The principles of science : a treatise on logic and scientific method

By Jevons

The Project Gutenberg eBook of The principles of science
    
This ebook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and
most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions
whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms
of the Project Gutenberg License included with this ebook or online
at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United States,
you will have to check the laws of the country where you are located
before using this eBook.

Title: The principles of science
        a treatise on logic and scientific method

Author: William Stanley Jevons

Release date: December 9, 2024 [eBook #74864]

Language: English

Original publication: London: Macmillan and Co

Credits: Thiers Halliwell, Peter Becker and the Online Distributed Proofreading Team at https://www.pgdp.net (This file was produced from images generously made available by The Internet Archive)


*** START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE PRINCIPLES OF SCIENCE ***

Transcriber’s notes:

The text of this book has been preserved as closely as practicable
to its original form. However, the author used some unusual symbols,
and I have taken the liberty of using Unicode characters with similar
appearance (ꖌ ᔕ) as substitutes, disregarding their official meaning
and aware that they might not display on all devices. An archaic symbol
used by the author to indicate the mathematical ‘factorial’ function
has been replaced by the modern equivalent, viz. ! Unusual placements
of various sub- and superscripted symbols remain as in the original text.

In this plain-text version, italic text is denoted by *asterisks*;
superscripted and subscripted characters are enclosed within {curly}
brackets preceded by a caret (^) or underline (_) respectively.

Inconsistencies of punctuation have been corrected silently, but
inconsistent spellings such as *Roemer, Römer, Rœmer* have not been
altered. A list of corrected spellings is appended at the end of the
book.

Footnotes have been renumbered consecutively and positioned below the
relevant paragraphs. A missing footnote marker has been inserted on
p.751 after tracking down the original document. A missing negative
symbol has been added to an exponent in a formula on p.327.

There is a misleading calculation on p.194 and the table that follows,
regarding progressive powers of two: ((2^{2})^{2})^{2} is equivalent to
(16)^{2} which equals 256 not 65,356 as stated, but 2^{16} does equal
65,356.

[sic] has been inserted on p.179 alongside a statement that the
alphabet contains 24 letters; however, the statement may well be
correct given that it was written in 1704 by a Flemish author and the
language is not specified.

A large arithmetic triangle on p.184 cannot be displayed optimally in
this plain-text version for lack of space




THE PRINCIPLES OF SCIENCE.

[Illustration]

[Illustration: THE LOGICAL MACHINE.]



                      THE PRINCIPLES OF SCIENCE:

                         *A TREATISE ON LOGIC*

                                 *AND*

                         *SCIENTIFIC METHOD.*


                                  BY

                          W. STANLEY JEVONS,

                 LL.D. (EDINB.), M.A. (LOND.), F.R.S.


                                London:

                           MACMILLAN AND CO.
                                 1883.


       *The Right of Translation and Reproduction is Reserved.*



  LONDON:
  R. Clay, Sons, & Taylor, Printers,
  BREAD STREET HILL.


  Stereotyped Edition.




PREFACE

*TO THE FIRST EDITION*.


It may be truly asserted that the rapid progress of the physical
sciences during the last three centuries has not been accompanied by
a corresponding advance in the theory of reasoning. Physicists speak
familiarly of Scientific Method, but they could not readily describe
what they mean by that expression. Profoundly engaged in the study
of particular classes of natural phenomena, they are usually too
much engrossed in the immense and ever-accumulating details of their
special sciences to generalise upon the methods of reasoning which they
unconsciously employ. Yet few will deny that these methods of reasoning
ought to be studied, especially by those who endeavour to introduce
scientific order into less successful and methodical branches of
knowledge.

The application of Scientific Method cannot be restricted to the sphere
of lifeless objects. We must sooner or later have strict sciences of
those mental and social phenomena, which, if comparison be possible,
are of more interest to us than purely material phenomena. But it
is the proper course of reasoning to proceed from the known to the
unknown--from the evident to the obscure--from the material and
palpable to the subtle and refined. The physical sciences may therefore
be properly made the practice-ground of the reasoning powers,
because they furnish us with a great body-of precise and successful
investigations. In these sciences we meet with happy instances of
unquestionable deductive reasoning, of extensive generalisation, of
happy prediction, of satisfactory verification, of nice calculation of
probabilities. We can note how the slightest analogical clue has been
followed up to a glorious discovery, how a rash generalisation has at
length been exposed, or a conclusive *experimentum crucis* has decided
the long-continued strife between two rival theories.

In following out my design of detecting the general methods of
inductive investigation, I have found that the more elaborate and
interesting processes of quantitative induction have their necessary
foundation in the simpler science of Formal Logic. The earlier, and
probably by far the least attractive part of this work, consists,
therefore, in a statement of the so-called Fundamental Laws of
Thought, and of the all-important Principle of Substitution, of which,
as I think, all reasoning is a development. The whole procedure of
inductive inquiry, in its most complex cases, is foreshadowed in
the combinational view of Logic, which arises directly from these
fundamental principles. Incidentally I have described the mechanical
arrangements by which the use of the important form called the Logical
Alphabet, and the whole working of the combinational system of Formal
Logic, may be rendered evident to the eye, and easy to the mind and
hand.

The study both of Formal Logic and of the Theory of Probabilities has
led me to adopt the opinion that there is no such thing as a distinct
method of induction as contrasted with deduction, but that induction
is simply an inverse employment of deduction. Within the last century
a reaction has been setting in against the purely empirical procedure
of Francis Bacon, and physicists have learnt to advocate the use of
hypotheses. I take the extreme view of holding that Francis Bacon,
although he correctly insisted upon constant reference to experience,
had no correct notions as to the logical method by which from
particular facts we educe laws of nature. I endeavour to show that
hypothetical anticipation of nature is an essential part of inductive
inquiry, and that it is the Newtonian method of deductive reasoning
combined with elaborate experimental verification, which has led to all
the great triumphs of scientific research.

In attempting to give an explanation of this view of Scientific Method,
I have first to show that the sciences of number and quantity repose
upon and spring from the simpler and more general science of Logic.
The Theory of Probability, which enables us to estimate and calculate
quantities of knowledge, is then described, and especial attention
is drawn to the Inverse Method of Probabilities, which involves, as
I conceive, the true principle of inductive procedure. No inductive
conclusions are more than probable, and I adopt the opinion that the
theory of probability is an essential part of logical method, so
that the logical value of every inductive result must be determined
consciously or unconsciously, according to the principles of the
inverse method of probability.

The phenomena of nature are commonly manifested in quantities of
time, space, force, energy, &c., and the observation, measurement,
and analysis of the various quantitative conditions or results
involved, even in a simple experiment, demand much employment of
systematic procedure. I devote a book, therefore, to a simple and
general description of the devices by which exact measurement is
effected, errors eliminated, a probable mean result attained, and
the probable error of that mean ascertained. I then proceed to the
principal, and probably the most interesting, subject of the book,
illustrating successively the conditions and precautions requisite
for accurate observation, for successful experiment, and for the sure
detection of the quantitative laws of nature. As it is impossible to
comprehend aright the value of quantitative laws without constantly
bearing in mind the degree of quantitative approximation to the truth
probably attained, I have devoted a special chapter to the Theory of
Approximation, and however imperfectly I may have treated this subject,
I must look upon it as a very essential part of a work on Scientific
Method.

It then remains to illustrate the sound use of hypothesis, to
distinguish between the portions of knowledge which we owe to empirical
observation, to accidental discovery, or to scientific prediction.
Interesting questions arise concerning the accordance of quantitative
theories and experiments, and I point out how the successive
verification of an hypothesis by distinct methods of experiment yields
conclusions approximating to but never attaining certainty. Additional
illustrations of the general procedure of inductive investigations are
given in a chapter on the Character of the Experimentalist, in which
I endeavour to show, moreover, that the inverse use of deduction was
really the logical method of such great masters of experimental inquiry
as Newton, Huyghens, and Faraday.

In treating Generalisation and Analogy, I consider the precautions
requisite in inferring from one case to another, or from one part of
the universe to another part; the validity of all such inferences
resting ultimately upon the inverse method of probabilities. The
treatment of Exceptional Phenomena appeared to afford an interesting
subject for a further chapter illustrating the various modes in which
an outstanding fact may eventually be explained. The formal part of
the book closes with the subject of Classification, which is, however,
very inadequately treated. I have, in fact, almost restricted myself to
showing that all classification is fundamentally carried out upon the
principles of Formal Logic and the Logical Alphabet described at the
outset.

In certain concluding remarks I have expressed the conviction which
the study of Logic has by degrees forced upon my mind, that serious
misconceptions are entertained by some scientific men as to the
logical value of our knowledge of nature. We have heard much of
what has been aptly called the Reign of Law, and the necessity and
uniformity of natural forces has been not uncommonly interpreted as
involving the non-existence of an intelligent and benevolent Power,
capable of interfering with the course of natural events. Fears have
been expressed that the progress of Scientific Method must therefore
result in dissipating the fondest beliefs of the human heart. Even
the ‘Utility of Religion’ is seriously proposed as a subject of
discussion. It seemed to be not out of place in a work on Scientific
Method to allude to the ultimate results and limits of that method. I
fear that I have very imperfectly succeeded in expressing my strong
conviction that before a rigorous logical scrutiny the Reign of Law
will prove to be an unverified hypothesis, the Uniformity of Nature an
ambiguous expression, the certainty of our scientific inferences to a
great extent a delusion. The value of science is of course very high,
while the conclusions are kept well within the limits of the data on
which they are founded, but it is pointed out that our experience is
of the most limited character compared with what there is to learn,
while our mental powers seem to fall infinitely short of the task of
comprehending and explaining fully the nature of any one object. I
draw the conclusion that we must interpret the results of Scientific
Method in an affirmative sense only. Ours must be a truly positive
philosophy, not that false negative philosophy which, building on a few
material facts, presumes to assert that it has compassed the bounds
of existence, while it nevertheless ignores the most unquestionable
phenomena of the human mind and feelings.

It is approximately certain that in freely employing illustrations
drawn from many different sciences, I have frequently fallen into
errors of detail. In this respect I must throw myself upon the
indulgence of the reader, who will bear in mind, as I hope, that the
scientific facts are generally mentioned purely for the purpose of
illustration, so that inaccuracies of detail will not in the majority
of cases affect the truth of the general principles illustrated.

  *December 15, 1873.*




PREFACE

*TO THE SECOND EDITION*.


Few alterations of importance have been made in preparing this second
edition. Nevertheless, advantage has been taken of the opportunity to
revise very carefully both the language and the matter of the book.
Correspondents and critics having pointed out inaccuracies of more
or less importance in the first edition, suitable corrections and
emendations have been made. I am under obligations to Mr. C. J. Monro,
M.A., of Barnet, and to Mr. W. H. Brewer, M.A., one of Her Majesty’s
Inspectors of Schools, for numerous corrections.

Among several additions which have been made to the text, I may mention
the abstract (p. 143) of Professor Clifford’s remarkable investigation
into the number of types of compound statement involving four classes
of objects. This inquiry carries forward the inverse logical problem
described in the preceding sections. Again, the need of some better
logical method than the old Barbara Celarent, &c., is strikingly shown
by Mr. Venn’s logical problem, described at p. 90. A great number
of candidates in logic and philosophy were tested by Mr. Venn with
this problem, which, though simple in reality, was solved by very few
of those who were ignorant of Boole’s Logic. Other evidence could
be adduced by Mr. Venn of the need for some better means of logical
training. To enable the logical student to test his skill in the
solution of inductive logical problems, I have given (p. 127) a series
of ten problems graduated in difficulty.

To prevent misapprehension, it should be mentioned that, throughout
this edition, I have substituted the name *Logical Alphabet* for
*Logical Abecedarium*, the name applied in the first edition to the
exhaustive series of logical combinations represented in terms of
*A*, *B*, *C*, *D* (p. 94). It was objected by some readers that
*Abecedarium* is a long and unfamiliar name.

To the chapter on Units and Standards of Measurement, I have added two
sections, one (p. 325) containing a brief statement of the Theory of
Dimensions, and the other (p. 319) discussing Professor Clerk Maxwell’s
very original suggestion of a Natural System of Standards for the
measurement of space and time, depending upon the length and rapidity
of waves of light.

In my description of the Logical Machine in the *Philosophical
Transactions* (vol. 160, p. 498), I said--“It is rarely indeed that
any invention is made without some anticipation being sooner or later
discovered; but up to the present time I am totally unaware of even
a single previous attempt to devise or construct a machine which
should perform the operations of logical inference; and it is only,
I believe, in the satirical writings of Swift that an allusion to an
actual reasoning machine is to be found.” Before the paper was printed,
however, I was able to refer (p. 518) to the ingenious designs of the
late Mr. Alfred Smee as attempts to represent thought mechanically. Mr.
Smee’s machines indeed were never constructed, and, if constructed,
would not have performed actual logical inference. It has now just
come to light, however, that the celebrated Lord Stanhope actually did
construct a mechanical device, capable of representing syllogistic
inferences in a concrete form. It appears that logic was one of the
favourite studies of this truly original and ingenious nobleman. There
remain fragments of a logical work, printed by the Earl at his own
press, which show that he had arrived, before the year 1800, at the
principle of the quantified predicate. He puts forward this principle
in the most explicit manner, and proposes to employ it throughout his
syllogistic system. Moreover, he converts negative propositions into
affirmative ones, and represents these by means of the copula “is
identic with.” Thus he anticipated, probably by the force of his own
unaided insight, the main points of the logical method originated in
the works of George Bentham and George Boole, and developed in this
work. Stanhope, indeed, has no claim to priority of discovery, because
he seems never to have published his logical writings, although they
were put into print. There is no trace of them in the British Museum
Library, nor in any other library or logical work, so far as I am
aware. Both the papers and the logical contrivance have been placed
by the present Earl Stanhope in the hands of the Rev. Robert Harley,
F.R.S., who will, I hope, soon publish a description of them.[1]

  [1] Since the above was written Mr. Harley has read an account of
  Stanhope’s logical remains at the Dublin Meeting (1878) of the
  British Association. The paper will be printed in *Mind*. (Note added
  November, 1878.)

By the kindness of Mr. Harley, I have been able to examine Stanhope’s
logical contrivance, called by him the Demonstrator. It consists of a
square piece of bay-wood with a square depression in the centre, across
which two slides can be pushed, one being a piece of red glass, and
the other consisting of wood coloured gray. The extent to which each
of these slides is pushed in is indicated by scales and figures along
the edges of the aperture, and the simple rule of inference adopted
by Stanhope is: “To the gray add the red and subtract the *holon*,”
meaning by holon (ὅλον) the whole width of the aperture. This rule
of inference is a curious anticipation of De Morgan’s numerically
definite syllogism (see below, p. 168), and of inferences founded on
what Hamilton called “Ultra-total distribution.” Another curious point
about Stanhope’s device is, that one slide can be drawn out and pushed
in again at right angles to the other, and the overlapping part of the
slides then represents the probability of a conclusion, derived from
two premises of which the probabilities are respectively represented
by the projecting parts of the slides. Thus it appears that Stanhope
had studied the logic of probability as well as that of certainty, here
again anticipating, however obscurely, the recent progress of logical
science. It will be seen, however, that between Stanhope’s Demonstrator
and my Logical Machine there is no resemblance beyond the fact that
they both perform logical inference.

