vigour, and wisdom itself perisheth with it; and how easy a matter it is, even for the weakest man to kill the strongest: there is no reason why any man, trusting to his own strength, should conceive himself made by nature above others. They are equals, who can do equal things one against the other; but they who can do the greatest things, namely, kill, can do equal things. All men therefore among themselves are by nature equal; the inequality we now discern, hath its spring from the civil law. [Sidenote: Whence the will of mischieving each other ariseth.] 4. All men in the state of nature have a desire and will to hurt, but not proceeding from the same cause, neither equally to be condemned. For one man, according to that natural equality which is among us, permits as much to others as he assumes to himself; which is an argument of a temperate man, and one that rightly values his power. Another, supposing himself above others, will have a license to do what he lists, and challenges respect and honour, as due to him before others; which is an argument of a fiery spirit. This man’s will to hurt ariseth from vain glory, and the false esteem he hath of his own strength; the other’s from the necessity of defending himself, his liberty, and his goods, against this man’s violence. [Sidenote: The discord arising from comparison of wits.] 5. Furthermore, since the combat of wits is the fiercest, the greatest discords which are, must necessarily arise from this contention. For in this case it is not only odious to contend against, but also not to consent. For not to approve of what a man saith, is no less than tacitly to accuse him of an error in that thing which he speaketh: as in very many things to dissent, is as much as if you accounted him a fool whom you dissent from. Which may appear hence, that there are no wars so sharply waged as between sects of the same religion, and factions of the same commonweal, where the contestation is either concerning doctrines or politic prudence. And since all the pleasure and jollity of the mind consists in this, even to get some, with whom comparing, it may find somewhat wherein to triumph and vaunt itself; it is impossible but men must declare sometimes some mutual scorn and contempt, either by laughter, or by words, or by gesture, or some sign or other; than which there is no greater vexation of mind, and than from which there cannot possibly arise a greater desire to do hurt. [Sidenote: From the appetite many have to the same thing.] 6. But the most frequent reason why men desire to hurt each other, ariseth hence, that many men at the same time have an appetite to the same thing; which yet very often they can neither enjoy in common, nor yet divide it; whence it follows that the strongest must have it, and who is strongest must be decided by the sword. [Sidenote: The definition of right.] 7. Among so many dangers therefore, as the natural lusts of men do daily threaten each other withal, to have a care of one’s self is so far from being a matter scornfully to be looked upon, that one has neither the power nor wish to have done otherwise. For every man is desirous of what is good for him, and shuns what is evil, but chiefly the chiefest of natural evils, which is death; and this he doth by a certain impulsion of nature, no less than that whereby a stone moves downward. It is therefore neither absurd nor reprehensible, neither against the dictates of true reason, for a man to use all his endeavours to preserve and defend his body and the members thereof from death and sorrows. But that which is not contrary to right reason, that all men account to be done justly, and with right. Neither by the word _right_ is anything else signified, than that liberty which every man hath to make use of his natural faculties according to right reason. Therefore the first foundation of natural right is this, that _every man as much as in him lies endeavour to protect his life and members_. [Sidenote: A right to the end gives also a right to the means.] 8. But because it is in vain for a man to have a right to the end, if the right to the necessary means be denied him, it follows, that since every man hath a right to preserve himself, he must also be allowed a right _to use all the means, and do all the actions, without which he cannot preserve himself_. [Sidenote: By the right of nature, every man is judge of the means which tend to his preservation.] 9. Now whether the means which he is about to use, and the action he is performing, be necessary to the preservation of his life and members or not, he himself, by the right of nature, must be judge. For if it be contrary to right reason that I should judge of mine own peril, say, that another man is judge. Why now, because he judgeth of what concerns me, by the same reason, because we are equal by nature, will I judge also of things which do belong to him. Therefore it agrees with right reason, that is, it is the right of nature that I judge of his opinion, that is, whether it conduce to my preservation or not. [Sidenote: By right of nature, all men have equal right to all things.] 10. Nature hath given to _every one a right to all_; that is, it was lawful for every man, in the bare state of nature,[3] or before such time as men had engaged themselves by any covenants or bonds, to do what he would, and against whom he thought fit, and to possess, use, and enjoy all what he would, or could get. Now because whatsoever a man would, it therefore seems good to him because he wills it, and either it really doth, or at least seems to him to contribute towards his preservation, (but we have already allowed him to be judge, in the foregoing article, whether it doth or not, insomuch as we are to hold all for necessary whatsoever he shall esteem so), and by the 7th article it appears that by the right of nature those things may be done, and must be had, which necessarily conduce to the protection of life and members, it follows, that in the state of nature, to have all, and do all, is lawful for all. And this is that which is meant by that common saying, _nature hath given all to all_. From whence we understand likewise, that in the state of nature profit is the measure of right. Footnote 3: _In the bare state of nature._ This is thus to be understood: what any man does in the bare state of nature, is injurious to no man; not that in such a state he cannot offend God, or break the laws of nature; for injustice against men presupposeth human laws, such as in the state of nature there are none. Now the truth of this proposition thus conceived, is sufficiently demonstrated to the mindful reader in the articles immediately foregoing; but because in certain cases the difficulty of the conclusion makes us forget the premises, I will contract this argument, and make it most evident to a single view. Every man hath right to protect himself, as appears by the seventh article. The same man therefore hath a right to use all the means which necessarily conduce to this end, by the eighth article. But those are the necessary means which he shall judge to be such, by the ninth article. He therefore hath a right to make use of, and to do all whatsoever he shall judge requisite for his preservation; wherefore by the judgment of him that doth it, the thing done is either right or wrong, and therefore right. True it is therefore in the bare state of nature, &c. But if any man pretend somewhat to tend necessarily to his preservation, which yet he himself doth not confidently believe so, he may offend against the laws of nature, as in the third chapter of this book is more at large declared. It hath been objected by some: if a son kill his father, doth he him no injury? I have answered, that a son cannot be understood to be at any time in the state of nature, as being under the power and command of them to whom he owes his protection as soon as ever he is born, namely, either his father’s or his mother’s, or him that nourished him; as is demonstrated in the ninth chapter. [Sidenote: The right of all to all is unprofitable.] 11. But it was the least benefit for men thus to have a common right to all things. For the effects of this right are the same, almost, as if there had been no right at all. For although any man might say of every thing, _this is mine_, yet could he not enjoy it, by reason of his neighbour, who having equal right and equal power, would pretend the same thing to be his. [Sidenote: The state of men without society is a state of war.] 12. If now to this natural proclivity of men, to hurt each other, which they derive from their passions, but chiefly from a vain esteem of themselves, you add, the right of all to all, wherewith one by right invades, the other by right resists, and whence arise perpetual jealousies and suspicions on all hands, and how hard a thing it is to provide against an enemy invading us with an intention to oppress and ruin, though he come with a small number, and no great provision; it cannot be denied but that the natural state of men, before they entered into society, was a mere war, and that not simply, but a war of all men against all men. [Sidenote: The definition of war and peace.]For what is WAR, but that same time in which the will of contesting by force is fully declared, either by words or deeds? The time remaining is termed PEACE. [Sidenote: War is an adversary to man’s preservation.] 13. But it is easily judged how disagreeable a thing to the preservation either of mankind, or of each single man, a perpetual war is. But it is perpetual in its own nature; because in regard of the equality of those that strive, it cannot be ended by victory. For in this state the conqueror is subject to so much danger, as it were to be accounted a miracle, if any, even the most strong, should close up his life with many years and old age. They of America are examples hereof, even in this present age: other nations have been in former ages; which now indeed are become civil and flourishing, but were then few, fierce, short-lived, poor, nasty, and deprived of all that pleasure and beauty of life, which peace and society are wont to bring with them. Whosoever therefore holds, that it had been best to have continued in that state in which all things were lawful for all men, he contradicts himself. For every man by natural necessity desires that which is good for him: nor is there any that esteems a war of all against all, which necessarily adheres to such a state, to be good for him. And so it happens, that through fear of each other we think it fit to rid ourselves of this condition, and to get some fellows; that if there needs must be war, it may not yet be against all men, nor without some helps. [Sidenote: That by the right of nature, it is lawful for any man to compel him whom he hath in his power, to give him caution for his future obedience.] 14. Fellows are gotten either by constraint, or by consent; by constraint, when after fight the conqueror makes the conquered serve him, either through fear of death, or by laying fetters on him: by consent, when men enter into society to help each other, both parties consenting without any constraint. But the conqueror may by right compel the conquered, or the strongest the weaker, (as a man in health may one that is sick, or he that is of riper years a child), unless he will choose to die, to give caution of his future obedience. For since the right of protecting ourselves according to our own wills, proceeded from our danger, and our danger from our equality, it is more consonant to reason, and more certain for our conservation, using the present advantage to secure ourselves by taking caution, than when they shall be full grown and strong, and got out of our power, to endeavour to recover that power again by doubtful fight. And on the other side, nothing can be thought more absurd, than by discharging whom you already have weak in your power, to make him at once both an enemy and a strong one. From whence we may understand likewise as a corollary in the natural state of men, that _a sure and irresistible power confers the right of dominion and ruling over those who cannot resist_; insomuch, as the right of all things that can be done, adheres essentially and immediately unto this omnipotence hence arising. [Sidenote: Nature dictates the seeking after peace.] 15. Yet cannot men expect any lasting preservation, continuing thus in the state of nature, that is, of war, by reason of that equality of power, and other human faculties they are endued withal. Wherefore to seek peace, where there is any hopes of obtaining it, and where there is none, to enquire out for auxiliaries of war, is the dictate of right reason, that is, the law of nature; as shall be showed in the next chapter. ------- CHAPTER II OF THE LAW OF NATURE CONCERNING CONTRACTS. 1. That the law of nature is not an agreement of men, but the dictate of reason. 2. That the fundamental law of nature, is to seek peace, where it may be had, and where not, to defend ourselves. 3. That the first special law of nature, is not to retain our right to all things. 4. What it is to quit our right: what to transfer it. 5. That in the transferring of our right, the will of him that receives it is necessarily required. 6. No words but those of the present tense, transfer any right. 7. Words of the future, if there be some other tokens to signify the will, are valid in the translation of right. 8. In matters of free gift, our right passeth not from us through any words of the future. 9. The definition of contract and compact. 10. In compacts, our right passeth from us through words of the future. 11. Compacts of mutual faith, in the state of nature are of no effect and vain; but not so in civil government. 12. That no man can make compacts with beasts, nor yet with God without revelation. 13. Nor yet make a vow to God. 14. That compacts oblige not beyond our utmost endeavour. 15. By what means we are freed from our compacts. 16. That promises extorted through fear of death, in the state of nature are valid. 17. A later compact contradicting the former, is invalid. 18. A compact not to resist him that shall prejudice my body, is invalid. 19. A compact to accuse one’s self, is invalid. 20. The definition of swearing. 21. That swearing is to be conceived in that form which he useth that takes the oath. 22. An oath superadds nothing to the obligation which is made by compact. 23. An oath ought not to be pressed, but where the breach of compacts may be kept private, or cannot be punished but from God himself. [Sidenote: That the law of nature is not an agreement of men, but the dictate of reason.] 1. All authors agree not concerning the definition of _the natural law_, who notwithstanding do very often make use of this term in their writings. The method therefore wherein we begin from definitions and exclusion of all equivocation, is only proper to them who leave no place for contrary disputes. For the rest, if any man say that somewhat is done against the law of nature, one proves it hence; because it was done against the general agreement of all the most wise and learned nations: but this declares not who shall be the judge of the wisdom and learning of all nations. Another hence, that it was done against the general consent of all mankind; which definition is by no means to be admitted. For then it were impossible for any but children and fools, to offend against such a law; for sure, under the notion of mankind, they comprehend all men actually endued with reason. These therefore either do nought against it, or if they do aught, it is without their own consent, and therefore ought to be excused. But to receive the laws of nature from the consents of them who oftener break than observe them, is in truth unreasonable. Besides, men condemn the same things in others, which they approve in themselves; on the other side, they publicly commend what they privately condemn; and they deliver their opinions more by hearsay, than any speculation of their own; and they accord more through hatred of some object, through fear, hope, love, or some other perturbation of mind, than true reason. And therefore it comes to pass, that whole bodies of people often do those things with the greatest unanimity and earnestness, which those writers most willingly acknowledge to be against the law of nature. But since all do grant, that is done by _right_, which is not done against reason, we ought to judge those actions only _wrong_, which are repugnant to right reason, that is, which contradict some certain truth collected by right reasoning from true principles. But that which is done _wrong_, we say it is done against some law. Therefore _true reason_ is a certain _law_; which, since it is no less a part of human nature, than any other faculty or affection of the mind, is also termed natural. Therefore the _law of nature_, that I may define it, is the dictate of right reason,[4] conversant about those things which are either to be done or omitted for the constant preservation of life and members, as much as in us lies. Footnote 4: _Right reason._] By right reason in the natural state of men, I understand not, as many do, an infallible faculty, but the act of reasoning, that is, the peculiar and true ratiocination of every man concerning those actions of his, which may either redound to the damage or benefit of his neighbours. I call it peculiar, because although in a civil government the reason of the supreme, that is, the civil law, is to be received by each single subject for the right; yet being without this civil government, in which state no man can know right reason from false, but by comparing it with his own, every man’s own reason is to be accounted, not only the rule of his own actions, which are done at his own peril, but also for the measure of another man’s reason, in such things as do concern him. I call it true, that is, concluding from true principles rightly framed, because that the whole breach of the laws of nature consists in the false reasoning, or rather folly of those men, who see not those duties they are necessarily to perform towards others in order to their own conservation. But the principles of right reasoning about such like duties, are those which are explained in the second, third, fourth, fifth, sixth, and seventh articles of the first chapter. [Sidenote: That the fundamental law of nature, is to seek peace where it may be had, and, where not, to defend ourselves.] 2. But the first and fundamental law of nature is, _that peace is to be sought after, where it may be found; and where not, there to provide ourselves for helps of war_. For we showed in the last article of the foregoing chapter, that this precept is the dictate of right reason; but that the dictates of right reason are natural laws, that hath been newly proved above. But this is the first, because the rest are derived from this, and they direct the ways either to peace or self-defence. [Sidenote: The first special law of nature is, that our rights to all things ought not to be retained.] 3. But one of the natural laws derived from this fundamental one is this: _that the right of all men to all things ought not to be retained; but that some certain rights ought to be transferred or relinquished_. For if every one should retain his right to all things, it must necessarily follow, that some by right might invade, and others, by the same right, might defend themselves against them. For every man by natural necessity endeavours to defend his body, and the things which he judgeth necessary towards the protection of his body. Therefore war would follow. He therefore acts against the reason of peace, that is, against the law of nature, whosoever he be, that doth not part with his right to all things. [Sidenote: What it is to quit our right: what to convey it.] 4. But he is said to part with his right, who either absolutely renounceth it, or conveys it to another. He absolutely renounceth it, who by some sufficient sign or meet tokens declares, that he is willing that it shall never be lawful for him to do that again, which before _by right_ he might have done. But he conveys it to another, who by some sufficient sign or meet tokens declares to that other, that he is willing it should be unlawful for him to resist him, in going about to do somewhat in the performance whereof he might before _with right_ have resisted him. But that the conveyance of right consists merely in not resisting, is understood by this, that before it was conveyed, he to whom he conveyed it, had even then also a right to all; whence he could not give any new right; but the resisting right he had before he gave it, by reason whereof the other could not freely enjoy his rights, is utterly abolished. Whosoever therefore acquires some right in the natural state of men, he only procures himself security and freedom from just molestation in the enjoyment of his primitive right. As for example, if any man shall sell or give away a farm, he utterly deprives himself only from all right to this farm; but he does not so others also. [Sidenote: The will of the receiver must necessarily be declared, before the right be conveyed.] 5. But in the conveyance of right, the will is requisite not only of him that conveys, but of him also that accepts it. If either be wanting, the right remains. For if I would have given what was mine to one who refused to accept of it, I have not therefore either simply renounced my right, or conveyed it to any man. For the cause which moved me to part with it to this man, was in him only, not in others too. [Sidenote: Words convey not, except they relate to the time present.] 6. But if there be no other token extant of our will either to quit or convey our right, but only words; those words must either relate to the present or time past; for if they be of the future only, they convey nothing. For example, he that speaks thus of the time to come, _I will give to-morrow_, declares openly that yet he hath not given it. So that all this day his right remains, and abides to-morrow too, unless in the interim he actually bestows it: for what is mine, remains mine till I have parted with it. But if I shall speak of the time present, suppose thus; _I do give or have given you this to be received to-morrow_: by these words is signified that I have already given it, and that his right to receive it to-morrow is conveyed to him by me to-day. [Sidenote: Words of the future suffice to convey, if other testimonies of our will be not wanting.] 7. Nevertheless, although words alone are not sufficient tokens to declare the will; if yet to words relating to the future there shall some other signs be added, they may become as valid as if they had been spoken of the present. If therefore, as by reason of those other signs, it appear that he that speaks of the future, intends those words should be effectual toward the perfect transferring of his right, they ought to be valid. For the conveyance of right depends not on words, but, as hath been instanced in the fourth article, on the declaration of the will. [Sidenote: In matters of free gift, words of the future convey no right.] 8. If any man convey some part of his right to another, and doth not this for some certain benefit received, or for some compact, a conveyance in this kind is called a gift or free donation. But in free donation, those words only oblige us, which signify the present or the time past; for if they respect the future, they oblige not as _words_, for the reason given in the foregoing article. It must needs therefore be, that the obligation arise from some other tokens of the will. But, because whatsoever is voluntarily done, is done for some good to him that wills it; there can no other token be assigned of the will to give it, except some benefit either already received, or to be acquired. But it is supposed that no such benefit is acquired, nor any compact in being; for if so, it would cease to be a free gift. It remains therefore, that a mutual good turn without agreement be expected. But no sign can be given, that he, who used future words toward him who was in no sort engaged to return a benefit, should desire to have his words so understood as to oblige himself thereby. Nor is it suitable to reason, that those who are easily inclined to do well to others, should be obliged by every promise, testifying their present good affection. And for this cause, a promiser in this kind must be understood to have time to deliberate, and power to change that affection, as well as he to whom he made that promise, may alter his desert. But he that deliberates, is so far forth free, nor can be said to have already given. But if he promise often, and yet give seldom, he ought to be condemned of levity, and be called not a donor, but doson. [Sidenote: The definition of contract and covenant.] 9. But the act of two, or more, mutually conveying their rights, is called a _contract_. But in every contract, either both parties instantly perform what they contract for, insomuch as there is no trust had from either to other; or the one performs, the other is trusted; or neither perform. Where both parties perform presently, there the contract is ended as soon as it is performed. But where there is credit given, either to one or both, there the party trusted promiseth after-performance; and this kind of promise is called a _covenant_. [Sidenote: In covenants, we pass away our rights by words signifying the future.] 10. But the covenant made by the party trusted with him who hath already performed, although the promise be made by words pointing at the future, doth no less transfer the right of future time, than if it had been made by words signifying the present or time past. For the other’s performance is a most manifest sign that he so understood the speech of him whom he trusted, as that he would certainly make performance also at the appointed time; and by this sign the party trusted knew himself to be thus understood; which because he hindered not, was an evident token of his will to perform. The promises therefore which are made for some benefit received, which are also covenants, are tokens of the will; that is, as in the foregoing section hath been declared, of the last act of deliberating, whereby the liberty of non-performance is abolished, and by consequence are obligatory. For where liberty ceaseth, there beginneth obligation. [Sidenote: Covenants, in the state of nature, are in vain and of none effect: not so in civil government.] 11. But the covenants which are made in contract of mutual trust, neither party performing out of hand, if there arise[5] a just suspicion in either of them, are in the state of nature invalid. For he that first performs, by reason of the wicked disposition of the greatest part of men studying their own advantage either by right or wrong, exposeth himself to the perverse will of him with whom he hath contracted. For it suits not with reason, that any man should perform first, if it be not likely that the other will make good his promise after; which, whether it be probable or not, he that doubts it must be judge of, as hath been showed in the foregoing chapter in the ninth article. Thus, I say, things stand in the state of nature. But in a civil state, when there is a power which can compel both parties, he that hath contracted to perform first, must first perform; because, that since the other may be compelled, the cause which made him fear the other’s non-performance, ceaseth. Footnote 5: _Arise._] For, except there appear some new cause of fear, either from somewhat done, or some other token of the will not to perform from the other part, it cannot be judged to be a just fear; for the cause which was not sufficient to keep him from making compact, must not suffice to authorize the breach of it, being made. [Sidenote: That no man can make compacts with beasts; neither with God, without revelation.] 12. But from this reason, that in all free gifts and compacts there is an acceptance of the conveyance of right required: it follows that no man can compact with him who doth not declare his acceptance. And therefore we cannot compact with beasts, neither can we give or take from them any manner of right, by reason of their want of speech and understanding. Neither can any man covenant with God, or be obliged to him by vow; except so far forth as it appears to him by Holy Scriptures, that he hath substituted certain men who have authority to accept of such-like vows and covenants, as being in God’s stead. [Sidenote: Nor yet vow to God.] 13. Those therefore do vow in vain, who are in the state of nature, where they are not tied by any civil law, except, by most certain revelation, the will of God to accept their vow or pact, be made known to them. For if what they vow be contrary to the law of nature, they are not tied by their vow; for no man is tied to perform an unlawful act. But if what is vowed, be commanded by some law of nature, it is not their vow, but the law itself which ties them. But if he were free, before his vow, either to do it or not do it, his liberty remains; because that the openly declared will of the obliger is requisite to make an obligation by vow; which, in the case propounded, is supposed not to be. Now I call him the obliger, to whom any one is tied; and the obliged, him who is tied. [Sidenote: Compacts oblige not beyond our utmost endeavours.] 14. Covenants are made of such things only as fall under our deliberation. For it can be no covenant without the will of the contractor. But the will is the last act of him who deliberates; wherefore they only concern things _possible_ and _to come_. No man, therefore, by his compact obligeth himself to an impossibility. But yet, though we often covenant to do such things as then seemed possible when we promised them, which yet afterward appear to be impossible, are we not therefore freed from all obligation. The reason whereof is, that he who promiseth a future, in certainty receives a present benefit, on condition that he return another for it. For his will, who performs the present benefit, hath simply before it for its object a certain good, equally valuable with the thing promised; but the thing itself not simply, but with condition if it could be done. But if it should so happen, that even this should prove impossible, why then he must perform as much as he can. Covenants, therefore, oblige us not to perform just the thing itself covenanted for, but our utmost endeavour; for this only is, the things themselves are not in our power. [Sidenote: In what manner we are freed from compacts.] 15. We are freed from covenants two ways, either by performing, or by being forgiven. By performing, for beyond that we obliged not ourselves. By being forgiven, because he whom we obliged ourselves to, by forgiving is conceived to return us that right which we passed over to him. For forgiving implies giving, that is, by the fourth article of this chapter, a conveyance of right to him to whom the gift is made. [Sidenote: Promises forced from us through fear of death, are valid in the state of nature.] 16. It is a usual question, whether compacts extorted from us through fear, do oblige or not. For example, if, to redeem my life from the power of a robber, I promise to pay him 100_l._ next day, and that I will do no act whereby to apprehend and bring him to justice: whether I am tied to keep promise or not. But though such a promise must sometimes be judged to be of no effect, yet it is not to be accounted so because it proceedeth from fear. For then it would follow, that those promises which reduced men to a civil life, and by which laws were made, might likewise be of none effect; (for it proceeds from fear of mutual slaughter, that one man submits himself to the dominion of another); and he should play the fool finely, who should trust his captive covenanting with the price of his redemption. It holds universally true, that promises do oblige, when there is some benefit received, and when the promise, and the thing promised, be lawful. But it is lawful, for the redemption of my life, both to promise and to give what I will of mine own to any man, even to a thief. We are obliged, therefore, by promises proceeding from fear, except the civil law forbid them; by virtue whereof, that which is promised becomes unlawful. [Sidenote: A latter compact contradicting the former, is invalid.] 17. Whosoever shall contract with one to do or omit somewhat, and shall after covenant the contrary with another, he maketh not the former, but the latter contract unlawful. For he hath no longer right to do or to omit aught, who by former contracts hath conveyed it to another. Wherefore he can convey no right by latter contracts, and what is promised is promised without right. He is therefore tied only to his first contract, to break which is unlawful. [Sidenote: A promise not to resist him that prejudices my body is invalid.] 18. No man is obliged by any contracts whatsoever not to resist him who shall offer to kill, wound, or any other way hurt his body. For there is in every man a certain high degree of fear, through which he apprehends that evil which is done to him to be the greatest; and therefore by natural necessity he shuns it all he can, and it is supposed he can do no otherwise. When a man is arrived to this degree of fear, we cannot expect but he will provide for himself either by flight or fight. Since therefore no man is tied to impossibilities, they who are threatened either with death, (which is the greatest evil to nature), or wounds, or some other bodily hurts, and are not stout enough to bear them, are not obliged to endure them. Furthermore, he that is tied by contract is trusted; for faith only is the bond of contracts; but they who are brought to punishment, either capital or more gentle, are fettered or strongly guarded; which is a most certain sign that they seemed not sufficiently bound from non-resistance by their contracts. It is one thing, if I promise thus: if I do it not at the day appointed, kill me. Another thing, if thus: if I do it not, though you should offer to kill me, I will not resist. All men, if need be, contract the first way, and there is need sometimes. This second way, none; neither is it ever needful. For in the mere state of nature, if you have a mind to kill, that state itself affords you a right; insomuch as you need not first trust him, if for breach of trust you will afterwards kill him. But in a civil state, where the right of life and death and of all corporal punishment is with the supreme, that same right of killing cannot be granted to any private person. Neither need the supreme himself contract with any man patiently to yield to his punishment; but only this, that no man offer to defend others from him. If in the state of nature, as between two realms, there should a contract be made on condition of killing if it were not performed, we must presuppose another contract of not killing before the appointed day. Wherefore on that day, if there be no performance, the right of war returns, that is a hostile state, in which all things are lawful, and therefore resistance also. Lastly, by the contract of not resisting, we are obliged, of two evils to make choice of that which seems the greater. For certain death is a greater evil than fighting. But of two evils it is impossible not to choose the least. By such a compact, therefore, we should be tied to impossibilities; which is contrary to the very nature of compacts. [Sidenote: The compact of self-accusation is invalid.] 19. Likewise no man is tied by any compacts whatsoever to accuse himself, or any other, by whose damage he is like to procure himself a bitter life. Wherefore neither is a father obliged to bear witness against his son, nor a husband against his wife, nor a son against his father, nor any man against any one by whose means he hath his subsistence; for in vain is that testimony which is presumed to be corrupted from nature. But although no man be tied to accuse himself by any compact, yet in a public trial he may by torture be forced to make answer. But such answers are no testimony of the fact, but helps for the searching out of truth; so that whether the party tortured his answer be true or false, or whether he answer not at all, whatsoever he doth, he doth it by right. [Sidenote: The definition of an oath.] 20. Swearing is a speech joined to a promise, whereby the promiser declares his renouncing of God’s mercy, unless he perform his word. Which definition is contained in the words themselves, which have in them the very essence of an oath, to wit, _so God help me_, or other equivalent, as with the Romans, _do thou Jupiter so destroy the deceiver, as I slay this same beast_. Neither is this any let, but that an oath may as well sometimes be affirmatory as promissory; for he that confirms his affirmation with an oath, promiseth that he speaks truth. But though in some places it was the fashion for subjects to swear by their kings, that custom took its original hence, that those kings took upon them divine honour. For oaths were therefore introduced, that by religion and consideration of the divine power, men might have a greater dread of breaking their faiths, than that wherewith they fear men, from whose eyes their actions may lie hid. [Sidenote: The swearing must be conceived in that fashion which he uses who takes it.] 21. Whence it follows that an oath must be conceived in that form, which he useth who takes it; for in vain is any man brought to swear by a God whom he believes not, and therefore neither fears him. For though by the light of nature it may be known that there is a God, yet no man thinks he is to swear by him in any other fashion, or by any other name, than what is contained in the precepts of his own proper, that is (as he who swears imagines) the true religion. [Sidenote: Swearing adds nothing to the obligation which is by compact.] 22. By the definition of an oath, we may understand that a bare contract obligeth no less, than that to which we are sworn. For it is the contract which binds us; the oath relates to the divine punishment, which it could not provoke, if the breach of contract were not in itself unlawful; but it could not be unlawful, if the contract were not obligatory. Furthermore, he that renounceth the mercy of God, obligeth himself not to any punishment; because it is ever lawful to deprecate the punishment, howsoever provoked, and to enjoy God’s pardon if it be granted. The only effect therefore of an oath is this; to cause men, who are naturally inclined to break all manner of faith, through fear of punishment to make the more conscience of their words and actions. [Sidenote: An oath is not to be pressed, but where the breach of contract can either be kept private, or not be punished but from God alone.] 23. To exact an oath where the breach of contract, if any be made, cannot but be known, and where the party compacted withal wants not power to punish, is to do somewhat more than is necessary unto self-defence, and shews a mind desirous not so much to benefit itself, as to prejudice another. For an oath, out of the very form of swearing, is taken in order to the provocation of God’s anger, that is to say, of him that is omnipotent, against those who therefore violate their faith, because they think that by their own strength they can escape the punishment of men; and of him that is omniscient, against those who therefore usually break their trust, because they hope that no man shall see them. ------- CHAPTER III. OF THE OTHER LAWS OF NATURE. 1. The second law of nature, is to perform contracts. 2. That trust is to be held with all men without exception. 3. What injury is. 4. Injury can be done to none but those with whom we contract. 5. The distinction of justice into that of men, and that of actions. 6. The distinction of commutative and distributive justice examined. 7. No injury can be done to him that is willing. 8. The third law of nature, concerning ingratitude. 9. The fourth law of nature, that every man render himself useful. 10. The fifth law, of mercy. 11. The sixth law, that punishments regard the future only. 12. The seventh law, against reproach. 13. The eighth law, against pride. 14. The ninth law, of humility. 15. The tenth, of equity, or against acceptance of persons. 16. The eleventh, of things to be had in common. 17. The twelfth, of things to be divided by lot. 18. The thirteenth, of birthright and first possession. 19. The fourteenth, of the safeguard of them who are mediators for peace. 20. The fifteenth, of constituting an umpire. 21. The sixteenth, that no man is judge in his own cause. 22. The seventeenth, that umpires must be without all hope of reward from those whose cause is to be judged. 23. The eighteenth, of witnesses. 24. The nineteenth, that there can no contract be made with the umpire. 25. The twentieth, against gluttony, and all such things as hinder the use of reason. 26. The rule by which we may presently know, whether what we are doing be against the law of nature or not. 27. The laws of nature oblige only in the court of conscience. 28. The laws of nature are sometimes broke by doing things agreeable to those laws. 29. The laws of nature are unchangeable. 30. Whosoever endeavours to fulfil the laws of nature, is a just man. 31. The natural and moral law are one. 32. How it comes to pass, that what hath been said of the laws of nature, is not the same with what philosophers have delivered concerning the virtues. 33. The law of nature is not properly a law, but as it is delivered in Holy Writ. [Sidenote: The second law of nature, to perform contracts.] 1. Another of the laws of nature is, to _perform contracts_, or _to keep trust_. For it hath been showed in the foregoing chapter, that the law of nature commands every man, as a thing necessary, to obtain peace, to convey certain rights from each to other; and that this, as often as it shall happen to be done, is called a contract. But this is so far forth only conducible to peace, as we shall perform ourselves what we contract with others shall be done or omitted; and in vain would contacts be made, unless we stood to them. Because therefore to stand to our covenants, or to keep faith, is a thing necessary for the obtaining of peace; it will prove, by the second article of the second chapter, to be a precept of the natural law. [Sidenote: That faith is to be kept with all men without exception.] 2. Neither is there in this matter any exception of the persons with whom we contract; as if they keep no faith with others, or hold that none ought to be kept, or are guilty of any other kind of vice. For he that contracts, in that he doth contract, denies that action to be in vain; and it is against reason for a knowing man to do a thing in vain; and if he think himself not bound to keep it, in thinking so he affirms the contract to be made in vain. He therefore who contracts with one with whom he thinks he is not bound to keep faith, he doth at once think a contract to be a thing done in vain, and not in vain; which is absurd. Either therefore we must hold trust with all men, or else not bargain with them; that is, either there must be a declared war, or a sure and faithful peace. [Sidenote: Injury defined.] 3. The breaking of a bargain, as also the taking back of a gift, (which ever consists in some action or omission), is called an injury. But that action or omission is called unjust; insomuch as an injury, and an unjust action or omission, signify the same thing, and both are the same with breach of contract and trust. And it seems the word _injury_ came to be given to any action or omission, because they were _without right_; he that acted or omitted, having before conveyed his right to some other. And there is some likeness between that which in the common course of life we call _injury_, and that which in the Schools is usually called _absurd_. For even as he who by arguments is driven to deny the assertion which he first maintained, is said to be brought to an absurdity; in like manner, he who through weakness of mind does or omits that which before he had by contract promised not to do or omit, commits an injury, and falls into no less contradiction than he who in the Schools is reduced to an absurdity. For by contracting for some future action, he wills it done; by not doing it, he wills it not done: which is to will a thing done and not done at the same time, which is a contradiction. An injury therefore is a kind of absurdity in conversation, as an absurdity is a kind of injury in disputation. [Sidenote: An injury can only be done to him with whom we contract.] 4. From these grounds it follows, that an injury can be done to no man[6] but him with whom we enter covenant, or to whom somewhat is made over by deed of gift, or to whom somewhat is promised by way of bargain. And therefore damaging and injuring are often disjoined. For if a master command his servant, who hath promised to obey him, to pay a sum of money, or carry some present to a third man; the servant, if he do it not, hath indeed damaged this third party, but he injured his master only. So also in a civil government, if any man offend another with whom he hath made no contract, he damages him to whom the evil is done; but he injures none but him to whom the power of government belongs. For if he who receives the hurt should expostulate the mischief, he that did it should answer thus: _what art thou to me; why should I rather do according to your than mine own will, since I do not hinder but you may do your own, and not my mind?_ In which speech, where there hath no manner of pre-contract passed, I see not, I confess, what is reprehensible. Footnote 6: _Injury can be done to no man, &c._] The word _injustice_ relates to some law: _injury_, to some person, as well as some law. For what is unjust, is unjust to all; but there may an injury be done, and yet not against me, nor thee, but some other; and sometimes against no private person, but the magistrate only; sometimes also neither against the magistrate, nor any private man, but only against God. For through contract and conveyance of right, we say, that an injury is done against this or that man. Hence it is, which we see in all kind of government, that what private men contract between themselves by word or writing, is released again at the will of the obliger. But those mischiefs which are done against the laws of the land, as theft, homicide, and the like, are punished, not as he wills to whom the hurt is done, but according to the will of the magistrate; that is, the constituted laws. [Sidenote: The distinction of justice into that of men and actions.] 5. These words, _just_ and _unjust_, as also _justice_ and _injustice_, are equivocal; for they signify one thing when they are attributed to persons, another when to actions. When they are attributed to actions, _just_ signifies as much as what is done with right, and _unjust_, as what is done with injury. He who hath done some just thing, is not therefore said to be a _just_ person, but _guiltless_; and he that hath done some unjust thing, we do not therefore say he is an _unjust_, but _guilty_ man. But when the words are applied to persons, _to be just_ signifies as much as to be delighted in just dealing, to study how to do righteousness, or to endeavour in all things to do that which is just; and _to be unjust_ is to neglect righteous dealing, or to think it is to be measured not according to my contract, but some present benefit. So as the justice or injustice of the mind, the intention, or the man, is one thing, that of an action or omission another; and innumerable actions of a just man may be unjust, and of an unjust man, just. But that man is to be accounted just, who doth just things because the law commands it, unjust things only by reason of his infirmity; and he is properly said to be unjust, who doth righteousness for fear of the punishment annexed unto the law, and unrighteousness by reason of the iniquity of his mind. [Sidenote: The distinction of commutative and distributive justice, examined.] 6. The justice of actions is commonly distinguished into two kinds, commutative and distributive; the former whereof, they say, consists in arithmetical, the latter in geometrical proportion; and that is conversant in exchanging, in buying, selling, borrowing, lending, location and conduction, and other acts whatsoever belonging to contractors; where, if there be an equal return made, hence, they say, springs a commutative justice: but this is busied about the dignity and merits of men; so as if there be rendered to every man κατὰ τὴν ἀξίαν, more to him who is more worthy, and less to him that deserves less, and that proportionably; hence, they say, ariseth distributive justice. I acknowledge here some certain distinction of equality: to wit, that one is an equality simply so called; as when two things of equal value are compared together, as a pound of silver with twelve ounces of the same silver: the other is an equality _secundum quod_; as when a thousand pounds is to be divided to a hundred men, six hundred pounds are given to sixty men, and four hundred to forty, where there is no equality between six hundred and four hundred; but when it happens that there is the same inequality in the number of them to whom it is distributed, every one of them shall take an equal part, whence it is called an equal distribution. But such like equality is the same thing with geometrical proportion. But what is all this to justice? For neither if I sell my goods for as much as I can get for them, do I injure the buyer, who sought and desired them of me; neither if I divide more of what is mine to him who deserves less, so long as I give the other what I have agreed for, do I wrong to either. Which truth our Saviour himself, being God, testifies in the Gospel. This therefore is no distinction of justice, but of equality. Yet perhaps it cannot be denied but that justice is a certain equality, as consisting in this only; that since we are all equal by nature, one should not arrogate more right to himself than he grants to another, unless he have fairly gotten it by compact. And let this suffice to be spoken against this distinction of justice, although now almost generally received by all; lest any man should conceive an injury to be somewhat else than the breach of faith or contract, as hath been defined above. [Sidenote: No injury can be done to him that is willing.] 7. It is an old saying, _volenti non fit injuria_, the willing man receives no injury; yet the truth of it may be derived from our principles. For grant that a man be willing that that should be done which he conceives to be an injury to him; why then, that is done by his will, which by contract was not lawful to be done. But he being willing that should be done which was not lawful by contract, the contract itself (by the fifteenth article of the foregoing chapter) becomes void. The right therefore of doing it returns; therefore it is done by right; wherefore it is no injury. [Sidenote: The third law of nature, of ingratitude.] 8. The third precept of the natural law is, _that you suffer not him to be the worse for you, who, out of the confidence he had in you, first did you a good turn; or that you accept not a gift, but with a mind to endeavour that the giver shall have no just occasion to repent him of his gift_. For without this, he should act without reason, that would confer a benefit where he sees it would be lost; and by this means all beneficence and trust, together with all kind of benevolence, would be taken from among men, neither would there be aught of mutual assistance among them, nor any commencement of gaining grace and favour; by reason whereof the state of war would necessarily remain, contrary to the fundamental law of nature. But because the breach of this law is not a breach of trust or contract, (for we suppose no contracts to have passed among them), therefore is it not usually termed an injury; but because good turns and thanks have a mutual eye to each other, it is called _ingratitude_. [Sidenote: The fourth law of nature, that every man render himself useful.] 9. The fourth precept of nature is, _that every man render himself useful unto others_: which that we may rightly understand, we must remember that there is in men a diversity of dispositions to enter into society, arising from the diversity of their affections, not unlike that which is found in stones, brought together in the building, by reason of the diversity of their matter and figure. For as a stone, which in regard of its sharp and angular form takes up more room from other stones than it fills up itself, neither because of the hardness of its matter can it well be pressed together, or easily cut, and would hinder the building from being fitly compacted, is cast away, as not fit for use: so a man, for the harshness of his disposition in retaining superfluities for himself, and detaining of necessaries from others, and being incorrigible by reason of the stubbornness of his affections, is commonly said to be useless and troublesome unto others. Now, because each one not by right only, but even by natural necessity, is supposed with all his main might to intend the procurement of those things which are necessary to his own preservation; if any man will contend on the other side for superfluities, by his default there will arise a war; because that on him alone there lay no necessity of contending; he therefore acts against the fundamental law of nature. Whence it follows, (which we were to show), that it is a precept of nature, that every man accommodate himself to others. But he who breaks this law may be called _useless_ and troublesome. Yet Cicero opposeth _inhumanity_ to this _usefulness_, as having regard to this very law. [Sidenote: The fifth law of nature, of mercifulness.] 10. The fifth precept of the law of nature is, _that we must forgive him who repents and asks pardon for what is past, having first taken caution for the time to come_. The pardon of what is past, or the remission of an offence, is nothing else but the granting of peace to him that asketh it, after he hath warred against us, and now is become penitent. But peace granted to him that repents not, that is, to him that retains a hostile mind, or that gives not caution for the future, that is, seeks not peace, but opportunity; is not properly peace, but fear, and therefore is not commanded by nature. Now to him that will not pardon the penitent and that gives future caution, peace itself it seems is not pleasing: which is contrary to the natural law. [Sidenote: The sixth law, that punishments only regard the future.] 11. The sixth precept of the natural law is, _that in revenge and punishments we must have our eye not at the evil past, but the future good_: that is, it is not lawful to inflict punishment for any other end, but that the offender may be corrected, or that others warned by his punishment may become better. But this is confirmed chiefly from hence, that each man is bound by the law of nature to forgive one another, provided he give caution for the future, as hath been showed in the foregoing article. Furthermore, because revenge, if the time past be only considered, is nothing else but a certain triumph and glory of mind, which points at no end; for it contemplates only what is past, but the end is a thing to come; but that which is directed to no end, is vain: that revenge therefore which regards not the future, proceeds from vain glory, and is therefore without reason. But to hurt another without reason, introduces a war, and is contrary to the fundamental law of nature. It is therefore a precept of the law of nature, that in revenge we look not backwards, but forward. Now the breach of this law is commonly called _cruelty_. [Sidenote: The seventh law of nature, against slander.] 12. But because all signs of hatred and contempt provoke most of all to brawling and fighting, insomuch as most men would rather lose their lives (that I say not, their peace) than suffer slander; it follows in the seventh place, that it is prescribed by the law of nature, that no man, either by deeds or words, countenance or laughter, _do declare himself to hate or scorn another_. The breach of which law is called _reproach_. But although nothing be more frequent than the scoffs and jeers of the powerful against the weak, and namely, of judges against guilty persons, which neither relate to the offence of the guilty, nor the duty of the judges; yet these kind of men do act against the law of nature, and are to be esteemed for contumelious. [Sidenote: The eighth law, against pride.] 13. The question whether of two men be the more worthy, belongs not to the natural, but civil state. For it hath been showed before (Chap. I. Art. 3) that all men by nature are equal; and therefore the inequality which now is, suppose from riches, power, nobility of kindred, is come from the civil law. I know that Aristotle, in his first book of Politics, affirms as a foundation of the whole political science, that some men by nature are made worthy to command, others only to serve; as if lord and servant were distinguished not by consent of men, but by an aptness, that is, a certain kind of natural knowledge or ignorance. Which foundation is not only against reason, (as but now hath been showed), but also against experience. For neither almost is any man so dull of understanding as not to judge it better to be ruled by himself, than to yield himself to the government of another; neither if the wiser and stronger do contest, have these always or often the upper hand of those. Whether therefore men be equal by nature, the equality is to be acknowledged; or whether unequal, because they are like to contest for dominion, it is necessary for the obtaining of peace, _that they be esteemed as equal_; and therefore it is in the eighth place a precept of the law of nature, _that every man be accounted by nature equal to another_; the contrary to which law is _pride_. [Sidenote: The ninth law, of humility.] 14. As it was necessary to the conservation of each man that he should part with some of his rights, so it is no less necessary to the same conservation that he retain some others, to wit, the right of bodily protection, of free enjoyment of air, water, and all necessaries for life. Since therefore many common rights are retained by those who enter into a peaceable state, and that many peculiar ones are also acquired, hence ariseth this ninth dictate of the natural law, to wit, that what rights soever any man challenges to himself, he also grant the same as due to all the rest; otherwise he frustrates the equality acknowledged in the former article. For what is it else to acknowledge an equality of persons in the making up of society, but to attribute equal right and power to those whom no reason would else engage to enter into society? But to ascribe _equal things to equals_, is the same with giving things _proportional_ to _proportionals_. The observation of this law is called _meekness_, the violation πλεονεξὶα; the breakers by the Latins are styled _immodici et immodesti_. [Sidenote: The tenth law of equity, or against acceptance of persons.] 15. In the tenth place it is commanded by the law of nature, _that every man in dividing right to others, shew himself equal to either party_. By the foregoing law we are forbidden to assume more right by nature to ourselves, than we grant to others. We may take less if we will; for that sometimes is an argument of modesty. But if at any time matter of right be to be divided by us unto others, we are forbidden by this law to favour one more or less than another. For he that by favouring one before another observes not this natural equality, reproaches him whom he thus undervalues: but it is declared above, that a reproach is against the laws of nature. The observance of this precept is called _equity_; the breach, _respect of persons_. The Greeks in one word term it προσωποληψία. [Sidenote: The eleventh law, of things to be had in common.] 16. From the foregoing law is collected this eleventh, _those things which cannot be divided, must be used in common if they can, and if the quantity of the matter permit, every man as much as he lists; but if the quantity permit not, then with limitation, and proportionally to the number of the users_. For otherwise that equality can by no means be observed, which we have showed in the foregoing article to be commanded by the law of nature. [Sidenote: The twelfth law, of things to be divided by lot.] 17. Also what cannot be divided nor had in common, it is provided by the law of nature, which may be the twelfth precept, _that the use of that thing be either by turns, or adjudged to one only by lot; and that in the using it by turns, it be also decided by lot, who shall have the first use of it_. For here also regard is to be had unto equality: but no other can be found but that of lot. [Sidenote: The thirteenth law, of birthright and first possession.] 18. But all lot is twofold, _arbitrary_ or _natural_. _Arbitrary_ is that which is cast by the consent of the contenders, and it consists in mere chance, as they say, or fortune. _Natural_ is primogeniture, in Greek κληρονομια, as it were, given by lot; or first possession. Therefore the things which can neither be divided nor had in common, must be granted to the first possessor; as also those things which belonged to the father are due to the son, unless the father himself have formerly conveyed away that right to some other. Let this therefore stand for the thirteenth law of nature. [Sidenote: The fourteenth law, of the safety of those who are mediators for peace.] 19. The fourteenth precept of the law of nature is, _that safety must be assured to the mediators for peace_. For the reason which commands the end, commands also the means necessary to the end. But the first dictate of reason is peace; all the rest are means to obtain it, and without which peace cannot be had. But neither can peace be had without mediation, nor mediation without safety. It is therefore a dictate of reason, that is, a law of nature, that we must give all security to the mediators for peace. [Sidenote: The fifteenth law, of appointing an umpire.] 20. Furthermore because, although men should agree to make all these and whatsoever other laws of nature, and should endeavour to keep them, yet doubts and controversies would daily arise concerning the application of them unto their actions, to wit, whether what was done were against the law or not, which we call the question of right; whence will follow a fight between parties, either-sides supposing themselves wronged: it is therefore necessary to the preservation of peace, because in this case no other fit remedy can possibly be thought on, that both the disagreeing parties refer the matter unto some third, and oblige themselves by mutual compacts to stand to his judgment in deciding the controversy. And he to whom they thus refer themselves, is called an arbiter. It is therefore the fifteenth precept of the natural law, _that both parties disputing concerning the matter of right, submit themselves unto the opinion and judgment of some third_. [Sidenote: The sixteenth law, that no man be judge in his own cause.] 21. But from this ground, that an arbiter or judge is chosen by the differing parties to determine the controversy, we gather that the arbiter must not be one of the parties. For every man is presumed to seek what is good for himself naturally, and what is just only for peace sake and accidentally; and therefore cannot observe that same equality commanded by the law of nature, so exactly as a third man would do. It is therefore in the sixteenth place contained in the law of nature, _that no man must be judge or arbiter in his own cause_. [Sidenote: The seventeenth law, that arbiters must be without all hope of reward from the parties whose cause is to be judged.] 22. From the same ground follows in the seventeenth place, _that no man must be judge, who propounds unto himself any hope of profit or glory from the victory of either part_: for the like reason sways here, as in the foregoing law. [Sidenote: The eighteenth law, of witnesses.] 23. But when there is some controversy of the fact itself, to wit, whether that be done or not which is said to be done, the natural law wills that the arbiter trust both parties alike, that is, because they affirm contradictories, that he believe neither. He must therefore give credit to a third, or a third and fourth, or more, that he may be able to give judgment of the fact, as often as by other signs he cannot come to the knowledge of it. The eighteenth law of nature therefore enjoins arbiters and judges of fact, _that where firm and certain signs of the fact appear not, there they rule their sentence by such witnesses as seem to be indifferent to both parts_. [Sidenote: The nineteenth law, that no contract is to be made with the judge.] 24. From the above declared definition of an arbiter may be furthermore understood, _that no contract or promise must pass between him and the parties whose judge he is appointed, by virtue whereof he may be engaged to speak in favour of either part, nay, or be obliged to judge according to equity, or to pronounce such sentence as he shall truly judge to be equal_. The judge is indeed bound to give such sentence as he shall judge to be equal, by the law of nature recounted in the 15th article: to the obligation of which law nothing can be added by way of compact. Such compact therefore would be in vain. Besides, if giving wrong judgment he should contend for the equity of it, except such compact be of no force, the controversy would remain after judgment given: which is contrary to the constitution of an arbiter, who is so chosen, as both parties have obliged themselves to stand to the judgment which he should pronounce. The law of nature therefore commands the judge to be disengaged, which is its nineteenth precept. [Sidenote: The twentieth law, against gluttony and such things as hinder the use of reason.] 25. Furthermore, forasmuch as the laws of nature are nought else but the dictates of reason; so as, unless a man endeavour to preserve the faculty of right reasoning, he cannot observe the laws of nature; it is manifest, that he who knowingly or willingly doth aught whereby the rational faculty may be destroyed or weakened, he knowingly and willingly breaks the law of nature. For there is no difference between a man who performs not his duty, and him who does such things willingly as make it impossible for him to do it. But they destroy and weaken the reasoning faculty, who do that which disturbs the mind from its natural state; that which most manifestly happens to drunkards, and gluttons. We therefore sin, in the twentieth place, against the law of nature by drunkenness. [Sidenote: The rule by which a man may presently know, whether what he is about to act be against the law of nature or not.] 26. Perhaps some man, who sees all these precepts of nature derived by a certain artifice from the single dictate of reason advising us to look to the preservation and safeguard of ourselves, will say that the deduction of these laws is so hard, that it is not to be expected they will be vulgarly known, and therefore neither will they prove obliging: for laws, if they be not known, oblige not, nay indeed, are not laws. To this I answer, it is true, that hope, fear, anger, ambition, covetousness, vain glory, and other perturbations of mind, do hinder a man, so as he cannot attain to the knowledge of these laws whilst those passions prevail in him: but there is no man who is not sometimes in a quiet mind. At that time therefore there is nothing easier for him to know, though he be never so rude and unlearned, than this only rule, that when he doubts whether what he is now doing to another may be done by the law of nature or not, he conceive himself to be in that other’s stead. Here instantly those perturbations which persuaded him to the fact, being now cast into the other scale, dissuade him as much. And this rule is not only easy, but is anciently celebrated in these words, _quod tibi fieri non vis, alteri ne feceris_: _do not that to others, you would not have done to yourself_. [Sidenote: The laws of nature oblige only in the court of conscience.] 