In the first edition I inserted a section (vol. i. p. 25), on
“Anticipations of the Principle of Substitution,” and I have reprinted
that section unchanged in this edition (p. 21). I remark therein that,
“In such a subject as logic it is hardly possible to put forth any
opinions which have not been in some degree previously entertained. The
germ at least of every doctrine will be found in earlier writings, and
novelty must arise chiefly in the mode of harmonising and developing
ideas.” I point out, as Professor T. M. Lindsay had previously done,
that Beneke had employed the name and principle of substitution, and
that doctrines closely approximating to substitution were stated by the
Port Royal Logicians more than 200 years ago.

I have not been at all surprised to learn, however, that other
logicians have more or less distinctly stated this principle of
substitution during the last two centuries. As my friend and successor
at Owens College, Professor Adamson, has discovered, this principle can
be traced back to no less a philosopher than Leibnitz.

The remarkable tract of Leibnitz,[2] entitled “Non inelegans Specimen
Demonstrandi in Abstractis,” commences at once with a definition
corresponding to the principle:--

“Eadem sunt quorum unum potest substitui alteri salva veritate. Si sint
*A* et *B*, et *A* ingrediatur aliquam propositionem veram, et ibi in
aliquo loco ipsius *A* pro ipso substituendo *B* fiat nova propositio
æque itidem vera, idque semper succedat in quacunque tali propositione,
*A* et *B* dicuntur esse eadem; et contra, si eadem sint *A* et *B*,
procedet substitutio quam dixi.”

  [2] Leibnitii *Opera Philosophica quæ extant*. Erdmann, Pars I.
  Berolini, 1840, p. 94.

Leibnitz, then, explicitly adopts the principle of substitution, but
he puts it in the form of a definition, saying that those things are
the same which can be substituted one for the other, without affecting
the truth of the proposition. It is only after having thus tested
the sameness of things that we can turn round and say that *A* and
*B*, being the same, may be substituted one for the other. It would
seem as if we were here in a vicious circle; for we are not allowed
to substitute *A* for *B*, unless we have ascertained by trial that
the result is a true proposition. The difficulty does not seem to be
removed by Leibnitz’ proviso, “idque semper succedat in quacunque
tali propositione.” How can we learn that because *A* and *B* may
be mutually substituted in some propositions, they may therefore
be substituted in others; and what is the criterion of likeness of
propositions expressed in the word “tali”? Whether the principle
of substitution is to be regarded as a postulate, an axiom, or a
definition, is just one of those fundamental questions which it seems
impossible to settle in the present position of philosophy, but this
uncertainty will not prevent our making a considerable step in logical
science.

Leibnitz proceeds to establish in the form of a theorem what is
usually taken as an axiom, thus (*Opera*, p. 95): “Theorema I. Quæ
sunt eadem uni tertio, eadem sunt inter se. Si *A* ∝ *B* et *B* ∝ *C*,
erit *A* ∝ *C*. Nam si in propositione *A* ∝ *B* (vera ea hypothesi)
substituitur *C* in locum *B* (quod facere licet per Def. I. quia *B* ∝
*C* ex hypothesi) fiet *A* ∝ *C*. Q. E. Dem.” Thus Leibnitz precisely
anticipates the mode of treating inference with two simple identities
described at p. 51 of this work.

Even the mathematical axiom that ‘equals added to equals make equals,’
is deduced from the principle of substitution. At p. 95 of Erdmann’s
edition, we find: “Si eidem addantur coincidentia fiunt coincidentia.
Si *A* ∝ *B*, erit *A* + *C* ∝ *B* + *C*. Nam si in propositione *A*
+ *C* ∝ *A* + *C* (quæ est vera per se) pro *A* semel substituas *B*
(quod facere licet per Def. I. quia *A* ∝ *B*) fiet *A* + *C* ∝ *B* +
*C* Q. E. Dem.” This is unquestionably the mode of deducing the several
axioms of mathematical reasoning from the higher axiom of substitution,
which is explained in the section on mathematical inference (p. 162) in
this work, and which had been previously stated in my *Substitution of
Similars*, p. 16.

There are one or two other brief tracts in which Leibnitz anticipates
the modern views of logic. Thus in the eighteenth tract in Erdmann’s
edition (p. 92), called “Fundamenta Calculi Ratiocinatoris”, he says:
“Inter ea quorum unum alteri substitui potest, salvis calculi legibus,
dicetur esse æquipollentiam.” There is evidence, also, that he had
arrived at the quantification of the predicate, and that he fully
understood the reduction of the universal affirmative proposition to
the form of an equation, which is the key to an improved view of logic.
Thus, in the tract entitled “Difficultates Quædam Logicæ,”[3] he says:
“Omne *A* est *B*; id est æquivalent *AB* et *A*, seu *A* non *B* est
non-ens.”

  [3] Erdmann, p. 102.

It is curious to find, too, that Leibnitz was fully acquainted with the
Laws of Commutativeness and “Simplicity” (as I have called the second
law) attaching to logical symbols. In the “Addenda ad Specimen Calculi
Universalis” we read as follows.[4] “Transpositio literarum in eodem
termino nihil mutat, ut *ab* coincidet cum *ba*, seu animal rationale
et rationale animal.”

“Repetitio ejusdem literæ in eodem termino est inutilis, ut *b* est
*aa*; vel *bb* est *a*; homo est animal animal, vel homo homo est
animal. Sufficit enim dici *a* est *b*, seu homo est animal.”

  [4] Ibid. p. 98.

Comparing this with what is stated in Boole’s *Mathematical Analysis of
Logic*, pp. 17–18, in his *Laws of Thought*, p. 29, or in this work,
pp. 32–35, we find that Leibnitz had arrived two centuries ago at a
clear perception of the bases of logical notation. When Boole pointed
out that, in logic, *xx* = *x*, this seemed to mathematicians to be a
paradox, or in any case a wholly new discovery; but here we have it
plainly stated by Leibnitz.

The reader must not assume, however, that because Leibnitz correctly
apprehended the fundamental principles of logic, he left nothing for
modern logicians to do. On the contrary, Leibnitz obtained no useful
results from his definition of substitution. When he proceeds to
explain the syllogism, as in the paper on “Definitiones Logicæ,”[5]
he gives up substitution altogether, and falls back upon the notion
of inclusion of class in class, saying, “Includens includentis est
includens inclusi, seu si *A* includit *B* et *B* includit *C*, etiam
*A* includet *C*.” He proceeds to make out certain rules of the
syllogism involving the distinction of subject and predicate, and
in no important respect better than the old rules of the syllogism.
Leibnitz’ logical tracts are, in fact, little more than brief memoranda
of investigations which seem never to have been followed out. They
remain as evidence of his wonderful sagacity, but it would be difficult
to show that they have had any influence on the progress of logical
science in recent times.

  [5] Erdmann, p. 100.

I should like to explain how it happened that these logical writings
of Leibnitz were unknown to me, until within the last twelve months. I
am so slow a reader of Latin books, indeed, that my overlooking a few
pages of Leibnitz’ works would not have been in any case surprising.
But the fact is that the copy of Leibnitz’ works of which I made
occasional use, was one of the edition of Dutens, contained in Owens
College Library. The logical tracts in question were not printed in
that edition, and with one exception, they remained in manuscript in
the Royal Library at Hanover, until edited by Erdmann, in 1839–40.
The tract “Difficultates Quædam Logicæ,” though not known to Dutens,
was published by Raspe in 1765, in his collection called *Œuvres
Philosophiques de feu M^{r.} Leibnitz*; but this work had not come to
my notice, nor does the tract in question seem to contain any explicit
statement of the principle of substitution.

It is, I presume, the comparatively recent publication of Leibnitz’
most remarkable logical tracts which explains the apparent ignorance of
logicians as regards their contents and importance. The most learned
logicians, such as Hamilton and Ueberweg, ignore Leibnitz’ principle
of substitution. In the Appendix to the fourth volume of Hamilton’s
*Lectures on Metaphysics and Logic*, is given an elaborate compendium
of the views of logical writers concerning the ultimate basis of
deductive reasoning. Leibnitz is briefly noticed on p. 319, but without
any hint of substitution. He is here quoted as saying, “What are the
same with the same third, are the same with each other; that is, if *A*
be the same with *B*, and *C* be the same with *B*, it is necessary
that *A* and *C* should also be the same with one another. For this
principle flows immediately from the principle of contradiction, and is
the ground and basis of all logic; if that fail, there is no longer any
way of reasoning with certainty.” This view of the matter seems to be
inconsistent with that which he adopted in his posthumous tract.

Dr. Thomson, indeed, was acquainted with Leibnitz’ tracts, and refers
to them in his *Outline of the Necessary Laws of Thought*. He calls
them valuable; nevertheless, he seems to have missed the really
valuable point; for in making two brief quotations,[6] he omits all
mention of the principle of substitution.

  [6] Fifth Edition, 1860, p. 158.

Ueberweg is probably considered the best authority concerning the
history of logic, and in his well-known *System of Logic and History
of Logical Doctrines*,[7] he gives some account of the principle of
substitution, especially as it is implicitly stated in the *Port Royal
Logic*. But he omits all reference to Leibnitz in this connection,
nor does he elsewhere, so far as I can find, supply the omission.
His English editor, Professor T. M. Lindsay, in referring to my
*Substitution of Similars*, points out how I was anticipated by Beneke;
but he also ignores Leibnitz. It is thus apparent that the most learned
logicians, even when writing especially on the history of logic,
displayed ignorance of Leibnitz’ most valuable logical writings.

  [7] Section 120.

It has been recently pointed out to me, however, that the Rev. Robert
Harley did draw attention, at the Nottingham Meeting of the British
Association, in 1866, to Leibnitz’ anticipations of Boole’s laws of
logical notation,[8] and I am informed that Boole, about a year after
the publication of his *Laws of Thought*, was made acquainted with
these anticipations by R. Leslie Ellis.

  [8] See his “Remarks on Boole’s Mathematical Analysis of Logic.”
  *Report of the 36th Meeting of the British Association, Transactions
  of the Sections*, pp. 3–6.

There seems to have been at least one other German logician who
discovered, or adopted, the principle of substitution. Reusch, in his
*Systema Logicum*, published in 1734, laboured to give a broader basis
to the *Dictum de Omni et Nullo*. He argues, that “the whole business
of ordinary reasoning is accomplished by the substitution of ideas in
place of the subject or predicate of the fundamental proposition. This
some call the *equation of thoughts*.” But, in the hands of Reusch,
substitution does not seem to lead to simplicity, since it has to be
carried on according to the rules of Equipollence, Reciprocation,
Subordination, and Co-ordination.[9] Reusch is elsewhere spoken of[10]
as the “celebrated Reusch”; nevertheless, I have not been able to find
a copy of his book in London, even in the British Museum Library; it is
not mentioned in the printed catalogue of the Bodleian Library; Messrs.
Asher have failed to obtain it for me by advertisement in Germany; and
Professor Adamson has been equally unsuccessful. From the way in which
the principle of substitution is mentioned by Reusch, it would seem
likely that other logicians of the early part of the eighteenth century
were acquainted with it; but, if so, it is still more curious that
recent historians of logical science have overlooked the doctrine.

  [9] Hamilton’s Lectures, vol. iv. p. 319.

  [10] Ibid. p. 326.

It is a strange and discouraging fact, that true views of logic should
have been discovered and discussed from one to two centuries ago, and
yet should have remained, like George Bentham’s work in this century,
without influence on the subsequent progress of the science. It may be
regarded as certain that none of the discoverers of the quantification
of the predicate, Bentham, Hamilton, Thomson, De Morgan, and Boole,
were in any way assisted by the hints of the principle contained in
previous writers. As to my own views of logic, they were originally
moulded by a careful study of Boole’s works, as fully stated in my
first logical essay.[11] As to the process of substitution, it was
not learnt from any work on logic, but is simply the process of
substitution perfectly familiar to mathematicians, and with which I
necessarily became familiar in the course of my long-continued study of
mathematics under the late Professor De Morgan.

  [11] *Pure Logic, or the Logic of Quality apart from Quantity;
  with Remarks on Boole’s System, and on the Relation of Logic and
  Mathematics.* London, 1864, p. 3.

I find that the Theory of Number, which I explained in the eighth
chapter of this work, is also partially anticipated in a single
scholium of Leibnitz. He first gives as an axiom the now well-known law
of Boole, as follows:--

“Axioma I. Si idem secum ipso sumatur, nihil constituitur novum, seu
*A* + *A* ∝ *A*.” Then follows this remarkable scholium: “Equidem in
numeris 4 + 4 facit 8, seu bini nummi binis additi faciunt quatuor
nummos, sed tunc bini additi sunt alii a prioribus; si iidem essent
nihil novi prodiret et perinde esset ac si joco ex tribus ovis facere
vellemus sex numerando, primum 3 ova, deinde uno sublato residua 2, ac
denique uno rursus sublato residuum.”

Translated this would read as follows:--

“Axiom I. If the same thing is taken together with itself, nothing new
arises, or *A* + *A* = *A*.

“Scholium. In numbers, indeed, 4 + 4 makes 8, or two coins added to two
coins make four coins, but then the two added are different from the
former ones; if they were the same nothing new would be produced, and
it would be just as if we tried in joke to make six eggs out of three,
by counting firstly the three eggs, then, one being removed, counting
the remaining two, and lastly, one being again removed, counting the
remaining egg.”

Compare the above with pp. 156 to 162 of the present work.

M. Littré has quite recently pointed out[12] what he thinks is an
analogy between the system of formal logic, stated in the following
pages, and the logical devices of the celebrated Raymond Lully. Lully’s
method of invention was described in a great number of mediæval books,
but is best stated in his *Ars Compendiosa Inveniendi Veritatem, seu
Ars Magna et Major*. This method consisted in placing various names
of things in the sectors of concentric circles, so that when the
circles were turned, every possible combination of the things was
easily produced by mechanical means. It might, perhaps, be possible to
discover in this method a vague and rude anticipation of combinational
logic; but it is well known that the results of Lully’s method were
usually of a fanciful, if not absurd character.

  [12] *La Philosophie Positive*, Mai-Juin, 1877, tom. xviii. p. 456.

A much closer analogue of the Logical Alphabet is probably to be found
in the Logical Square, invented by John Christian Lange, and described
in a rare and unnoticed work by him which I have recently found in the
British Museum.[13] This square involved the principle of bifurcate
classification, and was an improved form of the Ramean and Porphyrian
tree (see below, p. 702). Lange seems, indeed, to have worked out his
Logical Square into a mechanical form, and he suggests that it might
be employed somewhat in the manner of Napier’s Bones (p. 65). There
is much analogy between his Square and my Abacus, but Lange had not
arrived at a logical system enabling him to use his invention for
logical inference in the manner of the Logical Abacus. Another work
of Lange is said to contain the first publication of the well known
Eulerian diagrams of proposition and syllogism.[14]

  [13] *Inventum Novum Quadrati Logici*, &c., Gissæ Hassorum, 1714, 8vo.

  [14] See *Ueberweg’s System of Logic*, &c., translated by Lindsay,
  p. 302.

Since the first edition was published, an important work by Mr. George
Lewes has appeared, namely, his *Problems of Life and Mind*, which
to a great extent treats of scientific method, and formulates the
rules of philosophising. I should have liked to discuss the bearing
of Mr. Lewes’s views upon those here propounded, but I have felt it
to be impossible in a book already filling nearly 800 pages, to enter
upon the discussion of a yet more extensive book. For the same reason
I have not been able to compare my own treatment of the subject of
probability with the views expressed by Mr. Venn in his *Logic of
Chance*. With Mr. J. J. Murphy’s profound and remarkable works on
*Habit and Intelligence*, and on *The Scientific Basis of Faith*, I
was unfortunately unacquainted when I wrote the following pages. They
cannot safely be overlooked by any one who wishes to comprehend the
tendency of philosophy and scientific method in the present day.

It seems desirable that I should endeavour to answer some of the
critics who have pointed out what they consider defects in the
doctrines of this book, especially in the first part, which treats
of deduction. Some of the notices of the work were indeed rather
statements of its contents than critiques. Thus, I am much indebted
to M. Louis Liard, Professor of Philosophy at Bordeaux, for the very
careful exposition[15] of the substitutional view of logic which he
gave in the excellent *Revue Philosophique*, edited by M. Ribot.
(Mars, 1877, tom. iii. p. 277.) An equally careful account of the
system was given by M. Riehl, Professor of Philosophy at Graz, in
his article on “Die Englische Logik der Gegenwart,” published in the
*Vierteljahrsschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie*. (1 Heft,
Leipzig, 1876.) I should like to acknowledge also the careful and able
manner in which my book was reviewed by the *New York Daily Tribune*
and the *New York Times*.

  [15] Since the above was written M. Liard has republished this
  exposition as one chapter of an interesting and admirably lucid
  account of the progress of logical science in England. After a brief
  but clear introduction, treating of the views of Herschel, Mill, and
  others concerning Inductive Logic, M. Liard describes in succession
  the logical systems of George Bentham, Hamilton, De Morgan, Boole,
  and that contained in the present work. The title of the book is as
  follows:--*Les Logiciens Anglais Contemporains*. Par Louis Liard,
  Professeur de Philosophie à la Faculté des Lettres de Bordeaux.
  Paris: Librairie Germer Baillière. 1878. (Note added November, 1878.)

The most serious objections which have been brought against my
treatment of logic have regard to my failure to enter into an analysis
of the ultimate nature and origin of the Laws of Thought. The
*Spectator*,[16] for instance, in the course of a careful review, says
of the principle of substitution, “Surely it is a great omission not
to discuss whence we get this great principle itself; whether it is a
pure law of the mind, or only an approximate lesson of experience; and
if a pure product of the mind, whether there are any other products
of the same kind, furnished by our knowing faculty itself.” Professor
Robertson, in his very acute review,[17] likewise objects to the want
of psychological and philosophical analysis. “If the book really
corresponded to its title, Mr. Jevons could hardly have passed so
lightly over the question, which he does not omit to raise, concerning
those undoubted principles of knowledge commonly called the Laws of
Thought.... Everywhere, indeed, he appears least at ease when he
touches on questions properly philosophical; nor is he satisfactory
in his psychological references, as on pp. 4, 5, where he cannot
commit himself to a statement without an accompaniment of ‘probably,’
‘almost,’ or ‘hardly.’ Reservations are often very much in place, but
there are fundamental questions on which it is proper to make up one’s
mind.”

  [16] *Spectator*, September 19, 1874, p. 1178. A second portion of
  the review appeared in the same journal for September 26, 1874,
  p. 1204.

  [17] *Mind*: a Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy. No. II.
  April 1876. Vol. I. p. 206.

These remarks appear to me to be well founded, and I must state why
it is that I have ventured to publish an extensive work on logic,
without properly making up my mind as to the fundamental nature of the
reasoning process. The fault after all is one of omission rather than
of commission. It is open to me on a future occasion to supply the
deficiency if I should ever feel able to undertake the task. But I do
not conceive it to be an essential part of any treatise to enter into
an ultimate analysis of its subject matter. Analyses must always end
somewhere. There were good treatises on light which described the laws
of the phenomenon correctly before it was known whether light consisted
of undulations or of projected particles. Now we have treatises on the
Undulatory Theory which are very valuable and satisfactory, although
they leave us in almost complete doubt as to what the vibrating medium
really is. So I think that, in the present day, we need a correct and
scientific exhibition of the formal laws of thought, and of the forms
of reasoning based on them, although we may not be able to enter into
any complete analysis of the nature of those laws. What would the
science of geometry be like now if the Greek geometers had decided that
it was improper to publish any propositions before they had decided
on the nature of an axiom? Where would the science of arithmetic be
now if an analysis of the nature of number itself were a necessary
preliminary to a development of the results of its laws? In recent
times there have been enormous additions to the mathematical sciences,
but very few attempts at psychological analysis. In the Alexandrian and
early mediæval schools of philosophy, much attention was given to the
nature of unity and plurality chiefly called forth by the question of
the Trinity. In the last two centuries whole sciences have been created
out of the notion of plurality, and yet speculation on the nature of
plurality has dwindled away. This present treatise contains, in the
eighth chapter, one of the few recent attempts to analyse the notion of
number itself.

If further illustration is needed, I may refer to the differential
calculus. Nobody calls in question the formal truth of the results of
that calculus. All the more exact and successful parts of physical
science depend upon its use, and yet the mathematicians who have
created so great a body of exact truths have never decided upon the
basis of the calculus. What is the nature of a limit or the nature of
an infinitesimal? Start the question among a knot of mathematicians,
and it will be found that hardly two agree, unless it is in regarding
the question itself as a trifling one. Some hold that there are no such
things as infinitesimals, and that it is all a question of limits.
Others would argue that the infinitesimal is the necessary outcome of
the limit, but various shades of intermediate opinion spring up.

Now it is just the same with logic. If the forms of deductive and
inductive reasoning given in the earlier part of this treatise are
correct, they constitute a definite addition to logical science, and
it would have been absurd to decline to publish such results because I
could not at the same time decide in my own mind about the psychology
and philosophy of the subject. It comes in short to this, that my book
is a book on Formal Logic and Scientific Method, and not a book on
psychology and philosophy.

It may be objected, indeed, as the *Spectator* objects, that Mill’s
System of Logic is particularly strong in the discussion of the
psychological foundations of reasoning, so that Mill would appear to
have successfully treated that which I feel myself to be incapable of
attempting at present. If Mill’s analysis of knowledge is correct, then
I have nothing to say in excuse for my own deficiencies. But it is
well to do one thing at a time, and therefore I have not occupied any
considerable part of this book with controversy and refutation. What I
have to say of Mill’s logic will be said in a separate work, in which
his analysis of knowledge will be somewhat minutely analysed. It will
then be shown, I believe, that Mill’s psychological and philosophical
treatment of logic has not yielded such satisfactory results as some
writers seem to believe.[18]

  [18] Portions of this work have already been published in my
  articles, entitled “John Stuart Mill’s Philosophy Tested,” printed
  in the *Contemporary Review* for December, 1877, vol. xxxi. p. 167,
  and for January and April, 1878, vol. xxxi. p. 256, and vol. xxxii.
  p. 88. (Note added in November, 1878.)

Various minor but still important criticisms were made by Professor
Robertson, a few of which have been noticed in the text (pp. 27, 101).
In other cases his objections hardly admit of any other answer than
such as consists in asking the reader to judge between the work and the
criticism. Thus Mr. Robertson asserts[19] that the most complex logical
problems solved in this book (up to p. 102 of this edition) might be
more easily and shortly dealt with upon the principles and with the
recognised methods of the traditional logic. The burden of proof here
lies upon Mr. Robertson, and his only proof consists in a single case,
where he is able, as it seems to me accidentally, to get a special
conclusion by the old form of dilemma. It would be a long labour to
test the old logic upon every result obtained by my notation, and I
must leave such readers as are well acquainted with the syllogistic
logic to pronounce upon the comparative simplicity and power of the
new and old systems. For other acute objections brought forward by Mr.
Robertson, I must refer the reader to the article in question.

  [19] *Mind*, vol. i. p. 222.

One point in my last chapter, that on the Results and Limits of
Scientific Method, has been criticised by Professor W. K. Clifford in
his lecture[20] on “The First and the Last Catastrophe.” In vol. ii.
p. 438 of the first edition (p. 744 of this edition) I referred to
certain inferences drawn by eminent physicists as to a limit to
the antiquity of the present order of things. “According to Sir W.
Thomson’s deductions from Fourier’s *theory of heat*, we can trace down
the dissipation of heat by conduction and radiation to an infinitely
distant time when all things will be uniformly cold. But we cannot
similarly trace the Heat-history of the Universe to an infinite
distance in the past. For a certain negative value of the time, the
formulæ give impossible values, indicating that there was some initial
distribution of heat which could not have resulted, according to known
laws of nature, from any previous distribution.”

  [20] *Fortnightly Review*, New Series, April 1875, p. 480. Lecture
  reprinted by the Sunday Lecture Society, p. 24.

Now according to Professor Clifford I have here misstated Thomson’s
results. “It is not according to the known laws of nature, it is
according to the known laws of conduction of heat, that Sir William
Thomson is speaking.... All these physical writers, knowing what they
were writing about, simply drew such conclusions from the facts which
were before them as could be reasonably drawn. They say, here is a
state of things which could not have been produced by the circumstances
we are at present investigating. Then your speculator comes, he reads
a sentence and says, ‘Here is an opportunity for me to have my fling.’
And he has his fling, and makes a purely baseless theory about the
necessary origin of the present order of nature at some definite point
of time, which might be calculated.”

Professor Clifford proceeds to explain that Thomson’s formulæ only give
a limit to the heat history of, say, the earth’s crust in the solid
state. We are led back to the time when it became solidified from the
fluid condition. There is discontinuity in the history of the solid
matter, but still discontinuity which is within our comprehension.
Still further back we should come to discontinuity again, when the
liquid was formed by the condensation of heated gaseous matter. Beyond
that event, however, there is no need to suppose further discontinuity
of law, for the gaseous matter might consist of molecules which had
been falling together from different parts of space through infinite
past time. As Professor Clifford says (p. 481) of the bodies of the
universe, “What they have actually done is to fall together and get
solid. If we should reverse the process we should see them separating
and getting cool, and as a limit to that, we should find that all these
bodies would be resolved into molecules, and all these would be flying
away from each other. There would be no limit to that process, and we
could trace it as far back as ever we liked to trace it.”

Assuming that I have erred, I should like to point out that I have
erred in the best company, or more strictly, being a speculator, I
have been led into error by the best physical writers. Professor Tait,
in his *Sketch of Thermodynamics*, speaking of the laws discovered by
Fourier for the motion of heat in a solid, says, “Their mathematical
expressions point also to the fact that a uniform distribution of heat,
or a distribution tending to become uniform, must have arisen from some
primitive distribution of heat of a kind not capable of being produced
by known laws from any previous distribution.” In the latter words it
will be seen that there is no limitation to the laws of conduction,
and, although I had carefully referred to Sir W. Thomson’s original
paper, it is not unnatural that I should take Professor Tait’s
interpretation of its meaning.[21]

  [21] Sir W. Thomson’s words are as follows (*Cambridge Mathematical
  Journal*, Nov. 1842, vol. iii. p. 174). “When *x* is negative, the
  state represented cannot be the result of any *possible* distribution
  of temperature which has previously existed.” There is no limitation
  in the sentence to the laws of conduction, but, as the whole paper
  treats of the results of conduction in a solid, it may no doubt be
  understood that there is a *tacit* limitation. See also a second
  paper on the subject in the same journal for February, 1844, vol. iv.
  p. 67, where again there is no expressed limitation.

In his new work *On some Recent Advances in Physical Science*,
Professor Tait has recurred to the subject as follows:[22] “A profound
lesson may be learned from one of the earliest little papers of Sir W.
Thomson, published while he was an undergraduate at Cambridge, where
he shows that Fourier’s magnificent treatment of the conduction of
heat [in a solid body] leads to formulæ for its distribution which
are intelligible (and of course capable of being fully verified by
experiment) for all time future, but which, except in particular
cases, when extended to time past, remain intelligible for a finite
period only, and *then* indicate a state of things which could
not have resulted under known laws from any conceivable previous
distribution [of heat in the body]. So far as heat is concerned, modern
investigations have shown that a previous distribution of the *matter*
involved may, by its potential energy, be capable of producing such
a state of things at the moment of its aggregation; but the example
is now adduced not for its bearing on heat alone, but as a simple
illustration of the fact that all portions of our Science, especially
that beautiful one, the Dissipation of Energy, point unanimously to a
beginning, to a state of things incapable of being derived by present
laws [of tangible matter and its energy] from any conceivable previous
arrangement.” As this was published nearly a year after Professor
Clifford’s lecture, it may be inferred that Professor Tait adheres to
his original opinion that the theory of heat does give evidence of “a
beginning.”

  [22] Pp. 25–26. The parentheses are in the original, and show
  Professor Tait’s corrections in the verbatim reports of his lectures.
  The subject is treated again on pp. 168–9.

I may add that Professor Clerk Maxwell’s words seem to countenance the
same view, for he says,[23] “This is only one of the cases in which a
consideration of the dissipation of energy leads to the determination
of a superior limit to the antiquity of the observed order of things.”
The expression “observed order of things” is open to much ambiguity,
but in the absence of qualification I should take it to include the
aggregate of the laws of nature known to us. I should interpret
Professor Maxwell as meaning that the theory of heat indicates the
occurrence of some event of which our science cannot give any further
explanation. The physical writers thus seem not to be so clear about
the matter as Professor Clifford assumes.

  [23] *Theory of Heat* 1871, p. 245.

So far as I may venture to form an independent opinion on the subject,
it is to the effect that Professor Clifford is right, and that the
known laws of nature do not enable us to assign a “beginning.” Science
leads us backwards into infinite past duration. But that Professor
Clifford is right on this point, is no reason why we should suppose
him to be right in his other opinions, some of which I am sure are
wrong. Nor is it a reason why other parts of my last chapter should be
wrong. The question only affects the single paragraph on pp. 744–5 of
this book, which might, I believe, be struck out without necessitating
any alteration in the rest of the text. It is always to be remembered
that the failure of an argument in favour of a proposition does not,
generally speaking, add much, if any, probability to the contradictory
proposition. I cannot conclude without expressing my acknowledgments
to Professor Clifford for his kind expressions regarding my work as a
whole.