27. But because most men, by reason of their perverse desire of present profit, are very unapt to observe these laws, although acknowledged by them; if perhaps some, more humble than the rest, should exercise that equity and usefulness which reason dictates, the others not practising the same, surely they would not follow reason in so doing: nor would they hereby procure themselves peace, but a more certain quick destruction, and the keepers of the law become a mere prey to the breakers of it. It is not therefore to be imagined, that by nature, that is, by reason, men are obliged to the exercise of all these laws[7] in that state of men wherein they are not practised by others. We are obliged yet, in the interim, to a readiness of mind to observe them, whensoever their observation shall seem to conduce to the end for which they were ordained. We must therefore conclude, that the law of nature doth always and everywhere oblige in the internal court, or that of conscience; but not always in the external court, but then only when it may be done with safety. Footnote 7: _The exercise of all these laws._ Nay, among these laws some things there are, the omission whereof, provided it be done for peace or self-preservation, seems rather to be the fulfilling, than breach of the natural law. For he that doth all things against those that do all things, and plunders plunderers, doth equity. But on the contrary, to do that which in peace is a handsome action, and becoming an honest man, is dejectedness and poorness of spirit, and a betraying of one’s self, in the time of war. But there are certain natural laws, whose exercise ceaseth not even in the time of war itself. For I cannot understand what drunkenness or cruelty, that is, revenge which respects not the future good, can advance toward peace, or the preservation of any man. Briefly, in the state of nature, what is just and unjust, is not to be esteemed by the actions but by the counsel and conscience of the actor. That which is done out of necessity, out of endeavour for peace, for the preservation of ourselves, is done with right, otherwise every damage done to a man would be a breach of the natural law, and an injury against God. [Sidenote: The laws of nature are sometimes broken by an act agreeable to those laws.] 28. But the laws which oblige conscience, may be broken by an act not only contrary to them, but also agreeable with them; if so be that he who does it, be of another opinion. For though the act itself be answerable to the laws, yet his conscience is against them. [Sidenote: The laws of nature are immutable and eternal.] 29. _The laws of nature are immutable and eternal_: what they forbid, can never be lawful; what they command, can never be unlawful. For _pride_, _ingratitude_, _breach of contracts_ (or _injury_), _inhumanity_, _contumely_, will never be lawful, nor the contrary virtues to these ever unlawful, as we take them for dispositions of the mind, that is, as they are considered in the court of conscience, where only they oblige and are laws. Yet actions may be so diversified by circumstances and the civil law, that what is done with equity at one time, is guilty of iniquity at another; and what suits with reason at one time, is contrary to it another. Yet reason is still the same, and changeth not her end, which is peace and defence, nor the means to attain them, to wit, those virtues of the mind which we have declared above, and which cannot be abrogated by any custom or law whatsoever. [Sidenote: He who endeavours to fulfil the laws of nature, is just.] 30. It is evident by what hath hitherto been said, how easily the laws of nature are to be observed, because they require the endeavour only, (but that must be true and constant); which whoso shall perform, we may rightly call him _just_. For he who tends to this with his whole might, namely, that his actions be squared according to the precepts of nature, he shows clearly that he hath a mind to fulfil all those laws; which is all we are obliged to by rational nature. Now he that hath done all he is obliged to, is a just man. [Sidenote: The natural law is the same with the moral.] 31. All writers do agree, that the natural law is the same with the moral. Let us see wherefore this is true. We must know, therefore, that good and evil are names given to things to signify the inclination or aversion of them, by whom they were given. But the inclinations of men are diverse, according to their diverse constitutions, customs, opinions; as we may see in those things we apprehend by sense, as by tasting, touching, smelling; but much more in those which pertain to the common actions of life, where what this man commends, that is to say, calls _good_, the other undervalues, as being evil. Nay, very often the same man at diverse times praises and dispraises the same thing. Whilst thus they do, necessary it is there should be discord and strife. They are, therefore, so long in the state of war, as by reason of the diversity of the present appetite, they mete good and evil by diverse measures. All men easily acknowledge this state, as long as they are in it, to be evil, and by consequence that peace is good. They therefore who could not agree concerning a present, do agree concerning a future good; which indeed is a work of reason; for things present are obvious to the sense, things to come to our reason only. Reason declaring peace to be good, it follows by the same reason, that all the necessary means to peace be good also; and therefore that modesty, equity, trust, humanity, mercy, (which we have demonstrated to be necessary to peace), are good manners or habits, that is, virtues. The law therefore, in the means to peace, commands also good manners, or the practice of virtue; and therefore it is called _moral_. [Sidenote: Whence it comes to pass, that what hath been said concerning the law, is not the same with what hath been delivered by philosophers concerning the virtues.] 32. But because men cannot put off this same irrational appetite, whereby they greedily prefer the present good (to which, by strict consequence, many unforseen evils do adhere) before the future; it happens, that though all men do agree in the commendation of the foresaid virtues, yet they disagree still concerning their nature, to wit, in what each of them doth consist. For as oft as another’s good action displeaseth any man, that action hath the name given of some neighbouring vice; likewise the bad actions which please them, are ever intituled to some virtue. Whence it comes to pass that the same action is praised by these, and called virtue, and dispraised by those, and termed vice. Neither is there as yet any remedy found by philosophers for this matter. For since they could not observe the goodness of actions to consist in this, that it was in order to peace, and the evil in this, that it related to discord, they built a moral philosophy wholly estranged from the moral law, and unconstant to itself. For they would have the nature of virtues seated in a certain kind of mediocrity between two extremes, and the vices in the extremes themselves; which is apparently false. For _to dare_ is commended, and, under the name of _fortitude_ is taken for a virtue, although it be an extreme, if the cause be approved. Also the quantity of a thing given, whether it be great or little, or between both, makes not liberality, but the cause of giving it. Neither is it injustice, if I give any man more of what is mine own than I owe him. The laws of nature, therefore, are the sum of _moral_ philosophy; whereof I have only delivered such precepts in this place, as appertain to the preservation of ourselves against those dangers which arise from discord. But there are other precepts of _rational_ nature, from whence spring other virtues; for temperance, also, is a precept of reason, because intemperance tends to sickness and death. And so fortitude too, that is, that same faculty of resisting stoutly in present dangers, and which are more hardly declined than overcome; because it is a means tending to the preservation of him that resists. [Sidenote: The law of nature is not properly a law, but as it is delivered in Holy Scripture.] 33. But those which we call the laws of nature, (since they are nothing else but certain conclusions, understood by reason, of things to be done and omitted; but a law, to speak properly and accurately, is the speech of him who by right commands somewhat to others to be done or omitted), are not in propriety of speech laws, as they proceed from nature. Yet, as they are delivered by God in holy Scriptures, as we shall see in the chapter following, they are most properly called by the name of laws. For the sacred Scripture is the speech of God commanding over all things by greatest right. ------- CHAPTER IV. THAT THE LAW OF NATURE IS A DIVINE LAW. 1. The natural and moral law is divine. 2. Which is confirmed in Scripture, in general. 3. Specially, in regard of the fundamental law of nature in seeking of peace. 4. Also in regard of the first law of nature in abolishing all things to be had in common. 5. Also of the second law of nature, concerning faith to be kept. 6. Also of the third law, of thankfulness. 7. Also of the fourth law, of rendering ourselves useful. 8. Also of the fifth law, concerning mercy. 9. Also of the sixth law, that punishment only looks at the future. 10. Also of the seventh law, concerning slander. 11. Also of the eighth law, against pride. 12. Also of the ninth law, of equity. 13. Also of the tenth law, against respect of persons. 14. Also of the eleventh law, of having those things in common which cannot be divided. 15. Also of the twelfth law, of things to be divided by lot. 16. Also of appointing a judge. 17. Also of the seventeenth law, that the arbiters must receive no reward for their sentence. 18. Also of the eighteenth law, concerning witnesses. 19. Also of the twentieth law, against drunkenness. 20. Also in respect of that which hath been said, that the law of nature is eternal. 21. Also that the laws of nature do pertain to conscience. 22. Also that the laws of nature are easily observed. 23. Lastly, in respect of the rule by which a man may presently know, whether what he is about to act, be against the law of nature, or not. 24. The law of Christ is the law of nature. [Sidenote: The natural and moral law is divine.] 1. The same law which is _natural_ and _moral_, is also wont to be called _divine_, nor undeservedly; as well because reason, which is the law of nature, is given by God to every man for the rule of his actions; as because the precepts of living which are thence derived, are the same with those which have been delivered from the divine Majesty for the _laws_ of his heavenly kingdom, by our Lord Jesus Christ, and his holy prophets and apostles. What therefore by reasoning we have understood above concerning the law of nature, we will endeavour to confirm the same in this chapter by holy writ. [Sidenote: Which is confirmed in Scripture, in general.] 2. But first we will shew those places in which it is declared, that the divine law is seated in right reason. Psalm xxxvii. 30, 31: _The mouth of the righteous will be exercised in wisdom, and his tongue will be talking of judgment: the law of God is in his heart._ Jeremiah xxx. 33: _I will put my law in their inward parts, and write it in their hearts._ Psalm xix. 7: _The law of the Lord is an undefiled law, converting the soul._ Verse 8: _The commandment of the Lord is pure, and giveth light unto the eyes._ Deuteron. xxx. 11: _This commandment, which I command thee this day, it is not hidden from thee, neither is it far off, &c._ Verse. 14: _But the word is very nigh unto thee in my mouth, and in thine heart, that thou mayest do it._ Psalm cxix. 34: _Give me understanding, and I shall keep thy law._ Verse 105: _Thy word is a lamp unto my feet, and a light unto my paths._ Prov. ix. 10: _The knowledge of the holy is understanding._ Christ the law-giver, himself is called (John i. 1): _the word_. The same Christ is called (verse 9): _the true light, that lighteth every man that cometh in the world_. All which are descriptions of right reason, whose dictates, we have showed before, are the laws of nature. [Sidenote: Specially in regard of the fundamental law of nature in seeking of peace.] 3. But that that which we set down for the fundamental law of nature, namely, that peace was to be sought for, is also the sum of the Divine law, will be manifest by these places. Rom. iii. 17: _Righteousness_, which is the sum of the law, is called _the way of peace_. Psalm lxxxv. 10: _Righteousness and peace have kissed each other._ Matth. v. 9: _Blessed are the peace-makers, for they shall be called the children of God._ And after St. Paul, in his sixth chapter to the Hebrews, and the last verse, had called Christ (the legislator of that law we treat of), _an High-priest for ever after the order of Melchisedec_: he adds in the following chapter, the first verse: _This Melchisedec was king of Salem, priest of the most high God_, &c. (Verse 2): _First being by interpretation king of righteousness, and after that also king of Salem, which is, king of peace_. Whence it is clear, that Christ, the King, in his kingdom placeth righteousness and peace together. Psalm xxxiv. 14: _Eschew evil and do good; seek peace and pursue it._ Isaiah ix. 6, 7: _Unto us a child is born, unto us a son is given, and the government shall be upon his shoulder, and his name shall be called Wonderful, Counsellor, the Mighty God, the everlasting Father, the Prince of Peace._ Isaiah lii. 7: _How beautiful upon the mountains are the feet of him that bringeth good tidings, that publisheth peace, that bringeth good tidings of good, that publisheth salvation, that saith unto Sion, thy God reigneth!_ Luke ii. 14: In the nativity of Christ, the voice of them that praised God, saying, _Glory be to God on high, and in earth peace, good-will towards men._ And Isaiah liii. 5: the Gospel is called the _chastisement of our peace_. Isaiah lix. 8: Righteousness is called the _way of peace_. _The way of peace they know not, and there is no judgment in their goings._ Micah v. 4, 5, speaking of the Messias, he saith thus: _He shall stand and feed in the strength of the Lord, in the majesty of the name of the Lord his God, and they shall abide, for now shall he be great unto the end of the earth; and this man shall be your peace_, &c. Prov. iii. 1, 2: _My son, forget not my law, but let thine heart keep my commandments; for length of days, and long life, and peace, shall they add to thee._ [Sidenote: Also in regard of the first law of nature, in abolishing all things to be had in common.] 4. What appertains to the first law of abolishing the community of all things, or concerning the introduction of _meum_ and _tuum_; we perceive in the first place, how great an adversary this same community is to peace, by those words of Abraham to Lot (Gen. xiii. 8, 9): _Let there be no strife, I pray thee, between thee and me, and between thy herdmen and my herdmen; for we be brethren. Is not the whole land before thee? Separate thyself, I pray thee from me._ And all those places of Scripture by which we are forbidden to trespass upon our neighbours: as, _Thou shalt not kill_, _thou shalt not commit adultery_, _thou shalt not steal_, &c. do confirm the law of distinction between _mine_ and _thine_; for they suppose _the right of all men to all things_ to be taken away. [Sidenote: Also of the second law of nature, concerning faith to be kept.] 5. The same precepts establish the second law of nature, of keeping trust. For what doth, _Thou shalt not invade another’s right_, import, but this? _Thou shalt not take possession of that, which by thy contract ceaseth to be thine_: but it is expressly set down? Psalm xv. 1: to him that asked, _Lord who shall dwell in thy tabernacle?_ it is answered (verse 4): _He that sweareth unto his neighbour, and disappointeth him not._ And Prov. vi. 12: _My son, if thou be surety for thy friend, if thou have stricken thy hand with a stranger, thou art snared with the words of thy mouth._ [Sidenote: Also of the third law, of thankfulness.] 6. The third law concerning gratitude, is proved by these places. Deut. xxv. 4: _Thou shalt not muzzle the ox, when he treadeth out the corn_: which St. Paul (1 Cor. ix. 9) interprets to be spoken of men, not oxen only. Prov. xvii. 13; _Whoso rewardeth evil for good, evil shall not depart from his house._ And Deut. xx. 10, 11: _When thou comest nigh unto a city to fight against it, then proclaim peace unto it. And it shall be, if it make thee answer of peace, and open unto thee, then it shall be that all the people that is found therein, shall be tributaries unto thee, and they shall serve thee._ Prov. iii. 29: _Devise not evil against thy neighbour, seeing he dwelleth securely by thee._ [Sidenote: Also of the fourth law, of rendering ourselves useful.] 7. To the fourth law of accommodating ourselves, these precepts are conformable: Exod. xxiii. 4, 5: _If thou meet thine enemy’s ox, or his ass going astray, thou shalt surely bring it back to him again. If thou see the ass of him that hateth thee, lying under his burden, and wouldst forbear to help him, thou shalt surely help with him._ Also (verse 9): _Thou shalt not oppress a stranger._ Prov. iii. 30: _Strive not with a man without a cause, if he have done thee no harm._ Prov. xv. 18: _A wrathful man stirreth up strife; but he that is slow to anger, appeaseth strife._ Prov. xviii. 24: _There is a friend that sticketh closer than a brother._ The same is confirmed, Luke x, by the parable of the Samaritan, who had compassion on the Jew that was wounded by thieves; and by Christ’s precept (Matth. v. 39): _But I say unto you that ye resist not evil; but whosoever shall smite thee on the right cheek, turn to him the other also._ [Sidenote: Also of the fifth law, concerning mercy.] 8. Among infinite other places which prove the fifth law, these are some: Matth. vi. 14, 15: _If you forgive men their trespasses, your heavenly Father will also forgive you: but if you forgive not men their trespasses, neither will your Father forgive your trespasses._ Matth. xviii. 21, 22: _Lord how oft shall my brother sin against me, and I forgive him? Till seven times? Jesus saith unto him; I say not till seven times, but till seventy times seven times_; that is, _toties quoties_. [Sidenote: Also of the sixth law, that punishment only looks at the future.] 9. For the confirmation of the sixth law, all those places are pertinent which command us to shew mercy, such as Matth. v. 7: _Blessed are the merciful, for they shall obtain mercy._ Levit. xix. 18: _Thou shalt not avenge, nor bear any grudge against the children of thy people._ But there are, who not only think this law is not proved by Scripture, but plainly disproved from hence; that there is an eternal punishment reserved for the wicked after death, where there is no place either for amendment or example. Some resolve this objection by answering, that God, whom no law restrains, refers all to his glory, but that man must not do so; as if God sought his glory, that is to say, pleased himself in the death of a sinner. It is more rightly answered, that the institution of eternal punishment was before sin, and had regard to this only, that men might dread to commit sin for the time to come. [Sidenote: Also of the seventh law, concerning slander.] 10. The words of Christ prove this seventh: (Matth. v. 22): _But I say unto you, that whosoever is angry with his brother without a cause, shall be in danger of the judgment; and whosoever shall say unto his brother_ Racha, _shall be in danger of the council; but whosoever shall say, thou fool, shall be in danger of hell-fire_. Prov. x. 18: _He that uttereth a slander, is a fool._ Prov. xiv. 21: _He that despiseth his neighbour, sinneth._ Prov. xv. 1: _Grievous words stir up anger_. Prov. xxii. 10: _Cast out the scorner, and contention shall go out, and reproach shall cease._ [Sidenote: Also of the eighth, against pride.] 11. The eighth law of acknowledging equality of nature, that is, of humility, is established by these places: Matth. v. iii: _Blessed are the poor in spirit, for theirs is the kingdom of heaven._ Prov. vi. 16-19: _These six things doth the Lord hate, yea, seven are an abomination unto him. A proud look_, &c. Prov. xvi. 5: _Every one that is proud, is an abomination unto the Lord; though hand join in hand, he shall not be unpunished._ Prov. xi. 2: _When pride cometh, then cometh shame; but with the lowly is wisdom._ Thus Isaiah xl. 3: (where the coming of the Messias is shewed forth, for preparation towards his kingdom): _The voice of him that cried in the wilderness, was this: Prepare ye the way of the Lord, make straight in the desert a highway for our God. Every valley shall be exalted, and every mountain and hill shall be made low_: which doubtless is spoken to men, and not to mountains. [Sidenote: Also of the ninth, of equity.] 12. But that same equity, which we proved in the ninth place to be a law of nature, which commands every man to allow the same rights to others they would be allowed themselves, and which contains in it all the other laws besides, is the same which Moses sets down (Levit. xix. 18): _Thou shalt love thy neighbour as thyself._ And our Saviour calls it _the sum of the moral law_: Matth. xxii. 36-40: _Master, which is the great commandment in the law? Jesus said unto him, Thou shalt love the Lord thy God with all thine heart, and with all thy soul, and with all thy mind; this is the first and great commandment; and the second is like unto it, Thou shalt love thy neighbour as thyself. On these two commandments hang all the law and the prophets._ But to love our neighbour as ourselves, is nothing else but to grant him all we desire to have granted to ourselves. [Sidenote: Also the tenth, against respect of persons.] 13. By the tenth law respect of persons is forbid; as also by these places following: Matth. v. 45: _That ye may be children of your Father which is in heaven; for he maketh the sun to rise on the evil, and on the good_, &c. Coloss. iii. 11: _There is neither Greek nor Jew, circumcision nor uncircumcision, barbarian or Scythian, bond or free, but Christ is all, and in all._ Acts x. 34: _Of a truth I perceive that God is no respecter of persons._ 2 Chron. xix. 7: _There is no iniquity with the Lord our God, nor respect of persons, nor taking of gifts._ Ecclesiasticus xxxv. 12: _The Lord is Judge, and with him is no respect of persons._ Rom. ii. 11: _For there is no respect of persons with God._ [Sidenote: Also of the eleventh law, of having those things in common which cannot be divided.] 14. The eleventh law, which commands those things to be held in common which cannot be divided, I know not whether there be any express place in Scripture for it or not; but the practice appears every where, in the common use of wells, ways, rivers, sacred things, &c.; for else men could not live. [Sidenote: Also of the twelfth, of things to be divided by lot.] 15. We said in the twelfth place, that it was a law of nature, that where things could neither be divided nor possessed in common, they should be disposed by lot. Which is confirmed, as by the example of Moses who, by God’s command (Numb. xxvi. 55), divided the several parts of the land of promise unto the tribes by lot: so (Acts i. 24) by the example of the Apostles, who received Matthias before Justus into their number, by casting lots, and saying, _Thou, Lord, who knowest the hearts of all men, show whether of these two thou hast chosen_, &c. Prov. xvi. 33: _The lot is cast into the lap, but the whole disposing thereof is of the Lord._ And, which is the thirteenth law, the succession was due unto Esau, as being the first born of Isaac; if himself had not sold it (Gen. xxv. 33), or that the father had not otherwise appointed. [Sidenote: Also of appointing a judge.] 16. St. Paul, writing to the Corinthians (1 Epist. vi), reprehends the Corinthians of that city for going to law one with another before infidel judges, who were their enemies: calling it a fault, that they would not rather take wrong, and suffer themselves to be defrauded; for that is against that law, whereby we are commanded to be helpful to each other. But if it happen the controversy be concerning things necessary, what is to be done? Therefore the Apostle (verse 5) speaks thus: _I speak to your shame. Is it so, that there is not one wise man among you, no, not one that shall be able to judge between his brethren?_ He therefore, by those words, confirms that law of nature which we called the fifteenth, to wit, where controversies cannot be avoided; there by the consent of parties to appoint some arbiter, and him some third man; so as (which is the sixteenth law) neither of the parties may be judge in his own cause. [Sidenote: Also of the seventeenth law, that the arbiters must receive no reward for their sentence.] 17. But that the judge or arbiter must receive no reward for his sentence, which is the seventeenth law appears, Exod. xxiii. 8: _Thou shalt take no gift; for the gift blindeth the wise, and perverteth the words of the righteous._ Ecclesiasticus xx. 29: _Presents and gifts blind the eyes of the wise._ Whence it follows, that he must not be more obliged to one part than the other; which is the nineteenth law; and is also confirmed, Deut. i. 17: _Ye shall not respect persons in judgment, ye shall hear the small as well as the great_; and in all those places which are brought against respect of persons. [Sidenote: Also of the eighteenth, concerning witnesses.] 18. That in the judgment of fact witnesses must be had, which is the eighteenth law, the Scripture not only confirms, but requires more than one. Deut. xvii. 6: _At the mouth of two witnesses, or three witnesses, shall he that is worthy of death be put to death._ The same is repeated Deut. xix. 15. [Sidenote: Also of the twentieth law, against drunkenness.] 19. Drunkenness, which we have therefore in the last place numbered among the breaches of the natural law, because it hinders the use of right reason, is also forbid in Sacred Scripture for the same reason. Prov. xx. 1: _Wine is a mocker, strong drink is raging, whosoever is deceived thereby is not wise._ And Prov. xxxi. 4, 5: _It is not for kings to drink wine, lest they drink and forget the law, and pervert the judgment of any of the afflicted._ But that we might know that the malice of this vice consisted not formally in the quantity of the drink, but in that it destroys judgment and reason, it follows in the next verse: _Give strong drink to him that is ready to perish, and wine to those that be heavy of heart. Let him drink and forget his poverty, and remember his misery no more._ Christ useth the same reason in prohibiting drunkenness (Luke xxi. 34): _Take heed to yourselves, lest at any time your hearts be overcharged with surfeiting and drunkenness._ [Sidenote: Also in respect of that which hath been said, that the law of nature is eternal.] 20. That we said in the foregoing chapter, the law of nature is eternal, is also proved out of Matth. v. 18: _Verily I say unto you, till heaven and earth pass, one jot or one tittle shall in no wise pass from the law_; and Psalm cxix. 160: _Every one of thy righteous judgments endureth for ever._ [Sidenote: Also that the laws of nature do pertain to conscience.] 21. We also said, that the laws of nature had regard chiefly unto conscience; that is, that he is just, who by all possible endeavour strives to fulfil them. And although a man should order all his actions so much as belongs to external obedience just as the law commands, but not for the law’s sake, but by reason of some punishment annexed unto it, or out of vain glory; yet he is unjust. Both these are proved by the Holy Scriptures. The first (Isaiah lv. 7): _Let the wicked forsake his way, and the unrighteous man his thoughts, and let him return unto the Lord, and he will have mercy upon him; and to our God, for he will abundantly pardon._ Ezek. xviii. 31: _Cast away from you all your transgressions whereby you have transgressed, and make you a new heart and a new spirit; for why will you die, O House of Israel?_ By which, and the like places, we may sufficiently understand that God will not punish their deeds whose heart is right. The second, out of Isaiah xxix. 13, 14: _The Lord said, forasmuch as this people draw near me with their mouth, and with their lips do honour me, but have removed their hearts far from me, therefore I will proceed_, &c. Matth. v. 20: _Except your righteousness shall exceed the righteousness of the Scribes and Pharisees, ye shall in no case enter into the kingdom of heaven._ And in the following verses, our Saviour explains to them how that the commands of God are broken, not by deeds only, but also by the will. For the Scribes and Pharisees did in outward act observe the law most exactly, but for glory’s sake only; else they would as readily have broken it. There are innumerable places of Scripture in which is most manifestly declared, that God accepts the will for the deed, and that as well in good as in evil actions. [Sidenote: Also that the laws of nature are easily observed.] 22. That the law of nature is easily kept, Christ himself declares (Matth. xi. 28, 29, 30): _Come unto me_, &c. _Take my yoke upon you, and learn of me_, &c.; _for my yoke is easy, and my burden light_. [Sidenote: Lastly, in respect of the rule by which a man may presently know, whether what he is about to act be against the law of nature, or not.] 23. Lastly, the rule by which I said any man might know, whether what he was doing were contrary to the law or not, to wit, what thou wouldst not be done to, do not that to another; is almost in the self-same words delivered by our Saviour (Matth. vii. 12): _Therefore all things whatsoever ye would that men should do unto you, do you even so to them._ [Sidenote: The law of Christ is the law of nature.] 24. As the law of nature is all of it divine, so the law of Christ by conversion (which is wholly explained in the v. vi. and vii. chapters of St. Matthew’s Gospel), is all of it also (except that one commandment, of not marrying her who is put away for adultery; which Christ brought for explication of the divine positive law, against the Jews, who did not rightly interpret the Mosaical law) the doctrine of nature. I say, the whole law of Christ is explained in the fore-named chapters, not the whole doctrine of Christ; for faith is a part of Christian doctrine, which is not comprehended under the title of a law. For laws are made and given in reference to such actions as follow our will; not in order to our opinions and belief, which being out of our power, follow not the will. DOMINION. --- CHAPTER V. OF THE CAUSES AND FIRST BEGINNING OF CIVIL GOVERNMENT. 1. That the laws of nature are not sufficient to preserve peace. 2. That the laws of nature, in the state of nature, are silent. 3. That the security of living according to the laws of nature, consists in the concord of many persons. 4. That the concord of many persons is not constant enough for a lasting peace. 5. The reason why the government of certain brute creatures stands firm in concord only, and why not of men. 6. That not only consent, but union also, is required to establish the peace of men. 7. What union is. 8. In union, the right of all men is conveyed to one. 9. What civil society is. 10. What a civil person is. 11. What it is to have the supreme power, and what to be a subject 12. Two kinds of cities, natural, and by institution. [Sidenote: That the laws of nature suffice not for the conservation of peace.] 1. It is of itself manifest that the actions of men proceed from the will, and the will from hope and fear, insomuch as when they shall see a greater good or less evil likely to happen to them by the breach than observation of the laws, they will wittingly violate them. The hope therefore which each man hath of his security and self-preservation, consists in this, that by force or craft he may disappoint his neighbour, either openly or by stratagem. Whence we may understand, that the natural laws, though well understood, do not instantly secure any man in their practice; and consequently, that as long as there is no caution had from the invasion of others, there remains to every man that same primitive right of self-defence by such means as either he can or will make use of, that is, a right to all things, or the right of war. And it is sufficient for the fulfilling of the natural law, that a man be prepared in mind to embrace peace when it may be had. [Sidenote: That the laws of nature, in a state of nature, are silent.] 2. It is a trite saying, that all laws are silent in the time of war, and it is a true one, not only if we speak of the civil, but also of the natural laws, provided they be referred not to the mind, but to the actions of men, by chap. iii. art. 27. And we mean such a war, as is of all men against all men; such as is the mere state of nature; although in the war of nation against nation, a certain mean was wont to be observed. And therefore in old time, there was a manner of living, and as it were a certain economy, which they called ληστρικὴν, living by rapine; which was neither against the law of nature (things then so standing), nor void of glory to those who exercised it with valour, not with cruelty. Their custom was, taking away the rest, to spare life, and abstain from oxen fit for plough, and every instrument serviceable to husbandry. Which yet is not so to be taken, as if they were bound to do thus by the law of nature; but that they had regard to their own glory herein, lest by too much cruelty they might be suspected guilty of fear. [Sidenote: That the security of living according to the laws of nature, consists in the agreement of many.] 3. Since therefore the exercise of the natural law is necessary for the preservation of peace, and that for the exercise of the natural law security is no less necessary; it is worth the considering what that is which affords such a security. For this matter nothing else can be imagined, but that each man provide himself of such meet helps, as the invasion of one on the other may be rendered so dangerous, as either of them may think it better to refrain than to meddle. But first, it is plain that the consent of two or three cannot make good such a security; because that the addition but of one, or some few on the other side, is sufficient to make the victory undoubtedly sure, and heartens the enemy to attack us. It is therefore necessary, to the end the security sought for may be obtained, that the number of them who conspire in a mutual assistance be so great, that the accession of some few to the enemy’s party may not prove to them a matter of moment sufficient to assure the victory. [Sidenote: That the agreement of many is not constant enough to preserve a lasting peace.] 4. Furthermore, how great soever the number of them is who meet on self-defence, if yet they agree not among themselves of some excellent means whereby to compass this, but every man after his own manner shall make use of his endeavours, nothing will be done; because that, divided in their opinions, they will be a hinderance to each other; or if they agree well enough to some one action, through hope of victory, spoil, or revenge, yet afterward, through diversity of wits and counsels, or emulation and envy, with which men naturally contend, they will be so torn and rent, as they will neither give mutual help nor desire peace, except they be constrained to it by some common fear. Whence it follows that the consent of many, (which consists in this only, as we have already defined in the foregoing section, that they direct all their actions to the same end and the common good), that is to say, that the society proceeding from mutual help only, yields not that security which they seek for, who meet and agree in the exercise of the above-named laws of nature; but that somewhat else must be done, that those who have once consented for the common good to peace and mutual help, may by fear be restrained lest afterwards they again dissent, when their private interest shall appear discrepant from the common good. [Sidenote: Why the government of some brute creatures stands firm in concord alone, and not so of men.] 5. Aristotle reckons among those animals which he calls politic, not man only, but divers others, as the ant, the bee, &c.; which, though they be destitute of reason, by which they may contract and submit to government, notwithstanding by consenting, that is to say, ensuing or eschewing the same things, they so direct their actions to a common end, that their meetings are not obnoxious unto any seditions. Yet is not their gathering together a civil government, and therefore those animals not to be termed political; because their government is only a consent, or many wills concurring in one object, not (as is necessary in civil government) one will. It is very true, that in those creatures living only by sense and appetite, their consent of minds is so durable, as there is no need of anything more to secure it, and by consequence to preserve peace among them, than barely their natural inclination. But among men the case is otherwise. For, first, among them there is a contestation of honour and preferment; among beasts there is none: whence hatred and envy, out of which arise sedition and war, is among men; among beasts no such matter. Next, the natural appetite of bees, and the like creatures, is conformable; and they desire the common good, which among them differs not from their private. But man scarce esteems anything good, which hath not somewhat of eminence in the enjoyment, more than that which others do possess. Thirdly, those creatures which are void of reason, see no defect, or think they see none, in the administration of their commonweals; but in a multitude of men there are many who, supposing themselves wiser than others, endeavour to innovate, and divers innovators innovate divers ways; which is a mere distraction and civil war. Fourthly, these brute creatures, howsoever they may have the use of their voice to signify their affections to each other, yet want they that same art of words which is necessarily required to those motions in the mind, whereby good is represented to it as being better, and evil as worse than in truth it is. But the tongue of man is a trumpet of war and sedition: and it is reported of Pericles, that he sometimes by his elegant speeches thundered and lightened, and confounded whole Greece itself. Fifthly, they cannot distinguish between _injury_ and _harm_; thence it happens that as long as it is well with them, they blame not their fellows. But those men are of most trouble to the republic, who have most leisure to be idle; for they use not to contend for public places, before they have gotten the victory over hunger and cold. Last of all, the consent of those brutal creatures is natural; that of men by compact only, that is to say, artificial. It is therefore no matter of wonder, if somewhat more be needful for men to the end they may live in peace. Wherefore consent or contracted society, without some common power whereby particular men may be ruled through fear of punishment, doth not suffice to make up that security, which is requisite to the exercise of natural justice. [Sidenote: That not only consent, but union also, is required to establish the peace of men.] 6. Since therefore the conspiring of many wills to the same end doth not suffice to preserve peace, and to make a lasting defence, it is requisite that, in those necessary matters which concern peace and self-defence, there be but one will of all men. But this cannot be done, unless every man will so subject his will to some other one, to wit, either man or council, that whatsoever his will is in those things which are necessary to the common peace, it be received for the wills of all men in general, and of every one in particular. Now the gathering together of many men, who deliberate of what is to be done or not to be done for the common good of all men, is that which I call a _council_. [Sidenote: What union is.] 7. This submission of the wills of all those men to the will of one man or one council, is then made, when each one of them obligeth himself by contract to every one of the rest, not to resist the will of that one man or council, to which he hath submitted himself; that is, that he refuse him not the use of his wealth and strength against any others whatsoever; for he is supposed still to retain a right of defending himself against violence: and this is called _union_. But we understand that to be the will of the council, which is the will of the major part of those men of whom the council consists. [Sidenote: In union, the right of all men is transferred to one.] 8. But though the will itself be not voluntary, but only the beginning of voluntary actions; (for we will not to will, but to act); and therefore falls least of all under deliberation and compact; yet he who submits his will to the will of another, conveys to that other the right of his strength and faculties. Insomuch as when the rest have done the same, he to whom they have submitted, hath so much power, as by the terror of it he can conform the wills of particular men unto unity and concord. [Sidenote: What civil society is.] 9. Now union thus made, is called a city or civil society; and also a civil person. For when there is one will of all men, it is to be esteemed for one person; and by the word _one_, it is to be known and distinguished from all particular men, as having its own rights and properties. Insomuch as neither any one citizen, nor all of them together, (if we except him, whose will stands for the will of all), is to be accounted a city. A _city_ therefore, (that we may define it), is _one person_, whose will, by the compact of many men, is to be received for the will of them all; so as he may use all the power and faculties of each particular person to the maintenance of peace, and for common defence. [Sidenote: What a civil person is.] 10. But although every city be a civil person, yet every civil person is not a city; for it may happen that many citizens, by the permission of the city, may join together in one person, for the doing of certain things. These now will be civil persons; as the companies of merchants, and many other convents. But cities they are not, because they have not submitted themselves to the will of the company simply and in all things, but in certain things only determined by the city, and on such terms as it is lawful for any one of them to contend in judgment against the body itself of the sodality; which is by no means allowable to a citizen against the city. Such like societies, therefore, are civil persons subordinate to the city. [Sidenote: What it is to have the supreme power, what to be subject.] 11. In every city, that man or council, to whose will each particular man hath subjected his will so as hath been declared, is said to have the _supreme power_, or _chief command_, or _dominion_. Which power and right of commanding, consists in this, that each citizen hath conveyed all his strength and power to that man or council; which to have done, because no man can transfer his power in a natural manner, is nothing else than to have parted with his right of resisting. Each citizen, as also every subordinate civil person, is called the _subject_ of him who hath the chief command. [Sidenote: Two kinds of cities, natural, and by institution.] 12. By what hath been said, it is sufficiently showed in what manner and by what degrees many natural persons, through desire of preserving themselves and by mutual fear, have grown together into a civil person, whom we have called a _city_. But they who submit themselves to another for fear, either submit to him whom they fear, or some other whom they confide in for protection. They act according to the first manner, who are vanquished in war, that they may not be slain; they according to the second, who are not yet overcome, that they may not be overcome. The first manner receives its beginning from natural power, and may be called the natural beginning of a city; the latter from the council and constitution of those who meet together, which is a beginning by institution. Hence it is that there are two kinds of cities; the one natural, such as the paternal and despotical; the other institutive, which may be also called political. In the first, the lord acquires to himself such citizens as he will; in the other, the citizens by their own wills appoint a lord over themselves, whether he be one man or one company of men, endued with the command in chief. But we will speak, in the first place, of a city political or by institution; and next, of a city natural. ------- CHAPTER VI. OF THE RIGHT OF HIM, WHETHER COUNCIL OR ONE MAN ONLY, WHO HATH THE SUPREME POWER IN THE CITY. 1. There can no right be attributed to a multitude out of civil society, nor any action to which they have not under seal consented. 2. The right of the greater number consenting, is the beginning of a city. 3. That every man retains a right to protect himself according to his own free will, so long as there is no sufficient regard had to his security. 4. That a coercive power is necessary to secure us. 5. What the sword of justice is. 6. That the sword of justice belongs to him, who hath the chief command. 7. That the sword of war belongs to him also. 8. All judicature belongs to him too. 9. The legislative power is his only. 10. The naming of magistrates and other officers of the city belongs to him. 11 Also the examination of all doctrines. 12. Whatsoever he doth is unpunishable. 13. That the command his citizens have granted is absolute, and what proportion of obedience is due to him. 14. That the laws of the city bind him not. 15. That no man can challenge a propriety to anything against his will. 16. By the laws of the city only we come to know what theft, murder, adultery, and injury is. 17. The opinion of those who would constitute a city, where there should not be any one endued with an absolute power. 18. The marks of supreme authority. 19. If a city be compared with a man, he that hath the supreme power is in order to the city, as the human soul is in relation to the man. 20. That the supreme command cannot by right be dissolved through their consents, by whose compacts it was first constituted. [Sidenote: There can no right be attributed to a multitude, considered out of civil society; nor any action, to which they have not given their particular consents.] 1. We must consider, first of all, what a multitude[8] of men, gathering themselves of their own free wills into society, is; namely, that it is not any one body, but many men, whereof each one hath his own will and his peculiar judgment concerning all things that may be proposed. And though by particular contracts each single man may have his own right and propriety, so as one may say _this is mine_, the other, _that is his_; yet will there not be anything of which the whole multitude, as a person distinct from a single man, can rightly say, this is _mine_, more than another’s. Neither must we ascribe any action to the multitude, as its own; but if all or more of them do agree, it will not be an action, but as many actions as men. For although in some great sedition, it is commonly said, that the people of that city have taken up arms; yet is it true of those only who are in arms, or who consent to them. For the city, which is one person, cannot take up arms against itself. Whatsoever, therefore, is done by the multitude, must be understood to be done by every one of those by whom it is made up; and that he, who being in the multitude, and yet consented not, nor gave any helps to the things that were done by it, must be judged to have done nothing. Besides, in a multitude not yet reduced into one person, in that manner as hath been said, there remains that same state of nature in which all things belong to all men; and there is no place for _meum_ and _tuum_, which is called dominion and propriety, by reason that that security is not yet extant, which we have declared above to be necessarily requisite for the practice of the natural laws. Footnote 8: _Multitude, &c._] The doctrine of the power of a city over its citizens, almost wholly depends on the understanding of the difference which is between a multitude of men ruling, and a multitude ruled. For such is the nature of a city, that a multitude or company of citizens not only may have command, but may also be subject to command; but in diverse senses. Which difference I did believe was clearly enough explained in the first article; but by the objections of many against those things which follow, I discern otherwise. Wherefore it seemed good to me, to the end I might make a fuller explication, to add these few things. By multitude, because it is a collective word, we understand more than one: so as a multitude of men is the same with many men. The same word, because it is of the singular number, signifies one thing; namely, one multitude. But in neither sense can a multitude be understood to have one will given to it by nature, but to each a several; and therefore neither is any one action whatsoever to be attributed to it. Wherefore a multitude cannot promise, contract, acquire right, convey right, act, have, possess, and the like, unless it be every one apart, and man by man; so as there must be as many promises, compacts, rights, and actions, as men. Wherefore a multitude is no natural person. But if the same multitude do contract one with another, that the will of one man, or the agreeing wills of the major part of them, shall be received for the will of all; then it becomes one person. For it is endued with a will, and therefore can do voluntary actions, such as are commanding, making laws, acquiring and transferring of right, and so forth; and it is oftener called the people, than the multitude. We must therefore distinguish thus. When we say the people or multitude wills, commands, or doth anything, it is understood that the city which commands, wills and acts by the will of one, or the concurring wills of more; which cannot be done but in an assembly. But as oft as anything is said to be done by a multitude of men, whether great or small, without the will of that man or assembly of men, that is understood to be done by a subjected people; that is, by many single citizens together; and not proceeding from one will, but from diverse wills of diverse men, who are citizens and subjects, but not a city. [Sidenote: The beginning of a city is the right of the major part agreeing.] 2. Next, we must consider that every one of the multitude, by whose means there may be a beginning to make up the city, must agree with the rest, that in those matters which shall be propounded by any one in the assembly, that be received for the will of all, which the major part shall approve of; for otherwise there will be no will at all of a multitude of men, whose wills and votes differ so variously. Now, if any one will not consent, the rest, notwithstanding, shall among themselves constitute the city without him. Whence it will come to pass, that the city retains its primitive right against the dissenter; that is, the right of war, as against an enemy. [Sidenote: That every man retains a right of protecting himself according to his own judgment, as long as he is not secured.] 3. But because we said in the foregoing chapter, the sixth article, that there was required to the security of men, not only their consent, but also the subjection of their wills in such things as were necessary to peace and defence; and that in that union and subjection the nature of a city consisted; we must discern now in this place, out of those things which may be propounded, discussed, and stated in an assembly of men, all whose wills are contained in the will of the major part, what things are necessary to peace and common defence. But first of all, it is necessary to peace, that a man be so far forth protected against the violence of others, that he may live securely; that is, that he may have no just cause to fear others, so long as he doth them no injury. Indeed, to make men altogether safe from mutual harms, so as they cannot be hurt or injuriously killed, is impossible; and, therefore, comes not within deliberation. But care may be had, there be no just cause of fear; for security is the end wherefore men submit themselves to others; which if it be not had, no man is supposed to have submitted himself to aught, or to have quitted his right to all things, before that there was a care had of his security. [Sidenote: That a coercive power is necessary for security.] 4. It is not enough to obtain this security, that every one of those who are now growing up into a city, do covenant with the rest, either by words or writing, _not to steal_, _not to kill_, and to observe the like laws; for the pravity of human disposition is manifest to all, and by experience too well known how little (removing the punishment) men are kept to their duties through conscience of their promises. We must therefore provide for our security, not by compacts, but by punishments; and there is then sufficient provision made, when there are so great punishments appointed for every injury, as apparently it prove a greater evil to have done it, than not to have done it. For all men, by a necessity of nature, choose that which to them appears to be the less evil. [Sidenote: What the sword of justice is.] 5. Now, the right of punishing is then understood to be given to any one, when every man contracts not to assist him who is to be punished. But I will call this right, _the sword of justice_. But these kind of contracts men observe well enough, for the most part, till either themselves or their near friends are to suffer. [Sidenote: That the sword of justice belongs to him who hath the chief command.] 6. Because, therefore, for the security of particular men, and, by consequence, for the common peace, it is necessary that the right of using the sword for punishment be transferred to some man or council; that man or council is necessarily understood by right to have the supreme power in the city. For he that by right punisheth at his own discretion, by right compels all men to all things which he himself wills; than which a greater command cannot be imagined. [Sidenote: That the sword of war belongs to him also.] 7. But in vain do they worship peace at home, who cannot defend themselves against foreigners; neither is it possible for them to protect themselves against foreigners, whose forces are not united. And therefore it is necessary for the preservation of particulars, that there be some one council or one man, who hath the right to arm, to gather together, to unite so many citizens, in all dangers and on all occasions, as shall be needful for common defence against the certain number and strength of the enemy; and again, as often as he shall find it expedient, to make peace with them. We must understand, therefore, that particular citizens have conveyed their whole right of war and peace unto some one man or council; and that this right, which we may call _the sword of war_, belongs to the same man or council, to whom the sword of justice belongs. For no man can by right compel citizens to take up arms and be at the expenses of war, but he who by right can punish him who doth not obey. Both swords therefore, as well this of war as that of justice, even by the constitution itself of a city and essentially do belong to the chief command. [Sidenote: The power of judicature belongs to him.] 8. But because the right of the sword, is nothing else but to have power by right to use the sword at his own will, it follows, that the judgment of its right use pertains to the same party; for if the power of judging were in one, and the power of executing in another, nothing would be done. For in vain would he give judgment, who could not execute his commands; or, if he executed them by the power of another, he himself is not said to have the power of the sword, but that other, to whom he is only an officer. All judgment therefore, in a city, belongs to him who hath the swords; that is, to him who hath the supreme authority. [Sidenote: The legislative power is his also.] 9. Furthermore, since it no less, nay, it much more conduceth to peace, to prevent brawls from arising than to appease them being risen; and that all controversies are bred from hence, that the opinions of men differ concerning _meum_ and _tuum_, _just_ and _unjust_, _profitable_ and _unprofitable_, _good_ and _evil_, _honest_ and _dishonest_, and the like; which every man esteems according to his own judgment: it belongs to the same chief power to make some common rules for all men, and to declare them publicly, by which every man may know what may be called his, what another’s, what just, what unjust, what honest, what dishonest, what good, what evil; that is summarily, what is to be done, what to be avoided in our common course of life. But those rules and measures are usually called the civil laws, or the laws of the city, as being the commands of him who hath the supreme power in the city. And the _civil laws_ (that we may define them) are nothing else but _the commands of him who hath the chief authority in the city, for direction of the future actions of his citizens_. [Sidenote: That the naming of magistrates and officers belongs to him also.] 10. Furthermore, since the affairs of the city, both those of war and peace, cannot possibly be all administered by one man or one council without officers and subordinate magistrates; and that it appertaineth to peace and common defence, that they to whom it belongs justly to judge of controversies, to search into neighbouring councils, prudently to wage war, and on all hands warily to attend the benefit of the city, should also rightly exercise their offices; it is consonant to reason that they depend on, and be chosen by him who hath the chief command both in war and in peace. [Sidenote: The examination of doctrine belongs to him likewise.] 11. It is also manifest, that all voluntary actions have their beginning from, and necessarily depend on the will; and that the will of doing or omitting aught, depends on the opinion of the good and evil, of the reward or punishment which a man conceives he shall receive by the act or omission: so as the actions of all men are ruled by the opinions of each. Wherefore, by evident and necessary inference, we may understand that it very much concerns the interest of peace, that no opinions or doctrines be delivered to citizens, by which they may imagine that either by right they may not obey the laws of the city, that is, the commands of that man or council to whom the supreme power is committed, or that it is lawful to resist him, or that a less punishment remains for him that denies, than for him that yields obedience. For if one command somewhat to be done under penalty of natural death, another forbid it under pain of eternal death, and both by their own right, it will follow that the citizens, although innocent, are not only by right punishable, but that the city itself is altogether dissolved. For no man can serve two masters; nor is he less, but rather more a master, whom we believe we are to obey for fear of damnation, than he whom we obey for fear of temporal death. It follows therefore that this one, whether man or court, to whom the city hath committed the supreme power, have also this right; that he both judge what opinions[9] and doctrines are enemies unto peace, and also that he forbid them to be taught. Footnote 9: _Judge what opinions, &c._ There is scarce any principle, neither in the worship of God nor in human sciences, from whence there may not spring dissensions, discords, reproaches, and by degrees war itself. Neither doth this happen by reason of the falsehood of the principle, but of the disposition of men, who, seeming wise to themselves, will needs appear such to all others. But though such dissensions cannot be hindered from arising, yet may they be restrained by the exercise of the supreme power, that they prove no hindrance to the public peace. Of these kinds of opinions, therefore, I have not spoken in this place. There are certain doctrines wherewith subjects being tainted, they verily believe that obedience may be refused to the city, and that by right they may, nay ought, to oppose and fight against chief princes and dignities. Such are those which, whether directly and openly, or more obscurely and by consequence, require obedience to be given to others beside them to whom the supreme authority is committed. I deny not but this reflects on that power which many, living under other government, ascribe to the chief head of the Church of Rome, and also on that which elsewhere, out of that Church, bishops require in their’s to be given to them; and last of all, on that liberty which the lower sort of citizens, under pretence of religion, do challenge to themselves. For what civil war was there ever in the Christian world, which did not either grow from, or was nourished by this root? The judgment therefore of doctrines, whether they be repugnant to civil obedience or not, and if they be repugnant, the power of prohibiting them to be taught, I do here attribute to the civil authority. For since there is no man who grants not to the city the judgment of those things which belong to its peace and defence, and it is manifest that the opinions which I have already recited do relate to its peace; it follows necessarily, that the examination of those opinions, whether they be such or not, must be referred to the city; that is, to him who hath the supreme authority. [Sidenote: Whatsoever he doth is unpunishable.] 12. Last of all, from this consideration, that each citizen hath submitted his will to his who hath the supreme command in the city, so as he may not employ his strength against him; it follows manifestly, that whatsoever shall be done by him who commands, must not be punished. For as he who hath not power enough, cannot punish him naturally, so neither can he punish him by right, who by right hath not sufficient power. [Sidenote: That he hath an absolute dominion granted him by his citizens, and what proportion of obedience is due unto him.] 13. It is most manifest by what hath been said, that in every perfect city, that is, where no citizen hath right to use his faculties at his own discretion for the preservation of himself, or where the right of the private sword is excluded; there is a supreme power in some one, greater than which cannot by right be conferred by men, or greater than which no mortal man can have over himself. But that power, greater than which cannot by men be conveyed on a man, we call _absolute_.[10] For whosoever hath so submitted his will to the will of the city, that he can, unpunished, do any thing, make laws, judge controversies, set penalties, make use at his own pleasure of the strength and wealth of men, and all this by right; truly he hath given him the greatest dominion that can be granted. This same may be confirmed by experience, in all the cities which are or ever have been. For though it be sometimes in doubt what man or council hath the chief command, yet ever there is such a command and always exercised, except in the time of sedition and civil war; and then there are two chief commands made out of one. Now, those seditious persons who dispute against absolute authority, do not so much care to destroy it, as to convey it on others: for removing this power, they together take away civil society, and a confusion of all things returns. There is so much obedience joined to this absolute right of the chief ruler, as is necessarily required for the government of the city, that is to say, so much as that right of his may not be granted in vain. Now this kind of obedience, although for some reasons it may sometimes by right be denied, yet because a greater cannot be performed, we will call it _simple_. But the obligation to perform this grows not immediately from that contract, by which we have conveyed all our right on the city; but immediately from hence, that without obedience the city’s right would be frustrate, and by consequence there would be no city constituted. For it is one thing if I say, _I give you right to command what you will_; another, if I say, _I will do whatsoever you command_. And the command may be such, as I would rather die than do it. Forasmuch, therefore, as no man can be bound to will being killed, much less is he tied to that which to him is worse than death. If therefore I be commanded to kill myself, I am not bound to do it. For though I deny to do it, yet the right of dominion is not frustrated; since others may be found, who being commanded will not refuse to do it; neither do I refuse to do that, which I have contracted to do. In like manner, if the chief ruler command any man to kill him, he is not tied to do it; because it cannot be conceived that he made any such covenant. Nor if he command to execute a parent, whether he be innocent or guilty and condemned by the law; since there are others who being commanded will do that, and a son will rather die than live infamous and hated of all the world. There are many other cases in which, since the commands are shameful to be done by some and not by others, obedience may by right be performed by these, and refused by those; and this without breach of that absolute right which was given to the chief ruler. For in no case is the right taken away from him, of slaying those who shall refuse to obey him. But they who thus kill men, although by right given them from him that hath it, yet if they use that right otherwise than right reason requires, they sin against the laws of nature, that is, against God. Footnote 10: _Absolute._] A popular state openly challengeth absolute dominion, and the citizens oppose it not. For, in the gathering together of many men, they acknowledge the face of a city; and even the unskilful understand, that matters there are ruled by council. Yet monarchy is no less a city than democraty; and absolute kings have their counsellors, from whom they will take advice, and suffer their power, in matters of greater consequence, to be guided but not recalled. But it appears not to most men, how a city is contained in the person of a king. And therefore they object against absolute command: first, that if any man had such a right, the condition of the citizens would be miserable. For thus they think; he will take all, spoil all, kill all; and every man counts it his only happiness, that he is not already spoiled and killed. But why should he do thus? Not because he can; for unless he have a mind to it, he will not do it. Will he, to please one or some few, spoil all the rest? First, though by right, that is, without injury to them, he may do it, yet can he not do it justly, that is, without breach of the natural laws and injury against God. And therefore there is some security for subjects in the oaths which princes take. Next, if he could justly do it, or that he made no account of his oath, yet appears there no reason why he should desire it, since he finds no good in it. But it cannot be denied, but a prince may sometimes have an inclination to do wickedly. But grant then, that thou hadst given him a power which were not absolute, but so much only as sufficed to defend thee from the injuries of others; which, if thou wilt be safe, is necessary for thee to give; are not all the same things to be feared? For he that hath strength enough to protect all, wants not sufficiency to oppress all. Here is no other difficulty then, but that human affairs cannot be without some inconvenience. And this inconvenience itself is in the citizens, not in the government. For if men could rule themselves, every man by his own command, that is to say, could they live according to the laws of nature, there would be no need at all of a city, nor of a common coercive power. Secondly, they object, that there is no dominion in the Christian world absolute. Which, indeed, is not true; for all monarchies, and all other states, are so. For although they who have the chief command, do not all those things they would, and what they know profitable to the city; the reason of that is, not the defect of right in them, but the consideration of their citizens, who busied about their private interest, and careless of what tends to the public, cannot sometimes be drawn to perform their duties without the hazard of the city. Wherefore princes sometimes forbear the exercise of their right; and prudently remit somewhat of the act, but nothing of their right. [Sidenote: That he is not tied to observe the laws of the city.] 14. Neither can any man give somewhat to himself; for he is already supposed to have what he can give himself. Nor can he be obliged to himself; for the same party being both _the obliged_ and _the obliger_, and the obliger having power to release the obliged, it were merely in vain for a man to be obliged to himself; because he can release himself at his own pleasure, and he that can do this is already actually free. Whence it is plain, that the city is not tied to the civil laws; for the civil laws are the laws of the city, by which, if she were engaged, she should be engaged to herself. Neither can the city be obliged to her citizen; because, if he will, he can free her from her obligation; and he will, as oft as she wills; for the will of every citizen is in all things comprehended in the will of the city; the city therefore is free when she pleaseth, that is, she is now actually free. But the will of a council, or one who hath supreme authority given him, is the will of the city: he therefore contains the wills of all particular citizens. Therefore neither is he bound to the civil laws; for this is to be bound to himself; nor to any of his citizens. [Sidenote: That no man can challenge a propriety in aught against him who hath the supreme power.] 15. Now because, as hath been shown above, before the constitution of a city all things belonged to all men; nor is there that thing which any man can so call his, as any other may not, by the same right, claim as his own; for where all things are _common_, there can be nothing _proper_ to any man; it follows, that _propriety_ received its beginning[11] when cities received their’s, and that that only is _proper_ to each man, which he can keep by the laws and the power of the whole city, that is, of him on whom its chief command is conferred. Whence we understand, that each particular citizen hath a _propriety_ to which none of his fellow-citizens hath right, because they are tied to the same laws; but he hath no propriety in which the chief ruler (whose commands are the laws, whose will contains the will of each man, and who by every single person is constituted the supreme judge) hath not a right. But although there be many things which the city permits to its citizens, and therefore they may sometimes go to law against their chief; yet is not that action belonging to civil right, but to natural equity. Neither is it concerning what[12] by right he may do who hath the supreme power, but what he hath been willing should be done; and therefore he shall be judge himself, as though (the equity of the cause being well understood) he could not give wrong judgment. Footnote 11: _Propriety received its beginning, &c._] What is objected by some, that the propriety of goods, even before the constitution of cities, was found in fathers of families, that objection is vain; because I have already declared, that a family is a little city. For the sons of a family have a propriety of their goods granted them by their father, distinguished indeed from the rest of the sons of the same family, but not from the propriety of the father himself. But the fathers of divers families, who are subject neither to any common father nor lord, have a common right in all things. Footnote 12: _What by right he may do, &c._] As often as a citizen is granted to have an action of law against the supreme, that is, against the city, the question is not in that action, whether the city may by right keep possession of the thing in controversy, but whether by the laws formerly made she would keep it; for the law is the declared will of the supreme. Since then the city may raise money from the citizens under two titles, either as tribute, or as debt; in the former case there is no action of law allowed, for there can be no question whether the city have right to require tribute; in the latter it is allowed, because the city will take nothing from its citizens by fraud or cunning, and yet if need require, all they have, openly. And therefore he that condemns this place, saying, that by this doctrine it is easy for princes to free themselves from their debts, he does it impertinently. [Sidenote: It is known by the civil laws what theft, murder, adultery, and injury are.] 16. Theft, murder, adultery, and all injuries, are forbid by the laws of nature; but what is to be called _theft_, what _murder_, what _adultery_, what _injury_ in a citizen, this is not to be determined by the natural, but by the civil law. For not every taking away of the thing which another possesseth, but only another man’s goods, is theft; but what is our’s, and what another’s, is a question belonging to the civil law. In like manner, not every killing of a man is murder, but only that which the civil law forbids; neither is all encounter with women adultery, but only that which the civil law prohibits. Lastly, all breach of promise is an injury, where the promise itself is lawful; but where there is no right to make any compact, there can be no conveyance of it, and therefore there can no injury follow, as hath been said in the second chapter, Article 17. Now what we may contract for, and what not, depends wholly upon the civil laws. The city of Lacedæmon therefore rightly ordered, that those young men who could so take away certain goods from others as not to be caught, should go unpunished; for it was nothing else but to make a law, that what was so acquired should be their own, and not another’s. Rightly also is that man everywhere slain, whom we kill in war or by the necessity of self-defence. So also that copulation which in one city is matrimony, in another will be judged adultery. Also those contracts which make up marriage in one citizen, do not so in another, although of the same city; because that he who is forbidden by the city, that is, by that one man or council whose the supreme power is, to contract aught, hath no right to make any contract, and therefore having made any, it is not valid, and by consequence no marriage. But his contract which received no prohibition, was therefore of force, and so was matrimony. Neither adds it any force to any unlawful contracts, that they were made by an oath or sacrament;[13] for those add nothing to the strengthening of the contract, as hath been said above, Chap. II. Art. 22. What therefore theft, what murder, what adultery, and in general what injury is, must be known by the civil laws; that is, the commands of him who hath the supreme authority. Footnote 13: _That they were made by an oath or sacrament, &c._] Whether matrimony be a sacrament, (in which sense that word is used by some divines), or not, it is not my purpose to dispute. Only I say, that the legitimate contract of a man and woman to live together, that is, granted by the civil law, whether it be a sacrament or not, is surely a legitimate marriage; but that copulation which the city hath prohibited is no marriage, since it is of the essence of marriage to be a legitimate contract. There were legitimate marriages in many places, as among the Jews, the Grecians, the Romans, which yet might be dissolved. But with those who permit no such contracts but by a law that they shall never be broke, wedlock cannot be dissolved; and the reason is, because the city hath commanded it to be indissoluble, not because matrimony is a sacrament. Wherefore the ceremonies which at weddings are to be performed in the temple, to bless, or, if I may say so, to consecrate the husband and wife, will perhaps belong only to the office of clergymen; all the rest namely, who, when, and by what contracts marriages may be made, pertains to the laws of the city. [Sidenote: The opinion of those who would constitute a city, where there should not be any one endued with absolute power.] 17. This same supreme command and absolute power, seems so harsh to the greatest part of men, as they hate the very naming of them; which happens chiefly through want of knowledge, what human nature and the civil laws are; and partly also through their default, who, when they are invested with so great authority, abuse their power to their own lust. That they may therefore avoid this kind of supreme authority, some of them will have a city well enough constituted, if they who shall be the citizens’ convening, do agree concerning certain articles propounded, and in that convent agitated and approved, and do command them to be observed, and punishments prescribed to be inflicted on them who shall break them. To which purpose, and also to the repelling of a foreign enemy, they appoint a certain and limited return, with this condition, that if that suffice not, they may call a new convention of estates. Who sees not in a city thus constituted, that the assembly who prescribed those things had an absolute power? If therefore the assembly continue, or from time to time have a certain day and place of meeting, that power will be perpetual. But if they wholly dissolve, either the city dissolves with them, and so all is returned to the state of war: or else there is somewhere a power left to punish those who shall transgress the laws, whosoever or how many soever they be that have it; which cannot possibly be without an absolute power. For he that by right hath this might given, by punishments to restrain what citizens he pleaseth, hath such a power as a greater cannot possibly be given by any citizens. [Sidenote: The notes of supreme authority.] 18. It is therefore manifest, that in every city there is some one man, or council, or court, who by right hath as great a power over each single citizen, as each man hath over himself considered out of that civil state; that is, supreme and absolute, to be limited only by the strength and forces of the city itself, and by nothing else in the world. For if his power were limited, that limitation must necessarily proceed from some greater power. For he that prescribes limits, must have a greater power than he who is confined by them. Now that confining power is either without limit, or is again restrained by some other greater than itself; and so we shall at length arrive to a power, which hath no other limit but that which is the _terminus ultimus_ of the forces of all the citizens together. That same is called the supreme command; and if it be committed to a council, a supreme council, but if to one man, the supreme lord of the city. Now the notes of supreme command are these: to make and abrogate laws, to determine war and peace, to know and judge of all controversies, either by himself, or by judges appointed by him; to elect all magistrates, ministers, and counsellors. Lastly, if there be any man who by right can do some one action, which is not lawful for any citizen or citizens to do beside himself, that man hath obtained the supreme power. For those things which by right may not be done by any one or many citizens, the city itself can only do. He therefore that doth those things, useth the city’s right; which is the supreme power. [Sidenote: If the city be compared with a man, he who hath the supreme command is in order to the city, as the human soul is to the man.] 19. They who compare a city and its citizens with a man and his members, almost all say, that he who hath the supreme power in the city is in relation to the whole city, such as the head is to the whole man. But it appears by what hath been already said, that he who is endued with such a power, whether it be a man or a court, hath a relation to the city, not as that of the head, but of the soul to the body. For it is the soul by which a man hath a will, that is, can either will or nill; so by him who hath the supreme power, and no otherwise, the city hath a will, and can either will or nill. A court of counsellors is rather to be compared with the head, or one counsellor, whose only counsel (if of any one alone) the chief ruler makes use of in matters of greatest moment: for the office of the head is to counsel, as the soul’s is to command. [Sidenote: That the supreme power cannot by right be dissolved by their consents, by whose compacts it was constituted;] 20. Forasmuch as the supreme command is constituted by virtue of the compacts which each single citizen or subject mutually makes with the other; but all contracts, as they receive their force from the contractors, so by their consent they lose it again and are broken: perhaps some may infer hence, that by the consent of all the subjects together the supreme authority may be wholly taken away. Which inference, if it were true, I cannot discern what danger would thence by right arise to the supreme commanders. For since it is supposed that each one hath obliged himself to each other; if any one of them shall refuse, whatsoever the rest shall agree to do, he is bound notwithstanding. Neither can any man without injury to me, do that which by contract made with me he hath obliged himself not to do. But it is not to be imagined that ever it will happen, that all the subjects together, not so much as one excepted, will combine against the supreme power. Wherefore there is no fear for rulers in chief, that by any right they can be despoiled of their authority. If, notwithstanding, it were granted that their right depended only on that contract which each man makes with his fellow-citizen, it might very easily happen that they might be robbed of that dominion under pretence of right. For subjects being called either by the command of the city, or seditiously flocking together, most men think that the consents of all are contained in the votes of the greater part; which in truth is false. For it is not from nature that the consent of the major part should be received for the consent of all, neither is it true in tumults; but it proceeds from civil institution: and is then only true, when that man or court which hath the supreme power, assembling his subjects, by reason of the greatness of their number allows those that are elected a power of speaking for those who elected them; and will have the major part of voices, in such matters as are by him propounded to be discussed, to be as effectual as the whole. But we cannot imagine that he who is chief, ever convened his subjects with intention that they should dispute his right; unless weary of the burthen of his charge, he declared in plain terms that he renounces and abandons his government. Now, because most men through ignorance esteem not the consent of the major part of citizens only, but even of a very few, provided they be of their opinion, for the consent of the whole city; it may very well seem to them, that the supreme authority may by right be abrogated, so it be done in some great assembly of citizens by the votes of the greater number. But though a government be constituted by the contracts of particular men with particulars, yet its right depends not on that obligation only; there is another tie also towards him who commands. For each citizen compacting with his fellow, says thus: _I convey my right on this party, upon condition that you pass yours to the same_: by which means, that right which every man had before to use his faculties to his own advantage, is now wholly translated on some certain man or council for the common benefit. Wherefore what by the mutual contracts each one hath made with the other, what by the donation of right which every man is bound to ratify to him that commands, the government is upheld by a double obligation from the citizens; first, that which is due to their fellow-citizens; next, that which they owe to their prince. Wherefore no subjects, how many soever they be, can with any right despoil him who bears the chief rule of his authority, even without his own consent. ------- CHAPTER VII OF THE THREE KINDS OF GOVERNMENT, DEMOCRACY, ARISTOCRACY, MONARCHY. 1. That there are three kinds of government only, democracy, aristocracy, monarchy. 2. That oligarchy is not a diverse form of government distinct from aristocracy, nor anarchy any form at all. 3. That a tyranny is not a diverse state from a legitimate monarchy. 4. That there cannot be a mixed state, fashioned out of these several species. 5. That democracy, except there be certain times and places of meeting prefixed, is dissolved. 6. In a democracy the intervals of the times of meeting must be short, or the administration of government during the interval committed to some one. 7. In a democracy, particulars contract with particulars to obey the people: the people is obliged to no man. 8. By what acts aristocracy is constituted. 9. In an aristocracy the nobles make no compact, neither are they obliged to any citizen or to the whole people. 10. The nobles must necessarily have their set meetings. 11. By what acts monarchy is constituted. 12. Monarchy is by compact obliged to none for the authority it hath received. 13. Monarchy is ever in the readiest capacity to exercise all those acts which are requisite to good government 14. What kind of sin that is, and what sort of men are guilty of it, when the city performs not its office towards the citizens, nor the citizens towards the city. 15. A monarch made without limitation of time hath power to elect his successor. 16. Of limited monarchs. 17. A monarch, retaining his right of government, cannot by any promise whatsoever be conceived to have parted with his right to the means necessary to the exercise of his authority. 18. How a citizen is freed from subjection. [Sidenote: There are three kinds of government only; democracy, aristocracy, and monarchy.] 1. We have already spoken of a city by institution in its genus; we will now say somewhat of its species. As for the difference of cities, it is taken from the difference of the persons to whom the supreme power is committed. This power is committed either to _one man_, or _council_, or some _one court_ consisting of many men. Furthermore, a council of many men consists either of all the citizens, insomuch as every man of them hath a right to vote, and an interest in the ordering of the greatest affairs, if he will himself; or of a part only. From whence there arise three sorts of government; the one, when the power is in a council where every citizen hath a right to vote; and it is called a _democracy_. The other, when it is in a council, where not all, but some part only have their suffrages; and we call it an _aristocracy_. The third is that, when the supreme authority rests only in one; and it is styled a _monarchy_. In the first, he that governs is called δῆμος, the _people_; in the second, the _nobles_; in the third, the _monarch_. [Sidenote: Oligarchy is no state of a city distinct from aristocracy; neither is anarchy any state at all.] 2. Now, although ancient writers of politics have introduced three other kinds of government opposite to these; to wit, _anarchy_ or confusion to _democracy_; _oligarchy_, that is, the command of some few, to _aristocracy_, and _tyranny_ to _monarchy_; yet are not these three distinct forms of government, but three diverse titles given by those who were either displeased with that present government or those that bare rule. For men, by giving names, do usually not only signify the things themselves, but also their own affections, as love, hatred, anger, and the like. Whence it happens that what one man calls a _democracy_, another calls an _anarchy_; what one counts an _aristocracy_, another esteems an _oligarchy_; and whom one titles a _king_, another styles him a _tyrant_. So as we see, these names betoken not a diverse kind of government, but the _diverse opinions_ of the subjects concerning him who hath the supreme power. For first, who sees not that _anarchy_ is equally opposite to all the aforenamed forms? For that word signifies that there is no government at all, that is, not any city. But how is it possible that _no city_ should be the species of _a city_? Furthermore, what difference is there between an _oligarchy_, which signifies the command of a _few_ or _grandees_, or an _aristocracy_, which is that of the _prime_ or _chief heads_, more than that men differ so among themselves, that the same things seem not good to all men? Whence it happens that those persons, who by some are looked on as the _best_, are by others esteemed to be the _worst_ of all men. [Sidenote: That a tyranny is not a diverse state from a legitimate monarchy.] 3. But men, by reason of their passions, will very hardly be persuaded that a _kingdom_ and _tyranny_ are not diverse kinds of cities; who though they would rather have the city subject to one than many, yet do they not believe it to be well governed unless it accord with their judgments. But we must discover by reason, and not by passion, what the difference is between a king and a tyrant. But first, they differ not in this, that a tyrant hath the greater power; for greater than the supreme cannot be granted; nor in this, that one hath a limited power, the other not; for he whose authority is limited, is no king, but his subject that limits him. Lastly, neither differ they in their manner of acquisition; for if in a democratical or aristocratical government some one citizen should, by force, possess himself of the supreme power, if he gain the consent of all the citizens, he becomes a legitimate monarch; if not, he is an enemy, not a tyrant. They differ therefore in the sole exercise of their command, insomuch as he is said to be a king who governs well, and he a tyrant that doth otherwise. The case therefore is brought to this pass; that _a king_, legitimately constituted in his government, if he seem to his subjects to rule well and to their liking, they afford him the appellation of a _king_; if not, they count him a _tyrant_. Wherefore we see a _kingdom_ and _tyranny_ are not diverse forms of government, but one and the self-same monarch hath the name of a _king_ given him in point of honour and reverence to him, and of a _tyrant_ in way of contumely and reproach. But what we frequently find in books said against tyrants, took its original from Greek and Roman writers, whose government was partly democratical, and partly aristocratical, and therefore not tyrants only, but even kings were odious to them. [Sidenote: That there can no mixed state be formed out of these forenamed kinds of government.] 4. There are, who indeed do think it necessary that a supreme command should be somewhere extant in a city; but if it should be in any one, either man or council, it would follow, they say, that all the citizens must be slaves. Avoiding this condition, they imagine that there may be a certain form of government compounded of those three kinds we have spoken of, yet different from each particular; which they call a _mixed monarchy_, or _mixed aristocracy_, or _mixed democracy_, according as any one of these three sorts shall be more eminent than the rest. For example, if the naming of magistrates and the arbitration of war and peace should belong to the King, judicature to the Lords, and contribution of monies to the People, and the power of making laws to all together, this kind of state would they call a _mixed monarchy_ forsooth. But if it were possible that there could be such a state, it would no whit advantage the liberty of the subject. For as long as they all agree, each single citizen is as much subject as possibly he can be: but if they disagree, the state returns to a civil war and the right of the private sword; which certainly is much worse than any subjection whatsoever. But that there can be no such kind of government,[14] hath been sufficiently demonstrated in the foregoing chapter, art. 6-12. Footnote 14: _But that there can be no such kind of government._] Most men grant, that a government ought not to be divided; but they would have it moderated and bounded by some limits. Truly it is very reasonable it should be so; but if these men, when they speak of moderating and limiting, do understand dividing it, they make a very fond distinction. Truly, for my part, I wish that not only kings, but all other persons endued with supreme authority, would so temper themselves as to commit no wrong, and only minding their charges, contain themselves within the limits of the natural and divine laws. But they who distinguish thus, they would have the chief power bounded and restrained by others: which, because it cannot be done but they who do set the limits must needs have some part of the power, whereby they may be enabled to do it, the government is properly divided, not moderated. [Sidenote: That democracy, except it have certain times and places of meeting prescribed, is dissolved.] 5. Let us see a little now, in the constituting of each form of government what the constitutors do. Those who met together with intention to erect a city, were almost in the very act of meeting, a democracy. For in that they willingly met, they are supposed obliged to the observation of what shall be determined by the major part; which, while that convent lasts, or is adjourned to some certain days and places, is a clear democracy. For that convent, whose will is the will of all the citizens, hath the supreme authority; and because in this convent every man is supposed to have a right to give his voice, it follows that it is a democracy, by the definition given in the first article of this chapter. But if they depart and break up the convent, and appoint no time or place where and when they shall meet again, the public weal returns to anarchy and the same state it stood in before their meeting, that is, to the state of all men warring against all. The people, therefore, retains the supreme power, no longer than there is a certain day and place publicly appointed and known, to which whosoever will may resort. For except that be known and determined, they may either meet at divers times and places, that is, in factions, or not at all; and then it is no longer δῆμος, _the people_, but a dissolute multitude, to whom we can neither attribute any action or right. Two things therefore frame a democracy; whereof one, to wit, the perpetual prescription of convents, makes δῆμον, _the people_; the other, which is a plurality of voices, τὸ κράτος, or _the power_. [Sidenote: In democracy, the intervals of the times of convening must be short, or the administration of the government committed to some one.] 6. Furthermore, it will not be sufficient for the people, so as to maintain its supremacy, to have some certain known times and places of meeting, unless that either the intervals of the times be of less distance, than that anything may in the meantime happen whereby, by reason of the defect of power, the city may be brought into some danger; or at least that the exercise of the supreme authority be, during the interval, granted to some one man or council. For unless this be done, there is not that wary care and heed taken for the defence and peace of single men, which ought to be; and therefore it will not deserve the name of a city, because that in it, for want of security, every man’s right of defending himself at his own pleasure returns to him again. [Sidenote: In a democracy, particulars contract with particulars to obey the people: the people is obliged to no man.] 7. Democracy is not framed by contract of particular persons with the _people_, but by mutual compacts of single men each with other. But hence it appears, in the first place, that the persons contracting must be in being before the contract itself. But the _people_ is not in being before the constitution of government, as not being any person, but a multitude of single persons; wherefore there could then no contract pass between the people and the subject. Now, if after that government is framed, the subject make any contract with the people, it is in vain; because the people contains within its will the will of that subject, to whom it is supposed to be obliged; and therefore may at its own will and pleasure disengage itself, and by consequence is now actually free. But in the second place, that single persons do contract each with other, may be inferred from hence; that in vain sure would the city have been constituted, if the citizens had been engaged by no contracts to do or omit what the city should command to be done or omitted. Because, therefore, such kind of compacts must be understood to pass as necessary to the making up of a city, but none can be made (as is already shewed) between the subject and the people; it follows, that they must be made between single citizens, namely, that each man contract to submit his will to the will of the major part, on condition that the rest also do the like. As if every one should say thus: I give up my right unto the people for your sake, on condition that you also deliver up yours for mine. [Sidenote: By what acts an aristocracy is framed.] 8. An _aristocracy_ or council of nobles endowed with supreme authority, receives its original from a democracy, which gives up its right unto it. Where we must understand that certain men distinguished from others, either by eminence of title, blood, or some other character, are propounded to the people, and by plurality of voices are elected; and being elected, the whole right of the people or city is conveyed on them, insomuch as whatsoever the people might do before, the same by right may this court of elected nobles now do. Which being done, it is clear that the people, considered as one person, its supreme authority being already transferred on these, is no longer now in being. [Sidenote: In an aristocracy the nobles make no contract, nor are they obliged to any citizen, or to the whole people.] 9. As in democracy the people, so in an aristocracy the court of nobles is free from all manner of obligation. For seeing subjects not contracting with the people, but by mutual compacts among themselves, were tied to all that the people did; hence also they were tied to that act of the people, in resigning up its right of government into the hands of nobles. Neither could this court, although elected by the people, be by it obliged to anything. For being elected, the people is at once dissolved, as was declared above, and the authority it had as being a person, utterly vanisheth. Wherefore the obligation which was due to the _person_, must also vanish, and perish together with it. [Sidenote: The nobles must necessarily have their set meetings.] 10. _Aristocracy_ hath these considerations, together with _democracy_. First, that without an appointment of some certain times and places, at which the court of nobles may meet, it is no longer a court, or one person, but a dissolute multitude without any supreme power. Secondly, that the times of their assembling cannot be disjoined by long intervals without prejudice to the supreme power, unless its administration be transferred to some one man. Now the reasons why this happens, are the same which we set down in the fifth article. [Sidenote: By what acts a monarchy is framed.] 11. As an _aristocracy_, so also a _monarchy_ is derived from the power of the _people_, transferring its right, that is, its authority on one man. Here also we must understand, that some _one_ man, either by name or some other token, is propounded to be taken notice of above all the rest; and that by a plurality of voices the whole right of the people is conveyed on him; insomuch as whatsoever the people could do before he were elected, the same in every respect may he by right now do, being elected. Which being done, the people is no longer one _person_, but a rude multitude, as being only one before by virtue of the supreme command, whereof they now have made a conveyance from themselves on this one man. [Sidenote: That the monarch is by compact obliged to none for the authority he hath received.] 12. And therefore neither doth the monarch oblige himself to any for the command he receives. For he receives it from the people; but as hath been shewed above, the people, as soon as that act is done, ceaseth to be a _person_; but the _person_ vanishing, obligation to the _person_ vanisheth. The subjects therefore are tied to perform obedience to the monarch, by those compacts only by which they mutually obliged themselves to the observation of all that the people should command them, that is, to obey that _monarch_, if he were made by the _people_. [Sidenote: A monarch is ever in the readier capacity to exercise all those acts which are requisite to well governing.] 13. But a _monarchy_ differs as well from an _aristocracy_ as a _democracy_, in this chiefly; that in those there must be certain set times and places for deliberation and consultation of affairs, that is, for the actual exercise of it in all times and places. For the people or the nobles not being _one natural person_, must necessarily have their meetings. The _monarch_, who is one by nature, is always in a present capacity to execute his authority. [Sidenote: What kind of sin that is, and what sort of men are guilty of it, when the city performs not its office to the citizens, nor the citizens towards the city.] 14. Because we have declared above, (in art. 7, 9, 12), that they who have gotten the _supreme command_, are by no compacts obliged to any man, it necessarily follows, that they can do no _injury_ to the subjects. For _injury_, according to the definition made in chap. III. art. 3, is nothing else but a breach of contract; and therefore where no contracts have part, there can be no injury. Yet the people, the nobles, and the monarch may diverse ways transgress against the other laws of nature, as by cruelty, iniquity, contumely, and other like vices, which come not under this strict and exact notion of _injury_. But if the subject yield not obedience to the supreme, he will in propriety of speech be said to be _injurious_, as well to his fellow-subjects, because each man hath compacted with the other to obey; as to his _chief ruler_, in resuming that right which he hath given him, without his consent. And in a _democracy_ or _aristocracy_, if anything be decreed against any _law of nature_, the city itself, that is, the civil person sins not, but those subjects only by whose votes it was decreed; for sin is a consequence of the natural express will, not of the political, which is artificial. For if it were otherwise, they would be guilty by whom the decree was absolutely disliked. But in a _monarchy_, if the _monarch_ make any decree against the _laws of nature_, he sins himself; because in him the civil will and the natural are all one. [Sidenote: A monarch made without limitation of time, may elect his successors.] 15. The people who are about to make a _monarch_, may give him the _supremacy_ either simply without limitation of time, or for a certain season and time determined. If simply, we must understand that he who receives it, hath the self-same power which they had who gave it. On the same grounds, therefore, that the _people_ by right could make him a monarch, may he make another monarch. Insomuch as the _monarch_ to whom the command is simply given, receives a right not of _possession_ only, but of _succession_ also; so as he may declare whom he pleaseth for his successor. [Sidenote: Of limited monarchs.] 16. But if the power be given for a time limited, we must have regard to somewhat more than the bare gift only. First, whether the _people_ conveying its authority, left itself any right to meet at certain times and places, or not. Next, if it have reserved this power, whether it were done so as they might meet before that time were expired, which they prescribed to the monarch. Thirdly, whether they were contented to meet only at the will of that temporary monarch, and not otherwise. Suppose now the _people_ had delivered up its power to some one man for term of life only; which being done, let us suppose in the first place, that every man departed from the council without making any order at all concerning the place, where after his death they should meet again to make a new election. In this case, it is manifest by the fifth article of this chapter, that the _people_ ceaseth to be a _person_, and is become a dissolute multitude; every one whereof hath an equal, to wit, a natural right to meet with whom he lists at divers times, and in what places shall best please him; nay, and if he can, engross the supreme power to himself, and settle it on his own head. What monarch soever, therefore, hath a command in such a condition, he is bound by the _law of nature_, set down in chap. III. art. 8, _of not returning evil for good_, prudently to provide that by his death the city suffer not a dissolution; either by appointing a certain day and place, in which those subjects of his, who have a mind to it, may assemble themselves, or else by nominating a successor; whether of these shall to him seem most conducible to their common benefit. He therefore, who on this foresaid manner hath received his command during life, hath an absolute power, and may at his discretion dispose of the succession. In the next place, if we grant that the _people_ departed not from the election of the _temporary monarch_, before they decreed a certain time and place of meeting after his death; then the monarch being dead, the authority is confirmed in the people, not by any new acts of the subjects, but by virtue of the former right. For all the supreme command, as _dominion_, was in the people; but the use and exercise of it was only in the temporary monarch, as in one that takes the benefit, but hath not the right. But if the _people_ after the election of a _temporary monarch_, depart not from the court before they have appointed certain times and places to convene during the time prescribed him; as the dictators in ancient times were made by the people of Rome; such an one is not to be accounted a monarch, but the prime officer of the people. And if it shall seem good, the people may deprive him of his office even before that time; as the people of Rome did, when they conferred an equal power on Minutius, master of the horse, with Quintus Fabius Maximus, whom before they had made dictator. The reason whereof is, that it is not to be imagined, that he, whether man or council, who hath the readiest and most immediate power to act, should hold his command on such terms, as not to be able actually to execute it; for command is nothing else but a right of commanding, as oft as nature allows it possible. Lastly, if the _people_ having declared a _temporary monarch_, depart from the court on such terms, as it shall not be lawful for them to meet without the command of the monarch, we must understand the people to be immediately dissolved, and that his authority, who is thus declared, is absolute; forasmuch as it is not in the power of all the subjects to frame the city anew, unless he give consent who hath now alone the authority. Nor matters it, that he hath perhaps made any promise to assemble his subjects on some certain times; since there remains no _person_ now in being, but at his discretion, to whom the promise was made. What we have spoken of these four cases of a _people_ electing a _temporary monarch_, will be more clearly explained by comparing them with an _absolute monarch_ who hath no heir-apparent. For the people is lord of the subject in such a manner, as there can be no heir but whom itself doth appoint. Besides, the spaces between the times of the subjects’ meeting, may be fitly compared to those times wherein the monarch sleeps; for in either the _acts_ of commanding cease, the _power_ remains. Furthermore, to dissolve the convent, so as it cannot meet again, is the death of the _people_; just as sleeping, so as he can never wake more, is the death of a man. As therefore a king who hath no heir, going to his rest so as never to rise again, that is, dying, if he commit the exercise of his regal authority to any one till he awake, does by consequence give him the succession; the _people_ also electing a _temporary monarch_, and not reserving a power to convene, delivers up to him the whole dominion of the country. Furthermore, as a king going to sleep for some season, entrusts the administration of his kingdom to some other, and waking takes it again; so the people having elected a _temporary monarch_, and withal retaining a right to meet at a certain day and place, at that day receives its supremacy again. And as a king who hath committed the execution of his authority to another, himself in the meanwhile waking, can recal this commission again when he pleaseth; so the _people_, who during the time prescribed to the _temporary monarch_ doth by right convene, may if they please deprive the monarch of his authority. Lastly, the king, who commits his authority to another while himself sleeps, not being able to wake again till he whom he entrusted give consent, loses at once both his power and his life; so the people, who hath given the supreme power to a temporary monarch in such sort as they cannot assemble without his command, is absolutely dissolved, and the power remains with him whom they have chosen. [Sidenote: A monarch retaining his right of government, cannot, by any promise whatsoever, be conceived to have parted with his right to the means necessary to the exercise of his authority.] 17. If the monarch _promise_ aught to any one or many subjects together, by consequence whereof the exercise of his power may suffer prejudice, that _promise_ or _compact_, whether made by oath or without it, is null. For all _compact_ is a conveyance of right, which by what hath been said in the fourth article of the second chapter, requires meet and proper signs of the will in the conveyer. But he who sufficiently signifies his will of retaining the end, doth also sufficiently declare that he quits not his right to the means necessary to that end. Now he who hath promised to part with somewhat necessary to the supreme power, and yet retains the power itself, gives sufficient tokens that he no otherwise promised it, than so far forth as the power might be retained without it. Whensoever therefore it shall appear, that what is promised cannot be performed without prejudice to the power, the promise must be valued as not made, that is, of no effect. [Sidenote: By what means a subject is freed from his subjection.] 18. We have seen how subjects, nature dictating, have obliged themselves by mutual compacts to obey the supreme power. We will see now by what means it comes to pass, that they are released from these bonds of obedience. And first of all, this happens by _rejection_, namely, if a man cast off or forsake, but convey not the _right of his command_ on some other. For what is thus rejected, is openly exposed to all alike, catch who catch can; whence again, by the right of nature, every subject may heed the preservation of himself according to his own judgment. In the second place, if the kingdom fall into the power of the enemy, so as there can no more opposition be made against them, we must understand that he who before had the supreme authority, hath now lost it: for when the subjects have done their full endeavour to prevent their falling into the enemy’s hands, they have fulfilled those contracts of obedience which they made each with other; and what, being conquered, they promise afterwards to avoid death, they must with no less endeavour labour to perform. Thirdly, in a monarchy, (for a democracy and aristocracy cannot fail), if there be no successor, all the subjects are discharged from their obligations; for no man is supposed to be tied he knows not to whom; for in such a case it were impossible to perform aught. And by these three ways, all subjects are restored from their civil subjection to that liberty which all men have to all things; to wit, natural and savage; for the natural state hath the same proportion to the civil, (I mean, liberty to subjection), which passion hath to reason, or a beast to a man. Furthermore, each subject may lawfully be freed from his subjection by the will of him who hath the supreme power, namely, if he change his soil; which may be done two ways, either by permission, as he who gets license to dwell in another country; or command, as he who is banished. In both cases, he is free from the laws of his former country; because he is tied to observe those of the latter. ------- CHAPTER VIII. OF THE RIGHTS OF LORDS OVER THEIR SERVANTS. 1. What lord and servant signify. 2. The distinction of servants, into such as upon trust enjoy their natural liberty, and slaves, or such as serve being imprisoned or bound in fetters. 3. The obligation of a servant arises from the liberty of body allowed him by his lord. 4. Servants that are bound, are not by any compacts tied to their lords. 5. Servants have no propriety in their goods against their lord. 6. The lord may sell his servant, or alienate him by testament 7. The lord cannot injure his servant. 8. He that is lord of the lord, is lord also of his servants. 9. By what means servants are freed. 10. Dominion over beasts belongs to the right of nature. [Sidenote: What lord and servant are.] 1. In the two foregoing chapters we have treated of an _institutive_ or _framed_ government, as being that which receives its original from the consent of many, who by contract and faith mutually given have obliged each other. Now follows what may be said concerning a _natural_ government; which may also be called _acquired_, because it is that which is gotten by power and natural force. But we must know in the first place, by what means the right of dominion may be gotten over the persons of men. Where such a right is gotten, there is a kind of a little kingdom; for to be a _king_, is nothing else but to have dominion over many persons; and thus a great family is a kingdom, and a little kingdom a family. Let us return again to the state of nature, and consider men as if but even now sprung out of the earth, and suddenly, like mushrooms, come to full maturity, without all kind of engagement to each other. There are but three ways only, whereby one can have a dominion over the person of another; whereof the first is, if by mutual contract made between themselves, for peace and self-defence’s sake, they have willingly given up themselves to the power and authority of some man, or council of men; and of this we have already spoken. The second is, if a man taken prisoner in the wars, or overcome, or else distrusting his own forces, to avoid death, promises the conqueror or the stronger party his _service_, that is, to do all whatsoever he shall command him. In which contract, the good which the vanquished or inferior in strength doth receive, is the grant of his life, which by the right of war in the natural state of men he might have been deprived of; but the good which he promises, is his service and obedience. By virtue therefore of this promise, there is as absolute service and obedience due from the vanquished to the vanquisher, as possibly can be, excepting what repugns the divine laws; for he who is obliged to obey the commands of any man before he knows what he will command him, is simply and without any restriction tied to the performance of all commands whatsoever. Now he that is thus tied, is called a _servant_; he to whom he is tied, a _lord_. Thirdly, there is a right acquired over the person of a man by generation; of which kind of acquisition somewhat shall be spoken in the following chapter. [Sidenote: The distinction of servants, into such as upon trust enjoy their natural liberty, and slaves, or such as serve being imprisoned or fettered.] 2. Every one that is taken in the war, and hath his life spared him, is not supposed to have contracted with his lord; for every one is not trusted with so much of his natural liberty, as to be able, if he desired it, either to fly away, or quit his service, or contrive any mischief to his lord. And these serve indeed, but within prisons or bound within irons; and therefore they were called not by the common name of _servant_ only, but by the peculiar name of _slave_; even as now at this day, _un serviteur_, and _un serf_, or _un esclave_ have diverse significations. [Sidenote: The obligation of a servant ariseth from that freedom which is granted him by his lord.] 3. The obligation therefore of a _servant_ to his _lord_, ariseth not from a simple grant of his life; but from hence rather, that he keeps him not bound or imprisoned. For all obligation derives from contract; but where there is no trust, there can be no contract, as appears by chap. ii. art. 9; where a compact is defined to be the promise of him who is trusted. There is therefore a confidence and trust which accompanies the benefit of pardoned life, whereby the _lord_ affords him his corporal liberty; so that if no obligation nor bonds of contract had happened, he might not only have made his escape, but also have killed his lord who was the preserver of his life. [Sidenote: Servants that are bound, are not obliged to their lord by any contract.] 4. Wherefore such kind of _servants_ as are restrained by imprisonment or bonds, are not comprehended in that definition of _servants_ given above; because those serve not for the contract’s sake, but to the end they may not suffer. And therefore if they fly, or kill their _lord_, they offend not against the laws of nature. For to bind any man, is a plain sign that the binder supposes him that is bound, not to be sufficiently tied by any other obligation. [Sidenote: Servants have no propriety in their goods against their lord.] 5. The lord therefore hath no less dominion over a servant that is not, than over one that is bound; for he hath a supreme power over both, and may say of his servant no less than of another thing, whether animate or inanimate, _this is mine_. Whence it follows, that whatsoever the servant had before his servitude, that afterwards becomes the lord’s; and whatsoever he hath gotten, it was gotten for his lord. For he that can by right dispose of the _person_ of a man, may surely dispose of all those things which that _person_ could dispose of. There is therefore nothing which the servant may retain as his own against the will of his lord; yet hath he, by his lord’s distribution, a propriety and dominion over his own goods: insomuch as one servant may keep and defend them against the invasion of his fellow-servant, in the same manner as hath been shewed before, that a subject hath nothing properly _his own_ against the will of the supreme authority, but every subject hath a propriety against his fellow-subject. [Sidenote: The lord may sell his servant, or alienate him by testament.] 6. Since therefore both the servant himself, and all that belongs to him are his lord’s, and by the right of nature every man may dispose of his own in what manner he pleases; the lord may either sell, lay to pledge, or by testament convey the dominion he hath over his servant, according to his own will and pleasure. [Sidenote: The lord cannot be injurious to his servant.] 7. Furthermore, what hath before been demonstrated concerning subjects in an _institutive_ government, namely, that he who hath the supreme power can do his subject no injury; is true also concerning _servants_, because they have subjected their will to the will of the Lord. Wherefore, whatsoever he doth, it is done with their will; but no injury can be done to him that willeth it. [Sidenote: He that is lord of the lord, is lord also of his servants.] 8. But if it happen that the _lord_, either by captivity or voluntary subjection, doth become a _servant_ or _subject_ to another, that other shall not only be lord of him, but also of his _servants_; supreme lord over these, immediate lord over him. Now because not the servant only, but also all he hath, are his lord’s; therefore his servants now belong to this man, neither can the mediate lord dispose otherwise of them than shall seem good to the supreme. And therefore, if sometime in civil governments the lord have an absolute power over his servants, that is supposed to be derived from the right of nature, and not constituted, but slightly passed over by the civil law. [Sidenote: By what means servants are freed.] 9. A servant is by the same manner freed from his servitude, that a subject in an institutive government is freed from his subjection. First, if his lord enfranchise him; for the right which the servant transferred to his lord over himself, the same may the lord restore to the servant again. And this manner of bestowing of liberty is called _manumission_; which is just as if a city should permit a citizen to convey himself under the jurisdiction of some other city. Secondly, if the lord cast off his servant from him; which in a city is _banishment_; neither differs it from _manumission_ in effect, but in manner only. For there, liberty is granted as a favour, here, as a punishment: in both, the dominion is renounced. Thirdly, if the servant be taken prisoner, the old servitude is abolished by the new; for as all other things, so servants also are acquired by war, whom in equity the lord must protect, if he will have them to be his. Fourthly, the servant is freed for want of knowledge of a successor, the lord dying (suppose) without any testament or heir. For no man is understood to be obliged, unless he know to whom he is to perform the obligation. Lastly, the servant that is put in bonds, or by any other means deprived of his corporal liberty, is freed from that other obligation of contract. For there can be no contract where there is no trust, nor can that faith be broken which is not given. But the _lord_ who himself serves another, cannot so free his _servants_, but that they must still continue under the power of the supreme; for, as hath been shewed before, such servants are not his, but the supreme lord’s. [Sidenote: The dominion over beasts is by the right of nature.] 10. We get a right over irrational creatures, in the same manner that we do over the persons of men; to wit, by force and natural strength. For if in the state of nature it is lawful for every one, by reason of that war which is of all against all, to subdue and also to kill men as oft as it shall seem to conduce unto their good; much more will the same be lawful against brutes; namely, at their own discretion to reduce those to servitude, which by art may be tamed and fitted for use, and to persecute and destroy the rest by a perpetual war as dangerous and noxious. Our dominion therefore over beasts, hath its original from the _right of nature_, not from _divine positive right_. For if such a right had not been before the publishing of the Sacred Scriptures, no man by right might have killed a beast for his food, but he to whom the divine pleasure was made manifest by holy writ; a most hard condition for men indeed, whom the beasts might devour without injury, and yet they might not destroy them. Forasmuch therefore as it proceeds from the right of nature, that a beast may kill a man, it is also by the same right that a man may slay a beast. ------- CHAPTER IX. OF THE RIGHT OF PARENTS OVER THEIR CHILDREN, AND OF HEREDITARY GOVERNMENT. 1. Paternal dominion ariseth not from generation. 2. Dominion over infants belongs to him or her who first hath them in their power. 3. Dominion over infants is originally the mother’s. 4. The exposed infant is his, from whom he receives his preservation. 5. The child that hath one parent a subject, and the other a sovereign, belongs to him or her in authority. 6. In such a conjunction of man and woman, as neither hath command over the other, the children are the mother’s, unless by compact or civil law it be otherwise determined. 7. Children are no less subject to their parents, than servants to their lords and subjects to their princes. 8. Of the honour of parents and lords. 9. Wherein liberty consists, and the difference of subjects and servants. 10. There is the same right over subjects in an hereditary government, which there is in an institutive government. 11. The question concerning the right of succession belongs only to monarchy. 12. A monarch may by his will and testament dispose of his supreme authority: 13. Or give it, or sell it. 14. A monarch dying without testament, is ever supposed to will that a monarch should succeed him: 15. And some one of his children: 16. And a male rather than female: 17. And the eldest rather than the younger: 18. And his brother, if he want issue, before all others. 19. In the same manner that men succeed to the power, do they also succeed to the right of succession. [Sidenote: Paternal dominion ariseth not from generation.] 1. SOCRATES _is a man, and therefore a living creature_, is right reasoning; and that most evident, because there is nothing needful to the acknowledging of the truth of the consequence, but that the word _man_ be understood; because _a living creature_ is in the definition itself of _a man_, and every one makes up the proposition which was desired, namely this, _man is a living creature_. And this, _Sophroniscus is Socrates’ father, and therefore his lord_, is perhaps a true inference, but not evident; because the word _lord_ is not in the definition of _a father_: wherefore it is necessary, to make it more evident, that the connexion of _father_ and _lord_ be somewhat unfolded. Those that have hitherto endeavoured to prove the dominion of a parent over his children, have brought no other argument than that of _generation_; as if it were of itself evident, that what is begotten by me is mine; just as if a man should think, that because there is a triangle, it appears presently, without any further discourse, that its angles are equal to two right. Besides, since dominion, that is, supreme power is indivisible, insomuch as no man can serve two masters; but two persons, male and female, must concur in the act of generation; it is impossible that dominion should at all be acquired by generation only. Wherefore we will, with the more diligence, in this place inquire into the original of _paternal government_. [Sidenote: Dominion over infants belongs to him who first hath them in his power.] 2. We must therefore return to the state of nature, in which, by reason of the equality of nature, all men of riper years are to be accounted equal. There _by right of nature_ the conqueror is lord of the conquered. By the right therefore of _nature_, the dominion over the infant first belongs to him who first hath him in his power. But it is manifest that he who is newly born, is in the _mother’s_ power before any others; insomuch as she may rightly, and at her own will, either breed him up or adventure him to fortune. [Sidenote: Dominion over infants is originally the mother’s.] 3. If therefore she breed him, because the state of nature is the state of war, she is supposed to bring him up on this condition; that being grown to full age he become not her enemy; which is, that he obey her. For since by natural necessity we all desire that which appears good unto us, it cannot be understood that any man hath on such terms afforded life to another, that he might both get strength by his years, and at once become an enemy. But each man is an enemy to that other, whom he neither obeys nor commands. And thus in the state of nature, every woman that bears children, becomes both a _mother_ and a _lord_. But what some say, that in this case the _father_, by reason of the pre-eminence of sex, and not the _mother_ becomes _lord_, signifies nothing. For both reason shows the contrary; because the inequality of their natural forces is not so great, that the man could get the dominion over the woman without war. And custom also contradicts not; for women, namely Amazons, have in former times waged war against their adversaries, and disposed of their children at their own wills. And at this day, in divers places women are invested with the principal authority; neither do their husbands dispose of their children, but themselves; which in truth they do _by the right of nature_; forasmuch as they who have the supreme power, are not tied at all (as hath been shewed) to the civil laws. Add also, that in the state of nature it cannot be known who is the _father_, but by the testimony of the _mother_; the child therefore is his whose the mother will have it, and therefore her’s. Wherefore original dominion over _children_ belongs to the _mother_: and among men no less than other creatures, the birth follows the belly. [Sidenote: The exposed infant is his that preserves him.] 4. The dominion passes from the mother to others, divers ways. First, if she quit and forsake her right by _exposing_ the child. He therefore that shall bring up the child thus exposed, shall have the same dominion over it which the mother had. For that life which the mother had given it, (not by _getting_ but _nourishing_ it), she now by _exposing_ takes from it. Wherefore the obligation also which arose from the benefit of life, is by this exposition made void. Now the preserved oweth all to the preserver, whether in regard of his education as to a _mother_, or of his service as to a _lord_. For although the mother in the state of nature, where all men have a right to all things, may recover her son again, namely, by the same right that anybody else might do it; yet may not the son rightly transfer himself again unto his mother. [Sidenote: The son of a subject and chief, is his that commands.] 5. Secondly, if the mother be taken prisoner, her son is his that took her; because that he who hath dominion over the person, hath also dominion over all belonging to the person; wherefore over the son also, as hath been shewed in the foregoing chapter, in the fifth article. Thirdly, if the mother be a subject under what government soever, he that hath the supreme authority in that government, will also have the dominion over him that is born of her; for he is lord also of the mother, who is bound to obey him in all things. Fourthly, if a woman for society’s sake give herself to a man on this condition, that he shall bear the sway; he that receives his being from the contribution of both parties, is the _father’s_, in regard of the command he hath over the _mother_. But if a woman bearing rule shall have children by a subject, the children are the _mother’s_; for otherwise the woman can have no children without prejudice to her authority. And universally, if the society of the male and female be such an union, as the one have subjected himself to the other, the children belong to him or her that commands. [Sidenote: In such a conjunction of male and female, as neither hath the commanding power over the other, the children are the mother’s; except by pact or civil law it be otherwise determined.] 6. But in the state of nature, if a man and woman contract so, as neither is subject to the command of the other, the children are the mother’s, for the reasons above given in the third article, unless by pacts it be otherwise provided. For the _mother_ may by pact dispose of her right as she lists; as heretofore hath been done by the Amazons, who of those children which have been begotten by their neighbours, have by pact allowed them the _males_, and retained _females_ to themselves. But in a civil government, if there be a contract of marriage between a man and woman, the children are the _father’s_; because in all cities, to wit, constituted of _fathers_, not _mothers_ governing their families, the domestical command belongs to the man; and such a contract, if it be made according to the civil laws, is called matrimony. But if they agree only to lie together, the children are the _father’s_ or the _mother’s_ variously, according to the differing civil laws of divers cities. [Sidenote: Children are no less subject to their parents, than servants to their lords, and subjects to their city.] 7. Now because, by the third article, the _mother is originally lord of her children_, and from her the father, or somebody else by derived right; it is manifest that the children are no less subject to those by whom they are nourished and brought up, than servants to their lords, and subjects to him who bears the supreme rule; and that a parent cannot be injurious to his son, as long as he is under his power. A son also is freed from subjection in the same manner as a subject and servant are. For _emancipation_ is the same thing with _manumission_, and _abdication_ with _banishment_. [Sidenote: Of the honour due to parents and lords.] 8. The _enfranchised son_ or _released servant_, do now stand in less fear of their _lord_ and _father_, being deprived of his natural and lordly power over them; and, if regard be had to true and inward honour, do honour him less than before. For _honour_, as hath been said in the section above, is nothing else but the estimation of another’s power; and therefore he that hath least power, hath always least _honour_. But it is not to be imagined, that the _enfranchiser_ ever intended so to match the _enfranchised_ with himself, as that he should not so much as acknowledge a benefit, but should so carry himself in all things as if he were become wholly his equal. It must therefore be ever understood, that he who is freed from subjection, whether he be a _servant_, _son_, or some _colony_, doth promise all those external signs at least, whereby superiors used to be honoured by their inferiors. From whence it follows, that the precept of _honouring our parents_, belongs to the law of nature, not only under the title of _gratitude_, but also of _agreement_. [Sidenote: Wherein liberty doth consist; and the difference between subjects and servants.] 9. What then, will some one demand, is the difference between a _son_, or between a _subject_ and a _servant_? Neither do I know that any writer hath fully declared what _liberty_ and what _slavery_ is. Commonly, to do all things according to our own fancies, and that without punishment, is esteemed to be _liberty_; not to be able to do this, is judged _bondage_; which in a civil government, and with the peace of mankind, cannot possibly be done; because there is no city without a command and a restraining right. _Liberty_, that we may define it, is nothing else but _an absence of the lets and hindrances of motion_; as water shut up in a vessel is therefore not at liberty, because the vessel hinders it from running out; which, the vessel being broken, is made _free_. And every man hath more or less _liberty_, as he hath more or less space in which he employs himself: as he hath more _liberty_, who is in a large, than he that is kept in a close prison. And a man may be free toward one part, and yet not toward another; as the traveller is bounded on this and that side with hedges or stone walls, lest he spoil the vines or corn neighbouring on the highway. And these kinds of lets are external and absolute. In which sense all _servants_ and _subjects_ are _free_, who are not fettered and imprisoned. There are others which are arbitrary, which do not absolutely hinder motion, but by accident, to wit, by our own choice; as he that is in a ship, is not so hindered but he may cast himself into the sea, if he will. And here also the more ways a man may move himself, the more _liberty_ he hath. And herein consists civil _liberty_; for no man, whether _subject_, _son_, or _servant_, is so hindered by the punishments appointed by the _city_, the _father_, or the _lord_, how cruel soever, but that he may do all things, and make use of all means necessary to the preservation of his life and health. For my part therefore I cannot find what reason a mere _servant_ hath to make complaints, if they relate only to want of _liberty_; unless he count it a misery to be restrained from hurting himself, and to receive that life, which by war, or misfortune, or through his own idleness was forfeited, together with all manner of sustenance, and all things necessary to the conservation of health, on this condition only, that he will be ruled. For he that is kept in by punishments laid before him, so as he dares not let loose the reins to his will in all things, is not oppressed by servitude, but is governed and sustained. But this privilege free subjects and sons of a family have above servants in every government and family where servants are; that they may both undergo the more honourable offices of the city or family, and also enjoy a larger possession of things superfluous. And herein lies the difference between a _free subject_ and a _servant_, that he is _free_ indeed, who serves his city only; but a _servant_ is he, who also serves his fellow-subject. All other liberty is an exemption from the laws of the city, and proper only to those that bear rule. [Sidenote: There is the same right in an hereditary, which there is in an institutive government.] 10. A _father_ with his _sons_ and _servants_, grown into a civil person by virtue of his paternal jurisdiction, is called a _family_. This _family_, if through multiplying of _children_ and acquisition of _servants_ it becomes numerous, insomuch as without casting the uncertain die of war it cannot be subdued, will be termed an _hereditary kingdom_. Which though it differ from an _institutive monarchy_, being acquired by force, in the original and manner of its constitution; yet being constituted, it hath all the same properties, and the right of authority is everywhere the same; insomuch as it is not needful to speak anything of them apart. [Sidenote: The question concerning the right of succession belongs only to monarchy.] 