  2, The Chestnuts,
  West Heath,
  Hampstead, N. W.

  *August 15, 1877.*




CONTENTS.


  BOOK I.

  FORMAL LOGIC, DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE.


  CHAPTER I.

  INTRODUCTION.

  SECTION      PAGE

  1. Introduction                                                 1

  2. The Powers of Mind concerned in the Creation of Science      4

  3. Laws of Identity and Difference                              5

  4. The Nature of the Laws of Identity and Difference            6

  5. The Process of Inference                                     9

  6. Deduction and Induction                                     11

  7. Symbolic Expression of Logical Inference                    13

  8. Expression of Identity and Difference                       14

  9. General Formula of Logical Inference                        17

  10. The Propagating Power of Similarity                        20

  11. Anticipations of the Principle of Substitution             21

  12. The Logic of Relatives                                     22


  CHAPTER II.

  TERMS.

  1. Terms                                                       24

  2. Twofold meaning of General Names                            25

  3. Abstract Terms                                              27

  4. Substantial Terms                                           28

  5. Collective Terms                                            29

  6. Synthesis of Terms                                          30

  7. Symbolic Expression of the Law of Contradiction             31

  8. Certain Special Conditions of Logical Symbols               32


  CHAPTER III.

  PROPOSITIONS.

  1. Propositions                                                36

  2. Simple Identities                                           37

  3. Partial Identities                                          40

  4. Limited Identities                                          42

  5. Negative Propositions                                       43

  6. Conversion of Propositions                                  46

  7. Twofold Interpretation of Propositions                      47


  CHAPTER IV.

  DEDUCTIVE REASONING.

  1. Deductive Reasoning                                         49

  2. Immediate Inference                                         50

  3. Inference with Two Simple Identities                        51

  4. Inference with a Simple and a Partial Identity              53

  5. Inference of a Partial from Two Partial Identities          55

  6. On the Ellipsis of Terms in Partial Identities              57

  7. Inference of a Simple from Two Partial Identities           58

  8. Inference of a Limited from Two Partial Identities          59

  9. Miscellaneous Forms of Deductive Inference                  60

  10. Fallacies                                                  62


  CHAPTER V.

  DISJUNCTIVE PROPOSITIONS.

  1. Disjunctive Propositions                                    66

  2. Expression of the Alternative Relation                      67

  3. Nature of the Alternative Relation                          68

  4. Laws of the Disjunctive Relation                            71

  5. Symbolic Expression of the Law of Duality                   73

  6. Various Forms of the Disjunctive Proposition                74

  7. Inference by Disjunctive Propositions                       76


  CHAPTER VI.

  THE INDIRECT METHOD OF INFERENCE.

  1. The Indirect Method of Inference                            81

  2. Simple Illustrations                                        83

  3. Employment of the Contrapositive Proposition                84

  4. Contrapositive of a Simple Identity                         86

  5. Miscellaneous Examples of the Method                        88

  6. Mr. Venn’s Problem                                          90

  7. Abbreviation of the Process                                 91

  8. The Logical Alphabet                                        94

  9. The Logical Slate                                           95

  10. Abstraction of Indifferent Circumstances                   97

  11. Illustrations of the Indirect Method                       98

  12. Second Example                                             99

  13. Third Example                                             100

  14. Fourth Example                                            101

  15. Fifth Example                                             101

  16. Fallacies Analysed by the Indirect Method                 102

  17. The Logical Abacus                                        104

  18. The Logical Machine                                       107

  19. The Order of Premises                                     114

  20. The Equivalence of Propositions                           115

  21. The Nature of Inference                                   118


  CHAPTER VII.

  INDUCTION.

  1. Induction                                                  121

  2. Induction an Inverse Operation                             122

  3. Inductive Problems for Solution by the Reader              126

  4. Induction of Simple Identities                             127

  5. Induction of Partial Identities                            130

  6. Solution of the Inverse or Inductive Problem, involving
       Two Classes                                              134

  7. The Inverse Logical Problem, involving Three Classes       137

  8. Professor Clifford on the Types of Compound Statement
       involving Four Classes                                   143

  9. Distinction between Perfect and Imperfect Induction        146

  10. Transition from Perfect to Imperfect Induction            149


  BOOK II.

  NUMBER, VARIETY, AND PROBABILITY.


  CHAPTER VIII.

  PRINCIPLES OF NUMBER.

  1. Principles of Number                                       153

  2. The Nature of Numbe                                        156

  3. Of Numerical Abstraction                                   158

  4. Concrete and Abstract Number                               159

  5. Analogy of Logical and Numerical Terms                     160

  6. Principle of Mathematical Inference                        162

  7. Reasoning by Inequalities                                  165

  8. Arithmetical Reasoning                                     167

  9. Numerically Definite Reasoning                             168

  10. Numerical meaning of Logical Conditions                   171


  CHAPTER IX.

  THE VARIETY OF NATURE, OR THE DOCTRINE OF COMBINATIONS
  AND PERMUTATIONS.

  1. The Variety of Nature                                      173

  2. Distinction of Combinations and Permutations               177

  3. Calculation of Number of Combinations                      180

  4. The Arithmetical Triangle                                  182

  5. Connexion between the Arithmetical Triangle and the
       Logical Alphabet                                         189

  6. Possible Variety of Nature and Art                         190

  7. Higher Orders of Variety                                   192


  CHAPTER X.

  THEORY OF PROBABILITY.

  1. Theory of Probability                                      197

  2. Fundamental Principles of the Theory                       200

  3. Rules for the Calculation of Probabilities                 203

  4. The Logical Alphabet in questions of Probability           205

  5. Comparison of the Theory with Experience                   206

  6. Probable Deductive Arguments                               209

  7. Difficulties of the Theory                                 213


  CHAPTER XI.

  PHILOSOPHY OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE.

  1. Philosophy of Inductive Inference                          218

  2. Various Classes of Inductive Truths                        219

  3. The Relation of Cause and Effect                           220

  4. Fallacious Use of the Term Cause                           221

  5. Confusion of Two Questions                                 222

  6. Definition of the Term Cause                               224

  7. Distinction of Inductive and Deductive Results             226

  8. The Grounds of Inductive Inference                         228

  9. Illustrations of the Inductive Process                     229

  10. Geometrical Reasoning                                     233

  11. Discrimination of Certainty and Probability               235


  CHAPTER XII.

  THE INDUCTIVE OR INVERSE APPLICATION OF THE THEORY
  OF PROBABILITY.

  1. The Inductive or Inverse Application of the Theory         240

  2. Principle of the Inverse Method                            242

  3. Simple Applications of the Inverse Method                  244

  4. The Theory of Probability in Astronomy                     247

  5. The General Inverse Problem                                250

  6. Simple Illustration of the Inverse Problem                 253

  7. General Solution of the Inverse Problem                    255

  8. Rules of the Inverse Method                                257

  9. Fortuitous Coincidences                                    261

  10. Summary of the Theory of Inductive Inference              265


  BOOK III.

  METHODS OF MEASUREMENT.


  CHAPTER XIII.

  THE EXACT MEASUREMENT OF PHENOMENA.

  1. The Exact Measurement of Phenomena                         270

  2. Division of the Subject                                    274

  3. Continuous quantity                                        274

  4. The Fallacious Indications of the Senses                   276

  5. Complexity of Quantitative Questions                       278

  6. The Methods of Accurate Measurement                        282

  7. Conditions of Accurate Measurement                         282

  8. Measuring Instruments                                      284

  9. The Method of Repetition                                   288

  10. Measurements by Natural Coincidence                       292

  11. Modes of Indirect Measurement                             296

  12. Comparative Use of Measuring Instruments                  299

  13. Systematic Performance of Measurements                    300

  14. The Pendulum                                              302

  15. Attainable Accuracy of Measurement                        303


  CHAPTER XIV.

  UNITS AND STANDARDS OF MEASUREMENT.

  1. Units and Standards of Measurement                         305

  2. Standard Unit of Time                                      307

  3. The Unit of Space and the Bar Standard                     312

  4. The Terrestrial Standard                                   314

  5. The Pendulum Standard                                      315

  6. Unit of Density                                            316

  7. Unit of Mass                                               317

  8. Natural System of Standards                                319

  9. Subsidiary Units                                           320

  10. Derived Units                                             321

  11. Provisional Units                                         323

  12. Theory of Dimensions                                      325

  13. Natural Constants                                         328

  14. Mathematical Constants                                    330

  15. Physical Constants                                        331

  16. Astronomical Constants                                    332

  17. Terrestrial Numbers                                       333

  18. Organic Numbers                                           333

  19. Social Numbers                                            334


  CHAPTER XV.

  ANALYSIS OF QUANTITATIVE PHENOMENA.

  1. Analysis of Quantitative Phenomena                         335

  2. Illustrations of the Complication of Effects               336

  3. Methods of Eliminating Error                               339

  4. Method of Avoidance of Error                               340

  5. Differential Method                                        344

  6. Method of Correction                                       346

  7. Method of Compensation                                     350

  8. Method of Reversal                                         354


  CHAPTER XVI.

  THE METHOD OF MEANS.

  1. The Method of Means                                        357

  2. Several Uses of the Mean Result                            359

  3. The Mean and the Average                                   360

  4. On the Average or Fictitious Mean                          363

  5. The Precise Mean Result                                    365

  6. Determination of the Zero Point                            368

  7. Determination of Maximum Points                            371


  CHAPTER XVII.

  THE LAW OF ERROR.

  1. The Law of Error                                           374

  2. Establishment of the Law of Error                          375

  3. Herschel’s Geometrical Proof                               377

  4. Laplace’s and Quetelet’s Proof of the Law                  378

  5. Logical Origin of the Law of Error                         383

  6. Verification of the Law of Error                           383

  7. The Probable Mean Result                                   385

  8. The Probable Error of Results                              386

  9. Rejection of the Mean Result                               389

  10. Method of Least Squares                                   393

  11. Works upon the Theory of Probability                      394

  12. Detection of Constant Errors                              396


  BOOK IV.

  INDUCTIVE INVESTIGATION.


  CHAPTER XVIII.

  OBSERVATION.

  1. Observation                                                399

  2. Distinction of Observation and Experiment                  400

  3. Mental Conditions of Correct Observation                   402

  4. Instrumental and Sensual Conditions of Correct Observation 404

  5. External Conditions of Correct Observation                 407

  6. Apparent Sequence of Events                                409

  7. Negative Arguments from Non-Observation                    411


  CHAPTER XIX.

  EXPERIMENT.

  1. Experiment                                                 416

  2. Exclusion of Indifferent Circumstances                     419

  3. Simplification of Experiments                              422

  4. Failure in the Simplification of Experiments               424

  5. Removal of Usual Conditions                                426

  6. Interference of Unsuspected Conditions                     428

  7. Blind or Test Experiments                                  433

  8. Negative Results of Experiment                             434

  9. Limits of Experiment                                       437


  CHAPTER XX.

  METHOD OF VARIATIONS.

  1. Method of Variations                                       439

  2. The Variable and the Variant                               440

  3. Measurement of the Variable                                441

  4. Maintenance of Similar Conditions                          443

  5. Collective Experiments                                     445

  6. Periodic Variations                                        447

  7. Combined Periodic Changes                                  450

  8. Principle of Forced Vibrations                             451

  9. Integrated Variations                                      452


  CHAPTER XXI.

  THEORY OF APPROXIMATION.

  1. Theory of Approximation                                    456

  2. Substitution of Simple Hypotheses                          458

  3. Approximation to Exact Laws                                462

  4. Successive Approximations to Natural Conditions            465

  5. Discovery of Hypothetically Simple Laws                    470

  6. Mathematical Principles of Approximation                   471

  7. Approximate Independence of Small Effects                  475

  8. Four Meanings of Equality                                  479

  9. Arithmetic of Approximate Quantities                       481


  CHAPTER XXII.

  QUANTITATIVE INDUCTION.

  1. Quantitative Induction                                     483

  2. Probable Connexion of Varying Quantities                   484

  3. Empirical Mathematical Laws                                487

  4. Discovery of Rational Formulæ                              489

  5. The Graphical Method                                       492

  6. Interpolation and Extrapolation                            495

  7. Illustrations of Empirical Quantitative Laws               499

  8. Simple Proportional Variation                              501


  CHAPTER XXIII.

  THE USE OF HYPOTHESIS.

  1. The Use of Hypothesis                                      504

  2. Requisites of a good Hypothesis                            510

  3. Possibility of Deductive Reasoning                         511

  4. Consistency with the Laws of Nature                        514

  5. Conformity with Facts                                      516

  6. Experimentum Crucis                                        518

  7. Descriptive Hypotheses                                     522


  CHAPTER XXIV.

  EMPIRICAL KNOWLEDGE, EXPLANATION AND PREDICTION.

  1. Empirical Knowledge, Explanation and Prediction            525

  2. Empirical Knowledge                                        526

  3. Accidental Discovery                                       529

  4. Empirical Observations subsequently Explained              532

  5. Overlooked Results of Theory                               534

  6. Predicted Discoveries                                      536

  7. Predictions in the Science of Light                        538

  8. Predictions from the Theory of Undulations                 540

  9. Prediction in other Sciences                               542

  10. Prediction by Inversion of Cause and Effect               545

  11. Facts known only by Theory                                547


  CHAPTER XXV.

  ACCORDANCE OF QUANTITATIVE THEORIES.

  1. Accordance of Quantitative Theories                        551

  2. Empirical Measurements                                     552

  3. Quantities indicated by Theory, but Empirically Measured   553

  4. Explained Results of Measurement                           554

  5. Quantities determined by Theory and verified by
       Measurement                                              555

  6. Quantities determined by Theory and not verified           556

  7. Discordance of Theory and Experiment                       558

  8. Accordance of Measurements of Astronomical Distances       560

  9. Selection of the best Mode of Measurement                  563

  10. Agreement of Distinct Modes of Measurement                564

  11. Residual Phenomena                                        569


  CHAPTER XXVI.

  CHARACTER OF THE EXPERIMENTALIST.

  1. Character of the Experimentalist                           574

  2. Error of the Baconian Method                               576

  3. Freedom of Theorising                                      577

  4. The Newtonian Method, the True Organum                     581

  5. Candour and Courage of the Philosophic Mind                586

  6. The Philosophic Character of Faraday                       587

  7. Reservation of Judgment                                    592


  BOOK V.

  GENERALISATION, ANALOGY, AND CLASSIFICATION.


  CHAPTER XXVII.

  GENERALISATION.