11. It hath been spoken, by what right supreme authorities are constituted. We must now briefly tell you, by what right they may be continued. Now the right by which they are continued, is that which is called the right of _succession_. Now because in a _democracy_ the supreme authority is with the _people_, as long as there be any subjects in being, so long it rests with the same person; for the people hath no successor. In like manner in an _aristocracy_, one of the nobles dying, some other by the rest is substituted in his place; and therefore except they all die together, which I suppose will never happen, there is no succession. The query therefore of the right of succession takes place only in an _absolute monarchy_. For they who exercise the supreme power for a time only, are themselves no _monarchs_, but _ministers_ of state. [Sidenote: A monarch may dispose of the command of his government by testament:] 12. But first, if a monarch shall by testament appoint one to succeed him, the person appointed shall succeed. For if he be appointed by the _people_, he shall have all the right over the city which the _people_ had, as hath been showed in chap. VII. art. 11. But the people might choose him; by the same right therefore may he choose another. But in an _hereditary kingdom_, there are the same rights as in an _institutive_. Wherefore every monarch may by his will make a _successor_. [Sidenote: Or give it away, or sell it.] 13. But what a man may transfer on another by testament, that by the same right may he, yet living, give or sell away. To whomsoever therefore he shall make over the supreme power, whether by gift or sale, it is rightly made. [Sidenote: A monarch dying without testament, is ever understood to will that a monarch should succeed him:] 14. But if living he have not declared his will concerning his successor by testament nor otherwise, it is supposed, first, that he would not have his government reduced to an anarchy or the state of war, that is, to the destruction of his subjects; as well because he could not do that without breach of the laws of nature, whereby he was obliged to the performance of all things necessarily conducing to the preservation of peace; as also because, if that had been his will, it had not been hard for him to have declared that openly. Next, because the right passeth according to the will of the father, we must judge of the _successor_ according to the signs of his will. It is understood therefore, that he would have his subjects to be under a _monarchical_ government, rather than any other, because he himself in ruling hath before approved of that state by his example, and hath not afterward either by any word or deed condemned it. [Sidenote: And some one of his children:] 15. Furthermore, because by natural necessity all men wish them better, from whom they receive glory and honour, than others; but every man after death receives honour and glory from his children, sooner than from the power of any other men: hence we gather, that a father intends better for his children than any other person’s. It is to be understood therefore, that the will of the father, dying without testament, was that some of his children should succeed him. Yet this is to be understood with this proviso, that there be no more apparent tokens to the contrary: of which kind, after many successions, custom may be one. For he that makes no mention of his _succession_, is supposed to consent to the customs of his realm. [Sidenote: And a male rather than female:] 16. Among children the males carry the pre-eminence; in the beginning perhaps, because for the most part, although not always, they are fitter for the administration of greater matters, but specially of wars; but afterwards, when it was grown a custom, because that custom was not contradicted. And therefore the will of the father, unless some other custom or sign do clearly repugn it, is to be interpreted in favour of them. [Sidenote: And of the males, the eldest rather than the younger:] 17. Now because the sons are equal, and the power cannot be divided, the eldest shall succeed. For if there be any difference by reason of age, the eldest is supposed more worthy; for nature being judge, the most in years (because usually it is so) is the wisest; but other judge there cannot be had. But if the brothers must be equally valued, the succession shall be _by lot_. But _primogeniture_ is a natural lot, and by this the eldest is already preferred; nor is there any that hath power to judge, whether by this or any other kind of lots the matter is to be decided. Now the same reason which contends thus for the first-born son, doth no less for the first-born daughter. [Sidenote: And his brother, if he want issue, before all others.] 18. But if he have no children, then the command shall pass to his brothers and sisters; for the same reason that the children should have succeeded, if he had had them. For those that are nearest to us in nature, are supposed to be nearest in benevolence. And to his brothers sooner than his sisters, and to the elder sooner than the younger; for the reason is the same for these, that it was for the children. [Sidenote: In the same manner that men succeed to the power, do they also succeed to the right of succession.] 19. Furthermore, by the same reason that men succeed to the power, do they also succeed to the right of succession. For if the first-born die before the father, it will be judged that he transferred his right of succession unto his children; unless the father have otherwise decreed it. And therefore the nephews will have a fairer pretence to the succession, than the uncles. I say all these things will be thus, if the custom of the place (which the father by not contradicting will be judged to have consented to) do not hinder them. ------- CHAPTER X. COMPARISON BETWEEN THREE KINDS OF GOVERNMENT ACCORDING TO THEIR SEVERAL INCONVENIENCES. 1. A comparison of the natural state with the civil. 2. The conveniences and inconveniences of the ruler and his subjects are alike. 3. The praise of monarchy. 4. The government under one, cannot be said to be unreasonable in this respect, namely, because one hath more power than all the rest. 5. A rejection of their opinion, who say, that a lord with his servants cannot make a city. 6. Exactions are more grievous under a popular state, than a monarchy. 7. Innocent subjects are less exposed to penalties under a monarch, than under the people. 8. The liberty of single subjects is not less under a monarch, than under a people. 9. It is no disadvantage to the subjects, that they are not all admitted to public deliberations. 10. Civil deliberations are unadvisedly committed to great assemblies, by reason of the unskilfulness of the most part of men: 11. In regard of eloquence: 12. In regard of faction: 13. In regard of the unstableness of the laws: 14. In regard of the want of secrecy. 15. That these inconveniences adhere to democracy, forasmuch as men are naturally delighted with the esteem of wit. 16. The inconveniences of a city arising from a king that is a child. 17. The power of generals is an evident sign of the excellence of monarchy. 18. The best state of a city is that, where the subjects are the ruler’s inheritance. 19. The nearer aristocracy draws to monarchy, the better it is; the further it keeps from it, the worse. [Sidenote: A comparing the state of nature with the civil.] 1. What _democracy_, _aristocracy_, and _monarchy_ are, hath already been spoken; but which of them tends most to the preservation of the subjects’ peace and procuring their advantages, we must see by comparing them together. But first let us set forth the advantages and disadvantages of a city in general; lest some perhaps should think it better, that every man be left to live at his own will, than to constitute any society at all. Every man indeed out of the state of civil government hath a most entire, but unfruitful liberty; because that he who by reason of his own liberty acts all at his own will, must also by reason of the same liberty in others suffer all at another’s will. But in a constituted city, every subject retains to himself as much freedom as suffices him to live well and quietly; and there is so much taken away from others, as may make them not to be feared. Out of this state, every man hath such a right to all, as yet he can enjoy nothing; in it, each one securely enjoys his limited right. Out of it, any man may rightly spoil or kill another; in it, none but one. Out of it, we are protected by our own forces; in it, by the power of all. Out of it, no man is sure of the fruit of his labours; in it, all men are. Lastly, out of it, there is a dominion of passions, war, fear, poverty, slovenliness, solitude, barbarism, ignorance, cruelty; in it, the dominion of reason, peace, security, riches, decency, society, elegancy, sciences, and benevolence. [Sidenote: The gains and losses of the ruler and his subjects are alike.] 2. Aristotle, in his seventh book and fourteenth chapter of his _Politics_, saith, that there are two sorts of governments; whereof the one relates to the benefit of the _ruler_, the other to that of the _subjects_. As if where _subjects_ are severely dealt with, there were one, and where more mildly, there were another form of government. Which opinion may by no means be subscribed to; for all the profits and disprofits arising from government are the same, and common both to the _ruler_ and the _subject_. The damages which befall some particular subjects through misfortune, folly, negligence, sloth, or his own luxury, may very well be severed from those which concern the ruler. But those relate not to the government itself, being such as may happen in any form of government whatsoever. If these same happen from the first institution of the city, they will then be truly called the inconveniences of government; but they will be common to the ruler with his subjects, as their benefits are common. But the first and greatest benefit, peace and defence, is to both; for both he that commands, and he who is commanded, to the end that he may defend his life makes use at once of all the forces of his fellow-subjects. And in the greatest inconvenience that can befall a city, namely, the slaughter of subjects arising from anarchy, both the commander and the parties commanded are equally concerned. Next, if the ruler levy such a sum of vast moneys from his subjects, as they are not able to maintain themselves and their families, nor conserve their bodily strength and vigor, the disadvantage is as much his as theirs, who, with never so great a stock or measure of riches, is not able to keep his authority or his riches without the bodies of his subjects. But if he raise no more than is sufficient for the due administration of his power, that is a benefit equally to himself and his subjects, tending to a common peace and defence. Nor is it imaginable which way _public_ treasures can be a grievance to _private_ subjects, if they be not so exhausted as to be wholly deprived from all possibility to acquire, even by their industry, necessaries to sustain the strength of their bodies and minds. For even thus the grievance would concern the ruler; nor would it arise from the ill-institution or ordination of the government, because in all manner of governments subjects may be oppressed; but from the ill-administration of a well-established government. [Sidenote: The praise of monarchy.] 3. Now that _monarchy_, of the foresaid forms of _democracy_, _aristocracy_, and _monarchy_, hath the pre-eminence, will best appear by comparing the conveniences and inconveniences arising in each one of them. Those arguments therefore, that the _whole_ universe is governed by _one_ God; that the ancients preferred the monarchical state before all others, ascribing the rule of the gods to one Jupiter; that in the beginning of affairs and of nations, the decrees of princes were held for laws; that paternal government, instituted by God himself in the creation, was monarchical; that other governments were compacted by the artifice of men[15] out of the ashes of monarchy, after it had been ruined with seditions; and that the people of God were under the jurisdiction of kings: although, I say, these do hold forth _monarchy_ as the more eminent to us, yet because they do it by examples and testimonies, and not by solid reason, we will pass them over. Footnote 15: _Compacted by the artifice of men, &c._] It seems the ancients who made that same fable of Prometheus, pointed at this. They say that Prometheus, having stolen fire from the sun, formed a man out of clay, and that for this deed he was tortured by Jupiter with a perpetual gnawing in his liver. Which is, that by human invention, which is signified by Prometheus, laws and justice were by imitation taken from monarchy; by virtue whereof, as by fire removed from its natural orb, the multitude, as the dirt and dregs of men, was as it were quickened and formed into a civil person; which is termed aristocracy or democracy. But the author and abettors being found, who might securely and quietly have lived under the natural jurisdiction of kings, do thus smart for it; that being exposed still to alteration, they are tormented with perpetual cares, suspicions, and dissensions. [Sidenote: The government of one cannot be said to be evil in this respect, namely, because one hath more power than all the rest.] 4. Some there are, who are discontented with the government under _one_, for no other reason but because it is under _one_; as if it were an unreasonable thing, that _one_ man among so many should so far excel in power, as to be able at his own pleasure to dispose of all the rest. These men, sure, if they could, would withdraw themselves from under the dominion of _one_ God. But this exception against _one_ is suggested by envy, while they see one man in possession of what all desire. For the same cause, they would judge it to be as unreasonable if a _few_ commanded, unless they themselves either were, or hoped to be of the number. For if it be an unreasonable thing that all men have not an equal right, surely an aristocracy must be unreasonable also. But because we have showed that the state of equality is the state of war, and that therefore inequality was introduced by a general consent; this inequality, whereby he whom we have voluntarily given more to, enjoys more, is no longer to be accounted an unreasonable thing. The inconveniences therefore which attend the dominion of _one_ man, attend his _person_, not his _unity_. Let us therefore see whether brings with it the greater grievances to the subject, the command of _one_ man, or of _many_. [Sidenote: Rejection of their opinion, who say that a lord with his servants cannot make a city.] 5. But first we must remove their opinion, who deny that to be any city at all, which is compacted of never so great a number of servants under a common lord. In the ninth article of the fifth chapter, a city is defined to be _one person_ made out of _many men_, whose will by their own contracts is to be esteemed as the wills of them all; insomuch as he may use the strength and faculties of each single person for the public peace and safety. And by the same article of the same chapter, _one person_ is that, when the wills of many are contained in the will of one. But the will of each servant is contained in the will of his lord; as hath been declared in the fifth article of the eighth chapter; so as he may employ all their forces and faculties according to his own will and pleasure. It follows therefore that that must needs be a city, which is constituted by _a lord and many servants_. Neither can any reason be brought to contradict this, which doth not equally combat against a city constituted by _a father and his sons_. For to a lord who hath no children, _servants_ are in the nature of _sons_; for they are both his honour and safeguard; neither are _servants_ more subject to their _lords_, then _children_ to their _parents_, as hath been manifested above in the fifth article of the eighth chapter. [Sidenote: The exactions are more grievous under command of the people, than under the monarch.] 6. Among other grievances of supreme authority one is, that the ruler, beside those monies necessary for public charges, as the maintaining of public ministers, building, and defending of castles, waging wars, honourably sustaining his own household, may also, if he will, exact others through his lust, whereby to enrich his sons, kindred, favourites, and flatterers too. I confess this is a grievance, but of the number of those which accompany all kinds of government, but are more tolerable in a _monarchy_ than in a _democracy_. For though the monarch would enrich them, they cannot be many, because belonging but to one. But in a _democracy_, look how many demagogues, that is, how many powerful orators there are with the people, (which ever are many, and daily new ones growing), so many children, kinsmen, friends, and flatterers are to be rewarded. For every of them desire not only to make their families as potent, as illustrious in wealth, as may be, but also to oblige others to them by benefits, for the better strengthening of themselves. A _monarch_ may in great part satisfy his officers and friends, because they are not many, without any cost to his subjects; I mean without robbing them of any of those treasures given in for the maintenance of war and peace. In a _democracy_, where many are to be satisfied, and always new ones, this cannot be done without the subject’s oppression. Though a _monarch_ may promote unworthy persons, yet oft times he will not do it; but in a _democracy_, all the popular men are therefore supposed to do it, because it is necessary; for else the power of them who did it, would so increase, as it would not only become dreadful to those others, but even to the whole city also. [Sidenote: Innocent subjects are less obnoxious to punishment under a monarch, than under the people.] 7. Another grievance is, that same perpetual fear of death, which every man must necessarily be in while he considers with himself, that the ruler hath power not only to appoint what punishments he lists on any transgressions, but that he may also in his wrath and sensuality slaughter his innocent subjects, and those who never offended against the laws. And truly this is a very great grievance in any form of government, wheresoever it happens; for it is therefore a grievance, because it is, not because it may be done. But it is the fault of the ruler, not of the government. For all the acts of Nero are not essential to monarchy; yet subjects are less often undeservedly condemned under _one ruler_, than under the _people_. For kings are only severe against those who either trouble them with impertinent counsels, or oppose them with reproachful words, or control their wills; but they are the cause that that excess of power which one subject might have above another, becomes harmless. Wherefore some Nero or Caligula reigning, no men can undeservedly suffer but such as are known to him, namely, courtiers, and such as are remarkable for some eminent charge; and not all neither, but they only who are possessed of what he desires to enjoy. For they that are offensive and contumelious, are deservedly punished. Whosoever therefore in a _monarchy_ will lead a retired life, let him be what he will that reigns, he is out of danger. For the ambitious only suffer; the rest are protected from the injuries of the more potent. But in a popular dominion, there may be as many Neros as there are orators who soothe the _people_. For each one of them can do as much as the _people_, and they mutually give way to each other’s appetite, as it were by this secret pact, _spare me to-day and I’ll spare thee to-morrow_, while they exempt those from punishment, who to satisfy their lust and private hatred have undeservedly slain their fellow-subjects. Furthermore, there is a certain limit in private power, which if it exceed, it may prove pernicious to the realm; and by reason whereof it is necessary sometimes for _monarchs_ to have a care, that the common weal do thence receive no prejudice. When therefore this power consisted in the multitude of riches, they lessened it by diminishing their heaps; but if it were in popular applause, the powerful party, without any other crime laid to his charge, was taken from among them. The same was usually practised in _democracies_. For the Athenians inflicted a punishment of ten years’ banishment on those that were powerful, merely because of their powers, without the guilt of any other crime. And those who by liberal gifts did seek the favour of the common people, were put to death at Rome, as men ambitious of a kingdom. In this _democracy_ and _monarchy_ were even; yet differed they much in fame. Because fame derives from the people; and what is done by many, is commended by many. And therefore what the _monarch_ does, is said to be done out of envy to their virtues; which if it were done by the _people_, would be accounted policy. [Sidenote: Single persons have no less liberty under a monarch, than under the people.] 8. There are some, who therefore imagine _monarchy_ to be more grievous then _democracy_, because there is less liberty in that, than in this. If by liberty they mean an exemption from that subjection which is due to the laws, that is, the commands of the _people_; neither in _democracy_, nor in any other state of government whatsoever, is there any such kind of liberty. If they suppose liberty to consist in this, that there be few laws, few prohibitions, and those too such, that except they were forbidden, there could be no peace; then I deny that there is more liberty in _democracy_ than _monarchy_; for the one as truly consisteth with such a liberty, as the other. For although the word _liberty_ may in large and ample letters be written over the gates of any city whatsoever, yet is it not meant the _subject’s_, but the _city’s_ liberty; neither can that word with better right be inscribed on a city which is governed by the _people_, than that which is ruled by a _monarch_. But when private men or subjects demand liberty, under the name of liberty they ask not for liberty, but _dominion_; which yet for want of understanding they little consider. For if every man would grant the same liberty to another, which he desires for himself, as is commanded by the law of nature; that same natural state would return again, in which all men may by right do all things; which if they knew, they would abhor, as being worse than all kinds of civil subjection whatsoever. But if any man desire to have his single freedom, the rest being bound, what does he else demand but to have the _dominion_? For whoso is freed from all bonds, is lord over all those that still continue bound. Subjects therefore have no greater liberty in a _popular_, than in a _monarchical_ state. That which deceives them, is the equal participation of command and public places. For where the authority is in the people, single subjects do so far forth share in it, as they are parts of the people ruling; and they equally partake in public offices, so far forth as they have equal voices in choosing magistrates and public ministers. And this is that which Aristotle aimed at, himself also through the custom of that time miscalling dominion liberty. (_Polit._ lib. vi. cap. 2.) _In a popular state there is liberty by supposition; which is a speech of the vulgar, as if no man were free out of this state._ From whence, by the way, we may collect, that those subjects who in a _monarchy_ deplore their lost liberty, do only stomach this, that they are not received to the steerage of the commonweal. [Sidenote: It is no disadvantage to the subjects, that they are not all admitted to the public deliberations.] 9. But perhaps for this very reason, some will say that a _popular_ state is much to be preferred before a _monarchical_; because that where all men have a hand in public businesses, there all have an opportunity to shew their wisdom, knowledge, and eloquence, in deliberating matters of the greatest difficulty and moment; which by reason of that desire of praise which is bred in human nature, is to them who excel in such-like faculties, and seem to themselves to exceed others, the most delightful of all things. But in a monarchy, this same way to obtain praise and honour is shut up to the greatest part of subjects; and what is a grievance if this be none? I will tell you: to see his opinion, whom we scorn, preferred before ours; to have our wisdom undervalued before our own faces; by an uncertain trial of a little vain glory, to undergo most certain enmities (for this cannot be avoided, whether we have the better or the worse); to hate and to be hated, by reason of the disagreement of opinions; to lay open our secret councils and advices to all, to no purpose and without any benefit; to neglect the affairs of our own family: these, I say, are grievances. But to be absent from a trial of wits, although those trials are pleasant to the eloquent, is not therefore a grievance to them; unless we will say, that it is a grievance to valiant men to be restrained from fighting, because they delight in it. [Sidenote: Civil deliberations are unadvisedly committed to many, by reason of the unskilfulness of most men:] 10. Besides, there are many reasons, why deliberations are less successful in great assemblies than in lesser councils. Whereof one is, that to advise rightly of all things conducing to the preservation of a commonweal, we must not only understand matters at home, but foreign affairs too. At home, by what goods the country is nourished and defended, and whence they are fetched; what places are fit to make garrisons of; by what means soldiers are best to be raised and maintained; what manner of affections the subjects bear towards their prince or governors of their country; and many the like. Abroad, what the power of each neighbouring country is, and wherein it consists; what advantage or disadvantage we may receive from them; what their dispositions are both to us-ward, and how affected to each other among themselves; and what counsel daily passeth among them. Now, because very few in a great assembly of men understand these things, being for the most part unskilful, that I say not incapable of them, what can that same number of advisers with their impertinent opinions contribute to good counsels, other than mere lets and impediments? [Sidenote: By reason of their eloquence:] 11. Another reason why a great assembly is not so fit for consultation is, because every one who delivers his opinion holds it necessary to make a long-continued speech; and to gain the more esteem from his auditors, he polishes and adorns it with the best and smoothest language. Now the nature of eloquence is to make _good_ and _evil_, _profitable_ and _unprofitable_, _honest_ and _dishonest_, appear to be more or less than indeed they are; and to make that seem _just_ which is _unjust_, according as it shall best suit with his end that speaketh: for this is to persuade. And though they reason, yet take they not their rise from true principles, but from vulgar received opinions, which for the most part are erroneous. Neither endeavour they so much to fit their speech to the nature of the things they speak of, as to the passions of their minds to whom they speak; whence it happens, that opinions are delivered not by right reason, but by a certain violence of mind. Nor is this fault in the _man_, but in the nature itself of _eloquence_, whose end, as all the masters of rhetoric teach us, is not truth (except by chance), but victory; and whose property is not to inform, but to allure. [Sidenote: By reason of faction:] 12. The third reason why men advise less successfully in a great convent is, because that thence arise _factions_ in a commonweal; and out of _factions_, seditions and civil war. For when equal orators do combat with contrary opinions and speeches, the conquered hates the conqueror and all those that were of his side, as holding his council and wisdom in scorn, and studies all means to make the advice of his adversaries prejudicial to the state: for thus he hopes to see the glory taken from him, and restored unto himself. Furthermore, where the votes are not so unequal, but that the conquered have hopes, by the accession of some few of their own opinion, at another sitting to make the stronger party, the chief heads do call the rest together; they advise a part how they may abrogate the former judgment given; they appoint to be the first and earliest at the next convent; they determine what, and in what order each man shall speak, that the same business may again be brought to agitation; that so what was confirmed before by the number of their then present adversaries, the same may now in some measure become of no effect to them, being negligently absent. And this same kind of industry and diligence which they use to _make_ a people, is commonly called a _faction_. But when a _faction_ is inferior in votes, and superior, or not much inferior in power, then what they cannot obtain by craft and language, they attempt by force of arms; and so it comes to a civil war. But some will say, these things do not necessarily, nor often happen. He may as well say, that the chief parties are not necessarily desirous of vain glory, and that the greatest of them seldom disagree in great matters. [Sidenote: By reason of the unsettledness of the laws:] 13. It follows hence, that when the legislative power resides in such convents as these, the laws must needs be inconstant; and change, not according to the alteration of the state of affairs, nor according to the changeableness of men’s minds, but as the major part, now of this, then of that _faction_, do convene. Insomuch as the laws do float here and there, as it were upon the waters. [Sidenote: For want of secrecy.] 14. In the fourth place, the counsels of great assemblies have this inconvenience; that whereas it is oft of great consequence that they should be kept secret, they are for the most part discovered to the enemy before they can be brought to any effect; and their power and will is as soon known abroad, as to the _people_ itself commanding at home. [Sidenote: These inconveniences do adhere to democracy, forasmuch as men are naturally delighted with an opinion of wit.] 15. These inconveniences, which are found in the deliberations of great assemblies, do so far forth evince _monarchy_ to be better than _democracy_, as in _democracy_ affairs of great consequence are oftener trusted to be discussed by such like committees, than in a _monarchy_. Neither can it easily be done otherwise. For there is no reason why every man should not naturally mind his _own private_, than the _public_ business, but that here he sees a means to declare his eloquence, whereby he may gain the reputation of being ingenious and wise, and returning home to his friends, to his parents, to his wife and children, rejoice and triumph in the applause of his dexterous behaviour. As of old, all the delight Marcus Coriolanus had in his warlike actions, was to see his praises so well pleasing to his mother. But if the _people_ in a democracy would bestow the power of deliberating in matters of war and peace, either on one, or some very few, being content with the nomination of magistrates and public ministers, that is to say, with the authority without the ministration; then it must be confessed, that in this particular _democracy_ and _monarchy_ would be equal. [Sidenote: The inconveniences of government proceeding from a king who is a child.] 16. Neither do the conveniences or inconveniences which are found to be more in one kind of government than another, arise from hence, namely, because the government itself, or the administration of its affairs, are better committed to one than many; or on the other side, to many than to some few. For government is the _power_, the administration of it is the _act_. Now the _power_ in all kinds of government is equal; the _acts_ only differ, that is to say, the _actions_ and _motions_ of a commonweal, as they flow from the deliberations of many or few, of skilful or impertinent men. Whence we understand, that the conveniences or inconveniences of any government depend not on him in whom the authority resides, but on his officers; and therefore nothing hinders but that the commonweal may be well governed, although the _monarch_ be a woman, or youth, or infant, provided that they be fit for affairs who are endued with the public offices and charges. And that which is said, _woe to the land whose king is a child_, doth not signify the condition of a monarchy to be inferior to a popular state; but contrariwise, that by accident it is the grievance of a kingdom, that the _king being a child_, it often happens, that many by ambition and power intruding themselves into public councils, the government comes to be administered in a _democratical_ manner; and that thence arise those infelicities, which for the most part accompany the _dominion of the people_. [Sidenote: The power of generals is an argument of the excellency of monarchy.] 17. But it is a manifest sign that the most absolute _monarchy_ is the best state of government, that not only kings, but even those cities which are subject to the _people_ or to _nobles_, give the whole command of war to one only; and that so absolute, as nothing can be more. Wherein, by the way, this must be noted also; that no king can give a general greater authority over his army, than he himself by right may exercise over all his subjects. _Monarchy_ therefore is the best of all governments in the camps. But what else are many commonwealths, than so many camps strengthened with arms and men against each other; whose state, because not restrained by any common power, howsoever an uncertain peace, like a short truce, may pass between them, is to be accounted for the state of nature; which is the state of war. [Sidenote: The best state of a commonweal, is that where the subjects are the ruler’s inheritance.] 18. Lastly, since it was necessary for the preservation of ourselves to be subject to some _man_ or _council_, we cannot on better condition be subject to any, than one whose interest depends upon our safety and welfare; and this then comes to pass, when we are the inheritance of the ruler. For every man of his own accord endeavours the preservation of his inheritance. But the lands and monies of the subjects are not only the prince’s treasure, but their bodies and wildy minds. Which will be easily granted by those, who consider at how great rates the dominion of lesser countries is valued; and how much easier it is for men to procure money, than money men. Nor do we readily meet with any example that shows us when any subject, without any default of his own, hath by his prince been despoiled of his life or goods, through the sole licentiousness of his authority. [Sidenote: Aristocracy is so much better, by how much it approaches nearer to monarchy; the worse, by how much it is more distant from it.] 19. Hitherto we have compared a _monarchical_ with a _popular_ state; we have said nothing of _aristocracy_. We may conclude of this, by what hath been said of those, that that which is hereditary, and content with the election of magistrates; which transmits its deliberations to some few, and those most able; which simply imitates the government of _monarchs_ most, and the _people_ least of all; is for the subjects both better and more lasting than the rest. ------- CHAPTER XI. PLACES AND EXAMPLES OF SCRIPTURE OF THE RIGHTS OF GOVERNMENT, AGREEABLE TO WHAT HATH BEEN SAID BEFORE. 1. The beginning of institutive government from the consent of the people. 2. Judicature and wars depend on the will of supreme commanders. 3. That they who have the chief authority, are by right unpunishable. 4. That without a supreme power there is no government, but anarchy. 5. That from servants and sons there is a simple obedience due to their lords and parents. 6. Absolute authority proved by most evident places, as well of the New as the Old Testament. [Sidenote: The beginning of institutive government from the consent of the people.] 1. We have, in the sixth chapter and the second article, so derived the original of institutive or political government from the consent of the multitude, that it appears they must either all consent, or be esteemed as enemies. Such was the beginning of God’s government over the Jews instituted by Moses, (Exod. xix. 5-8): _If ye will obey my voice indeed_, &c. _Ye shall be unto me a kingdom of priests_, &c. _And Moses came and called the elders of the people_, &c. _And all the people answered, and said: All that the Lord hath spoken we will do._ Such also was the beginning of Moses’s power under God, or his vicegerency, (Exod. xx. 18-19): _And all the people saw the thunderings and lightenings, and the noise of the trumpet_, &c. _And they said unto Moses, speak thou unto us, and we will hear._ The like beginning also had Saul’s kingdom, (1 Sam. xii. 12, 13): _When ye saw that Nahash king of the children of Ammon came out against you, ye said unto me, nay, but a king shall reign over us, when the Lord your God was your king. Now therefore behold the king whom ye have chosen, and whom ye have desired._ But the major part only consenting, and not all; for there were certain _sons of Belial_, who said, (1 Sam. x. 27), _How shall this man save us? And they despised him_; those who did not consent, were put to death as enemies. And the people said unto Samuel (1 Sam. xi. 12): _Who is he that said, shall Saul reign over us? Bring the men, that we may put them to death._ [Sidenote: The power of judicature, and determination of wars, depend on the will of the supreme officer.] 2. In the same sixth chapter, the sixth and seventh articles, I have showed that all _judgment_ and _wars_ depend upon the will and pleasure of him who bears the supreme authority; that is to say, in a _monarchy_, on a monarch or king; and this is confirmed by the people’s own judgment. 1 Sam. viii. 20; _We also will be like all the nations, and our king shall judge us, and go out before us, and fight our battles._ And what pertains to _judgments_, and all other matters whereof there is any controversy, whether they be _good_ or _evil_, is confirmed by the testimony of King Solomon, (1 Kings iii. 9): _Give therefore thy servant an understanding heart to judge thy people, that I may discern between good and evil._ And that of Absolom, (2 Sam. xv. 3): _There is no man deputed of the king to hear thee._ [Sidenote: They who have the supreme authority are by right unpunishable.] 3. That kings may not be punished by their subjects, as hath been showed above in the sixth chapter and the twelfth article, King David also confirms; who, though Saul sought to slay him, did notwithstanding refrain his hand from killing him, and forbade Abishai, saying, (1 Sam. xxvi. 9): _Destroy him not; for who can stretch forth his hand against the Lords anointed, and be innocent?_ And when he had cut off the skirt of his garment, (1 Sam. xxiv. 6): _The Lord forbid_, saith he, _that I should do this thing unto my master the Lord’s anointed, to stretch forth mine hand against him_. And (_2 Sam._ i. 15) commanded the Amalekite, who for his sake had slain Saul, to be put to death. [Sidenote: That without a supreme power there is no government, but confusion.] 4. That which is said in the seventeenth chapter of _Judges_, at the sixth verse: _In those days there was no king in Israel, but every man did that which was right in his own eyes_: as though where there were not a _monarchy_, there were an _anarchy_ or confusion of all things: may be brought as a testimony to prove the excellency of monarchy above all other forms of government; unless that by the word _king_ may perhaps be understood not _one man_ only, but also a _court_; provided that in it there reside a supreme power. Which if it be taken in this sense, yet hence it may follow, that without a supreme and absolute power (which we have endeavoured to prove in the sixth chapter) there will be a liberty for every man to do what he hath a mind, or whatsoever shall seem right to himself; which cannot stand with the preservation of mankind. And therefore in all government whatsoever, there is ever a supreme power understood to be somewhere existent. [Sidenote: That servants and sons owe their lords and parents simple obedience.] 5. We have, in chap. VIII. art. 7 and 8, said that _servants_ must yield a simple obedience to their _lords_, and in chap IX. art. 7, that _sons_ owe the same obedience to their _parents_. Saint Paul says the same thing concerning servants (Coloss. iii. 22): _Servants obey in all things your masters according to the flesh, not with eye-service, as men-pleasers, but in singleness of heart, fearing God._ Concerning sons (Colos. iii. 20): _Children obey your parents in all things, for this is well-pleasing unto the Lord._ Now as we by simple obedience understand all things which are not contrary to the laws of God; so in those cited places of St. Paul, after the word _all things_, we must suppose, _excepting those which are contrary to the laws of God_. [Sidenote: The absolute power of princes proved by most evident testimonies of the Scripture, as well New as Old.] 6. But that I may not thus by piecemeal prove the right of princes, I will now instance those testimonies which altogether establish the whole power; namely, that there is an absolute and simple obedience due to them from their subjects. And first out of the New Testament: Matth. xxiii. 2, 3: _The Scribes and Pharisees sit in Moses’ seat; all therefore, whatsoever they bid you observe, that observe and do. Whatsoever they bid you_ (says Christ) _observe_, that is to say, _obey simply_. Why? Because they _sit in Moses’ seat_; namely, the _civil magistrate’s_, not Aaron, the priest’s. Rom. xiii. 1, 2: _Let every soul be subject to the higher powers; for there is no power but of God; the powers that be are ordained of God; whosoever therefore resisteth the power, resisteth the ordinance of God; and they that resist, shall receive to themselves damnation._ Now because the powers that were in St. Paul’s time, were ordained of God, and all kings did at that time require an absolute entire obedience from their subjects, it follows that such a power was ordained of God. 1 Peter ii. 13-15: _Submit yourselves unto every ordinance of man for the Lord’s sake, whether it be to the king as supreme, or unto governors as unto them that are sent by him for the punishment of wicked doers, and for the praise of them that do well; for so is the will of God._ Again St. Paul to Titus, (chap. iii. 1): _Put them in mind to be subject to principalities and powers, to obey magistrates, &c._ What principalities? Was it not to the principalities of those times, which required an absolute obedience? Furthermore, that we may come to the example of Christ himself, to whom the kingdom of the Jews belonged by hereditary right derived from David himself; he, when he lived in the manner of a subject, both paid tribute unto Cæsar, and pronounced it to be due to him, Matth. xxii. 21: _Give unto Cæsar_ (saith he) _the things which are Cæsar’s, and unto God the things which are God’s_. When it pleased him to show himself a king, he required entire obedience, Matth. xxi. 2, 3: _Go_ (said he) _into the village over against you, and straight-way ye shall find an ass tied, and a colt with her; loose them, and bring them unto me; and if any man say aught unto you, ye shall say the Lord hath need of them_. This he did therefore by the right of being lord, or a king of the Jews. But to take away a subject’s goods on this pretence only, because _the Lord hath need of them_, is an absolute power. The most evident places in the Old Testament are these: Deut. v. 27: _Go thou near, and hear all that the Lord our God shall say; and speak thou unto us all that the Lord our God shall speak unto thee, and we will hear it, and do it._ But under the word _all_, is contained absolute obedience. Again to Joshua (Joshua i. 16-18): _And they answered Joshua, saying, all that thou commandest us, we will do; and whithersoever thou sendest us, we will go; according as we hearkened unto Moses in all things, so will we hearken unto thee; only the Lord thy God be with thee, as he was with Moses; whosoever he be that doth rebel against thy commandment, and will not hearken unto thy words in all that thou commandest him, he shall be put to death._ And the parable of the bramble (Judges ix. 14, 15): _Then said all the trees unto the bramble, Come thou and reign over us. And the bramble said unto the trees, If in truth ye anoint me king over you, then come and put your trust in my shadow; and if not, let fire come out of the bramble, and devour the cedars of Lebanon._ The sense of which words is, that we must acquiesce to their sayings, whom we have truly constituted to be kings over us, unless we would choose rather to be consumed by the fire of a civil war. But the regal authority is more particularly described by God himself, in 1 Sam. viii. 9, &c.: _Show them the right of the king that shall reign over them, &c. This shall be the right of the king that shall reign over you; he will take your sons, and appoint them for himself, for his chariots, and to be his horsemen, and some shall run before his chariots, &c. And he will take your daughters to be confectionaries, &c. And he will take your vineyards, and give them to his servants, &c._ Is not this power absolute? And yet it is by God himself styled the _king’s right_. Neither was any man among the Jews, no not the _high-priest_ himself, exempted from this obedience. For when the king, namely, Solomon, said to Abiathar the priest (1 Kings ii. 26, 27): _Get thee to Anathoth unto thine own fields; for thou art worthy of death; but I will not at this time put thee to death, because thou barest the ark of the Lord God before David my father, and because thou hast been afflicted in all wherein my father was afflicted. So Solomon thrust out Abiathar from being priest unto the Lord_; it cannot by any argument be proved, that this act of his displeased the Lord; neither read we, that either Solomon was reproved, or that his person at that time was any whit less acceptable to God. ------- CHAPTER XII. OF THE INTERNAL CAUSES TENDING TO THE DISSOLUTION OF ANY GOVERNMENT. 1. That _the judging of good and evil belongs to private persons_ is a seditious opinion. 2. That _subjects do sin by obeying their princes_ is a seditious opinion. 3. That _tyrannicide is lawful_ is a seditious opinion. 4. That _those who have the supreme power are subject to the civil laws_ is a seditious opinion. 5. That _the supreme power may be divided_ is a seditious opinion. 6. That _faith and sanctity are not acquired by study and reason, but always supernaturally infused and inspired_, is a seditious opinion. 7. That _each subject hath a propriety or absolute dominion of his own goods_ is a seditious opinion. 8. Not to understand the difference between the people and the multitude, prepares toward sedition. 9. Too great a tax of money, though never so just and necessary, prepares toward sedition. 10. Ambition disposeth us to sedition. 11. So doth the hope of success. 12. Eloquence alone without wisdom, is the only faculty needful to raise seditions. 13. How the folly of the common people, and the elocution of ambitious men, concur to the destruction of a common-weal. [Sidenote: That the judgment of good and evil belongs to private persons, is a seditious opinion.] 1. Hitherto hath been spoken, by what causes and pacts commonweals are constituted, and what the rights of princes are over their subjects. Now we will briefly say somewhat concerning the causes which dissolve them, or the reasons of seditions. Now as in the motion of natural bodies three things are to be considered, namely, _internal disposition_, that they be susceptible of the motion to be produced; the _external agent_, whereby a certain and determined motion may in act be produced; and the _action itself_: so also in a commonweal where the subjects begin to raise tumults, three things present themselves to our regard; first, the _doctrines_ and the _passions_ contrary to peace, wherewith the minds of men are fitted and disposed; next, their quality and condition who solicit, assemble, and direct them, already thus disposed, to take up arms and quit their allegiance; lastly, the manner how this is done, or the _faction_ itself. But one and the first which disposeth them to sedition, is this, _that the knowledge of good and evil belongs to each single man_. In the state of nature indeed, where every man lives by equal right, and has not by any mutual pacts submitted to the command of others, we have granted this to be true; nay, proved it in chap. I. art. 9. But in the civil state it is false. For it was shown (chap. VI. art. 9) that the civil laws were the rules of _good_ and _evil_, _just_ and _unjust_, _honest_ and _dishonest_; that therefore what the legislator commands, must be held for _good_, and what he forbids for _evil_. And the legislator is ever that person who hath the supreme power in the commonweal, that is to say, the monarch in a monarchy. We have confirmed the same truth in chap. XI. art. 2, out of the words of Solomon. For if private men may pursue that as good and shun that as evil, which appears to them to be so, to what end serve those words of his: _Give therefore unto thy servant an understanding heart, to judge thy people, that I may discern between good and evil_? Since therefore it belongs to kings to discern between _good_ and _evil_, wicked are those, though usual, sayings, _that he only is a king who does righteously_, and _that kings must not be obeyed unless they command us just things_; and many other such like. Before there was any government, _just_ and _unjust_ had no being, their nature only being relative to some command: and every action in its own nature is indifferent; that it becomes _just_ or _unjust_, proceeds from the right of the magistrate. Legitimate kings therefore make the things they command just, by commanding them, and those which they forbid, unjust, by forbidding them. But private men, while they assume to themselves the knowledge of _good_ and _evil_, desire to be even as kings; which cannot be with the safety of the commonweal. The most ancient of all God’s commands is, (Gen. ii. 17): _Thou shalt not eat of the tree of knowledge of good and evil_: and the most ancient of all diabolical temptations, (Gen. iii. 5): _Ye shall be as gods, knowing good and evil_; and God’s expostulation with man, (verse 11): _Who told thee that thou wert naked? Hast thou eaten of the tree, whereof I commanded thee that thou shouldst not eat?_ As if he had said, how comest thou to judge that nakedness, wherein it seemed good to me to create thee, to be shameful, except thou have arrogated to thyself the knowledge of _good and evil_. [Sidenote: That subjects do sin in obeying their princes, is a seditious opinion.] 2. Whatsoever any man doth against his conscience, is a sin; for he who doth so, contemns the law. But we must distinguish. That is my sin indeed, which committing I do believe to be my sin; but what I believe to be another man’s sin, I may sometimes do that without any sin of mine. For if I be commanded to do that which is a sin in him who commands me, if I do it, and he that commands me be by right lord over me, I sin not. For if I wage war at the commandment of my prince, conceiving the war to be unjustly undertaken, I do not therefore do unjustly; but rather if I refuse to do it, arrogating to myself the knowledge of what is just and unjust, which pertains only to my prince. They who observe not this distinction, will fall into a necessity of sinning, as oft as anything is commanded them which either is, or seems to be unlawful to them: for if they obey, they sin against their conscience; and if they obey not, against right. If they sin against their conscience, they declare that they fear not the pains of the world to come; if they sin against right, they do, as much as in them lies, abolish human society and the civil life of the present world. Their opinion therefore who teach, _that subjects sin when they obey their prince’s commands which to them seem unjust_, is both erroneous, and to be reckoned among those which are contrary to civil obedience; and it depends upon that original error which we have observed above, in the foregoing article. For by our taking upon us to judge of _good_ and _evil_, we are the occasion that as well our obedience, as disobedience, becomes sin unto us. [Sidenote: That tyrannicide is lawful, is a seditious opinion.] 3. The third seditious doctrine springs from the same root, that _tyrannicide is lawful_; nay, at this day it is by many divines, and of old it was by all the philosophers, Plato, Aristotle, Cicero, Seneca, Plutarch, and the rest of the maintainers of the Greek and Roman anarchies, held not only lawful, but even worthy of the greatest praise. And under the title of _tyrants_, they mean not only monarchs, but all those who bear the chief rule in any government whatsoever; for not Pisistratus only at Athens, but those Thirty also who succeeded him, and ruled together, were all called _tyrants_. But he whom men require to be put to death as being _a tyrant_, commands either by right or without right. If without right, he is an enemy, and by right to be put to death; but then this must not be called the _killing a tyrant_, but an _enemy_. If by right, then the divine interrogation takes place: _Who hath told thee that he was a tyrant? Hast thou eaten of the tree, whereof I commanded thee that thou shouldst not eat?_ For why dost thou call him a _tyrant_, whom God hath made a _king_, except that thou, being a private person, usurpest to thyself the knowledge of _good_ and _evil_? But how pernicious this opinion is to all governments, but especially to that which is _monarchical_, we may hence discern; namely, that by it every _king_, whether good or ill, stands exposed to be condemned by the judgment, and slain by the hand of every murderous villain. [Sidenote: That even they who have the supreme power are subject to the civil laws, is a seditious opinion.] 4. The fourth opinion adversary to civil society, is their’s who hold, _that they who bear rule are subject also to the civil laws_. Which hath been sufficiently proved before not to be true, in chap VI. art. 14, from this argument: that a city can neither be bound to itself, nor to any subject; not to itself, because no man can be obliged except it be to another; not to any subject, because the single wills of the subjects are contained in the will of the city; insomuch that if the city will be free from all such obligation, the subjects will so too; and by consequence she is so. But that which holds true in a city, that must be supposed to be true in a man, or an assembly of men who have the supreme authority; for they make a city, which hath no being but by their supreme power. Now that this opinion cannot consist with the very being of government, is evident from hence; that by it the knowledge of what is _good_ and _evil_, that is to say, the definition of what is, and what is not against the laws, would return to each single person. Obedience therefore will cease, as oft as anything seems to be commanded contrary to the civil laws, and together with it all coercive jurisdiction; which cannot possibly be without the destruction of the very essence of government. Yet this error hath great props, Aristotle and others; who, by reason of human infirmity, suppose the supreme power to be committed with most security to the laws only. But they seem to have looked very shallowly into the nature of government, who thought that the constraining power, the interpretation of laws, and the making of laws, all which are powers necessarily belonging to government, should be left wholly to the laws themselves. Now although particular subjects may sometimes contend in judgment, and go to law with the supreme magistrate; yet this is only then, when the question is not what the magistrate may, but what by a certain rule he hath declared he would do. As, when by any law the judges sit upon the life of a subject, the question is not whether the magistrate could by his absolute right deprive him of his life; but whether by that law his will was that he should be deprived of it. But his will was, he should, if he brake the law; else his will was, he should not. This therefore, that a subject may have an action of law against his supreme magistrate, is not strength of argument sufficient to prove, that he is tied to his own laws. On the contrary, it is evident that he is not tied to his own laws; because no man is bound to himself. Laws therefore are set for Titius and Caius, not for the ruler. However, by the ambition of lawyers it is so ordered, that the laws to unskilful men seem not to depend on the authority of the magistrate, but their prudence. [Sidenote: That the supreme power may be divided, is a seditious opinion.] 5. In the fifth place, _that the supreme authority may be divided_, is a most fatal opinion to all commonweals. But diverse men divide it diverse ways. For some divide it, so as to grant a supremacy to the civil power in matters pertaining to peace and the benefits of this life; but in things concerning the salvation of the soul they transfer it on others. Now, because justice is of all things most necessary to salvation, it happens that subjects measuring justice, not as they ought, by the civil laws, but by the precepts and doctrines of them who, in regard of the magistrate, are either private men or strangers, through a superstitious fear dare not perform the obedience due to their princes; through fear falling into that which they most feared. Now what can be more pernicious to any state, than that men should, by the apprehension of everlasting torments, be deterred from obeying their princes, that is to say, the laws; or from being just? There are also some, who divide the supreme authority so as to allow the power of war and peace unto one whom they call a _monarch_; but the right of raising money they give to some others, and not to him. But because monies are the sinews of war and peace, they who thus divide the authority, do either really not divide it at all, but place it wholly in them in whose power the money is, but give the name of it to another: or if they do really divide it, they dissolve the government. For neither upon necessity can war be waged, nor can the public peace be preserved without money. [Sidenote: That faith and holiness are not acquired by study and reason, but are ever supernaturally infused and inspired, is a seditious opinion.] 6. It is a common doctrine, _that faith and holiness are not acquired by study and natural reason, but are always supernaturally infused and inspired into men_. Which, if it were true, I understand not why we should be commanded to give an account of our faith; or why any man, who is truly a Christian, should not be a prophet; or lastly, why every man should not judge what is fit for him to do, what to avoid, rather out of his own inspiration, than by the precepts of his superiors or right reason. A return therefore must be made to the private knowledge of _good_ and _evil_; which cannot be granted without the ruin of all governments. This opinion hath spread itself so largely through the whole Christian world, that the number of apostates from natural reason is almost become infinite. And it sprang from sick-brained men, who having gotten good store of holy words by frequent reading of the Scriptures, made such a connexion of them usually in their preaching, that their sermons, signifying just nothing, yet to unlearned men seemed most divine. For he whose nonsense appears to be a divine speech, must necessarily seem to be inspired from above. [Sidenote: That single subjects have any propriety or absolute dominion over their own goods, is a seditious opinion.] 7. The seventh doctrine opposite to government, is this; _that each subject hath an absolute dominion over the goods he is in possession of_: that is to say, such a _propriety_ as excludes not only the right of all the rest of his fellow-subjects to the same goods, but also of the magistrate himself. Which is not true; for they who have a _lord_ over them, have themselves no _lordship_, as hath been proved chap. viii. art. 5. Now the magistrate is lord of all his subjects, by the constitution of government. Before the yoke of civil society was undertaken, no man had any _proper right_; all things were _common_ to all men. Tell me therefore, how gottest thou this _propriety_ but from the magistrate? How got the magistrate it, but that every man transferred his right on him? And thou therefore hast also given up thy right to him. Thy _dominion_ therefore, and _propriety_, is just so much as he will, and shall last so long as he pleases; even as in a family, each son hath such _proper_ goods, and so long lasting, as seems good to the father. But the greatest part of men who profess civil prudence, reason otherwise. We are equal, say they, by nature; there is no reason why any man should by better right take my goods from me, than I his from him. We know that money sometimes is needful for the defence and maintenance of the public; but let them who require it, show us the present necessity, and they shall receive it. They who talk thus know not, that what they would have, is already done from the beginning, in the very constitution of government; and therefore speaking as in a dissolute multitude and yet not fashioned government, they destroy the frame. [Sidenote: Not to know the difference between a people and a multitude, prepares to sedition.] 8. In the last place, it is a great hindrance to civil government, especially monarchical, that men distinguish not enough between a _people_ and a _multitude_. The _people_ is somewhat that is _one_, having _one will_, and to whom _one action_ may be attributed; none of these can properly be said of a multitude. The _people_ rules in all governments. For even in _monarchies_ the _people_ commands; for the _people_ wills by the will of _one man_; but the multitude are citizens, that is to say, subjects. In a _democracy_ and _aristocracy_, the citizens are the _multitude_, but the _court_ is the _people_. And in a _monarchy_, the subjects are the _multitude_, and (however it seem a paradox) the king is the _people_. The common sort of men, and others who little consider these truths, do always speak of a _great number_ of men as of the _people_, that is to say, the _city_. They say, that the _city_ hath rebelled against the _king_ (which is impossible), and that the _people_ will and nill what murmuring and discontented subjects would have or would not have; under pretence of the _people_ stirring up the _citizens_ against the _city_, that is to say, the _multitude_ against the _people_. And these are almost all the opinions, wherewith subjects being tainted do easily tumult. And forasmuch as in all manner of government majesty is to be preserved by him or them, who have the supreme authority; the _crimen læsæ majestatis_ naturally cleaves to these opinions. [Sidenote: Too great a tax of money, though never so just and necessary, disposeth men to sedition.] 9. There is nothing more afflicts the mind of man than _poverty_, or the want of those things which are necessary for the preservation of life and honour. And though there be no man but knows, that riches are gotten with industry, and kept by frugality, yet all the poor commonly lay the blame on the evil government, excusing their own sloth and luxury; as if their private goods forsooth were wasted by public exactions. But men must consider, that they who have no patrimony, must not only labour that they may live, but fight too that they may labour. Every one of the Jews, who in Esdras’ time built the walls of Jerusalem, did the work with one hand, and held the sword in the other. In all government, we must conceive that the hand which holds the sword, is the _king_ or _supreme council_, which is no less to be sustained and nourished by the subjects’ care and industry, than that wherewith each man procures himself a private fortune; and that _customs_ and _tributes_ are nothing else but their reward who watch in arms for us, that the labours and endeavours of single men may not be molested by the incursion of enemies; and that their complaint, who impute their poverty to public persons, is not more just, than if they should say that they are become in want by paying of their debts. But the most part of men consider nothing of these things. For they suffer the same thing with them who have a disease they call an _incubus_; which springing from gluttony, it makes men believe they are invaded, oppressed, and stifled with a great weight. Now it is a thing manifest of itself, that they who seem to themselves to be burthened with the whole load of the commonweal, are prone to be seditious; and that they are affected with change, who are distasted at the present state of things. [Sidenote: Ambition disposeth men to sedition:] 10. Another noxious disease of the mind is theirs, who having little employment, want honour and dignity. All men naturally strive for honour and preferment; but chiefly they, who are least troubled with caring for necessary things. For these men are invited by their vacancy, sometimes to disputation among themselves concerning the commonweal, sometimes to an easy reading of histories, politics, orations, poems, and other pleasant books; and it happens that hence they think themselves sufficiently furnished both with wit and learning, to administer matters of the greatest consequence. Now because all men are not what they appear to themselves; and if they were, yet all (by reason of the multitude) could not be received to public offices; it is necessary that many must be passed by. These therefore conceiving themselves affronted, can desire nothing more, partly out of envy to those who were preferred before them, partly out of hope to overwhelm them, than ill-success to the public consultations. And therefore it is no marvel, if with greedy appetites they seek for occasions of innovations. [Sidenote: So doth hope of success.] 11. _The hope of overcoming_ is also to be numbered among other seditious inclinations. For let there be as many men as you will, infected with opinions repugnant to peace and civil government; let there be as many as there can, never so much wounded and torn with affronts and calumnies by them who are in authority; yet if there be no _hope of having the better of them_, or it appear not sufficient, there will no sedition follow; every man will dissemble his thoughts, and rather content himself with the present burthen than hazard a heavier weight. There are four things necessarily requisite to this _hope_. Numbers, instruments, mutual trust, and commanders. To resist public magistrates without a great number, is not sedition, but desperation. By instruments of war, I mean all manner of arms, munition, and other necessary provision: without which number can do nothing. Nor arms neither, without mutual trust. Nor all these, without union under some commander, whom of their own accord they are content to obey; not as being engaged by their submission to his command; (for we have already in this very chapter, supposed these kind of men not to understand being obliged beyond that which seems right and good in their own eyes); but for some opinion they have of his virtue, or military skill, or resemblance of humours. If these four be near at hand to men grieved with the present state, and measuring the justice of their actions by their own judgments; there will be nothing wanting to sedition and confusion of the realm, but one to _stir up_ and _quicken them_. [Sidenote: Eloquence alone without wisdom is the only faculty needful to raise seditions.] 