  1. Generalisation                                             594

  2. Distinction of Generalisation and Analogy                  596

  3. Two Meanings of Generalisation                             597

  4. Value of Generalisation                                    599

  5. Comparative Generality of Properties                       600

  6. Uniform Properties of all Matter                           603

  7. Variable Properties of Matter                              606

  8. Extreme Instances of Properties                            607

  9. The Detection of Continuity                                610

  10. The Law of Continuity                                     615

  11. Failure of the Law of Continuity                          619

  12. Negative Arguments on the Principle of Continuity         621

  13. Tendency to Hasty Generalisation                          623


  CHAPTER XXVIII.

  ANALOGY.

  1. Analogy                                                    627

  2. Analogy as a Guide in Discovery                            629

  3. Analogy in the Mathematical Sciences                       631

  4. Analogy in the Theory of Undulations                       635

  5. Analogy in Astronomy                                       638

  6. Failures of Analogy                                        641


  CHAPTER XXIX.

  EXCEPTIONAL PHENOMENA.

  1. Exceptional Phenomena                                      644

  2. Imaginary or False Exceptions                              647

  3. Apparent but Congruent Exceptions                          649

  4. Singular Exceptions                                        652

  5. Divergent Exceptions                                       655

  6. Accidental Exceptions                                      658

  7. Novel and Unexplained Exceptions                           661

  8. Limiting Exceptions                                        663

  9. Real Exceptions to Supposed Laws                           666

  10. Unclassed Exceptions                                      668


  CHAPTER XXX.

  CLASSIFICATION.

  1. Classification                                             673

  2. Classification involving Induction                         675

  3. Multiplicity of Modes of Classification                    677

  4. Natural and Artificial Systems of Classification           679

  5. Correlation of Properties                                  681

  6. Classification in Crystallography                          685

  7. Classification an Inverse and Tentative Operation          689

  8. Symbolic Statement of the Theory of Classification         692

  9. Bifurcate Classification                                   694

  10. The Five Predicates                                       698

  11. Summum Genus and Infima Species                           701

  12. The Tree of Porphyry                                      702

  13. Does Abstraction imply Generalisation?                    704

  14. Discovery of Marks or Characteristics                     708

  15. Diagnostic Systems of Classification                      710

  16. Index Classifications                                     714

  17. Classification in the Biological Sciences                 718

  18. Classification by Types                                   722

  19. Natural Genera and Species                                724

  20. Unique or Exceptional Objects                             728

  21. Limits of Classification                                  730


  BOOK VI.

  CHAPTER XXXI.

  REFLECTIONS ON THE RESULTS AND LIMITS OF SCIENTIFIC METHOD.

  1. Reflections on the Results and Limits of Scientific Method 735

  2. The Meaning of Natural Law                                 737

  3. Infiniteness of the Universe                               738

  4. The Indeterminate Problem of Creation                      740

  5. Hierarchy of Natural Laws                                  742

  6. The Ambiguous Expression--“Uniformity of Nature”           745

  7. Possible States of the Universe                            749

  8. Speculations on the Reconcentration of Energy              751

  9. The Divergent Scope for New Discovery                      752

  10. Infinite Incompleteness of the Mathematical Sciences      754

  11. The Reign of Law in Mental and Social Phenomena           759

  12. The Theory of Evolution                                   761

  13. Possibility of Divine Interference                        765

  14. Conclusion                                                766


  INDEX                                                         773




THE PRINCIPLES OF SCIENCE.




CHAPTER I.

INTRODUCTION.


Science arises from the discovery of Identity amidst Diversity. The
process may be described in different words, but our language must
always imply the presence of one common and necessary element. In
every act of inference or scientific method we are engaged about a
certain identity, sameness, similarity, likeness, resemblance, analogy,
equivalence or equality apparent between two objects. It is doubtful
whether an entirely isolated phenomenon could present itself to our
notice, since there must always be some points of similarity between
object and object. But in any case an isolated phenomenon could be
studied to no useful purpose. The whole value of science consists
in the power which it confers upon us of applying to one object the
knowledge acquired from like objects; and it is only so far, therefore,
as we can discover and register resemblances that we can turn our
observations to account.

Nature is a spectacle continually exhibited to our senses, in which
phenomena are mingled in combinations of endless variety and novelty.
Wonder fixes the mind’s attention; memory stores up a record of each
distinct impression; the powers of association bring forth the record
when the like is felt again. By the higher faculties of judgment and
reasoning the mind compares the new with the old, recognises essential
identity, even when disguised by diverse circumstances, and expects to
find again what was before experienced. It must be the ground of all
reasoning and inference that *what is true of one thing will be true
of its equivalent*, and that under carefully ascertained conditions
*Nature repeats herself*.

Were this indeed a Chaotic Universe, the powers of mind employed in
science would be useless to us. Did Chance wholly take the place of
order, and did all phenomena come out of an *Infinite Lottery*, to use
Condorcet’s expression, there could be no reason to expect the like
result in like circumstances. It is possible to conceive a world in
which no two things should be associated more often, in the long run,
than any other two things. The frequent conjunction of any two events
would then be purely fortuitous, and if we expected conjunctions to
recur continually, we should be disappointed. In such a world we might
recognise the same kind of phenomenon as it appeared from time to time,
just as we might recognise a marked ball as it was occasionally drawn
and re-drawn from a ballot-box; but the approach of any phenomenon
would be in no way indicated by what had gone before, nor would it be a
sign of what was to come after. In such a world knowledge would be no
more than the memory of past coincidences, and the reasoning powers, if
they existed at all, would give no clue to the nature of the present,
and no presage of the future.

Happily the Universe in which we dwell is not the result of chance,
and where chance seems to work it is our own deficient faculties which
prevent us from recognising the operation of Law and of Design. In
the material framework of this world, substances and forces present
themselves in definite and stable combinations. Things are not in
perpetual flux, as ancient philosophers held. Element remains element;
iron changes not into gold. With suitable precautions we can calculate
upon finding the same thing again endowed with the same properties.
The constituents of the globe, indeed, appear in almost endless
combinations; but each combination bears its fixed character, and
when resolved is found to be the compound of definite substances.
Misapprehensions must continually occur, owing to the limited extent
of our experience. We can never have examined and registered possible
existences so thoroughly as to be sure that no new ones will occur and
frustrate our calculations. The same outward appearances may cover
any amount of hidden differences which we have not yet suspected. To
the variety of substances and powers diffused through nature at its
creation, we should not suppose that our brief experience can assign
a limit, and the necessary imperfection of our knowledge must be ever
borne in mind.

Yet there is much to give us confidence in Science. The wider our
experience, the more minute our examination of the globe, the
greater the accumulation of well-reasoned knowledge,--the fewer in
all probability will be the failures of inference compared with the
successes. Exceptions to the prevalence of Law are gradually reduced
to Law themselves. Certain deep similarities have been detected among
the objects around us, and have never yet been found wanting. As the
means of examining distant parts of the universe have been acquired,
those similarities have been traced there as here. Other worlds and
stellar systems may be almost incomprehensively different from ours in
magnitude, condition and disposition of parts, and yet we detect there
the same elements of which our own limbs are composed. The same natural
laws can be detected in operation in every part of the universe within
the scope of our instruments; and doubtless these laws are obeyed
irrespective of distance, time, and circumstance.

It is the prerogative of Intellect to discover what is uniform and
unchanging in the phenomena around us. So far as object is different
from object, knowledge is useless and inference impossible. But so
far as object resembles object, we can pass from one to the other. In
proportion as resemblance is deeper and more general, the commanding
powers of knowledge become more wonderful. Identity in one or other
of its phases is thus always the bridge by which we pass in inference
from case to case; and it is my purpose in this treatise to trace out
the various forms in which the one same process of reasoning presents
itself in the ever-growing achievements of Scientific Method.


*The Powers of Mind concerned in the Creation of Science.*

It is no part of the purpose of this work to investigate the nature
of mind. People not uncommonly suppose that logic is a branch of
psychology, because reasoning is a mental operation. On the same
ground, however, we might argue that all the sciences are branches
of psychology. As will be further explained, I adopt the opinion of
Mr. Herbert Spencer, that logic is really an objective science, like
mathematics or mechanics. Only in an incidental manner, then, need
I point out that the mental powers employed in the acquisition of
knowledge are probably three in number. They are substantially as
Professor Bain has stated them[24]:--

  [24] *The Senses and the Intellect*, Second Ed., pp. 5, 325, &c.

  1. The Power of Discrimination.
  2. The Power of Detecting Identity.
  3. The Power of Retention.


We exert the first power in every act of perception. Hardly can we have
a sensation or feeling unless we discriminate it from something else
which preceded. Consciousness would almost seem to consist in the break
between one state of mind and the next, just as an induced current of
electricity arises from the beginning or the ending of the primary
current. We are always engaged in discrimination; and the rudiment of
thought which exists in the lower animals probably consists in their
power of feeling difference and being agitated by it.

Yet had we the power of discrimination only, Science could not be
created. To know that one feeling differs from another gives purely
negative information. It cannot teach us what will happen. In such a
state of intellect each sensation would stand out distinct from every
other; there would be no tie, no bridge of affinity between them. We
want a unifying power by which the present and the future may be linked
to the past; and this seems to be accomplished by a different power of
mind. Lord Bacon has pointed out that different men possess in very
different degrees the powers of discrimination and identification. It
may be said indeed that discrimination necessarily implies the action
of the opposite process of identification; and so it doubtless does in
negative points. But there is a rare property of mind which consists
in penetrating the disguise of variety and seizing the common elements
of sameness; and it is this property which furnishes the true measure
of intellect. The name of “intellect” expresses the interlacing of the
general and the single, which is the peculiar province of mind.[25] To
*cogitate* is the Latin *coagitare*, resting on a like metaphor. Logic,
also, is but another name for the same process, the peculiar work of
reason; for λογος is derived from λεγειν, which like the Latin *legere*
meant originally to gather. Plato said of this unifying power, that if
he met the man who could detect *the one in the many*, he would follow
him as a god.

  [25] Max Müller, *Lectures on the Science of Language*, Second
  Series, vol. ii. p. 63; or Sixth Edition, vol. ii. p. 67. The view
  of the etymological meaning of “intellect” is given above on the
  authority of Professor Max Müller. It seems to be opposed to the
  ordinary opinion, according to which the Latin *intelligere* means to
  choose between, to see a difference between, to discriminate, instead
  of to unite.


*Laws of Identity and Difference.*

At the base of all thought and science must lie the laws which express
the very nature and conditions of the discriminating and identifying
powers of mind. These are the so-called Fundamental Laws of Thought,
usually stated as follows:--

  1. The Law of Identity. *Whatever is, is.*

  2. The Law of Contradiction. *A thing cannot both be and not be.*

  3. The Law of Duality. *A thing must either be or not be.*

The first of these statements may perhaps be regarded as a description
of identity itself, if so fundamental a notion can admit of
description. A thing at any moment is perfectly identical with itself,
and, if any person were unaware of the meaning of the word “identity,”
we could not better describe it than by such an example.

The second law points out that contradictory attributes can never be
joined together. The same object may vary in its different parts;
here it may be black, and there white; at one time it may be hard and
at another time soft; but at the same time and place an attribute
cannot be both present and absent. Aristotle truly described this law
as the first of all axioms--one of which we need not seek for any
demonstration. All truths cannot be proved, otherwise there would be an
endless chain of demonstration; and it is in self-evident truths like
this that we find the simplest foundations.

The third of these laws completes the other two. It asserts that at
every step there are two possible alternatives--presence or absence,
affirmation or negation. Hence I propose to name this law the Law of
Duality, for it gives to all the formulæ of reasoning a dual character.
It asserts also that between presence and absence, existence and
non-existence, affirmation and negation, there is no third alternative.
As Aristotle said, there can be no mean between opposite assertions: we
must either affirm or deny. Hence the inconvenient name by which it has
been known--The Law of Excluded Middle.

It may be allowed that these laws are not three independent and
distinct laws; they rather express three different aspects of the
same truth, and each law doubtless presupposes and implies the other
two. But it has not hitherto been found possible to state these
characters of identity and difference in less than the threefold
formula. The reader may perhaps desire some information as to the
mode in which these laws have been stated, or the way in which they
have been regarded, by philosophers in different ages of the world.
Abundant information on this and many other points of logical history
will be found in Ueberweg’s *System of Logic*, of which an excellent
translation has been published by Professor T. M. Lindsay (see
pp. 228–281).


*The Nature of the Laws of Identity and Difference.*

I must at least allude to the profoundly difficult question concerning
the nature and authority of these Laws of Identity and Difference.
Are they Laws of Thought or Laws of Things? Do they belong to mind or
to material nature? On the one hand it may be said that science is a
purely mental existence, and must therefore conform to the laws of
that which formed it. Science is in the mind and not in the things,
and the properties of mind are therefore all important. It is true
that these laws are verified in the observation of the exterior world;
and it would seem that they might have been gathered and proved by
generalisation, had they not already been in our possession. But
on the other hand, it may well be urged that we cannot prove these
laws by any process of reasoning or observation, because the laws
themselves are presupposed, as Leibnitz acutely remarked, in the very
notion of a proof. They are the prior conditions of all thought and
all knowledge, and even to question their truth is to allow them true.
Hartley ingeniously refined upon this argument, remarking that if the
fundamental laws of logic be not certain, there must exist a logic of
a second order whereby we may determine the degree of uncertainty: if
the second logic be not certain, there must be a third; and so on *ad
infinitum*. Thus we must suppose either that absolutely certain laws of
thought exist, or that there is no such thing as certainty whatever.[26]

  [26] Hartley on Man, vol. i. p. 359.

Logicians, indeed, appear to me to have paid insufficient attention to
the fact that mistakes in reasoning are always possible, and of not
unfrequent occurrence. The Laws of Thought are often called necessary
laws, that is, laws which cannot but be obeyed. Yet as a matter of
fact, who is there that does not often fail to obey them? They are
the laws which the mind ought to obey rather than what it always does
obey. Our thoughts cannot be the criterion of truth, for we often
have to acknowledge mistakes in arguments of moderate complexity,
and we sometimes only discover our mistakes by collision between our
expectations and the events of objective nature.

Mr. Herbert Spencer holds that the laws of logic are objective
laws,[27] and he regards the mind as being in a state of constant
education, each act of false reasoning or miscalculation leading to
results which are likely to prevent similar mistakes from being again
committed. I am quite inclined to accept such ingenious views; but at
the same time it is necessary to distinguish between the accumulation
of knowledge, and the constitution of the mind which allows of the
acquisition of knowledge. Before the mind can perceive or reason at
all it must have the conditions of thought impressed upon it. Before
a mistake can be committed, the mind must clearly distinguish the
mistaken conclusion from all other assertions. Are not the Laws of
Identity and Difference the prior conditions of all consciousness and
all existence? Must they not hold true, alike of things material and
immaterial? and if so, can we say that they are only subjectively true
or objectively true? I am inclined, in short, to regard them as true
both “in the nature of thought and things,” as I expressed it in my
first logical essay;[28] and I hold that they belong to the common
basis of all existence. But this is one of the most difficult questions
of psychology and metaphysics which can be raised, and it is hardly
one for the logician to decide. As the mathematician does not inquire
into the nature of unity and plurality, but develops the formal laws of
plurality, so the logician, as I conceive, must assume the truth of the
Laws of Identity and Difference, and occupy himself in developing the
variety of forms of reasoning in which their truth may be manifested.