12. Sallust’s character of Cataline, than whom there never was a greater artist in raising seditions, is this: _that he had great eloquence, and little wisdom_. He separates _wisdom_ from _eloquence_; attributing this as necessary to a man born for commotions; adjudging that as an instructress of peace and quietness. Now eloquence is twofold. The one is an elegant and clear expression of the conceptions of the mind; and riseth partly from the contemplation of the things themselves, partly from an understanding of words taken in their own proper and definite signification. The other is a commotion of the passions of the mind, such as are _hope_, _fear_, _anger_, _pity_; and derives from a metaphorical use of words fitted to the passions. That forms a speech from true principles; this from opinions already received, what nature soever they are of. The art of that is logic, of this rhetoric; the end of that is truth, of this victory. Each hath its use; that in deliberations, this in exhortations; for that is never disjoined from _wisdom_, but this almost ever. But that this kind of powerful _eloquence_, separated from the true knowledge of things, that is to say, from wisdom, is the true character of them who solicit and stir up the people to innovations, may easily be gathered out of the work itself which they have to do. For they could not poison the people with those absurd opinions contrary to peace and civil society, unless they held them themselves; which sure is an ignorance greater than can well befall any wise man. For he that knows not whence the laws derive their power, which are the rules of _just_ and _unjust_, _honest_ and _dishonest_, _good_ and _evil_; what makes and preserves peace among men, what destroys it; what is _his_, and what _another’s_; lastly, what he would have done to himself, that he may do the like to others: is surely to be accounted but meanly wise. But that they can turn their auditors out of fools into madmen; that they can make things to them who are ill-affected, seem worse, to them who are well-affected, seem evil; that they can enlarge their hopes, lessen their dangers beyond reason: this they have from that sort of eloquence, not which explains things as they are, but from that other, which by moving their minds, makes all things to appear to be such as they in their minds, prepared before, had already conceived them. [Sidenote: How the folly of the common people, and the eloquence of ambitious men, concur to the dissolution of a commonweal.] 13. Many men, who are themselves very well affected to civil society, do through want of knowledge co-operate to the disposing of subjects’ minds to _sedition_, whilst they teach young men a doctrine conformable to the said opinions in their schools, and all the people in their pulpits. Now they who desire to bring this disposition into act, place their whole endeavour in this: first, that they may join the ill-affected together into _faction_ and _conspiracy_; next, that themselves may have the greatest stroke in the _faction_. They gather them into _faction_, while they make themselves the relators and interpreters of the counsels and actions of single men, and nominate the persons and places to assemble and deliberate of such things whereby the present government may be reformed, according as it shall seem best to their interests. Now to the end that they themselves may have the chief rule in the _faction_, the _faction_ must be kept in a _faction_; that is to say, they must have their secret meetings apart with a few, where they may order what shall afterward be propounded in a general meeting, and by whom, and on what subject, and in what order each of them shall speak, and how they may draw the powerfullest and most popular men of the _faction_ to their side. And thus when they have gotten a faction big enough, in which they may rule by their eloquence, they move it to take upon it the managing of affairs. And thus they sometimes oppress the commonwealth, namely, where there is no other faction to oppose them; but for the most part they rend it, and introduce a civil war. For _folly_ and _eloquence_ concur in the subversion of government, in the same manner (as the fable hath it) as heretofore the daughters of Pelias, king of Thessaly, conspired with Medea against their father. They going to restore the decrepit old man to his youth again, by the counsel of Medea they cut him into pieces, and set him in the fire to boil; in vain expecting when he would live again. So the common people, through their folly, like the daughters of Pelias, desiring to renew the ancient government, being drawn away by the _eloquence_ of ambitious men, as it were by the witchcraft of Medea; divided into _faction_ they consume it rather by those flames, than they reform it. ------- CHAPTER XIII. CONCERNING THE DUTIES OF THEM WHO BEAR RULE. 1. The right of supreme authority is distinguished from its exercise. 2. The safety of the people is the supreme law. 3. It behoves princes to regard the common benefit of many, not the peculiar interest of this or that man. 4. That by safety is understood all manner of conveniences. 5. A query, whether it be the duty of kings to provide for the salvation of their subjects’ souls, as they shall judge best according to their own consciences. 6. Wherein the safety of the people consists. 7. That discoverers are necessary for the defence of the people. 8. That to have soldiers, arms, garrisons, and moneys in readiness, in time of peace, is also necessary for the defence of the people. 9. A right instruction of subjects in civil doctrines, is necessary for the preserving of peace. 10. Equal distributions of public offices conduces much to the preservation of peace. 11. It is natural equity, that monies be taxed according to what every man spends, not what he possesses. 12. It conduceth to the preservation of peace, to keep down ambitious men. 13. And to break factions. 14. Laws whereby thriving arts are cherished and great costs restrained, conduce to the enriching of the subject. 15. That more ought not to be defined by the laws, than the benefit of the prince and his subjects requires. 16. That greater punishments must not be inflicted, than are prescribed by the laws. 13. Subjects must have right done them against corrupt judges. [Sidenote: The right of supreme authority is distinguished from its exercise.] 1. By what hath hitherto been said, the _duties_ of citizens and subjects in any kind of government whatsoever, and the _power_ of the supreme ruler over them are apparent. But we have as yet said nothing of the _duties_ of rulers, and how they ought to behave themselves towards their subjects. We must then distinguish between the _right_ and the _exercise_ of supreme authority; for they can be divided. As for example, when he who hath the _right_, either cannot or will not be present in judging trespasses, or deliberating of affairs. For kings sometimes by reason of their age cannot order their affairs; sometimes also, though they can do it themselves, yet they judge it fitter, being satisfied in the choice of their officers and counsellors, to exercise their power by them. Now where the _right_ and _exercise_ are severed, there the government of the commonweal is like the ordinary government of the world; in which God, the mover of all things, produceth natural effects by the means of secondary causes. But where he to whom the right of ruling doth belong, is himself present in all judicatures, consultations, and public actions, there the administration is such, as if God, beyond the ordinary course of nature, should immediately apply himself unto all matters. We will therefore in this chapter summarily and briefly speak somewhat concerning their _duties_, who exercise authority, whether by their own or other’s right. Nor is it my purpose to descend into those things, which being diverse from others, some princes may do, for this is to be left to the political practices of each commonweal. [Sidenote: The safety of the people is the supreme law.] 2. Now all the duties of rulers are contained in this one sentence, _the safety of the people is the supreme law_. For although they who among men obtain the chiefest dominion, cannot be subject to laws properly so called, that is to say, to the will of men, because to be chief and subject, are contradictories; yet is it their _duty_ in all things, as much as possibly they can, to yield obedience unto right reason, which is the natural, moral, and divine law. But because dominions were constituted for peace’s sake, and peace was sought after for safety’s sake; he, who being placed in authority, shall use his power otherwise than to the safety of the people, will act against the reasons of peace, that is to say, against the laws of nature. Now as the safety of the people dictates a law by which princes know their _duty_, so doth it also teach them an art how to procure themselves a benefit; for the power of the citizens is the power of the city, that is to say, his that bears the chief rule in any state. [Sidenote: It is the duty of princes to respect the common benefit of many, not the peculiar interest of this or that man.] 3. By the people in this place we understand, not one civil person, namely, the city itself which governs, but the multitude of subjects which are governed. For the city was not instituted for its own, but for the subjects’ sake: and yet a particular care is not required of _this_ or _that_ man. For the ruler (as such) provides no otherwise for the safety of his people, than by his laws, which are universal; and therefore he hath fully _discharged_ himself, if he have thoroughly endeavoured by wholesome constitutions to establish the welfare of the most part, and made it as lasting as may be; and that no man suffer ill, but by his own default, or by some chance which could not be prevented. But it sometimes conduces to the safety of the most part, that wicked men do suffer. [Sidenote: By safety is understood all manner of benefits.] 4. But by _safety_ must be understood, not the sole preservation of life in what condition soever, but in order to its happiness. For to this end did men freely assemble themselves and _institute_ a government, that they might, as much as their human condition would afford, live delightfully. They therefore who had undertaken the administration of power in such a kind of government, would sin against the law of nature, (because against their trust, who had committed that power unto them), if they should not study, as much as by good laws could be effected, to furnish their subjects abundantly, not only with the good things belonging to life, but also with those which advance to delectation. They who have acquired dominion by arms, do all desire that their subjects may be strong in body and mind, that they may serve them the better. Wherefore if they should not endeavour to provide them, not only with such things whereby they may live, but also with such whereby they may grow strong and lusty, they would act against their own scope and end. [Sidenote: Query, whether it be the duty of kings to provide for the salvation of their subjects’ souls, as they shall judge best in their own consciences.] 5. And first of all, princes do believe that it mainly concerns _eternal salvation_, what opinions are held of the Deity, and what manner of worship he is to be adored with. Which being supposed, it may be demanded whether chief rulers, and whosoever they be, whether one or more, who exercise supreme authority, sin not against the law of nature, if they cause not such a doctrine and worship to be taught and practised, or permit a contrary to be taught and practised, as they believe necessarily conduceth to the _eternal salvation_ of their subjects. It is manifest that they act against their conscience; and that they will, as much as in them lies, the eternal perdition of their subjects. For if they willed it not, I see no reason why they should suffer (when being supreme they cannot be compelled) such things to be taught and done, for which they believe them to be in a damnable state. But we will leave this difficulty in suspense. [Sidenote: Wherein the safety of the people consists.] 6. The benefits of subjects, respecting this life only, may be distributed into four kinds. 1. That they be defended against foreign enemies. 2. That peace be preserved at home. 3. That they be enriched, as much as may consist with public security. 4. That they enjoy a harmless liberty. For supreme commanders can confer no more to their civil happiness, than that being preserved from foreign and civil wars, they may quietly enjoy that wealth which they have purchased by their own industry. [Sidenote: That discoverers are necessary for the defence of the people.] 7. There are two things necessary for the people’s defence; _to be warned and to be forearmed_. For the state of commonwealths considered in themselves, is natural, that is to say, hostile. Neither if they cease from fighting, is it therefore to be called peace; but rather a breathing time, in which one enemy observing the motion and countenance of the other, values his security not according to the pacts, but the forces and counsels of his adversary. And this by natural right, as hath been showed in chap. II. art. 11, from this, that contracts are invalid in the state of nature, as oft as any just fear doth intervene. It is therefore necessary to the defence of the city, first, that there be some who may, as near as may be, _search into_ and _discover_ the counsels and motions of all those who may prejudice it. For _discoverers_ to ministers of state, are like the beams of the sun to the human soul. And we may more truly say in vision political, than natural, that the sensible and intelligible species of outward things, not well considered by others, are by the air transported to the soul; that is to say, to them who have the supreme authority: and therefore are they no less necessary to the preservation of the state, than the rays of the light are to the conservation of man. Or if they be compared to spider’s webs, which, extended on all sides by the finest threads, do warn them, keeping in their small holes, of all outward motions; they who bear rule, can no more know what is necessary to be commanded for the defence of their subjects without _spies_, than those spiders can, when they shall go forth, and whither they shall repair, without the motion of those threads. [Sidenote: To have soldiers, arms, garrisons, and money in readiness in time of peace, is necessary for the people’s defence.] 8. Furthermore, it is necessarily requisite to the people’s defence, that they be _forearmed_. Now to be forearmed is to be furnished with soldiers, arms, ships, forts, and monies, before the danger be instant; for the lifting of soldiers and taking up of arms after a blow is given, is too late at least, if not impossible. In like manner, not to raise forts and appoint garrisons in convenient places before the frontiers are invaded, is to be like those country swains, (as Demosthenes said), who ignorant of the art of fencing, with their bucklers guarded those parts of the body where they first felt the smart of the strokes. But they who think it then seasonable enough to raise monies for the maintenance of soldiers and other charges of war, when the danger begins to show itself, they consider not, surely, how difficult a matter it is to wring suddenly out of close-fisted men so vast a proportion of monies. For almost all men, what they once reckon in the number of their goods, do judge themselves to have such a right and propriety in it, as they conceive themselves to be injured whensoever they are forced to employ but the least part of it for the public good. Now a sufficient stock of monies to defend the country with arms, will not soon be raised out of the treasure of imposts and customs. We must therefore, for fear of war, in time of peace hoard up good sums, if we intend the safety of the commonweal. Since therefore it necessarily belongs to rulers, for the subjects’ safety to discover the enemy’s counsel, to keep garrisons, and to have money in continual readiness; and that princes are, by the law of nature, bound to use their whole endeavour in procuring the welfare of their subjects: it follows, that it is not only lawful for them to send out spies, to maintain soldiers, to build forts, and to require monies for these purposes; but also not to do thus is unlawful. To which also may be added, whatsoever shall seem to conduce to the lessening of the power of foreigners whom they suspect, whether by slight or force. For rulers are bound according to their power to prevent the evils they suspect; lest peradventure they may happen through their negligence. [Sidenote: A right instruction of subjects in civil doctrines, is necessary for the preserving of peace.] 9. But many things are required to the conservation of inward peace; because many things concur (as hath been showed in the foregoing chapter) to its perturbation. We have there showed, that some things there are, which dispose the minds of men to sedition, others which move and quicken them so disposed. Among those which dispose them, we have reckoned in the first place certain perverse doctrines. It is therefore the duty of those who have the chief authority, to root those out of the minds of men, not by commanding, but by teaching; not by the terror of penalties, but by the perspicuity of reasons. The laws whereby this evil may be withstood, are not to be made against the persons erring, but against the errors themselves. Those errors which, in the foregoing chapter, we affirmed were inconsistent with the quiet of the commonweal, have crept into the minds of ignorant men, partly from the pulpit, partly from the daily discourses of men, who, by reason of little employment otherwise, do find leisure enough to study; and they got into these men’s minds by the teachers of their youth in public schools. Wherefore also, on the other side, if any man would introduce sound doctrine, he must begin from the _academies_. There the true and truly demonstrated foundations of civil doctrine are to be laid; wherewith young men, being once endued, they may afterward, both in private and public, instruct the vulgar. And this they will do so much the more cheerfully and powerfully, by how much themselves shall be more certainly convinced of the truth of those things they profess and teach. For seeing at this day men receive propositions, though false, and no more intelligible than if a man should join together a company of terms drawn by chance out of an urn, by reason of the frequent use of hearing them; how much more would they for the same reason entertain true doctrines, suitable to their own understandings and the nature of things? I therefore conceive it to be the duty of supreme officers, to cause the true elements of civil doctrine to be written, and to command them to be taught in all the colleges of their several dominions. [Sidenote: Equal distribution of public burthens conduceth much to the preservation of peace.] 10. In the next place we showed, that grief of mind arising from _want_ did dispose the subjects to sedition; which want, although derived from their own luxury and sloth, yet they impute it to those who govern the realm, as though they were drained and oppressed by public pensions. Notwithstanding, it may sometimes happen that this complaint may be just; namely, when the burthens of the realm are unequally imposed on the subjects; for that which to all together is but a light weight, if many withdraw themselves it will be very heavy, nay, even intolerable to the rest: neither are men wont so much to grieve at the burthen itself, as at the inequality. With much earnestness therefore men strive to be freed from taxes; and in this conflict the less happy, as being overcome, do envy the more fortunate. To remove therefore all just complaint, it is the interest of the public quiet, and by consequence it concerns the duty of the magistrate, to see that the public burthens be equally borne. Furthermore, since what is brought by the subjects to public use, is nothing else but the price of their bought peace, it is good reason that they who equally share in the peace, should also pay an equal part, either by contributing their monies or their labours to the commonweal. Now it is the law of nature, (by art. 15, chap. III), that every man in distributing right to others, do carry himself equal to all. Wherefore rulers are, by the natural law, obliged to lay the burthens of the commonweal equally on their subjects. [Sidenote: It is natural equity, that monies be taxed according to what every man spends, not to what he possesseth.] 11. Now in this place we understand an equality, not of money, but of burthen; that is to say, an equality of reason between the burthens and the benefits. For although all equally enjoy peace, yet the benefits springing from thence are not equal to all; for some get greater possessions, others less; and again, some consume less, others more. It may therefore be demanded, whether subjects ought to contribute to the public according to the rate of what they gain, or of what they spend: that is to say, whether the persons must be taxed, so as to pay contribution according to their wealth; or the goods themselves, that every man contribute according to what he spends. But if we consider, where monies are raised according to wealth, there they who have made equal gain, have not equal possessions, because that one preserves what he hath got by frugality, another wastes it by luxury, and therefore equally rejoicing in the benefit of peace, they do not equally sustain the burthens of the commonweal: and on the other side, where the goods themselves are taxed, there every man, while he spends his private goods, in the very act of consuming them he undiscernably pays part due to the commonweal, according to, not what he hath, but what by the benefit of the realm he hath had: it is no more to be doubted, but that the former way of commanding monies is against equity, and therefore against the duty of rulers; the latter is agreeable to reason, and the exercise of their authority. [Sidenote: It conduces to the preservation of peace, to depress the ambitious.] 12. In the third place we said, that that trouble of mind which riseth from _ambition_, was offensive to public peace. For there are some, who seeming to themselves to be wiser than others, and more sufficient for the managing of affairs than they who at present do govern, when they can no otherwise declare how profitable their virtue would prove to the commonweal, they show it by harming it. But because ambition and greediness of honours cannot be rooted out of the minds of men, it is not the duty of rulers to endeavour it; but by constant application of rewards and punishments they may so order it, that men may know that the way to honour is not by contempt of the present government, nor by factions and the popular air, but by the contraries. They are good men who observe the decrees, the laws, and rights of their fathers. If with a constant order we saw these adorned with honours, but the factious punished and had in contempt by those who bear command, there would be more ambition to obey than withstand. Notwithstanding, it so happens sometimes, that as we must stroke a horse by reason of his too much fierceness, so a stiff-necked subject must be flattered for fear of his power; but as that happens when the rider, so this when the commander is in danger of falling. But we speak here of those whose authority and power is entire. Their duty, I say, it is to cherish obedient subjects, and to depress the factious all they can; nor can the public power be otherwise preserved, nor the subjects’ quiet without it. [Sidenote: And to dissolve factions.] 13. But if it be the duty of princes to restrain the factious, much more does it concern them to dissolve and dissipate the factions themselves. Now I call a _faction_, a multitude of subjects gathered together either by mutual _contracts_ among themselves, or by the power of some one, without his or their authority who bear the supreme rule. A _faction_, therefore, is as it were a city in a city: for as by an union of men in the state of nature, a city receives its being, so by a new union of subjects there ariseth a _faction_. According to this definition, a multitude of subjects who have bound themselves simply to obey any foreign prince or subject, or have made any pacts or leagues of mutual defence between themselves against all men, not excepting those who have the supreme power in the city, is a _faction_. Also favour with the vulgar, if it be so great that by it an army may be raised, except public caution be given either by hostages or some other pledges, contains _faction_ in it. The same may be said of private wealth, if it exceed; because all things obey money. Forasmuch therefore as it is true, that the state of cities among themselves is natural and hostile, those princes who permit factions, do as much as if they received an enemy within their walls: which is contrary to the subjects’ safety, and therefore also against the law of nature. [Sidenote: Laws whereby gaining arts are cherished and great expenses restrained, do conduce much to the enriching of the subject.] 14. There are two things necessary to the enriching of the subjects, _labour_ and _thrift_; there is also a third which helps, to wit, the _natural increase of the earth and water_; and there is a fourth too, namely, _the militia_, which sometimes augments, but more frequently lessens the subjects’ stock. The two first only are necessary. For a city constituted in an island of the sea, no greater than will serve for dwelling, may grow rich without sowing or fishing, by merchandize and handicrafts only; but there is no doubt, if they have a territory, that they may be richer with the same number, or equally rich being a greater number. But the fourth, namely, _the militia_, was of old reckoned in the number of the gaining arts, under the notion of _booting_ or _taking prey_; and it was by mankind, dispersed by families before the constitution of civil societies, accounted just and honourable. For preying is nothing else but a war waged with small forces. And great commonweals, namely, that of Rome and Athens, by the spoils of war, foreign tribute, and the territories they have purchased by their arms, have sometimes so improved the commonwealth, that they have not only not required any public monies from the poorer sort of subjects, but have also divided to each of them both monies and lands. But this kind of increase of riches is not to be brought into rule and fashion. For the militia, in order to profit, is like a die; wherewith many lose their estates, but few improve them. Since therefore there are three things only, _the fruits of the earth and water_, _labour_, and _thrift_, which are expedient for the enriching of subjects, the duty of commanders in chief shall be conversant only about those three. For the first those laws will be useful, which countenance the arts that improve the increase of the earth and water; such as are _husbandry_ and _fishing_. For the second all laws against idleness, and such as quicken industry, are profitable; as such whereby the _art of navigation_, by help whereof the commodities of the whole world, bought almost by labour only, are brought into one city; and the _mechanics_, under which I comprehend all the arts of the most excellent workmen; and the _mathematical sciences_, the fountains of navigatory and mechanic employments, are held in due esteem and honour. For the third those laws are useful, whereby all inordinate expense, as well in meats as in clothes, and universally in all things which are consumed with usage, is forbidden. Now because such laws are beneficial to the ends above specified, it belongs also to the office of supreme magistrates to establish them. [Sidenote: That more ought not to be determined by the laws, than the benefit of prince and subjects require.] 15. The liberty of subjects consists not in being exempt from the laws of the city, or that they who have the supreme power cannot make what laws they have a mind to. But because all the motions and actions of subjects are never circumscribed by laws, nor can be, by reason of their variety; it is necessary that there be infinite cases which are neither commanded nor prohibited, but every man may either do or not do them as he lists himself. In these, each man is said to enjoy his liberty; and in this sense liberty is to be understood in this place, namely, for that part of natural right which is granted and left to subjects by the civil laws. As water inclosed on all hands with banks, stands still and corrupts; having no bounds, it spreads too largely, and the more passages it finds the more freely it takes its current; so subjects, if they might do nothing without the commands of the law, would grow dull and unwieldy; if all, they would be dispersed; and the more is left undetermined by the laws, the more liberty they enjoy. Both extremes are faulty; for laws were not invented to take away, but to direct men’s actions; even as nature ordained the banks, not to stay, but to guide the course of the stream. The measure of this liberty is to be taken from the subjects’ and the city’s good. Wherefore, in the first place, it is against the charge of those who command and have the authority of making laws, that there should be more laws than necessarily serve for good of the magistrate and his subjects. For since men are wont commonly to debate what to do or not to do, by natural reason rather than any knowledge of the laws, where there are more laws than can easily be remembered, and whereby such things are forbidden as reason of itself prohibits not of necessity, they must through ignorance, without the least evil intention, fall within the compass of laws, as gins laid to entrap their harmless liberty; which supreme commanders are bound to preserve for their subjects by the laws of nature. [Sidenote: That greater punishments must not be inflicted, than are prescribed by the laws.] 16. It is a great part of that _liberty_, which is harmless to civil government and necessary for each subject to live happily, that there be no penalties dreaded but what they may both foresee and look for; and this is done, where there are either no punishments at all defined by the laws, or greater not required than are defined. Where there are none defined, there he that hath first broken the law, expects an indefinite or arbitrary punishment; and his fear is supposed boundless, because it relates to an unbounded evil. Now the law of nature commands them who are not subject to any civil laws, by what we have said in chap. III. art. 11, and therefore supreme commanders, that in taking revenge and punishing they must not so much regard the past evil as the future good; and they sin, if they entertain any other measure in arbitrary punishment than the public benefit. But where the punishment is defined; either by a law prescribed, as when it is set down in plain words that _he that shall do thus or thus, shall suffer so and so_; or by practice, as when the penalty, not by any law prescribed, but arbitrary from the beginning, is afterward determined by the punishment of the first delinquent; (for natural equity commands that equal transgressors be equally punished); there to impose a greater penalty than is defined by the law, is against the law of nature. For the end of punishment is not to compel the will of man, but to fashion it, and to make it such as he would have it who hath set the penalty. And deliberation is nothing else but a weighing, as it were in scales, the conveniences and inconveniences of the fact we are attempting; where that which is more weighty, doth necessarily according to its inclination prevail with us. If therefore the legislator doth set a less penalty on a crime, than will make our fear more considerable with us than our lust, that excess of lust above the fear of punishment, whereby sin is committed, is to be attributed to the legislator, that is to say, to the supreme; and therefore if he inflict a greater punishment than himself hath determined in his laws, he punisheth that in another in which he sinned himself. [Sidenote: Subjects must have right restored to them against corrupt judges.] 17. It pertains therefore to the harmless and necessary _liberty_ of subjects, that every man may without fear enjoy the rights which are allowed him by the laws. For it is in vain to have _our own_ distinguished by the laws from _another’s_, if by wrong judgment, robbery, or theft, they may be again confounded. But it falls out so, that these do happen where judges are corrupted. For the fear whereby men are deterred from doing evil, ariseth not from hence, namely, because penalties are set, but because they are executed. For we esteem the future by what is past, seldom expecting what seldom happens. If therefore judges corrupted either by gifts, favour, or even by pity itself, do often forbear the execution of the penalties due by the law, and by that means put wicked men in hope to pass unpunished: honest subjects encompassed with murderers, thieves, and knaves, will not have the liberty to converse freely with each other, nor scarce to stir abroad without hazard; nay, the _city_ itself is dissolved, and every man’s right of protecting himself at his own will returns to him. The law of nature therefore gives this precept to supreme commanders, that they not only do righteousness themselves, but that they also by penalties cause the judges, by them appointed, to do the same; that is to say, that they hearken to the complaints of their subjects; and as oft as need requires, make choice of some extraordinary judges, who may hear the matter debated concerning the ordinary ones. ------- CHAPTER XIV. OF LAWS AND TRESPASSES. 1. How law differs from counsel. 2. How from covenant. 3. How from right. 4. Division of laws into divine and human: the divine into natural and positive; and the natural into the laws of single men and of nations. 5. The division of human, that is to say, of civil laws into sacred and secular. 6. Into distributive and vindicative. 7. That distributive and vindicative are not species, but parts of the laws. 8. All law is supposed to have a penalty annexed to it. 9. The precepts of the decalogue of honouring parents, of murder, adultery, theft, false witness, are civil laws. 10. It is impossible to command aught by the civil law contrary to the law of nature. 11. It is essential to a law, both that itself and also the lawgiver be known. 12. Whence the lawgiver comes to be known. 13. Publishing and interpretation are necessary to the knowledge of a law. 14. The division of the civil law into written and unwritten. 15. The natural laws are not written laws; neither are the wise sentences of lawyers nor custom laws of themselves, but by the consent of the supreme power. 16. What the word sin, most largely taken, signifies. 17. The definition of sin. 18. The difference between a sin of infirmity and malice. 19. Under what kind of sin atheism is contained. 20. What treason is. 21. That by treason not the civil, but the natural laws are broken. 22. And that therefore it is to be punished not by the right of dominion, but by the right of war. 23. That obedience is not rightly distinguished into active and passive. [Sidenote: How law differs from counsel.] 1. They who less seriously consider the force of words, do sometimes confound _law_ with _counsel_, sometimes with _covenant_, sometimes with _right_. They confound _law_ with _counsel_, who think that it is the duty of monarchs not only to give ear to their _counsellors_, but also to obey them; as though it were in vain to take _counsel_, unless it were also followed. We must fetch the distinction between _counsel_ and _law_, from the difference between _counsel_ and _command_. Now _counsel_ is a _precept_, in which the reason of my obeying it is taken from _the thing itself which is advised_; but _command_ is a _precept_, in which the cause of my obedience depends on _the will of the commander_. For it is not properly said, _thus I will and thus I command_, except the will stand for a reason. Now when obedience is yielded to the laws, not for the thing itself, but by reason of the adviser’s will, the law is not a _counsel_, but a _command_, and is defined thus: _law is the command of that person, whether man or court, whose precept contains in it the reason of obedience_: as the precepts of God in regard of men, of magistrates in respect of their subjects, and universally of all the powerful in respect of them who cannot resist, may be termed their laws. _Law_ and _counsel_ therefore differ many ways. _Law_ belongs to him who hath power over them whom he adviseth; _counsel_ to them who have no power. To follow what is prescribed by _law_, is _duty_; what by _counsel_, is _free-will_. _Counsel_ is directed to his end, that receives it; _law_, to his that gives it. _Counsel_ is given to none but the willing; _law_ even to the unwilling. To conclude, the right of the _counsellor_ is made void by the will of him to whom he gives counsel; the right of the _law-giver_ is not abrogated at the pleasure of him who hath a _law_ imposed. [Sidenote: How it differs from a covenant.] 2. They confound _law_ and _covenant_, who conceive the laws to be nothing else but certain ὁμολογήματα, or forms of living determined by the common consent of men. Among whom is Aristotle, who defines _law_ on this manner; Νόμός ἐστι λόγος ὡρισμένος καθ’ ὁμολογίαν κοινὴν πόλεως, μγνύων πῶς δεῖ πράττειν ἕκαστα: that is to say, _law is a speech, limited according to the common consent of the city, declaring every thing that we ought to do_. Which definition is not simply of _law_, but of the _civil law_. For it is manifest that the _divine laws_ sprang not from the consent of men, nor yet the _laws of nature_. For if they had their original from the consent of men, they might also by the same consent be abrogated; but they are unchangeable. But indeed, that is no right definition of a _civil law_. For in that place, a city is taken either for one civil person, having one will; or for a multitude of men, who have each of them the liberty of their private wills. If for one person, those words _common consent_ are ill-placed here; for _one_ person hath no _common consent_. Neither ought he to have said, _declaring_ what was needful to be done, but _commanding_; for what the city declares, it commands its subjects. He therefore by a city understood a multitude of men, declaring by common consent (imagine it a writing confirmed by votes) some certain forms of living. But these are nothing else but some mutual contracts, which oblige not any man (and therefore are no laws) before that a supreme power being constituted, which can compel, have sufficient remedy against the rest, who otherwise are not likely to keep them. Laws therefore, according to this definition of Aristotle, are nothing else but naked and weak contracts; which then at length, when there is one who by right doth exercise the supreme power, shall either become _laws_ or _no laws_ at his will and pleasure. Wherefore he confounds _contracts_ with _laws_, which he ought not to have done; for contract is _a promise_, law a _command_. In contracts we say, _I will do this_; in laws, _do this_. Contracts oblige us;[16] laws tie us fast, being obliged. A _contract_ obligeth of _itself_; the _law_ holds the party obliged by virtue of the universal _contract_ of yielding obedience. Therefore in _contract_, it is first determined what is to be done, before we are obliged to do it; but in _law_, we are first obliged to perform, and what is to be done is determined afterwards. Aristotle therefore ought to have defined a _civil law_ thus: _a civil law is a speech limited by the will of the city, commanding everything behoveful to be done_. Which is the same with that we have given above, in chap. VI. art. 9: to wit, _that the civil laws are the command of him, whether man or court of men, who is endued with supreme power in the city, concerning the future actions of his subjects_. Footnote 16: _Contracts oblige us._] _To be obliged_, and _to be tied being obliged_, seems to some men to be one and the same thing; and that therefore here seems to be some distinction in words, but none indeed. More clearly therefore, I say thus: that a man is obliged by his contracts, that is, that he ought to perform for his promise sake; but that the law ties him being obliged, that is to say, it compels him to make good his promise for fear of the punishment appointed by the law. [Sidenote: How it differs from right.] 3. They confound _laws_ with _right_, who continue still to do what is permitted by _divine right_, notwithstanding it be forbidden by _the civil law_. That which is prohibited by the _divine law_, cannot be permitted by the _civil_; neither can that which is commanded by the _divine law_, be prohibited _by the civil_. Notwithstanding, that which is permitted by the _divine right_, that is to say, that which may be done by _divine right_, doth no whit hinder why the same may not be forbidden by the _civil laws_; for _inferior laws_ may restrain the liberty allowed by the _superior_, although they cannot enlarge them. Now _natural liberty_ is a right not constituted, but allowed by the laws. For the _laws_ being removed, our _liberty_ is absolute. This is first restrained by the _natural_ and _divine laws_; the residue is bounded by the _civil law_; and what remains, may again be restrained by the _constitutions_ of particular towns and societies. There is great difference therefore between _law_ and _right_. For law is _a fetter_, right is _freedom_; and they differ like contraries. [Sidenote: The division of laws into divine and human; and of the divine into natural and positive; and of the natural into those laws of single men, and those of nations.] 4. All _law_ may be divided, first according to the diversity of its authors into _divine_ and _human_. The _divine_, according to the two ways whereby God hath made known his will unto men, is twofold; _natural_ or _moral_, and _positive_. _Natural_ is that which God hath declared to all men by his _eternal word_ born with them, to wit, their _natural reason_; and this is that law, which in this whole book I have endeavoured to unfold. _Positive_ is that, which God hath revealed to us by _the word of prophecy_, wherein he hath spoken unto men as a man. Such are the laws which he gave to the Jews concerning their government and divine worship; and they may be termed the _divine civil laws_, because they were peculiar to the civil government of the Jews, his peculiar people. Again, _the natural law_ may be divided into that of _men_, which alone hath obtained the title of the _law of nature_; and _that of cities_, which may be called _that of nations_, but vulgarly it is termed the _right of nations_. The precepts of both are alike. But because cities once instituted do put on the personal proprieties of men, that _law_, which speaking of the duty of single men we call _natural_, being applied to whole cities and nations, is called the _right of nations_. And the same elements of _natural law and right_, which have hitherto been spoken of, being transferred to _whole cities_ and _nations_, may be taken for the elements of the _laws_ and _right of nations_. [Sidenote: The division of human, that is to say, civil laws into secular and sacred.] 5. All _human law_ is _civil_. For the state of men considered out of civil society, is hostile; in which, because one is not subject to another, there are no other laws beside the dictates of natural reason, which is the divine law. But in civil government the city only, that is to say, that man or court to whom the supreme power of the city is committed, is the legislator; and the laws of the city are civil. _The civil laws_ may be divided, according to the diversity of their subject matter, into _sacred_ or _secular_. _Sacred_ are those which pertain to religion, that is to say, to the ceremonies and worship of God: to wit, what persons, things, places, are to be consecrated, and in what fashion; what opinions concerning the Deity are to be taught publicly; and with what words and in what order supplications are to be made; and the like; and are not determined by any divine positive law. For the _civil sacred laws_ are the _human laws_ (which are also called _ecclesiastical_) concerning _things sacred_; but _the secular_, under a general notion, are usually called the _civil_ laws. [Sidenote: Into distributive and vindicative.] 6. Again, the _civil law_ (according to the two offices of the legislator, whereof one is to judge, the other to constrain men to acquiesce to his judgments) hath two parts; the one _distributive_, the other _vindicative_ or _penal_. By the _distributive_ it is, that every man hath his proper rights; that is to say, it sets forth rules for all things, whereby we may know what is properly our’s, what another man’s; so as others may not hinder us from the free use and enjoyment of our own, and we may not interrupt others in the quiet possession of their’s; and what is lawful for every man to do or omit, and what is not lawful. _Vindicative_ is that, whereby it is defined what punishment shall be inflicted on them who break the law. [Sidenote: Distributive and vindicative are not two species of the laws.] 7. Now _distributive_ and _vindicative_ are not two several _species_ of the laws, but two _parts_ of the same law. For if the law should say no more, but (for example) _whatsoever you take with your net in the sea, be it yours_, it is in vain. For although another should take that away from you which you have caught, it hinders not but that it still remains yours. For in the state of nature where all things are common to all, _yours_ and _others_ are all one; insomuch as what the law defines to be _yours_, was _yours_ even before the law, and after the law ceases not to be _yours_, although in another man’s possession. Wherefore the law doth nothing, unless it be understood to be so _yours_, as all other men be forbidden to interrupt your free use and secure enjoyment of it at all times, according to your own will and pleasure. For this is that which is required to a propriety of goods; not that a man may be able to use them, but to use them alone; which is done by prohibiting others to be an hinderance to him. But in vain do they also prohibit any men, who do not withal strike a fear of punishment into them. In vain therefore is the law, unless it contain both parts, that which _forbids_ injuries to be done, and that which _punisheth_ the doers of them. The first of them, which is called _distributive_, is _prohibitory_, and speaks to all; the second, which is styled _vindicative_ or _penary_, is _mandatory_, and only speaks to public ministers. [Sidenote: All law is supposed to have a penalty annexed to it.] 8. From hence also we may understand, _that every civil law hath a penalty annexed to it_, either explicitly or implicitly. For where the penalty is not defined, neither by any writing, nor by example of any who hath suffered the punishment of the transgressed law, there the penalty is understood to be arbitrary; namely, to depend on the will of the legislator, that is to say, of the supreme commander. For in vain is that law, which may be broken without punishment. [Sidenote: The precepts of the Decalogue of honouring parents, of murder, adultery, theft, false witnesses, are the civil laws.] 9. Now because it comes from the civil laws, both that every man have _his proper right_ and distinguished from _another’s_, and also that he is forbidden to invade another’s rights; it follows that these precepts: _Thou shalt not refuse to give the honour defined by the laws, unto thy parents_: _Thou shalt not kill the man, whom the laws forbid thee to kill_: _Thou shalt avoid all copulation forbidden by the laws_: _Thou shalt not take away another’s goods, against the lords will_: _Thou shalt not frustrate the laws and judgments by false testimony_: are civil laws. The natural laws command the same things, but implicitly. For the law of nature (as hath been said in chap. III. art. 2) commands us to _keep contracts_; and therefore also to perform obedience, when we have covenanted obedience, and to abstain from another’s goods, when it is determined by the civil law what belongs to another. But all subjects (by chap. VI. art. 13) do _covenant_ to obey his commands who hath the supreme power, that is to say, the civil laws, in the very constitution of government, even before it is possible to break them. For the law of nature did oblige in the state of nature; where first, because nature hath given all things to all men, nothing did properly belong to another, and therefore it was not possible to invade another’s right; next, where all things were common, and therefore all carnal copulations lawful; thirdly, where was the state of war, and therefore lawful to kill; fourthly, where all things were determined by every man’s own judgment, and therefore paternal respects also; lastly, where there were no public judgments, and therefore no use of bearing witness, either true or false. [Sidenote: It is not possible to command aught by the civil law, contrary to the laws of nature.] 10. Seeing therefore our obligation to observe those laws is more ancient than the promulgation of the laws themselves, as being contained in the very constitution of the city; by the virtue of the natural law which forbids breach of covenant, the law of nature commands us to keep all the civil laws. For where we are tied to obedience before we know what will be commanded us, there we are universally tied to obey in all things. Whence it follows, that no civil law whatsoever, which tends not to a reproach of the Deity, (in respect of whom cities themselves have no right of their own, and cannot be said to make laws), can possibly be against the law of nature. For though the law of nature forbid theft, adultery, &c; yet if the civil law command us to invade anything, that invasion is not theft, adultery, &c. For when the Lacedæmonians of old permitted their youths, by a certain law, to take away other men’s goods, they commanded that these goods should not be accounted other men’s, but their own who took them; and therefore such surreptions were no thefts. In like manner, copulations of heathen sexes, according to their laws, were lawful marriages. [Sidenote: It is essential to a law, that both it and the legislator be known.] 11. It is necessary to the essence of a law, that the subjects be acquainted with two things: first, what man or court hath the supreme power, that is to say, the right of making laws; secondly, what the law itself says. For he that neither knew either to whom or what he is tied to, cannot obey; and by consequence is in such a condition as if he were not tied at all. I say not that it is necessary to the essence of a law, that either one or the other be perpetually known, but only that it be once known. And if the subject afterward forget either the right he hath who made the law, or the law itself, that makes him no less tied to obey; since he might have remembered it, had he a will to obey. [Sidenote: Whence the legislator is known.] 12. _The knowledge of the legislator_ depends on the subject himself; for the right of making laws could not be conferred on any man without his own consent and covenant, either expressed or supposed; expressed, when from the beginning the citizens do themselves constitute a form of governing the city, or when by promise they submit themselves to the dominion of any one; or supposed at least, as when they make use of the benefit of the realm and laws for their protection and conservation against others. For to whose dominion we require our fellow subjects to yield obedience for our good, his dominion we acknowledge to be legitimate by that very request. And therefore ignorance of the power of making laws, can never be a sufficient excuse; for every man knows what he hath done himself. [Sidenote: Promulgation and interpretation are necessary to the knowledge of a law.] 13. _The knowledge of the laws_ depends on the legislator; who must publish them; for otherwise they are not laws. For law is the command of the law-maker, and his command is the declaration of his will; it is not therefore a law, except the will of the law-maker be declared, which is done by _promulgation_. Now in _promulgation_ two things must be manifest; whereof one is, that he or they who publish a law, either have a right themselves to make laws, or that they do it by authority derived from him or them who have it; the other is the sense of the law itself. Now, that the first, namely, published laws, proceed from him who hath the supreme command, cannot be manifest (speaking exactly and philosophically) to any, but them who have received them from the mouth of the commander. The rest believe; but the reasons of their belief are so many, that it is scarce possible they should not believe. And truly in a _democratical_ city, where every one may be present at the making of laws if he will, he that shall be absent, must believe those that were present. But in _monarchies_ and _aristocracies_, because it is granted but to few to be present, and openly to hear the commands of the _monarch_ or the _nobles_, it was necessary to bestow a power on those few of publishing them to the rest. And thus we believe those to be the _edicts_ and _decrees_ of princes, which are propounded to us for such, either by the writings or voices of them whose office it is to publish them. But yet, when we have these causes of belief; that we have seen the prince or supreme counsel constantly use such _counsellors_, _secretaries_, _publishers_, and _seals_, and the like arguments for the declaring of his will; that he never took any authority from them; that they have been punished, who not giving credit to such like promulgations have transgressed the law; not only he who thus believing shall obey the _edicts_ and _decrees_ set forth by them, is everywhere excused, but he that not believing shall not yield obedience, is punished. For the constant permission of these things is a manifest sign enough and evident declaration of the commander’s will; provided there be nothing contained in the _law_, _edict_, or _decree_, derogatory from his supreme power. For it is not to be imagined that he would have aught taken from his power by any of his officers, as long as he retains a will to govern. Now the _sense_ of the _law_, when there is any doubt made of it, is to be taken from them to whom the supreme authority hath committed the _knowledge of causes_ or _judgments_; for to _judge_, is nothing else than by _interpretation_ to apply the _laws_ to particular cases. Now we may know who they are that have this office granted them, in the same manner as we know who they be that have authority given them to publish laws. [Sidenote: The civil law divided into written and unwritten.] 14. Again the _civil law_, according to its two-fold manner of publishing, is of two sorts, _written_ and _unwritten_. By _written_, I understand that which wants a voice, or some other sign of the will of the legislator, that it may become a law. For all kind of laws are of the same age with mankind, both in nature and time; and therefore of more antiquity than the invention of letters, and the art of writing. Wherefore not a _writing_, but a _voice_ is necessary for a _written law_; this alone is requisite to the _being_, that to the _remembrance_ of a law. For we read, that before letters were found out for the help of memory, that _laws_, contracted into metre, were wont to be sung. The _unwritten_, is that which wants no other publishing than the voice of nature or natural reason; such are the _laws of nature_. For the natural law, although it be distinguished from the civil, forasmuch as it commands the will; yet so far forth as it relates to our actions, it is civil. For example, this same, _thou shalt not covet_, which only appertains to the mind, is a natural law only; but this, _thou shalt not invade_, is both natural and civil. For seeing it is impossible to prescribe such universal rules, whereby all future contentions, which perhaps are infinite, may be determined; it is to be understood that in all cases not mentioned by the _written laws_, the _law of natural equity_ is to be followed, which commands us to distribute equally to equals; and this by the virtue of the _civil law_, which also punisheth those who knowingly and willingly do actually transgress the _laws of nature_. [Sidenote: That the natural laws are not written laws, neither are the sentences of lawyers or customs laws of themselves, but by the consent of the supreme power.] 15. These things being understood, it appears, first, that the _laws of nature_, although they were described in the books of some philosophers, are not for that reason to be termed _written laws_: and that the writings of the interpreters of the laws, were no laws, for want of the supreme authority; nor yet those _orations of the wise_, that is to say, _judges_, but so far forth as by the consent of the supreme power they part into custom; and that then they are to be received among the _written laws_, not for the custom’s sake, (which by its own force doth not constitute a law), but for the will of the supreme commander; which appears in this, that he hath suffered his _sentence_, whether equal or unequal, to pass into custom. [Sidenote: What the word _sin_, taken in its largest sense, signifies.] 16. _Sin_, in its largest signification, comprehends every _deed_, _word_, and _thought_ against right reason. For every man, by reasoning, seeks out the means to the end which he propounds to himself. If therefore he reason right, that is to say, beginning from most evident principles he makes a discourse out of consequences continually necessary, he will proceed in a most direct way. Otherwise he will go astray, that is to say, he will either _do_, _say_, or _endeavour_ somewhat against his proper end; which when he hath done, he will indeed in reasoning be said to have _erred_, but in action and will to have _sinned_. For _sin_ follows _error_, just as the _will_ doth the _understanding_. And this is the most general acception of the word; under which is contained every _imprudent_ action, whether against the law, as to overthrow another man’s house, or not against the law, as to build his own upon the sand. [Sidenote: The definition of sin.] 17. But when we speak of _the laws_, the word _sin_ is taken in a more strict sense, and signifies not every thing done against right reason, but that only which is _blameable_; and therefore it is called _malum culpæ_, the evil of fault. But yet if anything be culpable, it is not presently to be termed _a sin_ or _fault_; but only if it be blameable with reason. We must therefore enquire what it is to be _blameable with reason_, what _against reason_. Such is the nature of man, that every one calls that _good_ which he desires, and _evil_ which he eschews. And therefore through the diversity of our affections it happens, that one counts that _good_, which another counts _evil_; and the same man what now he esteemed for _good_, he immediately after looks on as _evil_: and the same thing which he calls _good_ in himself, he terms _evil_ in another. For we all measure _good_ and _evil_ by the pleasure or pain we either feel at present, or expect hereafter. Now seeing the prosperous actions of enemies, because they increase their honours, goods, and power; and of equals, by reason of that strife of honours which is among them; both seem and are _irksome_, and therefore _evil_ to all; and men use to repute those _evil_, that is to say, to _lay some fault_ to their charge, from whom they receive _evil_; it is impossible to be determined by the consent of single men, whom the same things do not please and displease, what actions are, and what not to be blamed. They may agree indeed in some certain general things, as that _theft_, _adultery_, and the like are _sins_; as if they should say that all men account those things _evil_, to which they have given names which are usually taken in an _evil_ sense. But we demand not whether theft be a sin, but what is to be termed theft; and so concerning others, in like manner. Forasmuch therefore as in so great a diversity of censurers, what is by reason blameable is not to be measured by the reason of one man more than another, because of the equality of human nature; and there are no other reasons in being, but only those of _particular men_, and that of the _city_: it follows, that the _city_ is to determine what _with reason is culpable_. So as a _fault_, that is to say, a _sin_, is that which a man does, omits, says, or wills, against the reason of _the city_, that is, contrary to the laws. [Sidenote: The difference between a sin of infirmity and malice.] 18. But a man may do somewhat against the laws through human infirmity, although he desire to fulfil them; and yet his action, as being against the laws, is rightly blamed, and called a _sin_. But there are some who _neglect_ the laws; and as oft as any hope of gain and impunity doth appear to them, no conscience of contracts and betrothed faith can withhold them from their violation. Not only the deeds, but even the minds of these men are against the laws. They who sin only through infirmity, are _good men_ even when they sin; but these, even when they do not sin, are wicked. For though both the action and the mind be repugnant to the laws, yet those repugnances are distinguished by different appellations. For the irregularity of the action is called ἀδίκημα, _unjust deed_; that of the mind ἀδικὶα and κακὶα, _injustice_ and _malice_; that is the infirmity of a disturbed soul, this the _pravity_ of a sober mind. [Sidenote: Under what kind of sin atheism is contained.] 19. But seeing there is no sin which is not against some law, and that there is no law which is not the command of him who hath the supreme power, and that no man hath a supreme power which is not bestowed on him by our own consent; in what manner will he be said to sin, who either denies that there is a God, or that he governs the world, or casts any other reproach upon him? For he will say: _that he never submitted his will to God’s will, not conceiving him so much as to have any being: and granting that his opinion were erroneous, and therefore also a sin, yet were it to be numbered among those of imprudence or ignorance, which by right cannot be punished_. This speech seems so far forth to be admitted, that though this kind of sin be the greatest and most hurtful, yet is it to be referred to sins of imprudence;[17] but that it should be excused by imprudence or ignorance, is absurd. For the atheist is punished either immediately by God himself, or by kings constituted under God; not as a subject is punished by a king, because he keeps not the laws; but as one enemy by another, because he would not accept of the laws; that is to say, by the right of war, as the giants warring against God. For whosoever are not subject either to some common lord, or one to another, are enemies among themselves. Footnote 17: _Yet is it to be referred to sins of imprudence._] Many find fault that I have referred atheism to imprudence, and not to injustice; yea by some it is taken so, as if I had not declared myself an enemy bitter enough against atheists. They object further, that since I had elsewhere said that it might be known _there is a God_ by natural reason, I ought to have acknowledged that they sin at least against the law of nature, and therefore are not only guilty of imprudence, but injustice too. But I am so much an enemy to atheists, that I have both diligently sought for, and vehemently desired to find some law whereby I might condemn them of injustice. But when I found none, I inquired next what name God himself did give to men so detested by him. Now God speaks thus of the atheist: _The fool hath said in his heart, there is no God_. Wherefore I placed their sin in that rank which God himself refers to. Next I show them to be enemies of God. But I conceive the name of an enemy to be sometimes somewhat sharper, than that of an unjust man. Lastly, I affirm that they may under that notion be justly punished both by God, and supreme magistrates; and therefore by no means excuse or extenuate this sin. Now that I have said, that it might be known by natural reason _that there is a God_, is so to be understood, not as if I had meant that all men might know this; except they think, that because Archimedes by natural reason found out what proportion the circle hath to the square, it follows thence, that every one of the vulgar could have found out as much. I say therefore, that although it may be known to some by the light of reason that there is a God; yet men that are continually engaged in pleasures or seeking of riches and honour; also men that are not wont to reason aright, or cannot do it, or care not to do it; lastly, fools, in which number are atheists, cannot know this. [Sidenote: What the sin of treason is.] 20. Seeing that from the virtue of the covenant, whereby each subject is tied to the other to perform absolute and universal obedience (such as is defined above, chap. VI. art. 13) to the city, that is to say, to the sovereign power, whether that be one man or council, there is an obligation derived to observe each one of the civil laws; so that that covenant contains in itself all the laws at once; it is manifest that the subject who shall renounce the general covenant of obedience, doth at once renounce all the laws. Which trespass is so much worse than any other one sin, by how much to sin _always_, is worse than to sin _once_. And this is that sin which is called _treason_; and it is a word or deed whereby the citizen or subject declares, that he will no longer obey that man or court to whom the supreme power of the city is entrusted. And the subject declares this same will of his by deed, when he either doth or endeavours to do violence to the sovereign’s person, or to them who execute his commands. Of which sort are traitors, regicides, and such as take up arms against the city, or during a war fly to the enemy’s side. And they show the same will in word, who flatly deny that themselves or other subjects are tied to any such kind of obedience, either in the whole, as he who should say that we must not obey him (keeping the obedience which we owe to God entire) simply, absolutely, and universally; or in part, as he who should say, that he had no right to wage war at his own will, to make peace, enlist soldiers, levy monies, elect magistrates and public ministers, enact laws, decide controversies, set penalties, or do aught else without which the state cannot stand. And these and the like words and deeds are treason by the natural, not the civil law. But it may so happen, that some action, which before the civil law was made, was not treason, yet will become such if it be done afterwards. As if it be declared by the law, that it shall be accounted for a sign of renouncing public obedience, that is to say, for treason, if any man shall coin monies, or forge the privy-seal; he that after that declaration shall do this, will be no less guilty of treason than the other. Yet he sins less, because he breaks not all the laws at once, but one law only. For the law by calling that treason which by nature is not so, doth indeed by right set a more odious name, and perhaps a more grievous punishment on the guilty persons; but it makes not the sin itself more grievous. [Sidenote: Treason breaks not the civil, but the natural law.] 21. But that sin, which by the law of nature is treason, is a transgression of the natural, not the civil law. For since our obligation to civil obedience, by virtue whereof the civil laws are valid, is before all civil law, and the sin of treason is naturally nothing else but the breach of that obligation; it follows, that by the sin of treason that law is broken which preceded the civil law, to wit, the natural, which forbids us to violate covenants and betrothed faith. But if some sovereign prince should set forth a law on this manner, _thou shalt not rebel_, he would effect just nothing. For except subjects were before obliged to obedience, that is to say, not to rebel, all law is of no force. Now the obligation which obligeth to what we were before obliged to, is superfluous. [Sidenote: And therefore is punished not by the right of sovereignty, but by the right of war.] 22. Hence it follows, that _rebels_, _traitors_, and all others _convicted of treason_, are punished not by _civil_, but _natural_ right; that is to say, not as _civil subjects_, but as _enemies to the government_; not by the _right of sovereignty_ and _dominion_, but by the _right of war_. [Sidenote: Obedience not rightly distinguished into active and passive.] 23. There are some who think that those acts which are done against the law, when the punishment is determined by the law itself, are expiated, if the punished willingly undergo the punishment; and that they are not guilty before God of breaking the natural law, (although by breaking the civil laws, we break the natural too, which command us to keep the civil), who have suffered the punishment which the law required; as if by the law the fact were not prohibited, but a punishment were set instead of a price, whereby a license might be bought of doing what the law forbids. By the same reason they might infer too, that no transgression of the law were a sin; but that every man might enjoy the liberty which he hath bought by his own peril. But we must know, that the words of the law may be understood in a two-fold sense. The one as containing two parts, (as hath been declared above in art. 7), namely, that of absolutely prohibiting, as, _thou shalt not do this_; and revenging, as, _he that doth this, shall be punished_. The other, as containing a condition, for example, _thou shalt not do this thing, unless thou wilt suffer punishment_; and thus the law forbids not simply, but conditionally. If it be understood in the first sense, he that doth it sins, because he doth what the law forbids to be done; if in the second, he sins not, because he cannot be said to do what is forbidden him, that performs the condition. For in the first sense, all men are forbidden to do it; in the second, they only who keep themselves from the punishment. In the first sense, the vindicative part of the law obligeth not the guilty, but the magistrate to require punishment; in the second, he himself that owes the punishment, is obliged to exact it; to the payment whereof, if it be capital or otherwise grievous, he cannot be obliged. But in what sense the law is to be taken, depends on the will of him who hath the sovereignty. When therefore there is any doubt of the meaning of the law, since we are sure they sin not who do it not, it will be sin if we do it, howsoever the law may afterward be explained. For to do that which a man doubts whether it be a sin or not, when he hath freedom to forbear it, is a contempt of the laws; and therefore by chap. III. art. 28, a sin against the law of nature. Vain therefore is that same distinction of _obedience_ into _active_ and _passive_; as if that could be expiated by penalties constituted by human decrees, which is a sin against the law of nature, which is the law of God; or as though they sinned not, who sin at their own peril. RELIGION --- CHAPTER XV. OF THE KINGDOM OF GOD BY NATURE. 1. The proposition of the following contents. 2. Over whom God is said to rule by nature. 3. The word of God threefold; reason, revelation, prophecy. 4. The kingdom of God twofold; natural, and prophetic. 5. The right whereby God reigns, is seated in his omnipotence. 6. The same proved from Scripture. 7. The obligation of yielding obedience to God, proceeds from human infirmity. 8. The laws of God in his natural kingdom, are those which are recited above in chapters II. III. 9. What honour and worship is. 10. Worship consists either in attributes or in actions. 11. And there is one sort natural, another arbitrary. 12. One commanded, another voluntary. 13. What the end or scope of worship is. 14. What the natural laws are concerning God’s attributes. 15. What the actions are whereby naturally we do give worship. 16. In God’s natural kingdom, the city may appoint what worship of God it pleaseth. 17. God ruling by nature only, the city, that is to say, that man or court who under God hath the sovereign authority of the city, is the interpreter of all the laws. 18. Certain doubts removed. 19. What sin is in the natural kingdom of God; and what treason against the Divine Majesty. [Sidenote: The proposition of the following contents.] 1. We have already in the foregoing chapters, proved both by reason and testimonies of holy writ, that the estate of nature, that is to say, of absolute liberty, such as is theirs who neither govern nor are governed, is an anarchy or hostile state; that the precepts whereby to avoid this state, are _the laws of nature_; that there can be no civil government without a sovereign; and that they who have gotten this sovereign command, must be obeyed simply, that is to say, in all things which repugn not the commandments of God. There is this one thing only wanting to the complete understanding of all civil duty, and that is, to know which are the laws and commandments of God. For else we cannot tell whether that which the civil power commands us, be against the laws of God, or not; whence it must necessarily happen, that either by too much obedience to the civil authority we become stubborn against the divine Majesty; or for fear of sinning against God we run into disobedience against the civil power. To avoid both these rocks, it is necessary to know the divine laws. Now because the knowledge of the laws depends on the knowledge of the kingdom, we must in what follows speak somewhat concerning the _kingdom of God_. [Sidenote: Over whom God is said to reign:] 2. _The Lord is king, the earth may be glad thereof_; saith the psalmist, (Psalm xcvii. 1). And again the same psalmist, (Psalm xcix. 1): _The Lord is king, be the people never so impatient; he sitteth between the cherubims, be the earth never so unquiet_; to wit, whether men will or not, God is the king over all the earth; nor is he moved from his throne, if there be any who deny either his _existence_ or his _providence_. Now although God govern all men so by his power, that none can do anything which he would not have done: yet this, to speak properly and accurately, is not to reign. For he is said to reign, who rules not by _acting_, but _speaking_, that is to say, by _precepts_ and _threatenings_. And therefore we count not inanimate nor irrational bodies for subjects in the kingdom of God, although they be subordinate to the divine power; because they _understand not the commands and threats_ of God: nor yet the atheists, because they believe not that there is a God; nor yet those who believing there is a God, do not yet believe that he rules these inferior things: for even these, although they be governed by the power of God, yet do they not acknowledge any of his _commands_, nor stand in awe of his _threats_. Those only therefore are supposed to belong to God’s kingdom, who acknowledge him to be the governor of all things, and that he hath given _his commands_ to men, and appointed _punishments_ for the transgressors. The rest we must not call subjects, but enemies of God. [Sidenote: The word of God threefold; reason, revelation, prophesy.] 3. But none are said to govern by _commands_, but they who openly declare them to those who are governed by them. For the _commands_ of the rulers, are the _laws_ of the ruled; but _laws_ they are not, if not perspicuously published, insomuch as all excuse of ignorance may be taken away. Men indeed publish their laws by _word_ or _voice_; neither can they make their will universally known any other way. But God’s _laws_ are declared after a threefold manner: first, _by the tacit dictates of right reason_; next, by _immediate revelation_, which is supposed to be done either by a supernatural voice, or by a vision or dream, or divine inspiration; thirdly, by the _voice of one man_, whom God recommends to the rest, as worthy of belief, by the working of true miracles. Now he whose voice God thus makes use of to signify his will unto others, is called a _prophet_. These three manners may be termed the _threefold word of God_, to wit, the _rational word_, the _sensible word_, and _the word of prophecy_. To which answer the three manners whereby we are said to hear God; _right reasoning_, _sense_, and _faith_. God’s _sensible word_ hath come but to few; neither hath God spoken to men by revelation, except particularly to some, and to diverse diversely; neither have any laws of his kingdom been published on this manner unto any people. [Sidenote: The kingdom of God two-fold: natural, and prophetic.] 4. And according to the difference which is between the _rational word_ and the _word of prophecy_, we attribute a two-fold kingdom unto God: _natural_, in which he reigns by the dictates of right reason; and which is universal over all who acknowledge the divine power, by reason of that rational nature which is common to all: and _prophetical_, in which he rules also by the _word of prophecy_; which is peculiar, because he hath not given positive laws to all men, but to his peculiar people and some certain men elected by him. [Sidenote: The right whereby God governs, is seated in his omnipotence.] 5. God in his _natural kingdom_ hath a right to rule, and to punish those who break his laws, from his sole _irresistible power_. For all right over others is either from _nature_, or from _contract_. How the right of governing springs from _contract_, we have already showed in chap. VI. And the same right is derived from _nature_, in this very thing, that it is not by nature taken away. For when by nature all men had a right over all things, every man had a right of ruling over all as ancient as nature itself. But the reason why this was abolished among men, was no other but mutual fear, as hath been declared above in chap. II. art. 3; reason, namely, dictating that they must forego that right for the preservation of mankind; because the equality of men among themselves, according to their strength and natural powers, was necessarily accompanied with war; and with war joins the destruction of mankind. Now if any man had so far exceeded the rest in power, that all of them with joined forces could not have resisted him, there had been no cause why he should part with that right, which nature had given him. The right therefore of dominion over all the rest would have remained with him, by reason of that excess of power whereby he could have preserved both himself and them. They therefore whose power cannot be resisted, and by consequence God _Almighty_ derives his right of sovereignty from the _power_ itself. And as oft as God punisheth or slays a sinner, although he therefore punish him because he sinned, yet may we not say that he could not justly have punished or killed him although he had not sinned. Neither, if the will of God in punishing may perhaps have regard to some sin antecedent, doth it therefore follow, that the right of afflicting and killing depends not on _divine power_, but on _men’s sins_. [Sidenote: The same proved from Scripture.] 6. That question made famous by the disputations of the ancients: _why evil things befal the good, and good things the evil_: is the same with this of ours; _by what right God dispenseth good and evil things unto men_; and with its difficulty it not only staggers the faith of the vulgar concerning the divine Providence, but also philosophers, and which is more, even of holy men. Psalm lxxiii. 1, 2, 3: _Truly God is good to Israel, even to such as are of a clean heart; but as for me, my feet were almost gone, my steps had well nigh slipped. And why? I was grieved at the wicked; I do also see the ungodly in such prosperity._ And how bitterly did Job expostulate with God, that being _just_ he should yet be afflicted with so many calamities! God himself with open voice resolved this difficulty in the case of Job, and hath confirmed his right by arguments drawn not from Job’s sin, but from his own power. For Job and his friends had argued so among themselves; that they would needs make him guilty, because he was punished; and he would reprove their accusation by arguments fetched from his own innocence. But God, when he had heard both him and them, refutes his expostulation, not by condemning him of injustice or any sin, but by declaring his own power, (Job xxxviii. 4): _Where wast thou_ (says he) _when I laid the foundation of the earth, &c._ And for his friends, God pronounces himself angry against them (Job. xlii. 7): _Because they had not spoken of him the thing that is right, like his servant Job._ Agreeable to this is that speech of our Saviour’s in the man’s case who was born blind: when his disciples asking him whether he or his parents had sinned, that he was born blind, he answered, (John ix. 3): _Neither hath this man sinned, nor his parents; but that the works of God should be manifest in him._ For though it be said, (Rom. v. 12), _that death entered into the world by sin_: it follows not but that God by his right might have made men subject to diseases and death, although they had never sinned; even as he hath made the other animals mortal and sickly, although they cannot sin. [Sidenote: The obligation of yielding obedience unto God, proceeds from human infirmity.] 7. Now if God have the right of sovereignty from his power, it is manifest that the _obligation_ of yielding him obedience lies on men by reason of their weakness.[18] For that _obligation_ which rises from contract, of which we have spoken in chap. II. can have no place here; where the right of ruling, no covenant passing between, rises only from nature. But there are two species of _natural obligation_. One, when liberty is taken away by corporal impediments, according to which we say that heaven and earth, and all creatures, do obey the common laws of their creation. The other, when it is taken away by hope or fear, according to which the weaker, despairing of his own power to resist, cannot but yield to the stronger. From this last kind of obligation, that is to say, from fear or conscience of our own weakness in respect of the divine power, it comes to pass that we are obliged to obey God in his natural kingdom; reason dictating to all, acknowledging the divine power and providence, _that there is no kicking against the pricks_. Footnote 18: _By reason of their weakness._] If this shall seem hard to any man, I desire him with a silent thought to consider, if there were two Omnipotents, whether were bound to obey. I believe he will confess that neither is bound. If this be true, then it is also true what I have set down; that men are subject unto God, because they are not omnipotent. And truly our Saviour admonishing Paul, who at that time was an enemy to the Church, that he should not kick against the pricks; seems to require obedience from him for this cause, because he had not power enough to resist. [Sidenote: The laws of God in his natural kingdom, are those which are above set down in chaps. II. III.] 8. Because the _word of God_, ruling by nature only, is supposed to be nothing else but right reason, and the laws of kings can be known by their _word_ only; it is manifest that the laws of God, ruling by nature alone, are only the _natural laws_; namely, those which we have set down in chaps. II. and III. and deduced from the dictates of reason, _humility_, _equity_, _justice_, _mercy_; and other _moral virtues_ befriending _peace_, which pertain to the discharge of the duties of men one toward the other; and those which right reason shall dictate besides, concerning the honour and worship of the Divine Majesty. We need not repeat what those _natural laws_ or _moral virtues_ are; but we must see what honours and what divine worship, that is to say, what _sacred laws_ the same _natural reason_ doth dictate. [Sidenote: What honour and worship are.] 9. Honour to speak properly, is nothing else but an opinion of another’s _power_ joined with _goodness_; and to _honour_ a man, is the same with highly esteeming him: and so honour is not in the party _honoured_, but in the _honourer_. Now three passions do necessarily follow _honour_ thus placed in opinion; _love_, which refers to _goodness_; _hope_ and _fear_, which regard _power_. And from these arise all outward actions, wherewith the powerful are appeased and become propitious; and which are the effects, and therefore also the natural signs of honour itself. But the word _honour_ is transferred also to those outward effects of _honour_; in which sense, we are said to _honour_ him, of whose power we testify ourselves, either in word or deed, to have a very great respect; insomuch as _honour_ is the same with _worship_. Now _worship_ is an outward act, the sign of inward honour; and whom we endeavour by our homage to appease if they be angry, or howsoever to make them favourable to us, we are said to _worship_. [Sidenote: Worship consists either in attributes, or in actions.] 10. All signs of the mind are either _words_ or _deeds_; and therefore all _worship_ consists either in _words_ or _deeds_. Now both the one and the other are referred to three kinds; whereof the first is _praise_, or _public declaration of goodness_; the second a _public declaration of present power_, which is to _magnify_, μεγάλυνειν; the third is a _public declaration of happiness_, or of _power secure also for the future_, which is called μακαρισμὸς. I say that all kinds of honour may be discerned, not in _words_ only, but in _deeds_ too. But we then praise and celebrate in _words_, when we do it by way of proposition, or _dogmatically_, that is to say, by _attributes_ or _titles_; which may be termed praising and celebrating _categorically_ and _plainly_; as when we declare him whom we honour to be _liberal_, _strong_, _wise_. And then in _deeds_, when it is done by _consequence_ or by _hypothesis_ or supposition; as by _thanksgiving_, which supposeth _goodness_; or by _obedience_, which supposeth _power_; or by _congratulation_, which supposeth _happiness_. [Sidenote: And there is one sort natural, and another arbitrary.] 11. Now whether we desire to praise a man in _words_ or _deeds_, we shall find some things which signify honour with all men: such as among _attributes_, are the general words of _virtues_ and _powers_, which cannot be taken in ill sense; as _good_, _fair_, _strong_, _just_, and the like: and among _actions_, _obedience_, _thanksgiving_, _prayers_, and others of that kind, by which an acknowledgment of virtue and power is ever understood. Others, which signify honour but with some, and scorn with others, or else neither; such as in _attributes_, are those words, which, according to the diversity of opinions, are diversely referred to virtues or vices, to honest or dishonest things. As that a man slew his enemy, that he fled, that he is a philosopher, or an orator, and the like; which with some are had in honour, with others in contempt. In _deeds_, such as depend on the custom of the place, or prescriptions of civil laws; as in saluting to be bareheaded, to put off the shoes, to bend the body, to petition for anything standing, prostrate, kneeling, forms of ceremony, and the like. Now that _worship_ which is always and by all men accounted honourable, may be called _natural_; the other, which follows places and customs, _arbitrary_. [Sidenote: One commanded, another voluntary.] 12. Furthermore, _worship_ may be enjoined, to wit, by the _command_ of him that is worshipped, and it may be _voluntary_, namely, such as seems good to the worshipper. If it be _enjoined_, the actions expressing it do not signify honour, as they signify actions, but as they are _enjoined_: for they signify _obedience_ immediately, obedience _power_; insomuch as _worship enjoined_ consists in obedience. _Voluntary_ is honourable only in the nature of the actions; which if they do signify honour to the beholders, it is _worship_, if not, it is _reproach_. Again, _worship_ may be either _public_ or _private_. But _public_, respecting each single worshipper, may not be _voluntary_; respecting the city, it may. For seeing that which is done voluntarily, depends on the will of the doer, there would not one worship be given, but as many worships as worshippers; except the will of all men were united by the command of one. But _private_ worship may be _voluntary_, if it be done secretly; for what is done openly, is restrained either by laws or through modesty; which is contrary to the nature of a _voluntary_ action. [Sidenote: What the end or aim of worship is.] 13. Now that we may know what the _scope_ and _end_ of _worshipping_ others is, we must consider the cause why men delight in worship. And we must grant what we have showed elsewhere; that _joy_ consists in this, that a man contemplates virtue, strength, science, beauty, friends, or any _power_ whatsoever, as being, or as though it were his own; and it is nothing else but a _glory_ or triumph of the mind, conceiving itself honoured, that is to say, loved and feared, that is to say, having the services and assistances of men in readiness. Now because men believe him to be powerful, whom they see honoured, that is to say, esteemed powerful by others; it falls out that honour is increased by worship; and by the opinion of power true power is acquired. His _end_ therefore, who either commands or suffers himself to be worshipped, is, that by this means he may acquire as many as he can, either through love or fear, to be obedient unto him. [Sidenote: What the natural laws are concerning God’s attributes.] 14. But that we may understand what manner of _worship_ of God _natural reason_ doth assign us, let us begin from his _attributes_. Where first, it is manifest that _existence_ is to be allowed him; for there can be no will to honour him, who, we think, hath no being. Next, those philosophers who said, that God was the world or the world’s soul, that is to say, a part of it, spake unworthily of God; for they attribute nothing to him, but wholly deny his being. For by the word _God_ we understand the _world’s cause_. But in saying that the _world is God_, they say _that it hath no cause_, that is as much as _there is no God_. In like manner, they who maintain the world not to be created, but eternal; because there can be no cause of an eternal thing, in denying _the world to have a cause_, they deny also that _there is a God_. They also have a wretched apprehension of God, who imputing idleness to him, do take from him the government of the world and of mankind. For say, they should acknowledge him omnipotent; yet if he mind not these inferior things, that same thread-bare sentence will take place with them: _quod supra nos, nihil ad nos_; what is above us, doth not concern us. And seeing there is nothing for which they should either love or fear him, truly he will be to them as though he were not at all. Moreover, in _attributes_ which signify _greatness_ or _power_, those which signify some finite or limited thing, are not signs at all of an honouring mind. For we honour not God worthily, if we ascribe less _power_ or _greatness_ to him than possibly we can. But every finite thing is less than we can; for most easily we may always assign and attribute more to a finite thing. No _shape_ therefore must be assigned to God, for all _shape_ is _finite_; nor must he be said to be conceived or comprehended by imagination, or any other faculty of our soul; for whatsoever we conceive is _finite_. And although this word _infinite_ signify a conception of the mind, yet it follows not that we have any conception of an _infinite thing_. For when we say that a thing is _infinite_, we signify nothing really, but the impotency in our own mind; as if we should say, we know not whether or where it is limited. Neither speak they honourably enough of God, who say we have an _idea_ of him in our mind: for an idea is our conception; but conception we have none, except of a _finite_ thing. Nor they, who say that he hath _parts_, or that he is some certain _entire_ thing; which are also attributes of _finite_ things. Nor that he is in any place; for nothing can be said to be in a _place_, but what hath _bounds_ and _limits_ of its greatness on all sides. Nor that he is _moved_ or _is at rest_; for either of them suppose a _being in some place_. Nor that there are many Gods; because not many infinites. Furthermore, concerning _attributes of happiness_, those are unworthy of God which signify _sorrow_; (unless they be taken not for any passion, but, by a metonomy, for the effect); such as _repentance_, _anger_, _pity_. Or _want_; as _appetite_, _hope_, _concupiscence_, and that _love_ which is also called _lust_; for they are signs of _poverty_; since it cannot be understood that a man should _desire_, _hope_, and _wish_ for aught, but what he wants and stands in need of. Or any _passive faculty_; for _suffering_ belongs to a limited power, and which depends upon another. When we therefore attribute a _will_ to God, it is not to be conceived like unto ours, which is called _a rational desire_; (for if God _desires_, he _wants_, which for any man to say, is a contumely); but we must suppose some resemblance which we cannot conceive. In like manner when we attribute _sight_ and other _acts of the sense_ to him, or _knowledge_, or _understanding_, which in us are nothing else but a tumult of the mind, raised from outward objects pressing the organs; we must not think that any such thing befalls the Deity; for it is a sign of power _depending_ upon some other, which is not the most blessed thing. He therefore who would not ascribe any other titles to God than what reason commands, must use such as are either _negative_, as _infinite_, _eternal_, _incomprehensible_, &c.; or _superlative_, as _most good_, _most great_, _most powerful_, &c.; or _indefinite_, as _good_, _just_, _strong_, _creator_, _king_, and the like; in such sense, as not desiring to declare what he is; (which were to circumscribe him within the narrow limits of our phantasy); but to confess his own admiration and obedience, which is the property of humility and of a mind yielding all the honour it possibly can do. For reason dictates one name alone which doth signify the _nature_ of God, that is, _existent_, or simply, _that he is_; and one in _order_ to, and in _relation_ to us, namely _God_, under which is contained both _King_, and _Lord_, and _Father_. [Sidenote: What those actions are, whereby naturally we do give worship.] 15. Concerning the _outward actions_ wherewith God is to be worshipped, as also concerning his _titles_; it is a most general command of reason, that they be signs of a mind yielding honour. Under which are contained in the first place, _prayers_. “Qui fingit sacros auro vel marmore vultus, Non facit ille deos; qui rogat, ille facit.” For _prayers_ are the signs of hope; and hope is an acknowledgment of the divine _power_ or _goodness_. In the second place, _thanksgiving_; which is a sign of the same affection, but that _prayers go before_ the benefit, and _thanks follow it_. In the third, _gifts_, that is to say, _oblations_ and _sacrifices_; for these are _thanksgivings_. In the fourth, _not to swear by any other_. For a man’s oath is an imprecation of his wrath against him if he deceive, who both knows whether he do or not, and can punish him if he do, though he be never so powerful; which only belongs to God. For if there were any man from whom his subjects’ _malice_ could not lie hid, and whom no human power could resist, plighted faith would suffice without swearing; which broken, might be punished by that man. And for this very reason there would be no need of an oath. In the fifth place, _to speak warily of God_; for that is a sign of _fear_, and _fear_ is an acknowledgment of _power_. It follows from this precept, _that we may not take the name of God in vain, or use it rashly_; for either are inconsiderate. _That we must not swear, where there is no need_; for that is in vain. But need there is none, unless it be between cities, to avoid or take away contention by force, which necessarily must arise where there is no faith kept in promises: or in a city, for the better certainty of judicature. Also, _that we must not dispute of the divine nature_; for it is supposed _that all things in the natural kingdom of God are inquired into by reason only_, that is to say, out of the principles of natural science. But we are so far off by these to attain to the knowledge of the nature of God, that we cannot so much as reach to the full understanding of all the qualities of our own bodies, or of any other creatures. Wherefore there comes nothing from these disputes, but a rash imposition of names to the divine Majesty according to the small measure of our conceptions. It follows also, (which belongs to the right of God’s kingdom), that their speech is inconsiderate and rash, who say, _that this or that doth not stand with divine justice_. For even men count it an affront that their children should dispute their right, or measure their justice otherwise than by the rule of their commands. In the sixth, _whatsoever is offered up in prayers, thanksgivings, and sacrifices, must in its kind be the best and most betokening honour_; namely, _prayers_ must not be rash, or light, or vulgar, but beautiful, and well composed. For though it were absurd in the heathen to worship God in an image, yet was it not against reason to use poetry and music in their churches. Also _oblations must be clean, and presents sumptuous_; and such as are significative either of submission or gratitude, or commemorative of benefits received. For all these proceed from a desire of honouring. In the seventh, _that God must be worshipped not privately only, but openly and publicly in the sight of all men_; because that worship is so much more acceptable, by how much it begets honour and esteem in others; as hath been declared before in art. 13. Unless others therefore see it, that which is most pleasing in our worship vanisheth. In the last place, _that we use our best endeavour to keep the laws of nature_. For the undervaluing of our master’s command, exceeds all other affronts whatsoever; as on the other side, obedience is more acceptable than all other sacrifices. And these are principally the natural laws concerning the worship of God; those, I mean, which reason dictates to every man. But to whole cities, every one whereof is one person, the same natural reason further commands an _uniformity of public worship_. For the actions done by particular persons, according to their private reasons, are not the city’s actions; and therefore not the city’s worship. But what is done by the city, is understood to be done by the command of him or them who have the sovereignty; wherefore also together with the consent of all the subjects, that is to say, _uniformly_. [Sidenote: In the natural kingdom of God, the city may appoint what worship it pleaseth.] 16. The _natural laws_ set down in the foregoing article concerning the divine worship, only command the giving of natural signs of honour. But we must consider that there are two kinds of signs; the one _natural_; the other done upon _agreement_, or by express or tacit composition. Now because in every language the use of _words_ and _names_ come by appointment, it may also by appointment be altered; for that which depends on and derives its force from the will of men, can by the will of the same men agreeing be changed again or abolished. Such _names_ therefore as are _attributed_ to God by the appointment of men, can by the same appointment be taken away. Now what can be done by the appointment of men, that the city may do. The city therefore by right, that is to say, they who have the power of the whole city, shall judge what _names_ or _appellations_ are more, what less _honourable_ for God; that is to say, what doctrines are to be held and professed concerning the nature of God and his operations. Now actions do signify not by men’s appointment, but naturally; even as the effects are signs of their causes. Whereof some are always signs of scorn to them before whom they are committed; as those whereby the body’s uncleanness is discovered, and whatsoever men are ashamed to do before those whom they respect. Others are always signs of honour, as to draw near and discourse decently and humbly, to give way or to yield in any matter of private benefit. In these actions the city can alter nothing. But there are infinite others, which, as much as belongs to honour or reproach, are indifferent. Now these, by the institution of the city, may both be made signs of honour, and being made so, do in very deed become so. From whence we may understand, that we must obey the city in whatsoever it shall command to be used for a sign of honouring God, that is to say, for _worship_; provided it can be instituted for a sign of honour; because that is a sign of honour, which by the city’s command is used for such. [Sidenote: God ruling by nature only, the city, that is to say, that man or court which under God hath the sovereignty, is the interpreter of all the laws.] 17. We have already declared which were the laws of God, as well sacred as secular, in his government by the way of nature only. Now because there is no man but may be deceived in reasoning, and that it so falls out that men are of different opinions concerning the most actions; it may be demanded further, whom God would have to be the _interpreter of right reason_, that is to say, of his laws. And as for the _secular_ laws, (I mean those which concern justice and the carriage of men towards men), by what hath been said before of the constitution of a city, we have demonstratively showed it agreeable to reason, that all _judicature_ belongs to the city; and that _judicature_ is nothing else but an _interpretation of the laws_; and by consequence, that every where cities, that is to say, those who have the sovereign power, are the _interpreters of the laws_. As for the _sacred_ laws, we must consider what hath been before demonstrated in chap. V. art. 13, that every subject hath transferred as much right as he could on him or them who had the supreme authority. But he could have transferred his right of judging the manner how God is to be honoured; and therefore also he hath done it. That he could, it appears hence; that the manner of honouring God before the constitution of a city, was to be fetched from every man’s _private reason_. But every man can subject his _private_ reason to the reason of _the whole city_. Moreover, if each man should follow his own reason in the _worshipping_ of God, in so great a diversity of worshippers one would be apt to judge another’s worship uncomely, or impious; neither would the one seem to the other to honour God. Even that therefore which were most consonant to reason, would not be a _worship_; because that the nature of _worship_ consists in this, that it be the _sign of inward honour_. But there is no sign, but whereby somewhat becomes known to others; and therefore is there no sign of honour, but what seems so to others. Again, that is a true sign, which by the consent of men becomes a sign; therefore also that is honourable, which by the consent of men, that is to say, by the command of the city, becomes a sign of honour. It is not therefore against the will of God, declared by the way of reason only, to give him such signs of honour as the city shall command. Wherefore subjects can transfer their right of judging the manner of God’s worship, on him or them who have the sovereign power. Nay, they must do it; for else all manner of absurd opinions concerning the nature of God, and all ridiculous ceremonies which have been used by any nations, will be seen at once in the same city. Whence it will fall out, that every man will believe that all the rest do offer God an affront; so that it cannot be truly said of any, that he worships God; for no man worships God, that is to say, honours him outwardly, but he who doth those things, whereby he appears to others for to honour him. It may therefore be concluded, that the _interpretation_ of all laws, as well _sacred_ as _secular_, (God ruling by the way of _nature_ only), depends on the authority of the city, that is to say, that man or counsel to whom the sovereign power is committed; and that whatsoever God commands, he commands by his voice. And on the other side, that whatsoever is commanded by them, both concerning the manner of honouring God, and concerning secular affairs, is commanded by God himself. [Sidenote: Certain doubts removed.] 18. Against this, some man may demand, first, whether it doth not follow that the city must be obeyed, if it command us directly to affront God, or forbid us to worship him? I say, it does not follow, neither must we obey. For to affront, or not to worship at all, cannot by any man be understood for a manner of worshipping. Neither also had any one, before the constitution of a city, of those who acknowledge God to rule, a right to deny him the honour which was then due unto him; nor could he therefore transfer a right on the city of commanding any such things. Next, if it be demanded whether the city must be obeyed, if it command somewhat to be said or done, which is not a disgrace to God directly, but from whence by reasoning disgraceful consequences may be derived; as for example, if it were commanded to worship God in an image, before those who account that honourable: truly it is to be done.[19] For worship is instituted in sign of honour; but to worship him thus, is a sign of honour, and increaseth God’s honour among those who do so account of it. Or if it be commanded to call God by a name, which we know not what it signifies, or how it can agree with this word _God_; that also must be done. For what we do for honour’s sake, (and we know no better), if it be taken for a sign of honour, it is a sign of honour; and therefore if we refuse to do it, we refuse the enlarging of God’s honour. The same judgment must be had of all the _attributes_ and _actions_ about the merely rational worship of God, which may be controverted and disputed. For though this kind of commands may be sometimes contrary to right reason, and therefore sins in them who command them; yet are they not against right reason, nor sins in subjects; whose right reason, in points of controversy, is that which submits itself to the reason of the city. Lastly, if that man or counsel who hath the supreme power, command himself to be worshipped with the same _attributes_ and _actions_, wherewith God is to be worshipped; the question is, whether we must obey? There are many things, which may be commonly attributed both to God and men; for even men may be _praised_ and _magnified_. And there are many actions, whereby God and men may be worshipped. But the significations of the _attributes_ and _actions_ are only to be regarded. Those _attributes_ therefore, whereby we signify ourselves to be of an opinion, that there is any man endued with a sovereignty independent from God, or that he is immortal, or of infinite power, and the like; though commanded by princes, yet must they be abstained from. As also from those _actions_ signifying the same; as prayer to the absent; to ask those things which God alone can give, as rain and fair weather; to offer him what God can only accept, as oblations, holocausts; or to give a worship, than which a greater cannot be given, as sacrifice. For these things seem to tend to this end, that God may not be thought to rule; contrary to what was supposed from the beginning. But genuflection, prostration, or any other act of the body whatsoever, may be lawfully used even in civil worship; for they may signify an acknowledgment of the civil power only. For divine worship is distinguished from civil, not by the motion, placing, habit, or gesture of the body, but by the declaration of our opinion of him whom we do worship. As if we cast down ourselves before any man, with intention of declaring by that sign that we esteem him as God, it is divine worship; if we do the same thing as a sign of our acknowledgment of the civil power, it is civil worship. Neither is the _divine worship_ distinguished from _civil_, by any action usually understood by the words λατρεία and δουλεία; whereof the former marking out the _duty_ of servants, the latter their _destiny_, they are words of the same action in degree. Footnote 19: _Truly it is to be done._] We said in art. 14 of this chapter, that they who attributed limits to God, transgressed the natural law concerning God’s worship. Now they who worship him in an image, assign him limits. Wherefore they do that which they ought not to do. And this place seems to contradict the former. We must therefore know first, that they who are constrained by authority, do not set God any bounds; but they who command them. For they who worship unwillingly, do worship in very deed: but they either stand or fall there, where they are commanded to stand or fall by a lawful sovereign. Secondly, I say it must be done, not at all times and everywhere, but on supposition that there is no other rule of worshipping God, beside the dictates of human reason; for then the will of the city stands for reason. But in the kingdom of God by way of covenant, whether old or new, where idolatry is expressly forbid, though the city commands us to worship thus, yet must we not do it. Which, if he shall consider, who conceived some repugnancy between this and art. 14, will surely cease to think so any longer. [Sidenote: What is sin in the natural kingdom of God, and what treason against the divine majesty.] 19. From what hath been said may be gathered, that God reigning by the way of natural reason only, subjects do sin, first if they break the moral laws; which are unfolded in chapters II. and III. Secondly, if they break the laws or commands of the city, in those things which pertain to justice. Thirdly, if they worship not God κατὰ τὰ νόμικα Fourthly, if they confess not before men, both in words and deeds, that there is one God most good, most great, most blessed, the Supreme King of the world and of all worldly kings; that is to say, if they do not worship God. This fourth sin in the natural kingdom of God, by what hath been said in the foregoing chapter in art. 2, is the _sin of treason against the Divine Majesty_. For it is a denying of the Divine Power, or _atheism_. For sins proceed here, just as if we should suppose some man to be the sovereign king, who being himself absent, should rule by his viceroy. Against whom sure they would transgress, who should not obey his viceroy in all things; except he usurped the kingdom to himself, or would give it to some other. But they who should so absolutely obey him, as not to admit of this exception, might be said to be guilty of treason. ------- CHAPTER XVI. OF THE KINGDOM OF GOD UNDER THE OLD COVENANT. 1. Superstition possessing foreign nations, God instituted true religion by the means of Abraham. 2. By the covenant between God and Adam, all dispute is forbidden concerning the commands of superiors. 3. The manner of the covenant between God and Abraham. 4. In that covenant is contained an acknowledgment of God, not simply, but of him who appeared unto Abraham. 5. The laws unto which Abraham was tied, were no other beside those of nature, and the law of circumcision. 6. Abraham was the interpreter of the word of God, and of all laws among those that belonged to him. 7. Abraham’s subjects could not sin by obeying him. 8. God’s covenant with the Hebrews on Mount Sinai. 9. From thence God’s government took the name of a kingdom. 10. What laws were by God given to the Jews. 11. What the word of God is, and how to be known. 12. What was held the written word of God among the Jews. 13. The power of interpreting the word of God, and the supreme civil power, were united in Moses while he lived. 14. They were also united in the high-priest, during the life of Joshua. 15. They were united too in the high-priest until king Saul’s time. 16. They were also united in the kings until the captivity. 17. They were so in the high-priests after the captivity. 18. Denial of the Divine Providence, and idolatry, were the only treasons against the Divine Majesty among the Jews; in all things else they ought to obey their princes. [Sidenote: Superstition possessing foreign nations, God instituted the true religion by the means of Abraham.] 1. Mankind, from conscience of its own weakness and admiration of natural events, hath this; that most men believe God to be the invisible maker of all invisible things; whom they also fear, conceiving that they have not a sufficient protection in themselves. But the imperfect use they had of their reason, the violence of their passions did so cloud them, that they could not rightly worship him. Now the fear of invisible things, when it is severed from right reason, is superstition. It was therefore almost impossible for men, without the special assistance of God, to avoid both rocks of _atheism_ and _superstition_. For this proceeds from fear without right reason; that, from an opinion of right reason without fear. _Idolatry_ therefore did easily fasten upon the greatest part of men; and almost all nations did worship God in images and resemblances of finite things; and they worshipped spirits or vain visions, perhaps out of fear calling them devils. But it pleased the Divine Majesty, as we read it written in the sacred history, out of all mankind to call forth Abraham, by whose means he might bring men to the true worship of him; and to reveal himself supernaturally to him, and to make that most famous covenant with him and his seed, which is called the _old covenant_ or _testament_. He therefore is the head of true religion; he was the first that _after the deluge taught, that there was one God, the Creator of the universe_. And from him the _kingdom of God by way of covenants_, takes its beginning. _Joseph. Antiq. Jews_, lib. I.. cap. 7. [Sidenote: By the covenant between God and Adam, all dispute is forbidden concerning the commands of superiors.] 2. In the beginning of the world God reigned indeed, not only naturally, but also _by way of covenant_, over Adam and Eve; so as it seems he would have no obedience yielded to him, beside that which natural reason should dictate, but _by the way of covenant_, that is to say, by the consent of men themselves. Now because this _covenant_ was presently made void, nor ever after renewed, the original of God’s _kingdom_ (which we treat of in this place) is not to be taken thence. Yet this is to be noted by the way; that by that precept of not eating of the tree of _the knowledge of good and evil_, (whether the judicature of good and evil, or the eating of the fruit of some tree were forbidden), God did require a most simple obedience to his commands, without dispute whether that were _good_ or _evil_ which was commanded. For the fruit of the tree, if the command be wanting, hath nothing in its own nature, whereby the eating of it could be morally _evil_, that is to say, _a sin_. [Sidenote: The manner of the covenant between God and Abraham.] 3. Now the covenant between God and Abraham was made in this manner, (Gen. xvii. 7, 8): _I will establish my covenant between me and thee, and thy seed after thee in their generations, for an everlasting covenant, to be a God unto thee and to thy seed after thee. And I will give unto thee and to thy seed after thee, the land wherein thou art a stranger, all the land of Canaan, for an everlasting possession; and I will be their God._ Now it was necessary to institute some sign, whereby Abraham and his seed should retain the memory of this covenant; wherefore _circumcision_ was added to the covenant, but yet as a sign only, (verse 10, 11): _This is my covenant which ye shall keep between me and thee, and thy seed after thee; every man-child among you shall be circumcised, and ye shall circumcise the flesh of your foreskin; and it shall be a token of the covenant between me and you._ It is therefore covenanted, that Abraham shall acknowledge God to be his God and the God of his seed, that is to say, that he shall submit himself to be governed by him; and that God shall give unto Abraham the inheritance of that land wherein he then dwelt but as a pilgrim; and that Abraham, for a memorial sign of this covenant, should take care to see himself and his male seed _circumcised_. [Sidenote: In that covenant is contained an acknowledgment of God, not simply, but of him who appeared unto Abraham.] 4. But seeing that Abraham, even before the covenant, acknowledged God to be the Creator and King of the world; (for he never doubted either of the _being_ or the _providence_ of God); how comes it not to be superfluous, that God would purchase to himself with a price and by _contract_ an obedience which was due to him by nature; namely, by promising Abraham the land of Canaan, upon condition that he would receive him for his God; when by the right of nature he was already so? By those words therefore, _to be a God unto thee and to thy seed after thee_, we understand not that Abraham satisfied this _covenant_ by a bare acknowledgment of the power and dominion which God had naturally over men, that is to say, by acknowledging God indefinitely, which belongs to _natural reason_; but he must definitely acknowledge him, who said unto him, (Gen. xii. 1, 2): _Get thee out of thy country; &c._ (Gen. xiii. 14): _Lift up thine eyes, &c._: who appeared unto him, (Gen. xviii. 1, 2), in the shape of three celestial men; and (Gen. xv. 1), in a _vision_; and (verse 13), in a _dream_, which is _matter of faith_. In what shape God appeared unto Abraham, by what kind of sound he spake to him, is not expressed. Yet it is plain that Abraham believed that voice to be the voice of God and a true revelation, and would have all his to worship him, who had so spoken unto him, for God the Creator of the world; and that his faith was grounded on this, not that he believed _God to have a being_ or _that he was true_ in his promises, that which all men believe, but that he doubted not him to be God, whose voice and promises he had heard, and that the _God_ of Abraham signified not simply _God_, but _that God which appeared unto him_; even as the worship, which Abraham owed unto God in that notion, was not the worship of _reason_, but of _religion_ and _faith_, and that which not reason, but God had _supernaturally_ revealed. [Sidenote: The laws to which Abraham was tied were no other, but those of nature and that of circumcision.] 5. But we read of no laws given by God to Abraham, or by Abraham to his family, either then or after, secular or sacred; excepting the commandment of _circumcision_, which is contained in the _covenant_ itself. Whence it is manifest, that there were no other laws or worship, which Abraham was obliged to, but the laws of nature, rational worship, and circumcision. [Sidenote: Abraham among his own was the interpreter of the word of God and of all laws.] 6. Now Abraham was the _interpreter_ of all _laws_, as well sacred as secular, among those that belonged to him; not merely naturally, as using the laws of nature only, but even by the form of the covenant itself; in which obedience is promised by Abraham, not for himself only, but for his seed also; which had been in vain, except his children had been tied to obey his commands. And how can that be understood, which God says (Gen. xviii. 18, 19): _All the nations of the earth shall be blessed in him; for I know him, that he will command his children and his household after him, and they shall keep the way of the Lord to do justice and judgment_: unless his children and his household were supposed to be obliged to yield obedience unto his commands? [Sidenote: Abraham’s subjects could not sin in obeying him.] 7. Hence it follows, that Abraham’s subjects could not sin in obeying him, provided that Abraham commanded them not to deny God’s _existence_ or _providence_, or to do somewhat expressly contrary to the honour of God. In all other things, _the word of God_ was to be fetched from his lips only, as being the interpreter of all the _laws_ and _words_ of God. For Abraham alone could teach them who was the God of Abraham, and in what manner he was to be worshipped. And they who after Abraham’s death were subject to the sovereignty of Isaac or Jacob, did by the same reason obey them in all things without sin, as long as they acknowledged and professed _the God_ of Abraham to be their God. For they had submitted themselves _to God_ simply, before they did it to Abraham, and to Abraham before they did it to the God of Abraham: again, to the God of Abraham, before they did it to Isaac. In Abraham’s subjects therefore, to deny God was the only _treason against the divine Majesty_; but in their posterity, it was also treason _to deny the God of Abraham_, that is to say, to worship God otherwise than was instituted by Abraham, to wit, in images made with hands,[20] as other nations did; which for that reason were called _idolaters_. And hitherto, subjects might easily enough discern what was to be observed, what avoided in the commands of their princes. Footnote 20: _In images made with hands._ In chap. XV. art. 14, there we have showed such a kind of worship to be irrational. But if it be done by the command of a city, to whom the written word of God is not known nor received, we have then showed this worship (in article 18) to be rational. But where God reigns by way of covenant, in which it is expressly warned not to worship thus, as in the covenant made with Abraham; there, whether it be with or without the command of the city, it is ill done. [Sidenote: God’s covenant with the Hebrews at Mount Sinai.] 8. To go on now, following the guidance of the holy Scripture; the same _covenant_ was renewed (Gen. xxvi. 3, 4) with Isaac; and (Gen. xxviii. 13, 14) with Jacob; where God styles himself not simply God, whom nature doth dictate him to be, but distinctly the _God of Abraham and Isaac_. Afterward being about to renew the same _covenant_ by Moses with the whole people of Israel, (Exod. iii. 6): _I am_, saith he, _the God of thy Father, the God of Abraham, the God of Isaac, and the God of Jacob._ Afterward, when that people, not only the freest, but also the greatest enemy to human subjection, by reason of the fresh memory of their Egyptian bondage, abode in the wilderness near mount Sinai, that _ancient covenant_ was propounded to them all to be renewed in this manner (Exod. xix. 5, 6): _Therefore if ye will obey my voice indeed, and keep my covenant_, (to wit, that covenant which was made with Abraham, Isaac and Jacob); _then shall ye be a peculiar treasure unto me, above all people; for all the earth is mine, and ye shall be to me a kingdom of priests, and an holy nation. And all the people answered together, and said_, (verse 8) _All that the Lord hath spoken, will we do._ [Sidenote: From thence God’s government was called a kingdom.] 9. In this covenant, among other things, we must consider well the appellation of _kingdom_, not used before. For although God, both by _nature_ and by _covenant_ made with Abraham, was their king, yet owed they him an obedience and worship only natural, as being his subjects; and religious, such as Abraham instituted, as being the subjects of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob, their natural princes. For they had received no _word of God_ beside the natural word of right reason; neither had any _covenant_ passed between God and them, otherwise than as their wills were included in the will of Abraham, as their _prince_. But now by the covenant made at Mount Sinai, the consent of each man being had, there becomes an _institutive kingdom of God_ over them. That _kingdom of God_, so renowned in Scriptures and writings of divines, took its beginning from this time; and hither tends that which God said to Samuel, when the Israelites asked a king (1 Sam. viii. 7): _They have not rejected thee, but they have rejected me, that I should not reign over them_; and that which Samuel told the Israelites (1 Sam. xii. 12): _Ye said unto me, nay, but a king shall reign over us, when the Lord your God was your king_; and that which is said, Jer. xxxi. 31: _I will make a new covenant_, &c. _although I was an husband unto them_; and the doctrine also of Judas Galilæus, where mention is made in _Josephus’ Antiq. of the Jews_, (Book xviii. chap. 2), in these words: _But Judas Galilæus was the first author of this fourth way of those who followed the study of wisdom. These agree in all the rest with the Pharisees, excepting that they burn with a most constant desire of liberty; believing God alone to be held for their Lord and prince; and will sooner endure even the most exquisite kinds of torments, together with their kinsfolks and dearest friends, than call any mortal man their Lord._ [Sidenote: What laws were by God given to the Jews.] 10. The right of the kingdom being thus constituted by way of _covenant_, let us see in the next place, what _laws_ God propounded to them. Now those are known to all, to wit, the _decalogue_, and those other, as well _judicial_ as _ceremonial laws_, which we find from the twentieth chapter of Exodus to the end of Deuteronomy and the death of Moses. Now of those _laws_, delivered in general by the hand of Moses, some there are which oblige _naturally_, being made by God, as the _God of nature_, and had their force even before Abraham’s time. Others there are which oblige by virtue of the _covenant_ made with Abraham, being made by God as the God of Abraham, which had their force even before Moses’s time, by reason of the former _covenant_. But there are _others_ which oblige by virtue of that covenant only, which was made last with the people themselves; being made by God, as being _the peculiar_ king of the Israelites. Of the first sort are all the precepts of the decalogue which pertain unto manners; such as, _honour thy parents_, _thou shalt not kill_, _thou shalt not commit adultery_, _thou shalt not steal_, _thou shalt not bear false witness_, _thou shalt not covet_; for they are the laws of nature. Also the precept of not taking _God’s name in vain_; for it is a part of natural worship, as hath been declared in the foregoing chapter (art. 15). In like manner the second commandment, of not worshipping by way of any image made by themselves; for this also is a part of natural religion, as hath been showed in the same article. Of the second sort is the first commandment of the decalogue, _of not having any other Gods_; for in that consists the essence of the _covenant_ made with Abraham, by which God requires nothing else, but that he should be his God, and the God of his seed. Also the precept of _keeping holy the Sabbath_; for the sanctification of the seventh day is instituted in memorial of the six days’ creation, as appears out of these words (Exod. xxxi. 16-17): _It is a perpetual covenant_, (meaning _the Sabbath_), _and a sign between me and the children of Israel for ever; for in six days the Lord made heaven and earth, and on the seventh day he rested, and was refreshed._ Of the third kind are the _politic_, _judicial_, and _ceremonial laws_; which only belonged to the Jews. The _laws_ of the first and second sort written in _tables of stone_, to wit, the _decalogue_, was kept in the _ark_ itself. The rest written in the _volume_ of the whole law, were laid up in _the side of the ark_, (Deut. xxxi. 26). For these, retaining the faith of Abraham, might be changed; those could not. [Sidenote: What the word of God is, and how to be known.] 11. All God’s _laws_ are _God’s word_; but all _God’s word_ is not his _law_. _I am the Lord thy God which brought thee out of the land of Egypt_, is the word of God; it is no law. Neither is all that, which for the better declaring of _God’s word_ is pronounced or written together with it, instantly to be taken for _God’s word_. For, _Thus saith the Lord_, is not the voice of God, but of the preacher or prophet. All that, and only that, is the word of God, which a true prophet hath declared God to have spoken. Now the writings of the prophets, comprehending as well those things which God, as which the prophet himself speaks, are therefore called the word of God, because they contain the word of God. Now because all that, and that alone, is the _word of God_, which is recommended to us for such by a true prophet, it cannot be known what _God’s word_ is, before we know who is the true prophet; nor can we believe _God’s word_, before we believe the prophet. Moses was believed by the people of Israel for two things; his _miracles_ and his _faith_. For how great and most evident miracles soever he had wrought, yet would they not have trusted him, at least he was not to have been trusted, if he had called them out of Egypt to any other worship than the worship of the God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob their fathers. For it had been contrary to the _covenant_ made by themselves with God. In like manner two things there are; to wit, _supernatural prediction of things to come_, which is a mighty miracle; and _faith in the God of Abraham, their deliverer out of Egypt_; which God proposed to all the Jews to be kept for marks of a true prophet. He that wants either of these, is no prophet; nor is it to be received for God’s word, which he obtrudes for such. If faith be wanting, he is rejected in these words, (Deut. xiii. 1, 2, 3, 4, 5): _If there arise among you a prophet or a dreamer of dreams, and giveth thee a sign, or a wonder; and the sign or the wonder come to pass, whereof he spake unto thee, saying, Let us go after other gods, &c. that prophet, or that dreamer of dreams shall be put to death._ If prediction of events be wanting, he is condemned by these, (Deut. xviii. 21, 22): _And if thou say in thine heart, how shall we know the word which the Lord hath not spoken? When a prophet speaketh in the name of the Lord, if the thing follow not nor come to pass, that is the thing which the Lord hath not spoken; but the prophet hath spoken it presumptuously._ Now, that that is the word of God which is published for such by a true prophet; and that he was held to be a true prophet among the Jews, whose faith was true, and to whose predictions the events answered; is without controversy. But what it is, to follow other gods, and whether the events which are affirmed to answer their predictions, do truly answer them or not, may admit many controversies; especially in predictions which obscurely and enigmatically foretel the event; such as the predictions of almost all the prophets are; as who saw not God apparently, like unto Moses, but _in dark speeches, and in figures_. (Numb. xii. 8). But of these we cannot judge, otherwise than _by the way of natural reason_; because that judgment depends on the prophet’s interpretation, and on its proportion with the event. [Sidenote: What was held for the written word of God among the Jews.] 12. The Jews did hold the book of the whole law, which was called _Deuteronomy_, for _the written word of God_; and that only (forasmuch as can be collected out of sacred history) until the captivity. For this book was delivered by Moses himself to the priests, to be kept and laid up in the side of the ark of the covenant, and to be copied out by the kings; and the same a long time after, by the authority of king Josiah (2 Kings xxiii. 2), acknowledged again for _the word of God_. But it is not manifest, when the rest of the books of the Old Testament were first received into canon. But what concerns the prophets, Isaiah and the rest, since they foretold no other things than what were to come to pass, either in or after the captivity, their writings could not at that time be held for prophetic; by reason of the law cited above (Deut. xviii. 21, 22), whereby the Israelites were commanded not to account any man for a true prophet, but him whose prophecies were answered by the events. And hence peradventure it is, that the Jews esteemed the writings of those whom they slew when they prophesied, for prophetic afterward; that is to say, for the word of God. [Sidenote: The power of interpreting the word of God, and the supreme civil power, were united in Moses while he lived.] 13. It being known what laws there were under _the old covenant_, and what _word of God_ received from the beginning; we must furthermore consider, with whom the authority of judging, whether the writings of the prophets arising afterward were to be received for the _word of God_; that is to say, whether the events did answer their predictions or not; and with whom also the authority of interpreting the laws already received, and the written word of God, did reside: which thing is to be traced through all the times and several changes of the commonwealth of Israel. But it is manifest that this power, during the life of Moses, was entirely in himself. For if he had not been the _interpreter of the laws and word_, that office must have belonged either to _every private person_, or to a _congregation_ or _synagogue_ of many, or to the _high-priest_ or to other _prophets_. First, that that office belonged not to private men, or any congregation made of them, appears hence; that they were not admitted, nay, they were prohibited with most heavy threats, _to hear God speak_, otherwise than by the means of Moses. For it is written, (Exod. xix. 24, 25): _Let not the priests and the people break through, to come up unto the Lord, lest he break forth upon them. So Moses went down unto the people, and spake unto them._ It is further manifestly and expressly declared, upon occasion given by the rebellion of Corah, Dathan, and Abiram, and the two hundred and fifty princes of the assembly, that neither private men nor the congregation should pretend that God had spoken by them, and by consequence that they had the right of _interpreting God’s word_. For they contending, that God spake no less by them than by Moses, argue thus, (Numbers xvi. 3): _Ye take too much upon you, seeing all the congregation are holy, every one of them, and the Lord is among them. Wherefore then lift ye up yourselves above the congregation of the Lord?_ But how God determined this controversy, is easily understood by verses 33 and 35 of the same chapter, where _Corah, Dathan, and Abiram went down alive into the pit, &c. And there came out fire from the Lord, and consumed the two hundred and fifty men that offered incense._ Secondly, that Aaron the high-priest had not this authority, is manifest by the like controversy between him (together with his sister Miriam) and Moses. For the question was, whether God spake by Moses only, or by them also; that is to say, whether Moses alone, or whether they also were _interpreters of the word of God_. For thus they said, (Numb. xii. 2): _Hath the Lord indeed spoken only by Moses? Hath he not also spoken by us?_ But God reproved them; and made a distinction between Moses and other prophets, saying, (verse 6, 7, 8): _If there be a prophet among you, I the Lord will make myself known unto him in a vision, and will speak unto him in a dream: my servant Moses is not so, &c. For with him will I speak mouth to mouth, even apparently, and not in dark speeches, and the similitude of the Lord shall he behold. Wherefore then were ye not afraid to speak against my servant Moses?_ Lastly, that _the interpretation of the word of God_ as long as Moses lived, belonged not to any other prophets whatsoever, is collected out of that place which we now cited, concerning his eminency above all others; and out of natural reason, for as much as it belongs to the same prophet, who brings the commands of God, to unfold them too; but there was then no other _word of God_, beside that which was declared by Moses. And out of this also, that there was no other prophet extant at that time, who prophesied to the people, excepting the seventy elders who prophesied by _the spirit_ of Moses. And even that Joshua, who was then Moses’ servant, his successor afterward, believed to be injuriously done, till he knew it was by Moses’ consent; which thing is manifest by text of Scripture, (Numb. xi. 25): _And the Lord came down in a cloud, &c. and took of the spirit that was upon Moses, and gave it unto the seventy elders._ Now after it was told that they prophesied, Joshua said unto Moses, _Forbid them, my lord._ But Moses answered: _Why enviest thou for my sake?_ Seeing therefore Moses alone was the messenger of God’s word, and that the authority of interpreting it pertained neither to _private men_, nor to _the synagogue_, nor to the _high-priest_, nor to other _prophets_; it remains that Moses alone was _the interpreter of Gods word_, who also had the supreme power in civil matters; and that the conventions of Corah with the rest of his complices against Moses and Aaron, and of Aaron with his sister against Moses, were raised, not for the salvation of their souls, but by reason of their ambition and desire of dominion over the people. [Sidenote: They were also united in the high-priest, during the life of Joshua.] 14. In Joshua’s time _the interpretation of the laws_, and _of the word of God_, belonged to Eleazar the high-priest; who was also, under God, their absolute king. Which is collected, first of all, out of the _covenant itself_; in which the commonwealth of Israel is called a _priestly kingdom_, or, as it is recited in 1 Peter ii. 9, a _royal priesthood_. Which could in no wise be said, unless by the institution and _covenant_ of the people, the regal power were understood to belong to the _high-priest_. Neither doth this repugn what hath been said before, where Moses, and not Aaron, had the kingdom under God. Since it is necessary, when one man institutes the form of a future commonwealth, that one should govern the kingdom which he institutes during his life, (whether it be _monarchy_, _aristocracy_, or _democracy_); and have all that power for the present, which he is bestowing on others for the future. Now, that Eleazar the priest had not only _the priesthood_, but also the _sovereignty_, is expressly set down in Joshua’s call to the administration. For thus it is written (Numb, xxvii. 