  [27] *Principles of Psychology*, Second Ed., vol. ii. p. 86.

  [28] *Pure Logic, or the Logic of Quality apart from Quantity*, 1864,
  pp. 10, 16, 22, 29, 36, &c.

Again, I need hardly dwell upon the question whether logic treats of
language, notions, or things. As reasonably might we debate whether a
mathematician treats of symbols, quantities, or things. A mathematician
certainly does treat of symbols, but only as the instruments whereby
to facilitate his reasoning concerning quantities; and as the axioms
and rules of mathematical science must be verified in concrete objects
in order that the calculations founded upon them may have any validity
or utility, it follows that the ultimate objects of mathematical
science are the things themselves. In like manner I conceive that
the logician treats of language so far as it is essential for the
embodiment and exhibition of thought. Even if reasoning can take place
in the inner consciousness of man without the use of any signs, which
is doubtful, at any rate it cannot become the subject of discussion
until by some system of material signs it is manifested to other
persons. The logician then uses words and symbols as instruments of
reasoning, and leaves the nature and peculiarities of language to the
grammarian. But signs again must correspond to the thoughts and things
expressed, in order that they shall serve their intended purpose. We
may therefore say that logic treats ultimately of thoughts and things,
and immediately of the signs which stand for them. Signs, thoughts, and
exterior objects may be regarded as parallel and analogous series of
phenomena, and to treat any one of the three series is equivalent to
treating either of the other series.


*The Process of Inference.*

The fundamental action of our reasoning faculties consists in inferring
or carrying to a new instance of a phenomenon whatever we have
previously known of its like, analogue, equivalent or equal. Sameness
or identity presents itself in all degrees, and is known under various
names; but the great rule of inference embraces all degrees, and
affirms that *so far as there exists sameness, identity or likeness,
what is true of one thing will be true of the other*. The great
difficulty doubtless consists in ascertaining that there does exist
a sufficient degree of likeness or sameness to warrant an intended
inference; and it will be our main task to investigate the conditions
under which reasoning is valid. In this place I wish to point out that
there is something common to all acts of inference, however different
their apparent forms. The one same rule lends itself to the most
diverse applications.

The simplest possible case of inference, perhaps, occurs in the use of
a *pattern*, *example*, or, as it is commonly called, a *sample*. To
prove the exact similarity of two portions of commodity, we need not
bring one portion beside the other. It is sufficient that we take a
sample which exactly represents the texture, appearance, and general
nature of one portion, and according as this sample agrees or not with
the other, so will the two portions of commodity agree or differ.
Whatever is true as regards the colour, texture, density, material of
the sample will be true of the goods themselves. In such cases likeness
of quality is the condition of inference.

Exactly the same mode of reasoning holds true of magnitude and figure.
To compare the sizes of two objects, we need not lay them beside each
other. A staff, string, or other kind of measure may be employed to
represent the length of one object, and according as it agrees or not
with the other, so must the two objects agree or differ. In this case
the proxy or sample represents length; but the fact that lengths can
be added and multiplied renders it unnecessary that the proxy should
always be as large as the object. Any standard of convenient size, such
as a common foot-rule, may be made the medium of comparison. The height
of a church in one town may be carried to that in another, and objects
existing immovably at opposite sides of the earth may be vicariously
measured against each other. We obviously employ the axiom that
whatever is true of a thing as regards its length, is true of its equal.

To every other simple phenomenon in nature the same principle of
substitution is applicable. We may compare weights, densities, degrees
of hardness, and degrees of all other qualities, in like manner. To
ascertain whether two sounds are in unison we need not compare them
directly, but a third sound may be the go-between. If a tuning-fork is
in unison with the middle C of York Minster organ, and we afterwards
find it to be in unison with the same note of the organ in Westminster
Abbey, then it follows that the two organs are tuned in unison. The
rule of inference now is, that what is true of the tuning-fork as
regards the tone or pitch of its sound, is true of any sound in unison
with it.

The skilful employment of this substitutive process enables us to
make measurements beyond the powers of our senses. No one can count
the vibrations, for instance, of an organ-pipe. But we can construct
an instrument called the *siren*, so that, while producing a sound of
any pitch, it shall register the number of vibrations constituting the
sound. Adjusting the sound of the siren in unison with an organ-pipe,
we measure indirectly the number of vibrations belonging to a sound
of that pitch. To measure a sound of the same pitch is as good as to
measure the sound itself.

Sir David Brewster, in a somewhat similar manner, succeeded in
measuring the refractive indices of irregular fragments of transparent
minerals. It was a troublesome, and sometimes impracticable work to
grind the minerals into prisms, so that the power of refracting light
could be directly observed; but he fell upon the ingenious device
of compounding a liquid possessing the same refractive power as the
transparent fragment under examination. The moment when this equality
was attained could be known by the fragments ceasing to reflect or
refract light when immersed in the liquid, so that they became almost
invisible in it. The refractive power of the liquid being then measured
gave that of the solid. A more beautiful instance of representative
measurement, depending immediately upon the principle of inference,
could not be found.[29]

  [29] Brewster, *Treatise on New Philosophical Instruments*, p. 273.
  Concerning this method see also Whewell, *Philosophy of the Inductive
  Sciences*, vol. ii. p. 355; Tomlinson, *Philosophical Magazine*,
  Fourth Series, vol. xl. p. 328; Tyndall, in Youmans’ *Modern
  Culture*, p. 16.

Throughout the various logical processes which we are about
to consider--Deduction, Induction, Generalisation, Analogy,
Classification, Quantitative Reasoning--we shall find the one same
principle operating in a more or less disguised form.


*Deduction and Induction.*

The processes of inference always depend on the one same principle of
substitution; but they may nevertheless be distinguished according as
the results are inductive or deductive. As generally stated, deduction
consists in passing from more general to less general truths; induction
is the contrary process from less to more general truths. We may
however describe the difference in another manner. In deduction we are
engaged in developing the consequences of a law. We learn the meaning,
contents, results or inferences, which attach to any given proposition.
Induction is the exactly inverse process. Given certain results or
consequences, we are required to discover the general law from which
they flow.

In a certain sense all knowledge is inductive. We can only learn the
laws and relations of things in nature by observing those things. But
the knowledge gained from the senses is knowledge only of particular
facts, and we require some process of reasoning by which we may
collect out of the facts the laws obeyed by them. Experience gives
us the materials of knowledge: induction digests those materials, and
yields us general knowledge. When we possess such knowledge, in the
form of general propositions and natural laws, we can usefully apply
the reverse process of deduction to ascertain the exact information
required at any moment. In its ultimate foundation, then, all knowledge
is inductive--in the sense that it is derived by a certain inductive
reasoning from the facts of experience.

It is nevertheless true,--and this is a point to which insufficient
attention has been paid, that all reasoning is founded on the
principles of deduction. I call in question the existence of any method
of reasoning which can be carried on without a knowledge of deductive
processes. I shall endeavour to show that *induction is really the
inverse process of deduction*. There is no mode of ascertaining the
laws which are obeyed in certain phenomena, unless we have the power
of determining what results would follow from a given law. Just as the
process of division necessitates a prior knowledge of multiplication,
or the integral calculus rests upon the observation and remembrance
of the results of the differential calculus, so induction requires a
prior knowledge of deduction. An inverse process is the undoing of
the direct process. A person who enters a maze must either trust to
chance to lead him out again, or he must carefully notice the road by
which he entered. The facts furnished to us by experience are a maze of
particular results; we might by chance observe in them the fulfilment
of a law, but this is scarcely possible, unless we thoroughly learn the
effects which would attach to any particular law.

Accordingly, the importance of deductive reasoning is doubly supreme.
Even when we gain the results of induction they would be of no use
unless we could deductively apply them. But before we can gain them
at all we must understand deduction, since it is the inversion of
deduction which constitutes induction. Our first task in this work,
then, must be to trace out fully the nature of identity in all its
forms of occurrence. Having given any series of propositions we must be
prepared to develop deductively the whole meaning embodied in them, and
the whole of the consequences which flow from them.


*Symbolic Expression of Logical Inference.*

In developing the results of the Principle of Inference we require to
use an appropriate language of signs. It would indeed be quite possible
to explain the processes of reasoning by the use of words found in the
dictionary. Special examples of reasoning, too, may seem to be more
readily apprehended than general symbolic forms. But it has been shown
in the mathematical sciences that the attainment of truth depends
greatly upon the invention of a clear, brief, and appropriate system
of symbols. Not only is such a language convenient, but it is almost
essential to the expression of those general truths which are the very
soul of science. To apprehend the truth of special cases of inference
does not constitute logic; we must apprehend them as cases of more
general truths. The object of all science is the separation of what is
common and general from what is accidental and different. In a system
of logic, if anywhere, we should esteem this generality, and strive to
exhibit clearly what is similar in very diverse cases. Hence the great
value of *general symbols* by which we can represent the form of a
reasoning process, disentangled from any consideration of the special
subject to which it is applied.

The signs required in logic are of a very simple kind. As sameness or
difference must exist between two things or notions, we need signs to
indicate the things or notions compared, and other signs to denote the
relations between them. We need, then, (1) symbols for terms, (2) a
symbol for sameness, (3) a symbol for difference, and (4) one or two
symbols to take the place of conjunctions.

Ordinary nouns substantive, such as *Iron*, *Metal*, *Electricity*,
*Undulation*, might serve as terms, but, for the reasons explained
above, it is better to adopt blank letters, devoid of special
signification, such as A, B, C, &c. Each letter must be understood to
represent a noun, and, so far as the conditions of the argument allow,
*any noun*. Just as in Algebra, *x*, *y*, *z*, *p*, *q*, &c. are used
for *any quantities*, undetermined or unknown, except when the special
conditions of the problem are taken into account, so will our letters
stand for undetermined or unknown things.

These letter-terms will be used indifferently for nouns substantive
and adjective. Between these two kinds of nouns there may perhaps
be differences in a metaphysical or grammatical point of view.
But grammatical usage sanctions the conversion of adjectives into
substantives, and *vice versâ*; we may avail ourselves of this latitude
without in any way prejudging the metaphysical difficulties which may
be involved. Here, as throughout this work, I shall devote my attention
to truths which I can exhibit in a clear and formal manner, believing
that in the present condition of logical science, this course will lead
to greater advantage than discussion upon the metaphysical questions
which may underlie any part of the subject.

Every noun or term denotes an object, and usually implies the
possession by that object of certain qualities or circumstances common
to all the objects denoted. There are certain terms, however, which
imply the absence of qualities or circumstances attaching to other
objects. It will be convenient to employ a special mode of indicating
these *negative terms*, as they are called. If the general name A
denotes an object or class of objects possessing certain defined
qualities, then the term Not A will denote any object which does not
possess the whole of those qualities; in short, Not A is the sign for
anything which differs from A in regard to any one or more of the
assigned qualities. If A denote “transparent object,” Not A will denote
“not transparent object.” Brevity and facility of expression are of
no slight importance in a system of notation, and it will therefore
be desirable to substitute for the negative term Not A a briefer
symbol. De Morgan represented negative terms by small Roman letters,
or sometimes by small italic letters;[30] as the latter seem to be
highly convenient, I shall use *a*, *b*, *c*, ... *p*, *q*, &c., as the
negative terms corresponding to A, B, C, ... P, Q, &c. Thus if A means
“fluid,” *a* will mean “not fluid.”

  [30] *Formal Logic*, p. 38.


*Expression of Identity and Difference.*

To denote the relation of sameness or identity I unhesitatingly adopt
the sign =, so long used by mathematicians to denote equality. This
symbol was originally appropriated by Robert Recorde in his *Whetstone
of Wit*, to avoid the tedious repetition of the words “is equal to;”
and he chose a pair of parallel lines, because no two things can be
more equal.[31] The meaning of the sign has however been gradually
extended beyond that of equality of quantities; mathematicians have
themselves used it to indicate equivalence of operations. The force
of analogy has been so great that writers in most other branches
of science have employed the same sign. The philologist uses it to
indicate the equivalence of meaning of words: chemists adopt it to
signify identity in kind and equality in weight of the elements which
form two different compounds. Not a few logicians, for instance
Lambert, Drobitsch, George Bentham,[32] Boole,[33] have employed it
as the copula of propositions. De Morgan declined to use it for this
purpose, but still further extended its meaning so as to include the
equivalence of a proposition with the premises from which it can be
inferred;[34] and Herbert Spencer has applied it in a like manner.[35]

  [31] Hallam’s *Literature of Europe*, First Ed., vol. ii. p. 444.

  [32] *Outline of a New System of Logic*, London, 1827, pp. 133, &c.

  [33] *An Investigation of the Laws of Thought*, pp. 27, &c.

  [34] *Formal Logic*, pp. 82, 106. In his later work, *The Syllabus of
  a New System of Logic*, he discontinued the use of the sign.

  [35] *Principles of Psychology*, Second Ed., vol. ii. pp. 54, 55.

Many persons may think that the choice of a symbol is a matter of
slight importance or of mere convenience; but I hold that the common
use of this sign = in so many different meanings is really founded
upon a generalisation of the widest character and of the greatest
importance--one indeed which it is a principal purpose of this work to
explain. The employment of the same sign in different cases would be
unphilosophical unless there were some real analogy between its diverse
meanings. If such analogy exists, it is not only allowable, but highly
desirable and even imperative, to use the symbol of equivalence with a
generality of meaning corresponding to the generality of the principles
involved. Accordingly De Morgan’s refusal to use the symbol in logical
propositions indicated his opinion that there was a want of analogy
between logical propositions and mathematical equations. I use the sign
because I hold the contrary opinion.

I conceive that the sign = as commonly employed, always denotes
some form or degree of sameness, and the particular form is usually
indicated by the nature of the terms joined by it. Thus “6,720 pounds =
3 tons” is evidently an equation of quantities. The formula - × - = +
expresses the equivalence of operations. “Exogens = Dicotyledons” is a
logical identity expressing a profound truth concerning the character
and origin of a most important group of plants.

We have great need in logic of a distinct sign for the copula, because
the little verb *is* (or *are*), hitherto used both in logic and
ordinary discourse, is thoroughly ambiguous. It sometimes denotes
identity, as in “St. Paul’s is the *chef-d’œuvre* of Sir Christopher
Wren;” but it more commonly indicates inclusion of class within class,
or partial identity, as in “Bishops are members of the House of
Lords.” This latter relation involves identity, but requires careful
discrimination from simple identity, as will be shown further on.