18, 19, 20, 21): _Take thee Joshua the son of Nun, a man in whom is the Spirit, and lay thine hand upon him, and set him before Eleazar the priest, and before all the congregation, and give him a charge in their sight; and thou shalt put some of thine honour upon him, that all the congregation of the children of Israel may be obedient; and he shall stand before Eleazar the priest, who shall ask counsel for him after the judgment of Urim, before the Lord; at his word shall they go out, and at his word shall they come in, and all the children of Israel with him, even all the congregation. Where to ask counsel of God for whatsoever is to be done_, that is, _to interpret God’s word_, and in the name of God to command in all matters, belongs to Eleazar; and _to go out_ and _to come in at his word_, that is to say, to obey, belongs both to Joshua and _to all the people_. It is to be observed also, that that speech, _part of thy glory_, clearly denotes that Joshua had not a power equal with that which Moses had. In the meantime it is manifest, that even in Joshua’s time the supreme power and authority of interpreting the word of God, were both in one person. [Sidenote: They were also united in the high-priest, until king Saul’s time.] 15. After Joshua’s death follow the times of the Judges until king Saul; in which it is manifest that the right of the _kingdom_ instituted by God, remained with the _high-priest_. For the _kingdom_ was by covenant _priestly_, that is to say, God’s government by priests. And such ought it to have been, until that form, with God’s consent, were changed by the people themselves; which was not done before that requiring a king God consented unto them, and said unto Samuel (1 Sam. viii. 7): _Hearken unto the voice of the people in all that they say unto thee; for they have not rejected thee, but they have rejected me, that I should not reign over them._ The supreme civil power was therefore _rightly_ due by God’s own institution to the high-priest; but _actually_ that power was in the prophets, to whom (being raised by God in an extraordinary manner) the Israelites, a people greedy of prophets, submitted themselves to be protected and judged, by reason of the great esteem they had of prophecies. The reason of this thing was, because that though penalties were set and judges appointed in the institution of God’s priestly kingdom; yet, the right of inflicting punishment depended wholly on private judgment; and it belonged to a dissolute multitude and each single person to punish or not to punish, according as their private zeal should stir them up. And therefore Moses by his own command punished no man with death; but when any man was to be put to death, one or many stirred up the multitude against him or them, by divine authority, and saying, _Thus saith the Lord._ Now this was conformable to the nature of God’s peculiar kingdom. For there God reigns indeed, where his laws are obeyed not for fear of men, but for fear of himself. And truly, if men were such as they should be, this were an excellent state of civil government; but as men are, there is a coercive power (in which I comprehend both right and might) necessary to rule them. And therefore also God, from the beginning, prescribed laws by Moses for the future kings (Deut. xvii. 14-20). And Moses foretold this in his last words to the people, saying (Deut. xxxi. 29): _I know that after my death ye will utterly corrupt yourselves, and turn aside from the way that I have commanded you_, &c. When therefore according to this prediction there arose another generation (Judges ii. 10-11) _who knew not the Lord, nor yet the works which he had done for Israel, the children of Israel did evil in the sight of the Lord, and served Balaam_; to wit, they cast off God’s government, that is to say, that of the _priest_, by whom God ruled; and afterward, when they were overcome by their enemies and oppressed with bondage, they looked for God’s will, not at the hands of the _priest_ any more, but of the prophets. These therefore _actually_ judged Israel; but their obedience was _rightly due_ to the high-priest. Although therefore the priestly kingdom, after the death of Moses and Joshua, was without power; yet was it not without right. Now that the _interpretation of God’s word_ did belong to the same high-priest, is manifest by this; that God, after the tabernacle and the ark of the covenant was consecrated, spake no more in Mount Sinai, but in the tabernacle of the covenant, from the propitiatory which was between the _cherubims_, whither it was not lawful for any to approach except the high-priest. If therefore regard be had to the _right_ of the kingdom, the supreme civil power and the authority of interpreting God’s word were joined in the high-priest. If we consider the _fact_, they were united in the prophets who judged Israel. For as _judges_, they had the civil authority; as _prophets_, they interpreted God’s word. And thus every way hitherto these two powers continued inseparable. [Sidenote: They were united in the kings, until the captivity.] 16. Kings being once constituted, it is no doubt but the _civil authority_ belonged to them. For the kingdom of God by the way of priesthood (God consenting to the request of the Israelites) was ended; which Hierom also marks, speaking of the books of Samuel. Samuel, says he, Eli being dead and Saul slain, declares the old law abolished. Furthermore, the oaths of the new priesthood and new sovereignty in Zadok and David, do testify that the right, whereby the _kings_ did rule, was founded in the very concession of the people. The priest could rightly do whatsoever every man could rightly do himself; for the Israelites granted him _a right_ to _judge_ of all things, and to _wage war_ for all men; in which two are contained all right whatsoever can be conceived from man to man. _Our king_ say they (1 Sam. viii. 20) _shall judge us, and go out before us, and fight our battles_. _Judicature_ therefore belonged to the kings. But to _judge_ is nothing else, than by _interpreting_ to apply the _laws_ to the _facts_. To them therefore belonged the interpretation _of laws_ too. And because there was no other written word of God acknowledged beside the _law of_ Moses, until the captivity; the authority _of interpreting God’s word_ did also belong to the kings. Nay, forasmuch as the word of God must be taken for a law, if there had been another written word beside the Mosaical law, seeing the interpretation of laws belonged to the kings, the interpretation of it must also have belonged to them. When the book of Deuteronomy, in which the whole Mosaical _law_ was contained, being a long time lost was found again; _the priests_ indeed asked counsel of God concerning that book, but not by their own authority, but by the commandment of Josiah; and not immediately neither, but by the means of Holda the prophetess. Whence it appears that the authority of admitting books for the word of God, belonged not to the priest. Neither yet follows it, that that authority belonged to the prophetess; because others did judge of the prophets, whether they were to be held for true or not. For to what end did God give signs and tokens to all the people, whereby the true prophets might be discerned from the false; namely, the event of predictions, and conformity with the religion established by Moses; if they might not use those marks? The authority therefore of admitting books for _the word of God_, belonged to the king; and thus that book of the law was approved, and received again by the authority of king Josiah; as appears by the second book of the Kings, chap, xxii. xxiii.: where it is reported that he gathered together all the several degrees of his kingdom, _the elders, priests, prophets, and all the people; and he read in their ears all the words of the covenant_; that is to say, he caused that _covenant_ to be acknowledged for the _Mosaical covenant_; that is to say, _for the word of God_; and to be again received and confirmed by the Israelites. The civil power therefore, and the power of discerning God’s word from the words of men, and of interpreting God’s word even in the days of the kings, was wholly belonging to themselves. Prophets were sent not with authority, but in the form and by the right of proclaimers and preachers, of whom the hearers did judge. And if perhaps these were punished who did not listen to them plainly, teaching easy things; it doth not thence follow, that the kings were obliged to follow all things which they, in God’s name, did declare were to be followed. For though Josiah, the good king of Judah, were slain because he obeyed not the word of the Lord from the mouth of Necho king of Egypt; that is to say, because he rejected good counsel though it seemed to come from an enemy; yet no man I hope will say that Josiah was, by any bond either of divine or human laws, obliged to believe Pharaoh Necho king of Egypt, because he said _that God had spoken to him_. But what some man may object against kings, that for want of learning they are seldom able enough to interpret those books of antiquity, in the which God’s word is contained; and that for this cause, it is not reasonable that this office should depend on their authority; he may object as much against the priests and all mortal men; for they may err. And although priests were better instructed in nature and arts than other men, yet kings are able enough to appoint such interpreters under them; and so, though kings did not themselves interpret the word of God, yet the office of interpreting them might depend on their authority. And they who therefore refuse to yield up this authority to kings, because they cannot practice the office itself, do as much as if they should say, that the authority of teaching _geometry_ must not depend upon kings, except they themselves were geometricians. We read that kings have prayed for the people; that they have blessed the people; that they have consecrated the temple; that they have commanded the priests; that they have removed priests from their office; that they have constituted others. Sacrifices indeed they have not offered; for that was hereditary to Aaron and his sons. But it is manifest, as in Moses’ lifetime, so throughout all ages, from king Saul to the captivity of Babylon, that the priesthood was not a maistry, but a ministry. [Sidenote: The same were united in the priests, after the captivity.] 17. After their return from Babylonian bondage, the _covenant_ being renewed and signed, _the priestly kingdom_ was restored to the same manner it was in from the death of Joshua to the beginning of the kings; excepting that it is not expressly set down, that the returned Jews did give up the right of sovereignty either to Esdras, by whose direction they ordered their state, or to any other beside God himself. That reformation seems rather to be nothing else, than the bare promises and vows of every man, to observe those things which were written in the book of the law. Notwithstanding, (perhaps not by the people’s intention), by virtue of the _covenant_ which they then renewed, (for the covenant was the same with that which was made at Mount Sinai), that same state was a _priestly kingdom_; that is to say, the supreme civil authority and the sacred were united in the priests. Now, howsoever through the ambition of those who strove for the priesthood, and by the interposition of foreign princes, it was so troubled till our Saviour Jesus Christ’s time, that it cannot be understood out of the histories of those times, where that authority resided; yet it is plain, that in those times the power _of interpreting God’s word_ was not severed from the supreme civil power. [Sidenote: Among the Jews, the denial of the Divine providence and idolatry, were the only treasons against the Divine Majesty: in all other things they ought to obey their princes.] 18. Out of all this, we may easily know how the Jews, in all times from Abraham unto Christ, were to behave themselves in the commands of their _princes_. For as in kingdoms merely human, men must obey a subordinate magistrate in all things, excepting when his commands contain in them some treason; so in the kingdom of God, the Jews were bound to obey their _princes_, Abraham, Isaac, Jacob, Moses, the _priest_, the _king_, every one during their time in all things, except when their commands did contain some treason against _the Divine Majesty_. Now treason against the Divine Majesty was, first, _the denial of divine providence_; for this was _to deny God to be a king by nature_: next, _idolatry_, or the worship not of other, (for there is but one God), but of strange Gods; that is to say, a worship though of one God, yet under other _titles_, _attributes_, and _rites_, than what were established by Abraham and Moses; for this was to _deny the God of Abraham_ to be their king _by covenant_ made with Abraham and themselves. In all other things they were to obey. And if a king or priest, having the sovereign authority, had commanded somewhat else to be done which was against the laws, that had been his sin, and not his subject’s; whose duty it is, not to dispute, but to obey the commands of his superiors. ------- CHAPTER XVII. OF THE KINGDOM OF GOD BY THE NEW COVENANT. 1. The prophecies concerning Christ’s dignity. 2. The prophecies concerning his humility and passion. 3. That Jesus was that Christ. 4. That the kingdom of God by the new covenant, was not the kingdom of Christ, as Christ, but as God. 5. That the kingdom by the new covenant is heavenly, and shall begin from the day of judgment. 6. That the government of Christ in this world was not a sovereignty, but counsel, or a government by the way of doctrine and persuasion. 7. What the promises of the new covenant are, on both parts. 8. That no laws are added by Christ, beside the institution of the sacraments. 9. Repent ye, be baptized, keep the commandments, and the like forms of speech, are not laws. 10. It pertains to the civil authority, to define what the sin of injustice is. 11. It pertains to the civil authority, to define what conduces to the peace and defence of the city. 12. It pertains to the civil authority, to judge (when need requires) what definitions and what inferences are true. 13. It belongs to the office of Christ, to teach morally, not by the way of speculation, but as a law; to forgive sins, and to teach all things whereof there is no science, properly so called. 14. A distinction of things temporal from spiritual. 15. In how many several sorts the word of God may be taken. 16. That all which is contained in Holy Scripture, belongs not to the canon of Christian faith. 17. That the word of a lawful interpreter of Holy Scriptures, is the word of God. 18. That the authority of interpreting Scriptures, is the same with that of determining controversies of faith. 19. Divers significations of a Church. 20. What a Church is, to which we attribute rights, actions, and the like personal capacities. 21. A Christian city is the same with a Christian Church. 22. Many cities do not constitute one Church. 23. Who are ecclesiastical persons. 24. That the election of ecclesiastical persons belongs to the Church, their consecration to pastors. 25. That the power of remitting the sins of the penitent, and retaining those of the impenitent, belongs to the pastors; but that of judging concerning repentance belongs to the Church. 26. What excommunication is, and on whom it cannot pass. 27. That the interpretation of Scripture depends on the authority of the city. 28. That a Christian city ought to interpret Scriptures by ecclesiastical pastors. [Sidenote: The prophecies concerning Christ’s dignity.] 1. There are many clear prophecies extant in the Old Testament concerning our Saviour Jesus Christ, who was to restore the kingdom of _God_ by a new covenant; partly foretelling his regal _dignity_, partly his _humility and passion_. Among others concerning his dignity, these. God, blessing Abraham, makes him a promise of his son Isaac; and adds (Gen. xvii. 16): _And kings of people shall be of him._ Jacob blessing his son Judah (Gen. xlix. 10): _The sceptre_, quoth he, _shall not depart from Judah_. God to Moses (Deut. xviii. 18): _A prophet_, saith he, _will I raise them up from among their brethren, like unto thee, and will put my words in his mouth, and he shall speak unto them all that I shall command him; and it shall come to pass, that whosoever will not hearken unto my words, which he shall speak in my name, I will require it of him_. Isaiah (Isai. vii. 14): _The Lord himself shall give thee a sign; Behold a virgin shall conceive and bear a son, and shall call his name Emmanuel._ The same prophet (Isaiah ix. 6): _Unto us a child is born, unto us a son is given, and the government shall be upon his shoulders; and his name shall be called wonderful, counsellor, the mighty God, the everlasting Father, the Prince of Peace._ And again (Isaiah xi. 1-5): _There shall come forth a rod out of the stem of Jesse, and a branch shall grow out of his roots; the spirit of the Lord shall rest upon him_, &c.; _He shall not judge after the sight of his eyes, neither reprove after the hearing of his ears; but with righteousness shall he judge the poor_, &c.; _And he shall smite the earth with the rod of his mouth, and with the breath of his lips shall he slay the wicked_. Furthermore in the same Isaiah (chapters li. to lxii.), there is almost nothing else contained but a description of the coming and the works of Christ. Jeremiah (Jerem. xxxi. 31): _Behold the days come, saith the Lord, that I will make a new covenant with the house of Israel, and with the house of Judah._ And Baruch (Bar. iii. 35-37): _This is our God_, &c. _Afterward did he show himself upon earth, and conversed with men._ Ezekiel (Ezek. xxxiv. 23-25): _I will set up one shepherd over them, and he shall feed them; even my servant David. And I will make with them a covenant of peace_, &c. Daniel (Dan. vii. 13-14): _I saw in the night visions; and behold one like the Son of Man came with the clouds of heaven, and came to the ancient of days; and they brought him near before him; and there was given him dominion, and glory, and a kingdom, that all people, nations, and languages should serve him; his dominion is an everlasting dominion_, &c. Haggai (Haggai ii. 6-7): _Yet once it is a little while, and I will shake the heaven, and the earth, and the sea, and the dry land; and I will shake all nations; and the desire of all nations shall come._ Zachariah, under the type of Joshua the high-priest (Zach. iii. 8): _I will bring forth my servant the branch_, &c. And again (Zach. vi. 12): _Behold the man whose name is the Branch._ And again (Zach. ix. 9): _Rejoice greatly O daughter of Zion, shout O daughter of Jerusalem; behold thy king cometh to thee; he is just, having salvation._ The Jews moved by these and other prophecies, expected Christ their king to be sent from God; who should redeem them, and furthermore bear rule over all nations. Yea, this prophecy had spread over the whole Roman empire; which Vespasian too, though falsely, interpreted in favour of his own enterprises; _that out of Judea should come he that should have dominion_. [Sidenote: The prophecies of Christ’s humility and passion.] 2. Now the prophecies of _Christ’s humility and passion_, amongst others are these: (Isaiah liii. 4): _He hath borne our griefs, and carried our sorrows; yet we did esteem him stricken, smitten of God, and afflicted_; and by and by (verse 7): _He was oppressed, he was afflicted, yet he opened not his mouth; he is brought as a lamb to the slaughter, and as a sheep before her shearer is dumb, so opened he not his mouth_, &c. And again (verse 8): _He was cut out of the land of the living; for the transgression of my people was he stricken_, &c. (Verse 12): _Therefore I will divide him a portion with the great, and he shall divide the spoil with the strong; because he hath poured out his soul unto death, and he was numbered with the transgressors, and he bare the sin of many, and made intercession for the transgressors._ And that of Zachariah (Zach. ix. 9): _He is lowly, riding upon an ass, and upon a colt the foal of an ass._ [Sidenote: That Jesus was the Christ.] 3. In the reign of Tiberius Cæsar, Jesus our Saviour, a Galilean, began to preach; the son, as was supposed, of Joseph; declaring to the people of the Jews, that the kingdom of God expected by them was now come, and that himself was a _king_, that is to say, the Christ; explaining the _law_, choosing _twelve apostles_ and _seventy disciples_, after the number of the _princes_ of the tribes, and seventy elders (according to the pattern of Moses) to the ministry; _teaching the way of salvation_ by himself and them; purging the temple, doing great signs, and fulfilling all those things which the prophets had foretold of Christ to come. That this man, hated of the Pharisees, whose false doctrine and hypocritical sanctity he had reproved; and by their means, of the people accused of unlawful seeking for the kingdom, and crucified; was the true _Christ_ and _king_ promised by God, and sent from his Father to renew the _new covenant_ between them and God; both the evangelists do show, describing his genealogy, nativity, life, doctrine, death, and resurrection; and by comparing the things which he did with those which were foretold of him, all Christians do consent to. [Sidenote: That the kingdom of God by the new covenant, was not the kingdom of Christ, as Christ, but as God.] 4. Now from this, that _Christ_ was sent from God his Father to make a _covenant_ between him and the people, it is manifest, that though Christ were equal to his Father according to his nature, yet was he inferior according to the right of the kingdom. For this office, to speak properly, was not that of a king, but of a viceroy; such as Moses’ government was; for the kingdom was not his, but his _Father’s_. Which Christ himself signified when he was baptized as a subject, and openly professed when he taught his disciples to pray, _Our Father, thy kingdom come_, &c.: and when he said (Matth. xxvi. 29): _I will not drink of the blood of the grape, until that day when I shall drink it new with you in the kingdom of my Father._ And St. Paul (1 Cor. xv. 22-24): _As in Adam all die, so in Christ shall all be made alive; but every man in his own order; Christ the first fruits; afterward they that are Christ’s, who believed in his coming; then cometh the end when he shall have delivered up the kingdom to God even his Father._ The same notwithstanding is also called the _kingdom of Christ_: for both the mother of the sons of Zebedee petitioned Christ, saying (Matth. xx. 21): _Grant that these my two sons may sit, the one on thy right hand, the other on thy left, in thy kingdom_: and the thief on the cross (Luke xxiii. 42): _Lord remember me when thou comest into thy kingdom_: and St. Paul (Ephes. v. 5): _For this know ye, that no whoremonger_, &c. _shall enter into the kingdom of God, and of Christ_: and elsewhere (2 Tim. iv. 1): _I charge thee before God, and the Lord Jesus Christ, who shall judge the quick and dead at his appearing, and his kingdom_, &c.: (verse 18): _And the Lord shall deliver me from every evil work, and will preserve me unto his heavenly kingdom_. Nor is it to be marveled at, that the same kingdom is attributed to them both; since both the Father and the Son are the same God; and the new covenant concerning God’s kingdom, is not propounded in the name of the _Father_; but in the name of the _Father_, of the _Son_, and of the _Holy Ghost_, as of one God. [Sidenote: That the kingdom of God by the new covenant is heavenly, and begins from the day of judgment.] 5. But the kingdom of God, for restitution whereof Christ was sent from God his Father, takes not its beginning before his second coming; to wit, from the day of judgment, when he shall come in majesty accompanied with his angel. For it is promised the apostles, that in the kingdom of God they shall judge the twelve tribes of Israel, (Matth. xix. 28): _Ye which have followed me in the regeneration, when the Son of man shall sit in the throne of his glory, ye also shall sit upon twelve thrones judging the twelve tribes of Israel_: which is not to be done till the day of judgment. Christ therefore is not yet in the throne of his majesty; nor is that time, when Christ was conversant here in the world, called a kingdom, but a _regeneration_; that is to say, a renovation or restitution of the kingdom of God, and a calling of them who were hereafter to be received into his kingdom. And where it is said (Matth. xxv. 31-32): _When the Son of man shall come in his glory, and all the holy angels with him, then shall he sit upon the throne of his glory, and before him shall be gathered all nations; and he shall separate them one from another, as a shepherd divideth his sheep from the goats_: we may manifestly gather that there will be no local separation of God’s subjects from his enemies, but that they shall live mixed together until Christ’s second coming. Which is also confirmed by the comparison of the kingdom of heaven with wheat mingled with darnell, and with a net containing all sorts of fish. But a multitude of men, enemies and subjects, living promiscuously together, cannot properly be termed a kingdom. Besides, the apostles, when they asked our Saviour, whether he would at that time when he ascended into heaven, restore the kingdom unto Israel; did openly testify, that they then, when Christ ascended, thought the kingdom of God not to be yet come. Furthermore, the words of Christ, _My kingdom is not of this world_: and, _I will not drink_, &c. _till the kingdom of God come_: and, _God hath not sent his Son into the world, to judge the world, but that the world through him might be saved_: and, _If any man hear my words, and keep them not, I judge him not; for I came not to judge the world, but to save the world_: and, _Man, who made me a judge or divider between you?_ and the very appellation of _the kingdom of heaven_ testifies as much. The same thing is gathered out of the words of the prophet Jeremiah, speaking of the kingdom of God by the new covenant (Jer. xxxi. 34): _They shall teach no more every man his neighbour; saying, Know the Lord. For they shall all know me, from the least of them to the greatest of them, saith the Lord_: which cannot be understood of a kingdom in this world. The kingdom of God therefore, for the restoring whereof Christ came into the world; of which the prophets did prophecy, and of which praying we say, _Thy kingdom come_; if it is to have subjects locally separated from enemies, if judicature, if majesty, according as hath been foretold; shall begin from that time, wherein God shall separate the sheep from the goats; wherein the apostles shall judge the twelve tribes of Israel; wherein Christ shall come in majesty and glory; wherein lastly, all men shall so know God, that they shall not need to be taught; that is to say, at Christ’s second coming, or the day of judgment. But if the kingdom of God were now already restored, no reason could be rendered why Christ, having completed the work for which he was sent, should come again; or why we should pray, _Thy kingdom come_. [Sidenote: The government of Christ in this world was not a sovereignty, but counsel, or a government by way of doctrine and persuasion.] 6. Now, although the kingdom _of God_ by Christ to be established with a _new covenant_, were heavenly; we must not therefore think, that they, who believing in Christ would make that covenant, were not so to be governed here on the earth too, as that they should persevere in their faith and obedience promised by that covenant. For in vain had the kingdom of heaven been promised, if we were not to have been led into it; but none can be led, but those who are directed in the way. Moses, when he had instituted the _priestly kingdom_, himself though he were no priest, yet ruled and conducted the people all the time of their peregrination, until their entrance into the promised land. In the same manner is it our Saviour’s office, (whom God in this thing would have like unto Moses), as he was sent from his Father, so to govern the future subjects of his heavenly kingdom in this life, that they might attain to and enter into that; although the kingdom were not properly his, but his Father’s. But the government whereby Christ rules the faithful ones in this life, is not properly a _kingdom_ or _dominion_, but a _pastoral charge_, or _the right of teaching_; that is to say, God the Father gave him not a power to judge of _meum_ and _tuum_, as he doth to the kings of the earth; nor a _coercive power_, nor _legislative_; but of showing to the world, and teaching them _the way and knowledge of salvation_; that is to say, of preaching and declaring what they were to do, who would enter into the kingdom of heaven. That Christ had received no power from his Father to judge in questions of _meum_ and _tuum_, that is to say, in all questions of right among those who believed not, those words above cited do sufficiently declare: _Man, who made me a judge or divider between you?_ And it is confirmed by reason. For seeing Christ was sent to make _a covenant_ between God and men; and no man is obliged to perform obedience before the contract be made; if he should have judged of questions of _right_, no man had been tied to obey his sentence. But that the discerning of right was not committed to Christ in this world, neither among the faithful nor among infidels, is apparent in this; that that right without all controversy belongs to princes, as long as it is not by God himself derogated from their authority. But it is not derogated before the day of judgment; as appears by the words of St. Paul, speaking of the day of judgment (1 Cor. xv. 24): _Then cometh the end, when he shall have delivered up the kingdom to God even the Father, when he shall have put down all rule, and all authority, and power._ Secondly, the words of our Saviour reproving James and John, when they had said (Luke ix. 54): _Wilt thou that we call for fire from heaven, that it may consume them?_ (namely the Samaritans, who had denied to receive him going up to Jerusalem): and replying (verse 56), _The Son of man is not come to destroy souls, but to save them_; and those words: _Behold I send you as sheep among wolves_; _Shake off the dust of your feet_; and the like; and those words, _God sent not his Son into the world, to judge the world, but that the world through him might be saved_; and those: _If any man hear my words, and keep them not, I judge him not; for I came not to judge the world_, &c.: do all show, that he had no power given him to condemn or punish any man. We read indeed, that _the Father judgeth no man, but hath committed all judgment to the Son_; but since that both may, and must be understood of the day of future judgment, it doth not at all repugn what hath been said before. Lastly, that he was not sent to make new laws, and that therefore by his office and mission he was no legislator properly so called, nor Moses neither, but a bringer and publisher of his Father’s laws, (for God only, and neither Moses nor Christ, was a king by covenant), is collected hence; that he said, _I came not to destroy_, (to wit, the laws before given from God by Moses, which he presently interprets), _but to fulfil_; and, _He that shall break one of the least of these commandments, and shall teach men so, he shall be called least in the kingdom of heaven_. Christ therefore had not a royal or sovereign power committed to him from his Father in this world, but councillary and doctrinal only; which himself signifies, as well then when he calls his apostles not hunters, but fishers of men; as when he compares the kingdom of God to a grain of mustard-seed, and to a little leaven hid in meal. [Sidenote: What the promises of the new covenant are on both parts.] 7. God promised unto Abraham, first, a numerous seed, the possession of the land of Canaan, and a blessing upon all nations in his seed, on this condition; that he and his seed should serve him: next, unto the seed of Abraham according to the flesh, _a priestly_ kingdom, a government most free, in which they were to be subject to no human power, on this condition; that they should serve the God of Abraham on that fashion which Moses should teach: lastly, both to them and to all nations, a heavenly and _eternal_ kingdom, on condition that they should serve the God of Abraham on that manner which Christ should teach. For by _the new_, that is to say, _the Christian covenant_, it is covenanted on men’s part, to serve the God of Abraham _on that manner which Jesus should teach_: on God’s part, _to pardon their sins, and bring them into his celestial kingdom_. We have already spoken of the quality of the _heavenly_ kingdom, above in art. 5; but it is usually called, sometimes the _kingdom of heaven_, sometimes the _kingdom of glory_, sometimes the _life eternal_. What is required on men’s part, namely, to serve God as Christ should teach, contains two things; _obedience to be performed to God_, (for this is to serve God); and _faith in Jesus_, to wit, that we believe _Jesus to be that Christ who was promised by God_; for that only is the cause why his doctrine is to be followed, rather than any other’s. Now in holy Scriptures, _repentance_ is often put instead of _obedience_; because Christ teacheth everywhere, that with God the will is taken for the deed; but _repentance_ is an infallible sign of an obedient mind. These things being understood, it will most evidently appear out of many places of sacred Scripture, that those are the conditions of _the Christian covenant_ which we have named; to wit, giving remission of sins and eternal life on God’s part; and repenting and believing in Jesus Christ, on men’s part. First, the words, (Mark i. 15): _The kingdom of God is at hand; Repent ye and believe the gospel_, contain the whole covenant. In like manner those (Luke xxiv. 46-47): _Thus it is written, and thus it behoved Christ to suffer, and to rise from the dead the third day; and that repentance and remission of sins should be preached in his name among all nations, beginning at Jerusalem._ And those (Acts iii. 19): _Repent and be converted, that your sins may be blotted out when the times of refreshing shall come_, &c. And sometimes one part is expressly propounded, and the other understood, as here (John iii. 36): _He that believeth in the Son, hath everlasting life; He that believeth not the Son, shall not see life, but the wrath of God abideth on him_: where _faith_ is expressed, _repentance_ not mentioned; and in Christ’s preaching (Matth. iv. 17): _Repent, for the kingdom of heaven is at hand_: where _repentance_ is expressed, _faith_ is understood. But the parts of this _new contract_ are most manifestly and formally set down there, where a certain ruler, bargaining as it were for the kingdom of God, asketh our Saviour (Luke xviii. 18): _Good Master, what shall I do to inherit eternal life?_ But Christ first propounds one part of the price, namely, observation of the commandments, or obedience; which when he answered that he had kept, he adjoins the other, saying (verse 22): _Yet lackest thou one thing; Sell all that thou hast, and distribute to the poor, and thou shalt have treasure in heaven; and come, follow me._ This was matter of _faith_. He therefore not giving sufficient credit to Christ and his heavenly treasures, went away sorrowful. The same covenant is contained in these words (Mark xvi. 16): _He that believeth and is baptized, shall be saved; but he that believeth not, shall be damned_: where _faith_ is expressed, _repentance_ is supposed in those that are baptized. And in these words (John iii. 5): _Except a man be born again of water and the Holy Ghost, he cannot enter into the kingdom of heaven_: where, _to be born of water_, is the same with regeneration, that is to say, conversion to Christ. Now that _baptism_ is required in the two places cited just before, and in divers others, we must understand, that what _circumcision_ was to the _old covenant_, that _baptism_ is to the _new_. Seeing therefore that was not of the essence, but served for a memorial of the _old covenant_, as a ceremony or sign, (and was omitted in the wilderness); in like manner this also is used, not as pertaining to the essence, but in memory and for a sign of the _new covenant_ which we make with God. And provided the will be not wanting, the act through necessity may be omitted; but _repentance_ and _faith_, which are of the essence of the _covenant_, are always required. [Sidenote: There are no laws added by Christ, beside the institution of the sacraments.] 8. In the _kingdom_ of God after this life, there will be _no laws_; partly, because there is no room for laws, where there is none for sins; partly, because laws were given us from God, not to direct us in heaven, but unto heaven. Let us now therefore inquire what laws Christ established not himself; for he would not take upon him any legislative authority, as hath been declared above in art. 6; but propounded to us for his Father’s. We have a place in Scripture, where he contracts all the laws of God published till that time, into two precepts. (Matth. xxii. 37, 38, 39, 40): _Thou shalt love the Lord thy God with all thine heart, with all thy soul, and with all thy mind; this is the greatest and first commandment. And the second is like unto it, Thou shalt love thy neighbour as thyself. On these two commandments hang all the law and the prophets._ The first of these was given before by Moses in the same words (Deut. vi. 5); and the second even before Moses; for it is the natural law, having its beginning with rational nature itself: and both together is the sum of all laws. For all the laws of divine natural worship, are contained in these words, _Thou shalt love God_; and all the laws of divine worship due by the _old covenant_, in these words, _Thou shalt love thy God_, that is to say, _God_, as being the peculiar _King of Abraham_ and his seed; and all the laws natural and civil, in these words, _Thou shalt love thy neighbour as thyself._ For he that loves God and his neighbour, hath a mind to obey all laws, both divine and human. But God requires no more than a mind to obey. We have another place where Christ interprets the laws, namely, the fifth, sixth, and seventh entire chapters of St. Matthew’s Gospel. But all those laws are set down either in the _decalogue_ or in the _moral law_, or are contained in _the faith of Abraham_; as that law of not putting away a wife is contained in _the faith of Abraham_. For that same, _two shall be one flesh_, was not delivered, either by Christ first, or by Moses, but by Abraham, who first preached the creation of the world. The laws therefore which Christ contracts in one place, and explains in another, are no other than those to which all mortal men are obliged, who acknowledge the God of Abraham. Beside these, we read not of any law given by Christ, beside the institution of the sacraments of _baptism_ and the _eucharist_. [Sidenote: That these and the like forms, repent, be baptized, keep the commandments, are not laws.] 9. What may be said then of these kind of precepts, _Repent_, _Be baptized_, _Keep the Commandments_, _Believe the Gospel_, _Come unto me_, _Sell all that thou hast_, _Give to the poor_, _Follow me_; and the like? We must say that they are not _laws_, but a calling of us to the faith: such as is that of Isaiah (lv. 1): _Come; buy wine and milk without money and without price._ Neither if they come not, do they therefore sin against any law, but against prudence only; neither shall their infidelity be punished, but their former sins. Wherefore St. John saith of the unbeliever, _The wrath of God abideth on him_; he saith not, _The wrath of God shall come upon him_. And, _He that believeth not, is already judged_; he saith not, _shall be_ judged, but _is already_ judged. Nay, it cannot be well conceived, that remission of sins should be a benefit arising from _faith_, unless we understand also on the other side, that the punishment of sins is an hurt proceeding from _infidelity_. [Sidenote: It belongs to the civil authority, to define what the sin of injustice is.] 10. From hence, that our Saviour hath prescribed no distributive laws to the subjects of princes, and citizens of cities; that is to say, hath given no rules whereby a subject may know and discern what is _his own_, what _another man’s_, nor by what forms, words, or circumstances a thing must be _given_, _delivered_, _invaded_, _possessed_, that it may be known by right to belong to the _receiver_, _invader_, or _possessor_: we must necessarily understand that each single subject (not only with unbelievers, among whom Christ himself denied himself to be a _judge_ and _distributor_, but even with Christians) must take those rules from his city, that is to say, from that man or council which hath the supreme power. It follows therefore, that by those laws; _Thou shalt not kill_, _Thou shalt not commit adultery_, _Thou shalt not steal_, _Honour thy father and mother_; nothing else was commanded, but that subjects, and citizens, should absolutely obey their princes in all questions concerning _meum_ and _tuum_, _their own_ and _others’ right_. For by that precept, _Thou shalt not kill_, all slaughter is not prohibited; for he that said, _Thou shalt not kill_, said also, (Exod. xxxv. 2): _Whosoever doth work upon the sabbath, shall be put to death_. No, nor yet all slaughter, the cause not being heard; for he said, (Exod. xxxii. 27): _Slay every man his brother, and every man his companion, and every man his neighbour._ (Verse 28): _And there fell of the people about three thousand men._ Nor yet all slaughter of an innocent person; for Jephtha vowed (Judges xi. 31): _Whosoever cometh forth, &c. I will offer him up for a burnt offering unto the Lord_; and his vow was accepted of God. What then is forbidden? Only this: that no man kill another, who hath not _a right_ to kill him; that is to say, that no man kill, unless it belong to him to do so. The law of Christ therefore concerning killing, and consequently all manner of hurt done to any man, and what penalties are to be set, commands us to obey the city only. In like manner, by that precept, _Thou shalt not commit adultery_, all manner of copulation is not forbidden; but only that of lying with _another man’s wife_. But the judgment, which is another man’s wife, belongs to the city; and is to be determined by the rules which the city prescribes. This precept therefore commands both male and female to keep that faith entire, which they have mutually given according to the statutes of the city. So also by the precept, _thou shalt not steal_, all manner of invasion or secret surreption is not forbidden; but of _another man’s only_. The subject therefore is commanded this only, that he invade not nor take away aught which the city prohibits to be invaded or taken away; and universally, not to call anything _murder_, _adultery_, or _theft_, but what is done contrary to the civil laws. Lastly, seeing Christ hath commanded us to _honour our parents_, and hath not prescribed with what rites, what appellations, and what manner of obedience they are to be honoured; it is to be supposed that they are to be honoured with the will indeed, and inwardly, as kings and lords over their children, but outwardly, not beyond the city’s permission, which shall assign to every man, as all things else, so also _his honour_. But since the nature of justice consists in this, that every man have his own given him; it is manifest, that it also belongs to a Christian city to determine what is justice, what injustice, or a sin against justice. Now what belongs to a city, that must be judged to belong to him or them who have the sovereign power of the city. [Sidenote: It belongs to civil authority, to define what conduces to the peace and safety of the city.] 11. Moreover, because our Saviour hath not showed subjects any other laws for the government of a city, beside those of nature, that is to say, beside the command of obedience; no subject can privately determine who is a public friend, who an enemy, when war, when peace, when truce is to be made, nor yet what subjects, what authority and of what men, are commodious or prejudicial to the safety of the commonweal. These and all like matters therefore are to be learned, if need be, from the city, that is to say, from the sovereign powers. [Sidenote: It belongs to the civil authority, to judge, when need requires, what definitions and what inferences are true.] 12. Furthermore, all these things, to build castles, houses, temples; to move, carry, take away mighty weights; to send securely over seas; to contrive engines, serving for all manner of uses; to be well acquainted with the face of the whole world, the courses of the stars, the seasons of the year, the accounts of the times, and the nature of all things; to understand perfectly all natural and civil rights; and all manner of sciences, which, comprehended under the title of philosophy, are necessary partly to live, partly to live well; I say, the understanding of these (because Christ hath not delivered it) is to be learnt from reasoning; that is to say, by making necessary consequences, having first taken the beginning from experience. But men’s reasonings are sometimes right, sometimes wrong; and consequently, that which is concluded and held for a truth, is sometimes truth, sometimes error. Now errors, even about these philosophical points, do sometimes public hurt, and give occasions of great seditions and injuries. It is needful therefore, as oft as any controversy ariseth in these matters contrary to public good and common peace, that there be somebody to judge of the reasoning, that is to say, whether that which is inferred, be rightly inferred or not; that so the controversy may be ended. But there are no rules given by Christ to this purpose, neither came he into the world to teach _logic_. It remains therefore that the judges of such controversies, be the same with those whom God by nature had instituted before, namely, those who in each city are constituted by the sovereign. Moreover, if a controversy be raised of the accurate and proper signification, that is, the definition of those names or appellations which are commonly used; insomuch as it is needful for the peace of the city, or the distribution of right, to be determined; the determination will belong to the city. For men, by reasoning, do search out such kind of definitions in their observation of diverse conceptions, for the signification whereof those appellations were used at diverse times and for diverse causes. But the decision of the question, whether a man do reason rightly, belongs to the city. For example, if a woman bring forth a child of an unwonted shape, and the law forbid to kill a man; the question is, whether the child be a man. It is demanded therefore, what a man is. No man doubts but the city shall judge it, and that without taking an account of Aristotle’s definition, that man is a rational creature. And these things, namely, _right_, _policy_, and _natural sciences_, are subjects concerning which Christ denies that it belongs to his office to give any precepts, or teach any thing beside this only; that in all controversies about them, every single subject should obey the laws and determinations of his city. Yet must we remember this, that the same Christ, as God, could not only have taught, but also commanded what he would. [Sidenote: It belongs to the office of Christ, to teach morality, not as a speculation, but as a law; to forgive sins, and to teach all things whereof there is no science properly so called.] 13. The sum of our Saviour’s office was, to teach the way and all the means of salvation and eternal life. But justice and civil obedience, and observation of all the natural laws, is one of the means to salvation. Now these may be taught two ways; one, as _theorems_, by the way of natural reason, by drawing right and the natural laws from human principles and contracts; and this doctrine thus delivered, is subject to the censure of civil powers. The other, as laws, by divine authority, in showing the will of God to be such; and thus to teach, belongs only to him to whom the will of God is supernaturally known, that is to say, to Christ. Secondly, it belonged to the office of Christ to forgive sins to the penitent; for that was necessary for the salvation of men who had already sinned. Neither could it be done by any other. For remission of sins follows not repentance naturally, as a debt; but it depends, as a free gift, on the will of God supernaturally to be revealed. Thirdly, it belongs to the office of Christ to teach all those commandments of God, whether concerning his worship, or those points of faith which cannot be understood by natural reason, but only by revelation; of which nature are those, _that he was the Christ_; _that his kingdom was not terrestrial, but celestial_; _that there are rewards and punishments after this life_; _that the soul is immortal_; _that there should be such, and so many sacraments_; and the like. [Sidenote: A distinction of things temporal from spiritual.] 14. From what hath been said in the foregoing chapter, it is not hard to distinguish between things _spiritual_ and _temporal_. For since by _spiritual_, those things are understood, which have their foundation on the authority and office of Christ, and, unless Christ had taught them, could not have been known; and all other things are temporal; it follows, that the definition and determination of what is _just_ and _unjust_, the cognizance of all controversies about the _means of peace_ and _public defence_, and the examination of doctrines and books in all manner of _rational science_, depends upon _the temporal right_; but those which are _mysteries of faith_, depending on Christ’s word and authority only, their judgments belong to _spiritual right_. But it is reason’s inquisition, and pertains to _temporal right_ to define what is _spiritual_, and what _temporal_; because our Saviour hath not made that distinction. For although St. Paul in many places distinguish between _spiritual_ things and _carnal_ things; and call (Rom. viii. 5: 1 Cor. xii. 8-10) those things _spiritual_, which are of the _spirit_, to wit, the _word of wisdom_, _the word of knowledge_, _faith_, _the gift of healing_, _the working of miracles_, _prophecy_, _divers kind of tongues_, _interpretation of tongues_; all supernaturally inspired by the Holy Ghost, and such as the _carnal_ man understands not, but he only who hath known the mind of Christ (2 Cor. ii. 14-16); and those things _carnal_, which belong to worldly wealth (Rom. xv. 27); and the men _carnal men_ (1 Cor. iii. 1-3): yet hath he not defined, nor given us any rules whereby we may know what proceeds from natural reason, what from supernatural inspiration. [Sidenote: The word of God many ways taken.] 15. Seeing therefore it is plain that our Saviour hath committed to, or rather not taken away from _princes_, and those who in each city have obtained the sovereignty, the supreme authority of judging and determining all manner of controversies about _temporal_ matters; we must see henceforth to whom he hath left the same authority in matters _spiritual_. Which because it cannot be known, except it be out of _the word of God_ and _the tradition of the Church_, we must enquire in the next place what _the word of God is_, what _to interpret it_, what a _Church_ is, and what _the will and command of the Church_. To omit that the _word of God_ is in Scripture taken sometimes for the _Son of God_, it is used three manner of ways. First, most properly for that which God hath spoken. Thus, whatsoever God spake unto Abraham, the patriarchs, Moses, and the prophets, our Saviour to his disciples, or any others; is _the word of God_. Secondly, whatsoever hath been uttered by men on the motion or by command of the Holy Ghost; in which sense we acknowledge the Scriptures to be the _word of God_. Thirdly, in the New Testament indeed, the _word of God_ most frequently signifies the doctrine of the gospel, or the _word concerning God_, or _the word of the kingdom of God_ by Christ. As where it is said (Matth. iv. 23) that Christ preached the _gospel of the kingdom_: where the apostles are said to preach _the word of God_ (Acts xiii. 46): where the _word of God_ is called _the word of life_ (Acts v. 20): _of the word of the gospel_ (Acts xv. 7): _the word of faith_ (Rom. x. 8): _the word of truth_, that is to say, (adding an interpretation) _the gospel of salvation_, (Eph. i. 13): and where it is called _the word of the apostles_; for St. Paul says (2 Thess. iii. 14): _If any man obey not our word_, &c. Which places cannot be otherwise meant than of _the doctrine evangelical_. In like manner, where the word of God is said to be _sown_, _to increase_, and _to be multiplied_ (Acts xii. 24: and xiii. 49): it is very hard to conceive this to be spoken of the _voice of God_ or _of his apostles_; but of their doctrine, easy. And in this third acception is all that _doctrine of the Christian faith_, which at this day is preached in pulpits and contained in the books of divines, _the word of God_. [Sidenote: All things contained in the Scripture, belong not to the canon of Christian faith.] 16. Now the sacred Scripture is entirely _the word of God_ in this second acception, as being that which we acknowledge to be inspired from God; and innumerable places of it, in the first. And seeing the greatest part of it is conversant either in the prediction of the _kingdom of heaven_, or in prefigurations before the incarnation of Christ, or in evangelization and explication after; the sacred Scripture is also _the word of God_, and therefore the canon and rule of all _evangelical doctrine_, in this third signification; where _the word of God_ is taken for _the word concerning God_, that is to say, for _the gospel_. But because in the same Scriptures we read many things political, historical, moral, physical, and others which nothing at all concern the mysteries of our faith; those places, although they contain true doctrine, and are the canon of such kind of doctrines, yet can they not be the canon of the mysteries of Christian religion. [Sidenote: The word of a lawful interpreter of Scriptures, is the word of God.] 17. And truly, it is not the dead voice or letter of _the word of God_, which is the canon of Christian doctrine; but a true and genuine determination. For the mind is not governed by Scriptures, unless they be understood. There is need therefore of an interpreter to make the Scriptures canon, and hence follows one of these two things; that either the word of the interpreter is the word of God, or that the canon of Christian doctrine is not the word of God. The last of these must necessarily be false; for the rule of that doctrine which cannot be known by any human reason, but by divine revelation only, cannot be less than divine; for whom we acknowledge not to be able to discern whether some doctrine be true or not, it is impossible to account his opinion for a rule in the same doctrine. The first therefore is true, _that the word of an interpreter of Scriptures is the word of God_. The authority of interpreting Scriptures, is the same with that of determining controversies of faith. 18. Now that interpreter whose determination hath the honour to be held for _the word of God_, is not every one that translates the Scriptures out of the Hebrew and Greek tongue, to his Latin auditors in Latin, to his French in French, and to other nations in their mother tongue; for this is not to interpret. For such is the nature of speech in general, that although it deserve the chief place among those signs whereby we declare our conceptions to others, yet cannot it perform that office alone without the help of many circumstances. For the living voice hath its interpreters present, to wit, time, place, countenance, gesture, the counsel of the speaker, and himself unfolding his own meaning in other words as oft as need is. To recall these aids of interpretation, so much desired in the writings of old time, is neither the part of an ordinary wit, nor yet of the quaintest, without great learning and very much skill in antiquity. It sufficeth not therefore for interpretation of Scriptures, that a man understand the language wherein they speak. Neither is every one an authentic interpreter of Scriptures, who writes comments upon them. For men may err; they may also either bend them to serve their own ambition; or even resisting, draw them into bondage by their forestallings; whence it will follow, that an erroneous sentence must be held for _the word of God_. But although this might not happen, yet as soon as these commentators are departed, their commentaries will need explications; and in process of time, those explications expositions; those expositions new commentaries, without any end. So as there cannot, in any written interpretation whatsoever, be a canon or rule of Christian doctrine, whereby the controversies of religion may be determined. It remains, that there must be some canonical interpreter, whose legitimate office it is to end controversies begun, by explaining the word of God in the judgments themselves; and whose authority therefore must be no less obeyed, than theirs who first recommended the Scripture itself to us for a canon of faith; and that one and the same person be _an interpreter of Scripture_, and a _supreme judge of all manner of doctrines_. [Sidenote: Divers significations of a Church.] 19. What concerns the word _ecclesia_, or Church, originally it signifies the same thing that _concio_ or a congregation does in Latin; even as _ecclesiastes_ or churchman, the same that _concionator_ or preacher, that is to say, he who speaks to the congregation. In which sense we read in the Acts of the Apostles, of a _Church confused_, and of a _lawful Church_ (Acts xix, 32-39): that, taken for a concourse of people meeting in way of tumult; this, for a convocated assembly. But in holy writ by a _Church of Christians_, is sometimes understood the assembly, and sometimes the Christians themselves, although not actually assembled, if they be permitted to enter into the congregation and to communicate with them. For example, _Tell it to the Church_, (Matth. xviii. 17), is meant of a Church assembled; for otherwise it is impossible to _tell_ any thing to the Church. But _He laid waste the Church_, (Acts viii. 3), is understood of a Church not assembled. Sometimes a Church is taken for those who are baptized, or for the professors of the Christian faith, whether they be Christians inwardly or feignedly; as when we read of somewhat said or written to the Church, or said, or decreed, or done by the Church. Sometimes for the elect only, as when it is called _holy and without blemish_ (Ephes. v. 27). But the elect, as they are militant, are not properly called a Church; for they know not how to assemble; but they are a _future Church_, namely, in that day when severed from the reprobate they shall be triumphant. Again, a Church may be sometimes taken for all Christians collectively; as when Christ is called _the head of his Church_ (Ephes. v. 23); and _the head of his body the Church_ (Coloss. i. 18). Sometimes for its parts; as _the Church of Ephesus_, _the Church which is in his house_, _the seven Churches_, &c. Lastly, a Church, as it is taken for a company actually assembled, according to the divers ends of their meeting, signifies sometimes those who are met together to deliberate and judge; in which sense it is also called a council and a synod; sometimes those who meet together in the house of prayer to worship God, in which signification it is taken in the 1 Cor. xiv. 4, 5, 23, 28, &c. [Sidenote: What a Church is, to whom we attribute rights, actions, and the like appellations proper to a person.] 20. Now a _Church_, which hath personal rights and proper actions attributed to it, and of which that same must necessarily be understood, _Tell it to the Church_, and _he that obeys not the Church_, and all such like forms of speech, is to be defined so as by that word may be understood a multitude of men, who have made a new covenant with God in Christ, that is to say, a multitude of them who have taken upon them the sacrament of baptism; which multitude may both lawfully be called together by some one into one place, and, he so calling them, are bound to be present either in person or by others. For a multitude of men, if they cannot meet in assembly when need requires, is not to be called _a person_. For a Church can neither speak, nor discern, nor hear, but as it is a congregation. Whatsoever is spoken by particular men, (to wit, as many opinions almost as heads), that is the speech of one man, not of the Church. Furthermore, if an assembly be made, and it be unlawful, it shall be considered as null. Not any one of these therefore who are present in a tumult, shall be tied to the decree of the rest; but specially if he dissent. And therefore neither can such a Church make any decree; for then a multitude is said to decree somewhat, when every man is obliged by the decree of the major part. We must therefore grant to the definition of a Church, to which we attribute _things belonging to a person_, not only a possibility of assembling, but also of doing it lawfully. Besides, although there be some one who may lawfully call the rest together; yet if they who are called, may lawfully not appear; which may happen among men who are not subject one to another; that same _Church_ is not _one person_. For by what right they, who being called to a certain time and place do meet together, are _one Church_; by the same, others flocking to another place appointed by them, are _another Church_. And every number of men of one opinion is a Church; and by consequence, there will be as many Churches as there are divers opinions; that is to say, the same multitude of men will at once prove to be _one_, and _many Churches_. Wherefore a Church is not one, except there be a certain and known, that is to say, a lawful power, by means whereof every man may be obliged to be present in the congregation, either himself in person, or by proxy; and that becomes _one_, and is capable of _personal_ functions, by the union of a lawful power of convocating synods and assemblies of Christians; not by uniformity of doctrine; and otherwise it is a multitude, and _persons_ in the plural, howsoever agreeing in opinions. [Sidenote: A Christian city is the same with a Christian Church.] 21. It follows what hath been already said by necessary connexion, that _a city of Christian men_ and a _Church_ is altogether the same thing, of the same men, termed by two names, for two causes. For the _matter of a city_ and a _Church_ is one, to wit, the same Christian men. And the _form_, which consists in a lawful power of assembling them, is the same too; for it is manifest that every subject is obliged to come thither, whither he is summoned by his _city_. Now that which is called a _city_, as it is made up of _men_, the same, as it consists of _Christians_, is styled a _Church_. [Sidenote: Many cities do not constitute one Church.] 22. This too is very coherent with the same points: _if there be many Christian cities, they are not altogether personally one Church_. They may indeed by mutual consent become one _Church_, but no otherwise than as they must also become one city. For they cannot assemble but at some certain time, and to some place appointed. But persons, places, and times, belong to civil right; neither can any subject or stranger lawfully set his foot on any place, but by the permission of the city, which is lord of the place. But the things which cannot lawfully be done but by the permission of the city, those, if they be lawfully done, are done by the city’s authority. The _universal Church_ is indeed one _mystical body_, whereof Christ is the head; but in the same manner that all men together, acknowledging God for the ruler of the world, are one kingdom and one city; which notwithstanding is neither one _person_, nor hath it one common action or determination. Furthermore, where it is said that _Christ is the head of his body the Church_, it manifestly appears that that was spoken by the Apostle of the elect; who, as long as they are in this world, are a _Church_ only in _potentia_; but shall not actually be so before they be separated from the reprobate, and gathered together among themselves in the day of judgment. The Church of Rome of old was very great, but she went not beyond the bounds of her empire, and therefore neither was she _universal_; unless it were in that sense, wherein it was also said of the city of Rome, _Orbem jam totum victor Romanus habebat_; when as yet he had not the twentieth part of it. But after that the civil empire was divided into parts, the single cities thence arising were so many Churches: and that power which the Church of Rome had over them, might perhaps wholly depend on the authority of those Churches, who having cast off the emperors, were yet content to admit the doctors of Rome. [Sidenote: Who are clergymen.] 23. They may be called _churchmen_, who exercise a public office in the Church. But of offices, there was one a _ministery_, another a _maistery_. The offices of the _ministers_, was to serve tables, to take care of the temporal goods of the Church, and to distribute, at that time when all propriety of riches being abolished they were fed in common, to each man his portion. The _maisters_, according to their order, were called some _apostles_, some _bishops_, some _presbyters_, that is to say, _elders_; yet not so, as that by the name of _presbyter_, the _age_, but the office might be distinguished. For Timothy was a _presbyter_, although a young man. But because for the most part the _elders_ were received into the _maistership_, the word, denoting age, was used to signify the office. The same _maisters_, according to the diversity of their employments, were called some of them _apostles_, some _prophets_, some _evangelists_, some _pastors_ or _teachers_. And the _apostolical_ work indeed was universal; the _prophetical_, to declare their own revelations in the Church; the _evangelical_, to preach or to be publishers of the gospel among the infidels; that of the _pastors_, to teach, confirm, and rule the minds of those who already believed. [Sidenote: The election of churchmen belongs to the Church; their consecration to the pastors.] 24. In the election of churchmen two things are to be considered; the election of the persons, and their _consecration_ or institution, which also is called _ordination_. The first twelve apostles Christ himself both elected and ordained. After Christ’s ascension, Matthias was elected in the room of Judas the traitor; the Church, which at that time consisted of a congregation of about one hundred and twenty men, choosing two men: _and they appointed two_, Joseph and Matthias: but God himself by lot approving of Matthias. And St. Paul calls these twelve _the first and great apostles_; also the apostles _of the circumcision_. Afterward were added two other apostles, Paul and Barnabas; ordained indeed by the doctors and prophets of the Church of Antioch (which was _a particular Church_) by the imposition of hands; but elected by the command of the Holy Ghost. That they were both apostles, is manifest in Acts xiii. 2, 3. That they received their apostleship from hence, namely, because they were separated, by command of the spirit, for the work of God from the rest of the prophets and doctors of the Church of Antioch, St. Paul himself shows; who calls himself, for distinction sake (Rom. i. 1), _an apostle separated unto the Gospel of God_. But if it be demanded further, _by what authority_ it came to pass, that that was received for the command of the Holy Ghost, which those prophets and doctors did say proceeded from him; it must necessarily be answered, _by the authority of the Church of Antioch_. For the prophets and doctors must be examined by the Church, before they be admitted. For St. John (1 Epist. iv. 1) saith: _Believe not every spirit; but try the spirits, whether they are of God; because many false prophets are gone out into the world_. But by what Church, but that to which that epistle was written? In like manner St. Paul (Gal. ii. 14) reproves the Churches of Galatia, because they Judaized; although they seemed to do so by the authority of Peter. For when he had told them, that he had reprehended Peter himself in these words: _If thou being a Jew, livest after the manner of Gentiles, and not as do the Jews; why compellest thou the Gentiles to live as do the Jews_: not long after he questions them, saying (Gal. iii. 2): _This only would I learn of you: received ye the Spirit by the works of the law, or by the hearing of faith?