When with this sign of equality we join two nouns or logical terms, as
in

  Hydrogen = The least dense element,

we signify that the object or group of objects denoted by one term is
identical with that denoted by the other, in everything except the
names. The general formula

  A = B

must be taken to mean that A and B are symbols for the same object
or group of objects. This identity may sometimes arise from the mere
imposition of names, but it may also arise from the deepest laws of the
constitution of nature; as when we say

  Gravitating matter = Matter possessing inertia,
  Exogenous plants = Dicotyledonous plants,
  Plagihedral quartz crystals = Quartz crystals causing
    the plane of polarisation of light to rotate.

We shall need carefully to distinguish between relations of terms which
can be modified at our own will and those which are fixed as expressing
the laws of nature; but at present we are considering only the mode of
expression which may be the same in either case.

Sometimes, but much less frequently, we require a symbol to indicate
difference or the absence of complete sameness. For this purpose we
may generalise in like manner the symbol ~, which was introduced by
Wallis to signify difference between quantities. The general formula

  B ~ C

denotes that B and C are the names of two objects or groups which are
not identical with each other. Thus we may say

  Acrogens ~ Flowering plants.
  Snowdon ~ The highest mountain in Great Britain.

I shall also occasionally use the sign ᔕ to signify in the most general
manner the existence of any relation between the two terms connected by
it. Thus ᔕ might mean not only the relations of equality or inequality,
sameness or difference, but any special relation of time, place, size,
causation, &c. in which one thing may stand to another. By A ᔕ B I
mean, then, any two objects of thought related to each other in any
conceivable manner.


*General Formula of Logical Inference.*

The one supreme rule of inference consists, as I have said, in the
direction to affirm of anything whatever is known of its like, equal
or equivalent. The *Substitution of Similars* is a phrase which seems
aptly to express the capacity of mutual replacement existing in any
two objects which are like or equivalent to a sufficient degree.
It is matter for further investigation to ascertain when and for
what purposes a degree of similarity less than complete identity is
sufficient to warrant substitution. For the present we think only of
the exact sameness expressed in the form

  A = B.

Now if we take the letter C to denote any third conceivable object, and
use the sign ᔕ in its stated meaning of *indefinite relation*, then the
general formula of all inference may be thus exhibited:--

  From       A = B ᔕ C
  we may infer   A ᔕ C

or, in words--*In whatever relation a thing stands to a second thing,
in the same relation it stands to the like or equivalent of that second
thing.* The identity between A and B allows us indifferently to place
A where B was, or B where A was; and there is no limit to the variety
of special meanings which we can bestow upon the signs used in this
formula consistently with its truth. Thus if we first specify only the
meaning of the sign ᔕ, we may say that if *C is the weight of B*, then
*C is also the weight of A*. Similarly

  If C is the father of B, C is the father of A;
  If C is a fragment of B, C is a fragment of A;
  If C is a quality of B, C is a quality of A;
  If C is a species of B, C is a species of A;
  If C is the equal of B, C is the equal of A;

and so on *ad infinitum*.

We may also endow with special meanings the letter-terms A, B, and C,
and the process of inference will never be false. Thus let the sign
ᔕ mean “is height of,” and let

  A = Snowdon,
  B = Highest mountain in England or Wales,
  C = 3,590 feet;

then it obviously follows since “3,590 feet is the height of Snowdon,”
and “Snowdon = the highest mountain in England or Wales,” that, “3,590
feet is the height of the highest mountain in England or Wales.”

One result of this general process of inference is that we may in any
aggregate or complex whole replace any part by its equivalent without
altering the whole. To alter is to make a difference; but if in
replacing a part I make no difference, there is no alteration of the
whole. Many inferences which have been very imperfectly included in
logical formulas at once follow. I remember the late Prof. De Morgan
remarking that all Aristotle’s logic could not prove that “Because a
horse is an animal, the head of a horse is the head of an animal.” I
conceive that this amounts merely to replacing in the complete notion
*head of a horse*, the term “horse,” by its equivalent *some animal* or
*an animal*. Similarly, since

  The Lord Chancellor = The Speaker of the House of Lords,

it follows that

  The death of the Lord Chancellor = The death of the Speaker of the
  House of Lords;

and any event, circumstance or thing, which stands in a certain
relation to the one will stand in like relation to the other. Milton
reasons in this way when he says, in his Areopagitica, “Who kills a
man, kills a reasonable creature, God’s image.” If we may suppose him
to mean

  God’s image = man = some reasonable creature,

it follows that “The killer of a man is the killer of some reasonable
creature,” and also “The killer of God’s image.”

This replacement of equivalents may be repeated over and over again to
any extent. Thus if *person* is identical in meaning with *individual*,
it follows that

  Meeting of persons = meeting of individuals;

and if *assemblage* = *meeting*, we may make a new replacement and show
that

  Meeting of persons = assemblage of individuals.

We may in fact found upon this principle of substitution a most general
axiom in the following terms[36]:--

  [36] *Pure Logic, or the Logic of Quality*, p. 14.

  *Same parts samely related make same wholes.*

If, for instance, exactly similar bricks and other materials be used
to build two houses, and they be similarly placed in each house, the
two houses must be similar. There are millions of cells in a human
body, but if each cell of one person were represented by an exactly
similar cell similarly placed in another body, the two persons would
be undistinguishable, and would be only *numerically* different. It
is upon this principle, as we shall see, that all accurate processes
of measurement depend. If for a weight in a scale of a balance we
substitute another weight, and the equilibrium remains entirely
unchanged, then the weights must be exactly equal. The general test of
equality is substitution. Objects are equally bright when on replacing
one by the other the eye perceives no difference. Objects are equal in
dimensions when tested by the same gauge they fit in the same manner.
Generally speaking, two objects are alike so far as when substituted
one for another no alteration is produced, and *vice versâ* when alike
no alteration is produced by the substitution.


*The Propagating Power of Similarity.*

The relation of similarity in all its degrees is reciprocal. So far
as things are alike, either may be substituted for the other; and
this may perhaps be considered the very meaning of the relation. But
it is well worth notice that there is in similarity a peculiar power
of extending itself among all the things which are similar. To render
a number of things similar to each other we need only render them
similar to one standard object. Each coin struck from a pair of dies
not only resembles the matrix or original pattern from which the dies
were struck, but resembles every other coin manufactured from the same
original pattern. Among a million such coins there are not less than
499,999,500,000 *pairs of coins* resembling each other. Similars to
the same are similars to all. It is one great advantage of printing
that all copies of a document struck from the same type are necessarily
identical each with each, and whatever is true of one copy will be true
of every copy. Similarly, if fifty rows of pipes in an organ be tuned
in perfect unison with one row, usually the Principal, they must be
in unison with each other. Similarity can also reproduce or propagate
itself *ad infinitum*: for if a number of tuning-forks be adjusted in
perfect unison with one standard fork, all instruments tuned to any one
fork will agree with any instrument tuned to any other fork. Standard
measures of length, capacity, weight, or any other measurable quality,
are propagated in the same manner. So far as copies of the original
standard, or copies of copies, or copies again of those copies, are
accurately executed, they must all agree each with every other.

It is the capability of mutual substitution which gives such great
value to the modern methods of mechanical construction, according
to which all the parts of a machine are exact facsimiles of a fixed
pattern. The rifles used in the British army are constructed on the
American interchangeable system, so that any part of any rifle can be
substituted for the same part of another. A bullet fitting one rifle
will fit all others of the same bore. Sir J. Whitworth has extended
the same system to the screws and screw-bolts used in connecting
together the parts of machines, by establishing a series of standard
screws.


*Anticipations of the Principle of Substitution.*

In such a subject as logic it is hardly possible to put forth any
opinions which have not been in some degree previously entertained. The
germ at least of every doctrine will be found in earlier writers, and
novelty must arise chiefly in the mode of harmonising and developing
ideas. When I first employed the process and name of *substitution*
in logic,[37] I was led to do so from analogy with the familiar
mathematical process of substituting for a symbol its value as given in
an equation. In writing my first logical essay I had a most imperfect
conception of the importance and generality of the process, and I
described, as if they were of equal importance, a number of other laws
which now seem to be but particular cases of the one general rule of
substitution.

  [37] *Pure Logic*, pp. 18, 19.

My second essay, “The Substitution of Similars,” was written shortly
after I had become aware of the great simplification which may be
effected by a proper application of the principle of substitution. I
was not then acquainted with the fact that the German logician Beneke
had employed the principle of substitution, and had used the word
itself in forming a theory of the syllogism. My imperfect acquaintance
with the German language had prevented me from acquiring a complete
knowledge of Beneke’s views; but there is no doubt that Professor
Lindsay is right in saying that he, and probably other logicians,
were in some degree familiar with the principle.[38] Even Aristotle’s
dictum may be regarded as an imperfect statement of the principle of
substitution; and, as I have pointed out, we have only to modify that
dictum in accordance with the quantification of the predicate in order
to arrive at the complete process of substitution.[39] The Port-Royal
logicians appear to have entertained nearly equivalent views, for
they considered that all moods of the syllogism might be reduced
under one general principle.[40] Of two premises they regard one as
the *containing proposition* (propositio continens), and the other as
the *applicative proposition*. The latter proposition must always be
affirmative, and represents that by which a substitution is made; the
former may or may not be negative, and is that in which a substitution
is effected. They also show that this method will embrace certain cases
of complex reasoning which had no place in the Aristotelian syllogism.
Their views probably constitute the greatest improvement in logical
doctrine made up to that time since the days of Aristotle. But a true
reform in logic must consist, not in explaining the syllogism in one
way or another, but in doing away with all the narrow restrictions of
the Aristotelian system, and in showing that there exists an infinite
variety of logical arguments immediately deducible from the principle
of substitution of which the ancient syllogism forms but a small and
not even the most important part.

  [38] Ueberweg’s *System of Logic*, transl. by Lindsay, pp. 442–446,
  571, 572. The anticipations of the principle of substitution to be
  found in the works of Leibnitz, Reusch, and perhaps other German
  logicians, will be noticed in the preface to this second edition.

  [39] *Substitution of Similars* (1869), p. 9.

  [40] *Port-Royal Logic*, transl. by Spencer Baynes, pp. 212–219. Part
  III. chap. x. and xi.


*The Logic of Relatives.*

There is a difficult and important branch of logic which may be
called the Logic of Relatives. If I argue, for instance, that because
Daniel Bernoulli was the son of John, and John the brother of James,
therefore Daniel was the nephew of James, it is not possible to prove
this conclusion by any simple logical process. We require at any rate
to assume that the son of a brother is a nephew. A simple logical
relation is that which exists between properties and circumstances of
the same object or class. But objects and classes of objects may also
be related according to all the properties of time and space. I believe
it may be shown, indeed, that where an inference concerning such
relations is drawn, a process of substitution is really employed and an
identity must exist; but I will not undertake to prove the assertion
in this work. The relations of time and space are logical relations
of a complicated character demanding much abstract and difficult
investigation. The subject has been treated with such great ability by
Peirce,[41] De Morgan,[42] Ellis,[43] and Harley, that I will not in
the present work attempt any review of their writings, but merely refer
the reader to the publications in which they are to be found.

  [41] *Description of a Notation for the Logic of Relatives, resulting
  from an Amplification of the Conceptions of Boole’s Calculus of
  Logic.* By C. S. Peirce. *Memoirs of the American Academy*, vol. ix.
  Cambridge, U.S., 1870.

  [42] *On the Syllogism No IV., and on the Logic of Relations.* By
  Augustus De Morgan. *Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical
  Society*, vol. x. part ii., 1860.

  [43] *Observations on Boole’s Laws of Thought.* By the late R. Leslie
  Ellis; communicated by the Rev. Robert Harley, F.R.S. *Report of the
  British Association*, 1870. *Report of Sections*, p. 12. Also, *On
  Boole’s Laws of Thought*. By the Rev. Robert Harley, F.R.S., *ibid.*
  p. 14.




CHAPTER II.

TERMS.


Every proposition expresses the resemblance or difference of the things
denoted by its terms. As inference treats of the relation between two
or more propositions, so a proposition expresses a relation between two
or more terms. In the portion of this work which treats of deduction
it will be convenient to follow the usual order of exposition. We will
consider in succession the various kinds of terms, propositions, and
arguments, and we commence in this chapter with terms.

The simplest and most palpable meaning which can belong to a term
consists of some single material object, such as Westminster Abbey,
Stonehenge, the Sun, Sirius, &c. It is probable that in early stages of
intellect only concrete and palpable things are the objects of thought.
The youngest child knows the difference between a hot and a cold body.
The dog can recognise his master among a hundred other persons, and
animals of much lower intelligence know and discriminate their haunts.
In all such acts there is judgment concerning the likeness of physical
objects, but there is little or no power of analysing each object and
regarding it as a group of qualities.

The dignity of intellect begins with the power of separating points of
agreement from those of difference. Comparison of two objects may lead
us to perceive that they are at once like and unlike. Two fragments of
rock may differ entirely in outward form, yet they may have the same
colour, hardness, and texture. Flowers which agree in colour may differ
in odour. The mind learns to regard each object as an aggregate of
qualities, and acquires the power of dwelling at will upon one or other
of those qualities to the exclusion of the rest. Logical abstraction,
in short, comes into play, and the mind becomes capable of reasoning,
not merely about objects which are physically complete and concrete,
but about things which may be thought of separately in the mind though
they exist not separately in nature. We can think of the hardness of
a rock, or the colour of a flower, and thus produce abstract notions,
denoted by abstract terms, which will form a subject for further
consideration.

At the same time arise general notions and classes of objects. We
cannot fail to observe that the quality *hardness* exists in many
objects, for instance in many fragments of rock; mentally joining these
together, we create the class *hard object*, which will include, not
only the actual objects examined, but all others which may happen to
agree with them, as they agree with each other. As our senses cannot
possibly report to us all the contents of space, we cannot usually
set any limits to the number of objects which may fall into any such
class. At this point we begin to perceive the power and generality of
thought, which enables us in a single act to treat of indefinitely or
even infinitely numerous objects. We can safely assert that whatever is
true of any one object coming under a class is true of any of the other
objects so far as they possess the common qualities implied in their
belonging to the class. We must not place a thing in a class unless
we are prepared to believe of it all that is believed of the class in
general; but it remains a matter of important consideration to decide
how far and in what manner we can safely undertake thus to assign
the place of objects in that general system of classification which
constitutes the body of science.


*Twofold Meaning of General Names.*

Etymologically the *meaning* of a name is that which we are caused
to think of when the name is used. Now every general name causes us
to think of some one or more of the objects belonging to a class; it
may also cause us to think of the common qualities possessed by those
objects. A name is said to *denote* the object of thought to which it
may be applied; it *implies* at the same time the possession of certain
qualities or circumstances. The objects denoted form the *extent*
of meaning of the term; the qualities implied form the *intent* of
meaning. Crystal is the name of any substance of which the molecules
are arranged in a regular geometrical manner. The substances or objects
in question form the extent of meaning; the circumstance of having the
molecules so arranged forms the intent of meaning.