_ Where it is evident, that it was Judaism which he reprehended the Galatians for, notwithstanding that the apostle Peter compelled them to Judaize. Seeing therefore it belonged to the Church, and not to Peter, and therefore also not to any man, to determine what doctors they should follow; it also pertained to the authority of the Church of Antioch, to elect their prophets and doctors. Now, because the Holy Ghost separated to himself the apostles Paul and Barnabas by the imposition of hands from doctors thus elected, it is manifest, _that imposition of hands and consecration_ of the prime doctors in each Church, belongs to the doctors of the same Church. But _bishops_, who were also called _presbyters_, although all presbyters were not bishops, were ordained sometimes by _apostles_; for Paul and Barnabas, when they had taught in Derbe, Lystra, and Iconium, ordained _elders_ in every Church (Acts xiv. 23): sometimes by other bishops; for Titus was by Paul left in Crete, that he should ordain _elders_ in every city (Tit. i. 5). And Timothy was advised (1 Tim. iv. 14) _Not to neglect the gift that was in him, which was given him by prophecy with the laying on of the hands of the presbytery_. And he had rules given him concerning the election of _presbyters_. But that cannot be understood otherwise, than of the ordination of those who were elected by the Church; for no man can constitute a doctor in the Church, but by the Church’s permission. For the duty of the apostles themselves was not to command, but to teach. And although they who were recommended by the apostles or presbyters, were not rejected, for the esteem that was had of the recommenders; yet seeing they could not be elected without the _will_ of the Church, they were also supposed elected by the _authority_ of the Church. In like manner ministers, who are called _deacons_, were _ordained_ by the apostles; yet _elected_ by the Church. For when the seven deacons were to be elected and ordained, the apostles elected them not: but, _look ye out_, say they (Acts vi. 3, 5, 6), _among you, brethren, seven men of honest report, &c.: and they chose Stephen, &c.: and they set them before the apostles_. It is apparent therefore by the custom of the primitive Church under the apostles, that the _ordination_ or _consecration_ of all churchmen, which is done by _prayer_ and _imposition of hands_, belonged to the _apostles_ and _doctors_; but the _election_ of those who were to be consecrated, _to the Church_. [Sidenote: The power of remitting sins to the penitent, and retaining those of the impenitent, belongs to the pastors; but judgment of the repentance, to the Church.] 25. Concerning the power of _binding_ and _loosing_, that is to say, of _remitting_ and _retaining of sins_; there is no doubt but it was given by Christ to the pastors then yet for to come, in the same manner as it was to the present apostles. Now the apostles had all the power _of remitting of sins_ given them, which Christ himself had. _As the Father hath sent me_, says Christ, (John xx. 21), _so send I you_; and he adds (verse 23): _Whose soever_ _sins ye remit, they are remitted; and whose soever sins ye retain, they are retained_. But what _binding_ and _loosing_, or _remitting_ and _retaining of sins_, is, admits of some scruple. For first, to _retain_ his sins, who being baptized into remission of sins, is truly penitent, seems to be against the very covenant itself of the New Testament; and therefore could not be done by Christ himself, much less by his pastors. And to _remit_ the impenitent, seems to be against the will of God the Father, from whom Christ was sent to convert the world and to reduce men unto obedience. Furthermore, if each pastor had an authority granted him to _remit_ and _retain_ sins in this manner, all awe of princes and civil magistrates, together with all kind of civil government would be utterly destroyed. For Christ hath said it, nay even nature itself dictates, that _we should not fear them who slay the body, but cannot kill the soul; but rather fear him, who can cast both soul and body into hell_ (Matth. x. 28). Neither is any man so mad, as not to choose to yield obedience rather to them who can remit and retain their sins, than to the powerfulest kings. Nor yet on the other side is it to be imagined, that _remission of sins_ is nothing else but an exemption from ecclesiastical punishments. For what evil hath excommunication in it, beside the eternal pains which are consequent to it? Or what benefit is to be received into the Church, if there were salvation out of it? We must therefore hold, _that pastors have power truly and absolutely to forgive sins; but to the penitent: and to retain them; but of the impenitent_. But while men think that to repent, is nothing else, but that every one condemn his actions and change those counsels which to himself seem sinful and blameable; there is an opinion risen, that there may be repentance before any confession of sins to men, and that repentance is not an effect, but a cause of confession. And thence the difficulty of those, who say that the sins of the penitent are already forgiven in baptism, and theirs who repent not, cannot be forgiven at all, is against Scripture, and contrary to the words of Christ, _whose soever sins ye remit_, &c. We must therefore, to resolve this difficulty, know in the first place, that a true acknowledgment of sin is repentance. For he that knows he hath sinned, knows he hath erred; but to will an error, is impossible; therefore he that knows he hath sinned, wishes he had not done it; which is to repent. Further, where it may be doubtful whether that which is done be a sin or not, we must consider, that repentance doth not precede confession of sins, but is subsequent to it: for there is no repentance but of sins acknowledged. The penitent therefore must both acknowledge the fact, and know it to be a sin, that is to say, against the law. If a man therefore think, that what he hath done is not against the law, it is impossible he should repent of it. Before repentance therefore, it is necessary there be an application of the facts unto the law. But it is in vain to apply the facts unto the law without an interpreter: for not the words of the law, but the sentence of the law-giver is the rule of men’s actions. But surely either one man, or some men are the interpreters of the law; for every man is not judge of his own fact, whether it be a sin or not. Wherefore the fact, of which we doubt whether it be a sin or not, must be unfolded before some man or men; and the doing of this is confession. Now when the interpreter of the law hath judged the fact to be a sin, if the sinner submit to his judgment and resolve with himself not to do so any more, it is repentance; and thus, either it is not true repentance, or else it is not antecedent, but subsequent to confession. These things being thus explained, it is not hard to understand what kind of power that of _binding_ and _loosing_ is. For seeing in remission of sins there are two things considerable; one, the _judgment_ or _condemnation_ whereby the fact is judged to be a sin; the other, when the party condemned does acquiesce and obey the sentence, that is to say, repents, _the remission of the sin_; or, if he repent not, _the retention_: the first of these, that is to say, the judging whether it be a sin or not, belongs _to the interpreter of the law_, that is, the _sovereign judge_; the second, namely, remission or retention of the sin, _to the pastor_; and it is that, concerning which the power _of binding_ and _loosing_ is conversant. And that this was the true meaning of our Saviour Christ in the institution of the same power, is apparent in Matth. xviii. 15-18, thus. He there speaking to his disciples, says: _If thy brother sin against thee, go and tell him his fault between him and thee alone_. Where we must observe by the way, that _if thy brother sin against thee_, is the same with, _if he do thee injury_; and therefore Christ spake of those matters which belonged to the civil tribunal. He adds; _if he hear thee not_, (that is to say, if he deny that he hath done it, or if having confessed the fact, he denies it to be unjustly done), _take with thee yet one or two; and if he refuse to hear them, tell it to the Church_. But why to the Church, except that she might judge whether it were a sin or not? But if _he refuse to hear the Church_; that is, if he do not submit to the Church’s sentence, but shall maintain that to be no sin, which she judges to be a sin; that is to say, if he repent not; (for certain it is, that no man repents himself of the action which he conceives not to be a sin); he saith not, _Tell it to the apostles_; that we might know that the definitive sentence in the question, whether it were a sin or not, was not left unto them; but to the Church. _But let him be unto thee_, says he, _as an heathen, or publican_; that is, as one out of the Church, as one that is not baptized, that is to say, as one whose _sins are retained_. For all Christians were baptized into remission of sins. But because it might have been demanded, who it was that had so great a power, as that of withholding the benefit of baptism from the impenitent; Christ shows that the same persons, to whom he had given authority to baptize the penitent into the remission of sins, and to make them of heathen men Christians, had also authority to retain their sins who by the Church should be adjudged to be impenitent, and to make them of Christian men heathens: and therefore presently subjoins: _Verily I say unto you, whose soever sins ye shall bind upon earth, they shall be bound also in heaven; and whose soever sins ye shall loose upon earth, they shall be loosed also in heaven_. Whence we may understand, that the power of binding and loosing, or of remitting and retaining of sins, which is called in another place the power of the keys, is not different from the power given in another place in these words (Matth. xxviii. 19): _Go, and teach all nations, baptizing them in the name of the Father, and of the Son, and of the Holy Ghost_. And even as the pastors cannot refuse to baptize him whom the Church judges worthy, so neither can they retain his sins whom the Church holds fitting to be absolved, nor yet remit his sins whom the Church pronounceth disobedient. And it is the Church’s part to judge of the sin, the pastor’s to cast out or to receive into the Church those that are judged. Thus St. Paul to the Church of Corinth (1 Cor. v. 12): _Do not ye judge_, saith he, _of those that are within?_ Yet he himself pronounced the sentence of excommunication against the incestuous person. _I indeed_, saith he (verse 3), _as absent in body, but present in Spirit_, &c. [Sidenote: What excommunication is, and on whom it cannot pass.] 26. The act of retaining sins is that which is called by the Church _excommunication_, and by St. Paul _delivering over to Satan_. The word _excommunication_ sounding the same with ἀποσυάγωγον poiein], _casting out of the synagogue_, seems to be borrowed from the Mosaical law; wherein they who were by the priest adjudged leprous, were commanded (Levit. xiii. 46) to be kept apart out of the camp, until by the judgment of the priest they were again pronounced clean, and by certain rites, among which the washing of the body was one, were purified. From hence in process of time it become a custom of the Jews, not to receive those who passed from Gentilism to Judaism, supposing them to be unclean, unless they were first _washed_; and those who dissented from the doctrine of the synagogue, they cast out of the synagogue. By resemblance of this custom, those that came to Christianity, whether they were Jews or Gentiles, were not received into the Church without baptism; and those that dissented from the Church, were deprived of the Church’s communion. Now, they were therefore said _to be delivered over to Satan_, because all that was out of the Church, was comprehended within his kingdom. The end of this kind of discipline was, that being destitute for a time of the grace and spiritual privileges of the Church, they might be humbled to salvation; but the effect in regard of secular matters, that _being excommunicated_, they should not only be prohibited all congregations or churches, and the participation of the mysteries, but as being contagious they should be avoided by all other Christians, even more than heathen. For the apostle allowed to accompany with heathen; but with these, _not so much as to eat_ (1 Cor. v. 10-11). Seeing then the effect of _excommunication_ is such, it is manifest, in the first place, that _a Christian city cannot be excommunicated_. For a Christian city is a Christian Church, (as hath been declared above, in art. 21), and of the same extension; but a Church cannot be excommunicated. For either she must excommunicate herself, which is impossible; or she must be excommunicated by some other Church; and this, either _universal_ or _particular_. But seeing _an universal Church_ is no _person_, (as hath been proved in art. 22), and therefore neither acts nor does any thing, it cannot _excommunicate_ any man; and a particular Church by excommunicating another Church, doth nothing. For where there is not one common congregation, there cannot be any excommunication. Neither if some one Church (suppose that of Jerusalem), should have excommunicated another, (suppose that of Rome), would it any more have excommunicated this, than herself: for he that deprives another of his communion, deprives himself also of the communion of that other. Secondly, _no man can excommunicate the subjects of any absolute government all at once, or forbid them the use of their temples or their public worship of God_. For they cannot be excommunicated by a Church, which themselves do constitute. For if they could, there would not only not remain a Church, but not so much as a _commonweal_, and they would be dissolved of themselves; and this were not _to be excommunicated_ or _prohibited_. But if they be excommunicated by some other Church, that Church is to esteem them as heathen. But no _Christian Church_, by the doctrine of Christ, can forbid the heathen to gather together and communicate among themselves, as it shall seem good to their cities; especially if they meet to worship Christ, although it be done in a singular custom and manner: therefore also not the _excommunicated_, who are to be dealt with as heathen. Thirdly, _a prince who hath the sovereign power, cannot be excommunicated_. For by the doctrine of Christ, neither one nor many subjects together can interdict their prince any public or private places, or deny him entrance into any assembly whatsoever, or prohibit him the doing of what he will with his own jurisdiction. For it is treason among all cities, for any one or many subjects jointly to arrogate to themselves any authority over the whole city. But they who arrogate to themselves an authority over him who hath the supreme power of the city, do arrogate the same authority over the city itself. Besides, a sovereign prince, if he be a Christian, hath this further advantage; that the city whose will is contained in his, is that very thing which we call a Church. The _Church_ therefore excommunicates no man, but whom it excommunicates by the authority of the prince. But the prince excommunicates not himself; his subjects therefore cannot do it. It may be indeed, that an assembly of rebellious citizens or traitors may pronounce the sentence of excommunication against their prince; but not _by right_. Much less can one prince be excommunicated by another; for this would prove not an excommunication, but a provocation to war by the way of affront. For since that is not one Church, which is made up of citizens belonging to two absolute cities, for want of power of lawfully assembling them, (as hath been declared before, in art. 22); they who are of one Church are not bound to obey another, and therefore cannot be excommunicated for their disobedience. Now, what some may say, that princes, seeing they are members of the universal Church, may also by the authority of the universal Church be excommunicated, signifies nothing: because _the universal Church_, (as hath been showed in art. 22), is not _one person_, of whom it may be said that _she acted, decreed, determined, excommunicated, absolved_, and the like personal attributes; neither hath she any governor upon earth, at whose command she may assemble and deliberate. For to be guide of the universal Church, and to have the power of assembling her, is the same thing as to be governor and lord over all the Christians in the world; which is granted to none, but God only. [Sidenote: The interpretation of Scripture depends on the authority of the city.] 27. It hath been showed above in art. 18, that the authority of _interpreting the Holy Scriptures_ consisted not in this, that the interpreter might without punishment expound and explicate his sentence and opinion taken thence unto others, either by writing or by his own voice; but that others have not a right to do or teach aught contrary to his sentence; insomuch as _the interpretation_ we speak of, is the same with _the power of defining_ in all manner of controversies to be determined by sacred Scriptures. Now we must show that that power belongs to each Church; and depends on his or their authority who have the supreme command, provided that they be Christians. For if it depend not on the civil authority, it must either depend on the opinion of each private subject, or some foreign authority. But among other reasons, the inconveniences that must follow private opinions, cannot suffer its dependance on them. Of which this is the chief; that not only all civil obedience would be taken away (contrary to Christ’s precept); but all human society and peace would be dissolved (contrary to the laws of nature). For seeing every man is his own interpreter of Scripture, that is to say, since every man makes himself judge of what is pleasing and displeasing unto God; they cannot obey their princes, before that they have judged whether their commands be conformable to the word of God, or not. And thus either they obey not, or they obey for their own opinion’s sake; that is to say, they obey themselves, not their sovereign; civil obedience therefore is lost. Again, when every man follows his own opinion, it is necessary that the controversies which rise among them, should become innumerable and indeterminable; whence there will breed among men, who by their own natural inclinations do account all dissensions an affront, first hatred, then brawls and wars; and thus all manner of peace and society would vanish. We have furthermore for an example, that which God under the old law required to be observed concerning the book of the law; namely, that it should be transcribed and publicly used; and he would have it to be the canon of divine doctrine, but the controversies about it not to be determined by private persons, but only by the priests. Lastly, it is our Saviour’s precept, that if there be any matter of offence between private persons, they should _hear the Church_. Wherefore it is the Church’s duty to define controversies; it therefore belongs not to private men, but to the Church to interpret Scriptures. But that we may know that the authority of _interpreting God’s Word_, that is to say, of determining all questions concerning God and religion, belongs not to any foreign person whatsoever; we must consider, first, what weight such a power has in the minds of the citizens, and their actions. For no man can be ignorant that the voluntary actions of men, by a natural necessity, do follow those opinions which they have concerning good and evil, reward and punishment. Whence it happens, that necessarily they would choose rather to obey those, by whose judgment they believe that they shall be eternally happy or miserable. Now, by whose judgment it is appointed what doctrines are necessary to salvation, by their judgment do men expect their eternal bliss or perdition; they will therefore yield them obedience in all things. Which being thus, most manifest it is, that those subjects, who believe themselves bound to acquiesce to a foreign authority in those doctrines which are necessary to salvation, do not _per se_ constitute a city, but are the subjects of that foreign power. Nor therefore, although some sovereign prince should by writing grant such an authority to any other, yet so as he would be understood to have retained the civil power in his own hands, shall such a writing be valid, or transfer aught necessary for the retaining or good administration of his command. For by chap. II. art. 4, no man is said _to transfer his right, unless he give some proper sign, declaring his will to transfer it_. But he who hath openly declared his will to keep his sovereignty, cannot have given a sufficient sign of transferring the means necessary for the keeping it. This kind of writing therefore will not be a sign of will, but of ignorance in the contractors. We must consider next, how absurd it is for a city or sovereign to commit the ruling of his subjects’ consciences to an enemy; for they are, as hath been showed above in chap. V. art. 6, in an hostile state, whosoever have not joined themselves into the unity of one person. Nor contradicts it this truth, that they do not always fight: for truces are made between enemies. It is sufficient for an hostile mind, that there is suspicion; that the frontiers of cities, kingdoms, empires, strengthened with garrisons, do with a fighting posture and countenance, though they strike not, yet as enemies mutually behold each other. Lastly, how unequal is it to demand that, which by the very reason of your demand you confess to be the right of another. I am the interpreter of Scriptures to you, who are the subject of another state. Why? By what covenants passed between you and me? By divine authority. Whence known? Out of holy Scripture: behold the book, read it. In vain, unless I may also interpret the same for myself. That interpretation therefore doth by right belong to me, and the rest of my private fellow-subjects; which we both deny. It remains therefore that in all _Christian Churches_, that is to say, in all _Christian cities_, the _interpretation_ of sacred Scripture, that is to say, the right of determining all controversies, depends on and derives from the authority of that man or council, which hath the sovereign power of the city. [Sidenote: A Christian city must interpret Scriptures by clergymen.] 28. Now because there are two kinds of controversies: the one about spiritual matters, that is to say, questions of faith, the truth whereof cannot be searched into by natural reason; such are the questions concerning _the nature and office of Christ_, _of rewards and punishments to come_, _of the sacraments_, _of outward worship_, and the like: the other, about questions of human science, whose truth is sought out by natural reason and syllogisms, drawn from the covenants of men, and definitions, that is to say, significations received by use and common consent of words; such as are all questions of right and philosophy; for example, when in matter of right it is questioned, whether there be _a promise_ and _covenant_, or not, that is nothing else but to demand whether such words, spoken in such a manner, be by common use and consent of the subjects _a promise_ or _covenant_; which if they be so called, then it is true that a contract is made; if not, then it is false: that truth therefore depends on the compacts and consents of men. In like manner, when it is demanded in philosophy, whether the same thing may entirely be in divers places at once; the determination of the question depends on the knowledge of the common consent of men, about the signification of the word _entire_. For if men, when they say a thing is entirely somewhere, do signify by common consent that they understand nothing of the same to be elsewhere; it is false that the same thing is in divers places at once. That truth therefore depends on the consents of men, and by the same reason, in all other questions concerning _right_ and _philosophy_. And they who do judge that anything can be determined, contrary to this common consent of men concerning the appellations of things, out of obscure places of Scripture; do also judge that the use of speech, and at once all human society, is to be taken away. For he who hath sold a whole field, will say he meant one whole ridge; and will retain the rest as unsold. Nay, they take away reason itself; which is nothing else but a searching out of the truth made by such consent. This kind of questions, therefore, need not be determined by the city by way of interpretation of Scriptures; for they belong not to God’s _Word_, in that sense wherein _the Word of God_ is taken for the _Word concerning God_; that is to say, for the _doctrine of the gospel_. Neither is he who hath the sovereign power in the Church, obliged to employ any _ecclesiastical doctors_ for the judging of any such kind of matters as these. But for the deciding of questions of faith, that is to say, _concerning God_, which transcend human capacity, we stand in need of a divine blessing, (that we may not be deceived at least in necessary points), to be derived from Christ himself by the imposition of hands. For, seeing to the end we may attain to eternal salvation we are obliged to a supernatural doctrine, and which therefore it is impossible for us to understand; to be left so destitute as that we can be deceived in necessary points, is repugnant to equity. This infallibility our Saviour Christ promised (in those things which are necessary to salvation) to his apostles until the day of judgment; that is to say, to the apostles, and pastors succeeding the apostles, who were to be consecrated _by the imposition of hands_. He therefore, who hath the sovereign power in the city, is obliged as a Christian, where there is any question concerning _the mysteries of faith_, to interpret the Holy Scriptures by _clergymen_ lawfully ordained. And thus in Christian cities, the judgment both of _spiritual_ and _temporal matters_ belongs unto the civil authority. And that man or council who hath the supreme power, is head both of _the city_ and _of the Church_; for a _Church_ and _a Christian city_ is but one thing. ------- CHAPTER XVIII. CONCERNING THOSE THINGS WHICH ARE NECESSARY FOR OUR ENTRANCE INTO THE KINGDOM OF HEAVEN. 1. The difficulty propounded concerning the repugnancy of obeying God and men, is to be removed by the distinctions between the points necessary and not necessary to salvation. 2. All things necessary to salvation, are contained in faith and obedience. 3. What kind of obedience that is, which is required of us. 4. What faith is, and how distinguished from profession, from science, from opinion. 5. What it is to believe in Christ. 6. That that article alone, that Jesus is the Christ, is necessary to salvation; is proved from the scope of the evangelists. 7. From the preachings of the apostles. 8. From the easiness of Christian religion. 9. From this also, that it is the foundation of faith. 10. From the most evident words of Christ and his apostles. 11. In that article is contained the faith of the Old Testament. 12. How faith and obedience concur to salvation. 13. In a Christian city, there is no contradiction between the commands of God and of the city. 14. The doctrines which this day are controverted about religion, do for the most part relate to the right of dominion. [Sidenote: The difficulty propounded concerning the repugnance of obeying God and men, is to be removed by the distinction between the points necessary, and not necessary to salvation.] 1. It was ever granted, that all authority _in secular matters_ derived from him who had the sovereign power, whether he were one man or an assembly of men. That the same _in spiritual matters_ depended on the authority of the _Church_, is manifest by the lastly foregoing proofs; and besides by this, that all Christian cities are Churches endued with this kind of authority. From whence a man, though but dull of apprehension, may collect, that in _a Christian city_, that is to say, in a city whose sovereignty belongs to a Christian prince or council, _all power, as well spiritual as secular, is united under Christ_, and therefore it is to be obeyed in all things. But on the other side, _because we must rather obey God than men_, there is a difficulty risen, how obedience may safely be yielded to them, if at any time somewhat should be commanded by them to be done which Christ hath prohibited. The reason of this difficulty is, that seeing God no longer speaks to us by Christ and his prophets in open voice, but by the holy Scriptures, which by divers men are diversely understood; they know indeed what princes and a congregated Church do command; but whether that which they do command, be contrary to the word of God or not, this they know not; but with a wavering obedience between the punishments of temporal and spiritual death, as it were sailing between Scylla and Charybdis, they often run themselves upon both. But they who rightly distinguish between the things necessary to salvation, and those which are not necessary, can have none of this kind of doubt. For if the command of the prince or city be such, that he can obey it without hazard of his eternal salvation, it is unjust not to obey them; and the apostle’s precepts take place (Col. iii. 20-22): _Children obey your parents in all things: servants in all things obey your masters according to the flesh._ And the command of Christ (Matth. xxiii. 2-3): _The Scribes and Pharisees sit in Moses’ chair; all things therefore whatsoever they command you, that observe and do._ On the contrary, if they command us to do those things which are punished with eternal death, it were madness not rather to choose to die a natural death, than by obeying to die eternally: and then comes in that which Christ says (Matth. x. 28): _Fear not them who kill the body, but cannot kill the soul._ We must see, therefore, what all those things are, which are necessary to salvation. [Sidenote: All things necessary to salvation, are contained in faith and obedience.] 2. Now all things necessary to salvation are comprehended in two virtues, _faith_ and _obedience_. The latter of these, if it could be perfect, would alone suffice to preserve us from damnation; but because we have all of us been long since guilty of disobedience against God in Adam, and besides we ourselves have since actually sinned, _obedience_ is not sufficient without _remission of sins_. But this, together with our entrance into the kingdom of heaven, is the reward of _faith_; nothing else is requisite to salvation. For the kingdom of heaven is shut to none but sinners, that is to say, those who have not performed due _obedience_ to the laws; and not to those neither, if they believe the necessary articles of the Christian faith. Now, if we shall know in what points obedience doth consist, and which are the necessary articles of the Christian faith; it will at once be manifest what we must do, and what abstain from, at the command of cities and of princes. [Sidenote: What kind of obedience that is, which is required of us.] 3. But by obedience in this place is signified not _the fact_, but the _will_ and _desire_ wherewith we purpose, and endeavour as much as we can, to obey for the future. In which sense the word _obedience_ is equivalent to _repentance_; for the virtue of repentance consists not in the sorrow which accompanies the remembrance of sin; but in our conversion into the way, and full purpose to sin no more; without which that sorrow is said to be the sorrow not of a penitent, but a desperate person. But because they who love God cannot but desire to obey the divine law, and they who love their neighbours cannot but desire to obey the moral law; which consists (as hath been showed above in chap. III.) in the prohibition of _pride_, _ingratitude_, _contumely_, _inhumanity_, _cruelty_, _injury_, and the like offences, whereby our neighbours are prejudiced; therefore also _love_, or _charity_, is equivalent to the word _obedience_. Justice, also, which is a constant will of giving to every man his due, is equivalent with it. But that _faith_ and _repentance_ are sufficient for salvation, is manifest by the covenant itself of baptism. For they who were by Peter converted on the day of _Pentecost_, demanding him, what they should do: he answered (Acts ii. 38): _Repent and be baptized every one of you, in the name of Jesus, for the remission of your sins._ There was nothing therefore to be done for the obtaining of baptism, that is to say, for to enter into the kingdom of God, but _to repent and believe in the name of Jesus_; for the kingdom of heaven is promised by the covenant which is made in baptism. Furthermore, by the words of Christ, answering the lawyer who asked him what he should do to inherit eternal life (Luke xviii. 20): _Thou knowest the commandments: Thou shalt not kill, thou shalt not commit adultery_, &c.: which refer to obedience; and (Mark x. 21): _Sell all that thou hast, and come and follow me_: which relates to faith. And by that which is said: _The just shall live by faith_; not every man, but the _just_; for _justice_ is the same disposition of will which _repentance and obedience_ are. And by the words of St. Mark (i. 15): _The time is fulfilled, and the kingdom of God is at hand; repent ye, and believe the gospel_; by which words is not obscurely signified, that there is no need of other virtues for our entrance into the kingdom of God, excepting those of _repentance and faith_. The obedience therefore which is _necessarily_ required to salvation, is nothing else but _the will_ or _endeavour_ to obey; that is to say, of doing according to the laws of God; that is, the moral laws, which are the same to all men, and the civil laws; that is to say, the commands of sovereigns in _temporal_ matters, and the ecclesiastical laws in _spiritual_. Which two kinds of laws are divers in divers cities and Churches, and are known by their promulgation and public sentences. [Sidenote: What faith is, and how distinguished from profession, from science, and from opinion.] 4. That we may understand what the _Christian faith_ is, we must define _faith_ in general; and distinguish it from those other acts of the mind, wherewith commonly it is confounded. The object of _faith_ universally taken, namely, _for that which is believed_, is evermore a _proposition_, that is to say, a speech affirmative or negative, which we grant to be true. But because propositions are granted for divers causes, it falls out that these kind of concessions are diversely called. But we grant propositions sometimes, which notwithstanding we receive not into our minds; and this either for a time, to wit, so long, till by consideration of the consequences we have well examined the truth of them, which we call _supposing_; or also simply, as through fear of the laws, which is to _profess_, or _confess_ by outward tokens; or for a voluntary compliance sake, which men use out of civility to those whom they respect, and for love of peace to others, which is _absolute yielding_. Now the propositions which we receive for truth, we always grant for some reasons of our own; and these are derived either from the _proposition itself_, or from the _person propounding_. They are derived from the _proposition itself_, by calling to mind what things those words, which make up the proposition, do by common consent usually signify. If so, then the assent which we give, is called _knowledge_ or _science_. But if we cannot remember what is certainly understood by those words, but sometimes one thing, sometimes another seem to be apprehended by us, then we are said to think. For example, if it be propounded that _two and three make five_; and by calling to mind, that the order of numeral words is so appointed by the common consent of them who are of the same language with us, (as it were, by a certain contract necessary for human society), that _five_ shall be the name of so many unities as are contained in two and three taken together, a man assent that this is therefore true, because two and three together are the same with five: this assent shall be called knowledge. And to know this truth is nothing else, but to acknowledge that it is made by ourselves. For by whose will and rules of speaking the number || is called two, ||| is called three, and ||||| is called five; by their will also it comes to pass that this proposition is true, _two and three taken together make five_. In like manner if we remember what it is that is called _theft_, and what _injury_; we shall understand by the words themselves, whether it be true that _theft is an injury_, or not. _Truth_ is the same with a _true proposition_; but _the proposition is true_ in which the _word consequent_, which by logicians is called _the predicate_, embraceth _the word antecedent_ in its amplitude, which they call _the subject_. And to _know truth_, is the same thing as to _remember_ that it was made by ourselves by the very usurpation of the words. Neither was it rashly nor unadvisedly said by Plato of old, _that knowledge was memory_. But it happens sometimes, that words although they have a certain and defined signification by constitution, yet by vulgar use either to adorn or deceive, they are so wrested from their own significations, that to remember the conceptions for which they were first imposed on things, is very hard, and not to be mastered but by a sharp judgment and very great diligence. It happens too that there are many words, which have no proper, determined, and everywhere the same signification; and are understood not by their own, but by virtue of other signs used together with them. Thirdly, there are some words of things unconceivable. Of those things, therefore, whereof they are the words, there is no conception; and therefore in vain do we seek for the truth of those propositions, which they make out of the words themselves. In these cases, while by considering the definitions of words we search out the truth of some proposition, according to the hope we have of finding it, we think it sometimes true, and sometimes false; either of which apart is called _thinking_, and also _believing_; both together, _doubting_. But when our reasons, for which we assent to some proposition, derive not from the _proposition itself_, but from the _person propounding_, whom we esteem so learned that he is not deceived, and we see no reason why he should deceive us; our assent, because it grows not from any confidence of our own, but from another man’s knowledge, is called _faith_. And by the confidence of whom we do believe, we are said _to trust them_, or _to trust in them_. By what hath been said, the difference appears, first, between _faith_ and _profession_; for that is always joined with inward assent; this not always. That is an inward persuasion of the mind, this an outward obedience. Next, between _faith_ and _opinion_; for this depends on our own reason, that on the good esteem we have of another. Lastly, between _faith_ and _knowledge_; for this deliberately takes a proposition broken and chewed; that swallows it down whole and entire. The explication of words, whereby the matter enquired after is propounded, is conducible to knowledge; nay, the only way _to know_, is by _definition_. But this is prejudicial to _faith_; for those things which exceed human capacity, and are propounded to be believed, are never more evident by explication, but, on the contrary, more obscure and harder to be credited. And the same thing befalls a man, who endeavours to demonstrate _the mysteries of faith_ by natural reason, which happens to a sick man, who will needs chew before he will swallow his wholesome but bitter pills; whence it comes to pass, that he presently brings them up again; which perhaps would otherwise, if he had taken them well down, have proved his remedy. [Sidenote: What it is to believe in Christ.] 5. We have seen therefore what it is _to believe_. But what is it _to believe in Christ_? Or what proposition is that, which is the object of our faith in Christ? For when we say, _I believe in Christ_, we signify indeed whom, but not what we believe. Now, _to believe in Christ_ is nothing else but to believe that Jesus is the Christ, namely, he who according to the prophecies of Moses and the prophets of Israel, was to come into this world _to institute the kingdom of God_. And this sufficiently appears out of the words of Christ himself to Martha (John xi. 25-27): _I am_, saith he, _the resurrection and the life; he that believeth in me, though he were dead, yet shall he live; and whosoever liveth and believeth in me, shall never die. Believest thou this? She saith unto him, yea, Lord, I believe that thou art the Christ the Son of God, which should come into the world._ In which words, we see that the question, _believest thou in me_, is expounded by the answer, _thou art the Christ_. To believe in Christ therefore is nothing else but to believe Jesus himself, saying that he is the Christ. [Sidenote: That that article alone, that Jesus is the Christ, is necessary to salvation, is proved out of the scope of the evangelists.] 6. _Faith_ and _obedience_ both necessarily concurring to salvation, what kind of obedience that same is, and to whom due, hath been showed above in art. 3. But now we must enquire what _articles of faith_ are requisite. And I say, that to a Christian[21] there is no other article of faith requisite as _necessary_ to salvation, but only this, _that Jesus is the Christ_. But we must distinguish, as we have already done before in art. 4, between _faith_ and _profession_. _A profession_, therefore, of more articles, if they be commanded, may be necessary; for it is a part of our _obedience_ due to the laws. But we enquire not now what _obedience_, but what _faith_ is necessary to salvation. And this is proved, first, out of the scope of the Evangelists, which was, by the description of our Saviour’s life, to establish this one article: and we shall know that such was the scope and counsel of the Evangelists, if we observe but the history itself. St. Matthew (chap. i.), beginning at his genealogy, shows that Jesus was of the lineage of David, born of a virgin: chap, ii., that he was adored by the _wise men_ as king of the Jews; that Herod for the same cause sought to slay him: chap. iii., iv., that his kingdom was preached both by John the Baptist and himself: chapters v. vi. vii., that he taught the laws, not as the Scribes, but as one having authority: chapters viii. ix., that he cured diseases miraculously: chap. x., that he sent his apostles, the preachers of his kingdom, throughout all the parts of Judea to proclaim his kingdom: chap. xi., that he commanded the messengers, sent from John to enquire whether he were the Christ or not, to tell him what they had seen, namely, the miracles which were only compatible with Christ: chap. xii., that he proved and declared his kingdom to the Pharisees and others by arguments, parables, and signs; and the following chapters to xxi., that he maintained himself to be the Christ against the Pharisees: chap. xxi., that he was saluted with the title of king, when he entered into Jerusalem: chaps. xxii., xxiii., xxiv., xxv., that he forewarned others of _false Christs_; and that he showed in parables what manner of kingdom his should be: chaps. xxvi. xxvii., that he was taken and accused for this reason, because he said he was a king; and that a title was written on his cross, _this is Jesus the king of the Jews_: lastly, chap. xxviii., that after his resurrection, he told his apostles that all power was given unto him both in heaven and in earth. All which tends to this end; that we should believe Jesus to be the Christ. Such therefore was the scope of St. Matthew in describing his gospel. But such as his was, such also was the rest of the Evangelists; which St. John sets down expressly in the end of his gospel (John xx. 31): _These things_, saith he, _are written, that ye may know that Jesus is the Christ, the Son of the living God_. Footnote 21: _I say, that to a Christian._] Although I conceive this assertion to be sufficiently proved by the following reasons, yet I thought it worth my labour to make a more ample explication of it; because I perceive that being somewhat new, it may possibly be distasteful to many divines. First therefore, when I say this article, _that Jesus is the Christ_, is necessary to salvation; I say not that faith only is necessary, but I require justice also, or that obedience which is due to the laws of God; that is to say, a will to live righteously. Secondly, I deny not but the profession of many articles, provided that that profession be commanded by the Church, is also necessary to salvation. But seeing faith is internal, profession external, I say that the former only is properly faith; the latter a part of obedience; insomuch as that article alone sufficeth for inward belief, but is not sufficient for the outward profession of a Christian. Lastly, even as if I had said that true and inward repentance of sins was only necessary to salvation, yet were it not to be held for a paradox; because we suppose justice, obedience, and a mind reformed in all manner of virtues to be contained in it. So when I say that the faith of one article is sufficient to salvation, it may well be less wondered at; seeing that in it so many other articles are contained. For these words, _Jesus is the Christ_, do signify that Jesus was that person, whom God had promised by his prophets should come into the world to establish his kingdom; that is to say, that Jesus is the Son of God, the creator of heaven and earth, born of a virgin, dying for the sins of them who should believe in him; that he was Christ, that is to say, a king; that he revived (for else he were not like to reign) to judge the world, and to reward every one according to his works (for otherwise he cannot be a king); also that men shall rise again, for otherwise they are not like to come to judgment. The whole symbol of the apostles is therefore contained in this one article. Which, notwithstanding, I thought reasonable to contract thus; because I found that many men for this alone, without the rest, were admitted into the kingdom of God, both by Christ and his apostles; as the thief on the cross, the eunuch baptized by Philip, the two thousand men converted to the Church at once by St. Peter. But if any man be displeased that I do not judge all those eternally damned, who do not inwardly assent to every article defined by the Church, and yet do not contradict, but, if they be commanded, do submit: I know not what I shall say to them. For the most evident testimonies of Holy Writ, which do follow, do withhold me from altering my opinion. [Sidenote: By the apostles’ sermons.] 7. Secondly, this is proved by the preaching of the apostles. For they were the proclaimers of his kingdom; neither did Christ send them to preach aught but the kingdom of God (Luke ix. 2: Acts x. 42). And what they did after Christ’s ascension, may be understood by the accusation which was brought against them (Acts xvii. 6-7): _They drew Jason_, saith St. Luke, _and certain brethren unto the rulers of the city, crying, these are the men that have turned the world upside down, and are come hither also, whom Jason hath received; and these all do contrary to the decrees of Cæsar, saying that there is another king, one Jesus_. It appears also, what the subject of the apostle’s sermon was, out of these words (Acts xvii. 2-3): _Opening and alleging out of the Scriptures_ (to wit, of the Old Testament) _that Christ must needs have suffered and risen again from the dead; and that this Jesus is the Christ_. [Sidenote: By the easiness of Christian religion.] 8. Thirdly, by the places, in which the easiness of those things, which are required by Christ to the attaining of salvation, is declared. For if an internal assent of the mind were necessarily required to the truth of all and each proposition, which this day is controverted about the Christian faith, or by divers churches is diversely defined; there would be nothing more difficult than the Christian religion. And how then would that be true (Matth. xi. 30): _My yoke is easy and my burden light_; and that (Matth. xviii. 6): _little ones do believe in him_; and that (1 Cor. i. 21): _it pleased God by the foolishness of preaching, to save those that believe_? Or how was the thief hanging on the cross sufficiently instructed to salvation, the confession of whose faith was contained in these words: _Lord, remember me when thou comest into thy kingdom_? Or how could St. Paul himself, from an enemy, so soon become a doctor of Christians? [Sidenote: By this, that it is the foundation of faith.] 9. Fourthly, by this, that that article is the foundation of faith; neither rests it on any other foundation. Matth. xxiv. 23, 24: _If any man shall say unto you, Lo here is Christ, or he is there; believe it not. For there shall arise false Christs and false prophets, and shall show great signs and wonders_, &c. Whence it follows, that for the faith’s sake which we have in this article, we must not believe any signs and wonders. Gal. i. 8: _Although we or an angel from heaven_, saith the apostle, _should preach to you any other gospel, than what we have preached; let him be accursed_. By reason of this article, therefore, we might not trust the very apostles and angels themselves, and therefore, I conceive, not the Church neither, if they should teach the contrary. 1 John iv. 1-2: _Beloved, believe not every spirit, but try the spirits whether they are of God; because many false prophets are gone out into the world. Hereby know ye the spirit of God; every spirit that confesseth Jesus Christ is come in the flesh, is of God_, &c. That article therefore is the measure of the spirits, whereby the authority of the doctors is either received, or rejected. It cannot be denied, indeed, but that all who at this day are Christians, did learn from the doctors that it was Jesus, who did all those things whereby he might be acknowledged to be the Christ. Yet it follows not, that the same persons believed that article for the doctor’s or the Church’s, but for Jesus’ own sake. For that article was before _the Christian Church_, (Matth. xvi. 18), although all the rest were after it; and the Church was founded upon it, not it upon the Church. Besides, this article, that _Jesus is the Christ_, is so fundamental, that all the rest are by St. Paul (1 Cor. iii. 11-15) said to be built upon it: _For other foundation can no man lay, than that which is laid; which is Jesus Christ_; that is to say, that _Jesus is the Christ. Now if any man build upon this foundation, gold, silver, precious stones, wood, hay, stubble; every man’s work shall be made manifest; if any man’s work abide, which he hath built thereupon, he shall receive a reward; if any man’s work shall be burnt, he shall suffer loss, but he himself shall be saved._ From whence it plainly appears, that by _foundation_ is understood this article, _that Jesus is the Christ_: for gold, and silver, precious stones, wood, hay, stubble, whereby the doctrines are signified, are not built upon the person of Christ: and also, that false doctrines may be raised upon this foundation; yet not so as they must necessarily be damned who teach them. [Sidenote: By the plain words of Christ and his apostles.] 10. Lastly, that this article alone is needful to be inwardly believed, may be most evidently proved out of many places of holy Scripture, let who will be the interpreter. John v. 39: _Search the Scriptures; for in them ye think ye have eternal life; and they are they which testify of me._ But Christ meant the Scriptures of the Old Testament only; for the New was then not yet written. Now, there is no other testimony concerning Christ in the Old Testament, but that an eternal king was to come in such a place, that he was to be born of such parents, that he was to teach and do such things whereby, as by certain signs, he was to be known. All which testify this one thing; that Jesus who was so born, and did teach and do such things, was the Christ. Other faith then was not required to attain eternal life, besides this article, John xi. 26: _Whosoever liveth and believeth in me, shall never die._ But to believe in Jesus, as is there expressed, is the same with believing that Jesus was the Christ. He therefore that believes that, shall never die; and by consequence, that article alone is necessary to salvation. John xx. 31: _These are written, that ye might believe that Jesus is the Christ, the Son of God; and that believing, ye might have life through his name._ Wherefore he that believes thus, shall have eternal life; and therefore needs no other faith. 1 John iv. 2: _Every spirit, that confesseth that Jesus Christ is come in the flesh, is of God._ And 1 John v. 1: _Whosoever believeth that Jesus is the Christ, is born of God._ And verse 5: _Who is he that overcometh the world, but he that believeth that Jesus is the Son of God?_ If therefore there be no need to believe anything else, to the end a man may be _of God, born of God, and overcome the world_, than that Jesus is the Christ; that one article then is sufficient to salvation. Acts viii. 36-37: _See, here is water; what doth hinder me to be baptized? And Philip said, If thou believest with all thine heart, thou mayest. And he answered and said, I believe that Jesus Christ is the Son of God._ If then this article being believed with the whole heart, that is to say, with inward faith, was sufficient for baptism; it is also sufficient for salvation. Besides these places, there are innumerable others, which do clearly and expressly affirm the same thing. Nay, wheresoever we read that our Saviour commended the faith of any one, or that he said, _thy faith hath saved thee_, or that he healed any one for his faith’s sake; there the proposition believed was no other but this, _Jesus is the Christ_, either directly or consequently. [Sidenote: In this article is contained the faith of the Old Testament.] 11. But because no man can believe _Jesus to be the Christ_, who, when he knows that by Christ is understood that same king, who was promised from God by Moses and the prophets for to be the king and Saviour of the world, doth not also believe Moses and the prophets; neither can he believe these, who believes not that God is, and that _he governs the world_; it is necessary, that the faith of God and of the Old Testament be contained in this faith of the New. Seeing therefore that atheism, and the denial of the Divine Providence, were the only treason against the Divine Majesty in the kingdom of God by nature; but idolatry also in the kingdom of God by the old covenant; now in this kingdom, wherein God rules by way of a new covenant, apostacy is also added, or the renunciation of this article once received, that Jesus is the Christ. Truly other doctrines, provided they have their determination from a lawful Church, are not to be contradicted; for that is the sin of disobedience. But it hath been fully declared before, that they are not needful to be believed with an _inward faith_. [Sidenote: How faith and obedience do concur to salvation.] 12. _Faith_ and _obedience_ have divers parts in accomplishing the salvation of a Christian; for this contributes the _power_ or _capacity_, that the _act_; and either is said to justify in its kind. For Christ forgives not the sins of all men, but of the _penitent_ or the _obedient_, that is to say, the _just_. I say not the _guiltless_, but the _just_; for _justice_ is a will of obeying the laws, and may be consistent with a sinner; and with Christ, the will to obey is obedience. For not every man, but _the just shall live by faith_. _Obedience_ therefore _justifies_, because it _maketh just_; in the same manner as temperance maketh temperate, prudence prudent, chastity chaste; namely, essentially; and puts a man in such a state, as makes him capable of pardon. Again, Christ hath not promised forgiveness of sins to all just men; but only _those of them who believe him to be the Christ_. _Faith_ therefore _justifies_ in such a sense as a judge may be said to _justify_, who _absolves_, namely, by the _sentence_ which _actually_ saves a man; and in this acception of justification (for it is an equivocal term) _faith alone_ justifies; but in the other, _obedience only_. But neither obedience alone, nor faith alone, do _save_ us; but both together. [Sidenote: In a Christian city there is no contrariety between the command of God, and of the city.] 13. By what hath been said hitherto, it will be easy to discern what the duty of Christian subjects is towards their sovereigns; who, as long as they profess themselves Christians, cannot command their subjects to deny Christ, or to offer him any contumely: for if they should command this, they would profess themselves to be no Christians. For seeing we have showed, both by natural reason and out of holy Scriptures, that subjects ought in all things to obey their princes and governors, excepting those which are contrary to the command of God; and that the commands of God, in a Christian city, concerning _temporal affairs_, that is to say, those which are to be discussed by human reason, are the laws and sentence of the city, delivered from those who have received authority from the city to make laws and judge of controversies; but concerning spiritual matters, that is to say, those which are to be defined by the holy Scripture, are the laws and sentences of the city, that is to say, the Church, (for a Christian city and a Church, as hath been showed in the foregoing chapter, art. 10, are the same thing), delivered by pastors lawfully ordained, and who have to that end authority given them by the city; it manifestly follows, that in a Christian commonweal obedience is due to the sovereign in all things, as well _spiritual_ as _temporal_. And that the same obedience, even from a Christian subject, is due in all _temporal matters_ to those princes who are no Christians, is without any controversy; but in _matters spiritual_, that is to say, those things which concern God’s worship, some Christian Church is to be followed. For it is an hypothesis of the Christian faith, that God speaks not in things supernatural but by the way of Christian interpreters of holy Scriptures. But what? Must we resist princes, when we cannot obey them? Truly, no; for this is contrary to our civil covenant. What must we do then? Go to Christ by martyrdom; which if it seem to any man to be a hard saying, most certain it is that he believes not with his whole heart, _that Jesus is the Christ, the Son of the living God_; for he would then desire to be dissolved, and to be with Christ; but he would by a feigned Christian faith elude that obedience, which he hath contracted to yield unto the city. [Sidenote: The doctrines which this day are controverted about religion, do for the most part belong to the right of dominion.] 14. But some men perhaps will wonder, if (excepting this one article, that Jesus is the Christ, which only is necessary to salvation in relation to internal faith) all the rest belong to obedience; which may be performed, although a man do not inwardly believe, so he do but desire to believe, and make an outward profession, as oft as need requires, of whatsoever is propounded by the Church; how it comes about that there are so many tenets, which are all held so to concern our faith, that except a man do inwardly believe them, he cannot enter into the kingdom of heaven. But if he consider that, in most controversies, the contention is about human sovereignty; in some, matter of gain and profit; in others, the glory of wits: he will surely wonder the less. The question about _the propriety of the Church_, is a question about the _right of sovereignty_. For it being known what a _Church_ is, it is known at once to whom the rule over Christians doth belong. For if every Christian city be that Church, which Christ himself hath commanded every Christian, subject to that city, to hear; then every subject is bound to obey his city, that is to say, him or them who have the supreme power, not only in _temporal_, but also in _spiritual matters_. But if every Christian city be not that Church, then is there some other Church more universal, which must be obeyed. All Christians therefore must obey that Church, just as they would obey Christ, if he came upon earth. It will therefore rule either by the way of monarchy, or by some assembly. This question then concerns the _right of ruling_. To the same end belongs the question concerning _infallibility_. For whosoever were truly and internally believed by all mankind, that he could not err, would be sure of all dominion, as well _temporal_ as _spiritual_, over all mankind, unless himself would refuse it. For if he say that he must be obeyed in _temporals_, because it is supposed he cannot err, that right of dominion is immediately granted him. Hither also tends the privilege of interpreting Scriptures. For he to whom it belongs to interpret the controversies arising from the divers interpretations of Scriptures, hath authority also simply and absolutely to determine all manner of controversies whatsoever. But he who hath this, hath also the command over all men who acknowledge the Scriptures to be the word of God. To this end drive all the disputes about _the power of remitting and retaining sins_; or _the authority of excommunication_. For every man, if he be in his wits, will in all things yield that man an absolute obedience, by virtue of whose sentence he believes himself to be either saved or damned. Hither also tends the power of _instituting societies_. For they depend on him by whom they subsist, who hath as many subjects as monks, although living in an enemy’s city. To this end also refers the question concerning the _judge of lawful matrimony_. For he to whom that judicature belongs, to him also pertains the knowledge of all those cases which concern the inheritance and succession of all the goods and rights, not of private men only, but also of sovereign princes. And hither also in some respect tends the _virgin life of ecclesiastical persons_; for unmarried men have less coherence than others with civil society. And besides, it is an inconvenience not to be slighted, that princes must either necessarily forego the priesthood, which is a great bond of civil obedience; or have no hereditary kingdom. To this end also tends the _canonization of saints_, which the heathen called _apotheosis_. For he that can allure foreign subjects with so great a reward, may bring those who are greedy of such glory, to dare and do anything. For what was it but an honourable name with posterity, which the Decii and other Romans sought after; and a thousand others, who cast themselves upon incredible perils? The controversies about _purgatory_, and _indulgences_, are matter of gain. The questions of _free-will_, _justification_, and _the manner of receiving Christ in the sacrament_, are philosophical. There are also questions concerning some rites not introduced, but left in the Church not sufficiently purged from Gentilism. But we need reckon no more. All the world knows that such is the nature of men, that dissenting in questions which concern their _power_, or _profit_, or _pre-eminence of wit_, they slander and curse each other. It is not therefore to be wondered at, if almost all tenets, after men grew hot with disputings, are held forth by some or other to be _necessary_ to salvation and for our entrance into the kingdom of heaven. Insomuch as they who hold them not, are not only condemned as guilty of disobedience; which in truth they are, after the Church hath once defined them; but of infidelity: which I have declared above to be wrong, out of many evident places of Scripture. To which I add this one of Saint Paul’s (Rom. xiv. 3, 5): _Let not him that eateth, despise him that eateth not, and let not him that eateth not, judge him that eateth; for God hath received him. One man esteemeth one day above another, another esteemeth every day alike. Let every man be fully persuaded in his own mind._ END OF VOL. II. ------------------------------------------------------------------------ Transcriber’s Note In the summary of Chapter XIII, the last article is misnumbered as ‘13’, rather than ‘17.’ On p. 221, a reference to article 13 in Chapter V almost certainly should have been to the 12th article of that chapter. Other errors deemed most likely to be the printer’s have been corrected, and are noted here. The references are to the page and line in the original. 3.1 ζῶον πολιτικ[ο/ό]ν Replaced. 5.5 that same [ἐυ/εὐ]δοκιμεῖν Replaced. 56.14 Prov. xxii. 10[)]: Removed. 99.31 For being e[r/l]ected, the people is at once Replaced. dissolved 102.20 make him a mona[a/r]ch Replaced. 106.31 have obliged themsel[u/v]es Replaced. 147.5 the will of God[.] Added. 196.3 The defin[in]ition of sin. Removed. 196.32 to which th[a/e]y have given Replaced. 197.28 ἀδ[ι/ί]κημα Stress added. 228.3 concern[-/ing] the commands Added. 238.20 that is[ to] say Added. 272.25 _the word[ of] faith_ Added. 283.34 (verse 2[2/3]) Replaced. 285.7 and their[’]s who repent not Removed. 312.8 in the Old Test[i/a]ment Replaced. 316.31 the rule over Christ[ai/ia]ns Transposed. *** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE ENGLISH WORKS OF THOMAS HOBBES, VOLUME 2 (OF 5) *** Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will be renamed. Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S. copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following the terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use of the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research. Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution. START: FULL LICENSE THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at www.gutenberg.org/license. Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™ electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8. 1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below. 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in the United States and you are located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without charge with others. 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any country other than the United States. 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg: 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™ work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed: This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United States, you will have to check the laws of the country where you are located before using this eBook. 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9. 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work. 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg™. 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project Gutenberg™ License. 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary, compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1. 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying, performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9. 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works provided that: • You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation.” • You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™ License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg™ works. • You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of receipt of the work. • You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works. 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below. 1.F. 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment. 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE. 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem. 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE. 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions. 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause. Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg™ Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from people in all walks of life. Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at www.gutenberg.org. Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws. The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS. The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate. While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who approach us with offers to donate. International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff. Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate. Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg™ electronic works Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support. Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition. Most people start at our website which has the main PG search facility: www.gutenberg.org. This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™, including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.