When we compare general terms together, it may often be found that
the meaning of one is included in the meaning of another. Thus
all *crystals* are included among *material substances*, and all
*opaque crystals* are included among *crystals*; here the inclusion
is in extension. We may also have inclusion of meaning in regard to
intension. For, as all crystals are material substances, the qualities
implied by the term material substance must be among those implied by
crystal. Again, it is obvious that while in extension of meaning opaque
crystals are but a part of crystals, in intension of meaning crystal
is but part of opaque crystal. We increase the intent of meaning of a
term by joining to it adjectives, or phrases equivalent to adjectives,
and the removal of such adjectives of course decreases the intensive
meaning. Now, concerning such changes of meaning, the following
all-important law holds universally true:--*When the intent of meaning
of a term is increased the extent is decreased; and* vice versâ, *when
the extent is increased the intent is decreased*. In short, as one is
increased the other is decreased.

This law refers only to logical changes. The number of steam-engines
in the world may be undergoing a rapid increase without the intensive
meaning of the name being altered. The law will only be verified,
again, when there is a real change in the intensive meaning, and an
adjective may often be joined to a noun without making a change.
*Elementary metal* is identical with *metal*; *mortal man* with *man*;
it being a *property* of all metals to be elements, and of all men to
be mortals.

There is no limit to the amount of meaning which a term may have. A
term may denote one object, or many, or an infinite number; it may
imply a single quality, if such there be, or a group of any number
of qualities, and yet the law connecting the extension and intension
will infallibly apply. Taking the general name *planet*, we increase
its intension and decrease its extension by prefixing the adjective
*exterior*; and if we further add *nearest to the earth*, there remains
but one planet, *Mars*, to which the name can then be applied. Singular
terms, which denote a single individual only, come under the same law
of meaning as general names. They may be regarded as general names of
which the meaning in extension is reduced to a minimum. Logicians have
erroneously asserted, as it seems to me, that singular terms are devoid
of meaning in intension, the fact being that they exceed all other
terms in that kind of meaning, as I have elsewhere tried to show.[44]

  [44] Jevons’ *Elementary Lessons in Logic*, pp. 41–43; *Pure Logic*,
  p. 6. See also J. S. Mill, *System of Logic*, Book I. chap. ii.
  section 5, and Shedden’s *Elements of Logic*, London, 1864, pp. 14,
  &c. Professor Robertson objects (*Mind*, vol. i. p. 210) that I
  confuse *singular* and *proper* names; if so, it is because I hold
  that the same remarks apply to proper names, which do not seem to me
  to differ logically from singular names.


*Abstract Terms.*

Comparison of objects, and analysis of the complex resemblances and
differences which they present, lead us to the conception of *abstract
qualities*. We learn to think of one object as not only different from
another, but as differing in some particular point, such as colour, or
weight, or size. We may then convert points of agreement or difference
into separate objects of thought which we call qualities and denote by
*abstract terms*. Thus the term *redness* means something in which a
number of objects agree as to colour, and in virtue of which they are
called red. Redness forms, in fact, the intensive meaning of the term
red.

Abstract terms are strongly distinguished from general terms by
possessing only one kind of meaning; for as they denote qualities
there is nothing which they cannot in addition imply. The adjective
“red” is the name of red objects, but it implies the possession by
them of the quality *redness*; but this latter term has one single
meaning--the quality alone. Thus it arises that abstract terms are
incapable of plurality. Red objects are numerically distinct each
from each, and there are multitudes of such objects; but redness is a
single quality which runs through all those objects, and is the same in
one as it is in another. It is true that we may speak of *rednesses*,
meaning different kinds or tints of redness, just as we may speak of
*colours*, meaning different kinds of colours. But in distinguishing
kinds, degrees, or other differences, we render the terms so far
concrete. In that they are merely red there is but a single nature in
red objects, and so far as things are merely coloured, colour is a
single indivisible quality. Redness, so far as it is redness merely,
is one and the same everywhere, and possesses absolute oneness. In
virtue of this unity we acquire the power of treating all instances of
such quality as we may treat any one. We possess, in short, general
knowledge.


*Substantial Terms.*

Logicians appear to have taken little notice of a class of terms which
partake in certain respects of the character of abstract terms and yet
are undoubtedly the names of concrete existing things. These terms are
the names of substances, such as gold, carbonate of lime, nitrogen, &c.
We cannot speak of two golds, twenty carbonates of lime, or a hundred
nitrogens. There is no such distinction between the parts of a uniform
substance as will allow of a discrimination of numerous individuals.
The qualities of colour, lustre, malleability, density, &c., by which
we recognise gold, extend through its substance irrespective of
particular size or shape. So far as a substance is gold, it is one and
the same everywhere; so that terms of this kind, which I propose to
call *substantial terms*, possess the peculiar unity of abstract terms.
Yet they are not abstract; for gold is of course a tangible visible
body, entirely concrete, and existing independently of other bodies.

It is only when, by actual mechanical division, we break up the uniform
whole which forms the meaning of a substantial term, that we introduce
number. *Piece of gold* is a term capable of plurality; for there may
be a great many pieces discriminated either by their various shapes and
sizes, or, in the absence of such marks, by simultaneously occupying
different parts of space. In substance they are one; as regards the
properties of space they are many.[45] We need not further pursue this
question, which involves the distinction between unity and plurality,
until we consider the principles of number in a subsequent chapter.

  [45] Professor Robertson has criticised my introduction of
  “Substantial Terms” (*Mind*, vol. i. p. 210), and objects, perhaps
  correctly, that the distinction if valid is extra-logical. I am
  inclined to think, however, that the doctrine of terms is, strictly
  speaking, for the most part extra-logical.


*Collective Terms.*

We must clearly distinguish between the *collective* and the *general
meanings* of terms. The same name may be used to denote the whole body
of existing objects of a certain kind, or any one of those objects
taken separately. “Man” may mean the aggregate of existing men, which
we sometimes describe as *mankind*; it is also the general name
applying to any man. The vegetable kingdom is the name of the whole
aggregate of *plants*, but “plant” itself is a general name applying
to any one or other plant. Every material object may be conceived as
divisible into parts, and is therefore collective as regards those
parts. The animal body is made up of cells and fibres, a crystal
of molecules; wherever physical division, or as it has been called
*partition*, is possible, there we deal in reality with a collective
whole. Thus the greater number of general terms are at the same time
collective as regards each individual whole which they denote.

It need hardly be pointed out that we must not infer of a collective
whole what we know only of the parts, nor of the parts what we know
only of the whole. The relation of whole and part is not one of
identity, and does not allow of substitution. There may nevertheless be
qualities which are true alike of the whole and of its parts. A number
of organ-pipes tuned in unison produce an aggregate of sound which
is of exactly the same pitch as each separate sound. In the case of
substantial terms, certain qualities may be present equally in each
minutest part as in the whole. The chemical nature of the largest mass
of pure carbonate of lime is the same as the nature of the smallest
particle. In the case of abstract terms, again, we cannot draw a
distinction between whole and part; what is true of redness in any case
is always true of redness, so far as it is merely red.


*Synthesis of Terms.*

We continually combine simple terms together so as to form new terms
of more complex meaning. Thus, to increase the intension of meaning of
a term we write it with an adjective or a phrase of adjectival nature.
By joining “brittle” to “metal,” we obtain a combined term, “brittle
metal,” which denotes a certain portion of the metals, namely, such as
are selected on account of possessing the quality of *brittleness*.
As we have already seen, “brittle metal” possesses less extension and
greater intension than metal. Nouns, prepositional phrases, participial
phrases and subordinate propositions may also be added to terms so as
to increase their intension and decrease their extension.

In our symbolic language we need some mode of indicating this junction
of terms, and the most convenient device will be the juxtaposition of
the letter-terms. Thus if A mean brittle, and B mean metal, then AB
will mean brittle metal. Nor need there be any limit to the number of
letters thus joined together, or the complexity of the notions which
they may represent.

Thus if we take the letters

  P = metal,
  Q = white,
  R = monovalent,
  S = of specific gravity 10·5,
  T = melting above 1000° C.,
  V = good conductor of heat and electricity,

then we can form a combined term PQRSTV, which will denote “a white
monovalent metal, of specific gravity 10·5, melting above 1000° C., and
a good conductor of heat and electricity.”

There are many grammatical usages concerning the junction of words and
phrases to which we need pay no attention in logic. We can never say
in ordinary language “of wood table,” meaning “table of wood;” but we
may consider “of wood” as logically an exact equivalent of “wooden”; so
that if

  X = of wood,
  Y = table,

there is no reason why, in our symbols, XY should not be just as
correct an expression for “table of wood ” as YX. In this case indeed
we might substitute for “of wood ” the corresponding adjective
“wooden,” but we should often fail to find any adjective answering
exactly to a phrase. There is no single word by which we could express
the notion “of specific gravity 10·5:” but logically we may consider
these words as forming an adjective; and denoting this by S and metal
by P, we may say that SP means “metal of specific gravity 10·5.” It
is one of many advantages in these blank letter-symbols that they
enable us completely to neglect all grammatical peculiarities and to
fix our attention solely on the purely logical relations involved.
Investigation will probably show that the rules of grammar are mainly
founded upon traditional usage and have little logical signification.
This indeed is sufficiently proved by the wide grammatical differences
which exist between languages, though the logical foundation must be
the same.


*Symbolic Expression of the Law of Contradiction.*

The synthesis of terms is subject to the all-important Law of
Thought, described in a previous section (p. 5) and called the Law of
Contradiction, It is self-evident that no quality can be both present
and absent at the same time and place. This fundamental condition
of all thought and of all existence is expressed symbolically by a
rule that a term and its negative shall never be allowed to come
into combination. Such combined terms as A*a*, B*b*, C*c*, &c., are
self-contradictory and devoid of all intelligible meaning. If they
could represent anything, it would be what cannot exist, and cannot
even be imagined in the mind. They can therefore only enter into our
consideration to suffer immediate exclusion. The criterion of false
reasoning, as we shall find, is that it involves self-contradiction,
the affirming and denying of the same statement. We might represent
the object of all reasoning as the separation of the consistent and
possible from the inconsistent and impossible; and we cannot make any
statement except a truism without implying that certain combinations of
terms are contradictory and excluded from thought. To assert that “all
A’s are B’s” is equivalent to the assertion that “A’s which are not B’s
cannot exist.”

It will be convenient to have the means of indicating the exclusion of
the self-contradictory, and we may use the familiar sign for *nothing*,
the cipher 0. Thus the second law of thought may be symbolised in the
forms

  A*a* = 0     AB*b* = 0     ABC*a* = 0

We may variously describe the meaning of 0 in logic as the
*non-existent*, the *impossible*, the *self-inconsistent*, the
*inconceivable*. Close analogy exists between this meaning and its
mathematical signification.


*Certain Special Conditions of Logical Symbols.*

In order that we may argue and infer truly we must treat our logical
symbols according to the fundamental laws of Identity and Difference.
But in thus using our symbols we shall frequently meet with
combinations of which the meaning will not at first sight be apparent.
If in one case we learn that an object is “yellow and round,” and in
another case that it is “round and yellow,” there arises the question
whether these two descriptions are identical in meaning or not. Again,
if we proved that an object was “round round,” the meaning of such an
expression would be open to doubt. Accordingly we must take notice,
before proceeding further, of certain special laws which govern the
combination of logical terms.

In the first place the combination of a logical term with itself is
without effect, just as the repetition of a statement does not alter
the meaning of the statement; “a round round object” is simply “a round
object.” What is yellow yellow is merely yellow; metallic metals cannot
differ from metals, nor circular circles from circles. In our symbolic
language we may similarly hold that AA is identical with A, or

  A = AA = AAA = &c.

The late Professor Boole is the only logician in modern times who has
drawn attention to this remarkable property of logical terms;[46]
but in place of the name which he gave to the law, I have proposed
to call it The Law of Simplicity.[47] Its high importance will only
become apparent when we attempt to determine the relations of logical
and mathematical science. Two symbols of quantity, and only two, seem
to obey this law; we may say that 1 × 1 = 1, and 0 × 0 = 0 (taking 0
to mean absolute zero or 1 – 1); there is apparently no other number
which combined with itself gives an unchanged result. I shall point
out, however, in the chapter upon Number, that in reality all numerical
symbols obey this logical principle.

  [46] *Mathematical Analysis of Logic*, Cambridge, 1847, p. 17. *An
  Investigation of the Laws of Thought*, London, 1854, p. 31.

  [47] *Pure Logic*, p. 15.

It is curious that this Law of Simplicity, though almost unnoticed
in modern times, was known to Boëthius, who makes a singular remark
in his treatise *De Trinitate et Unitate Dei* (p. 959). He says: “If
I should say sun, sun, sun, I should not have made three suns, but I
should have named one sun so many times.”[48] Ancient discussions about
the doctrine of the Trinity drew more attention to subtle questions
concerning the nature of unity and plurality than has ever since been
given to them.

  [48] “Velut si dicam, Sol, Sol, Sol, non tres soles effecerim, sed
  uno toties prædicaverim.”

It is a second law of logical symbols that order of combination is a
matter of indifference. “Rich and rare gems” are the same as “rare and
rich gems,” or even as “gems, rich and rare.” Grammatical, rhetorical,
or poetic usage may give considerable significance to order of
expression. The limited power of our minds prevents our grasping many
ideas at once, and thus the order of statement may produce some effect,
but not in a simply logical manner. All life proceeds in the succession
of time, and we are obliged to write, speak, or even think of things
and their qualities one after the other; but between the things and
their qualities there need be no such relation of order in time or
space. The sweetness of sugar is neither before nor after its weight
and solubility. The hardness of a metal, its colour, weight, opacity,
malleability, electric and chemical properties, are all coexistent
and coextensive, pervading the metal and every part of it in perfect
community, none before nor after the others. In our words and symbols
we cannot observe this natural condition; we must name one quality
first and another second, just as some one must be the first to sign a
petition, or to walk foremost in a procession. In nature there is no
such precedence.

I find that the opinion here stated, to the effect that relations of
space and time do not apply to many of our ideas, is clearly adopted by
Hume in his celebrated *Treatise on Human Nature* (vol. i. p. 410). He
says:[49]--“An object may be said to be no where, when its parts are
not so situated with respect to each other, as to form any figure or
quantity; nor the whole with respect to other bodies so as to answer
to our notions of contiguity or distance. Now this is evidently the
case with all our perceptions and objects, except those of sight and
feeling. A moral reflection cannot be placed on the right hand or on
the left hand of a passion, nor can a smell or sound be either of a
circular or a square figure. These objects and perceptions, so far from
requiring any particular place, are absolutely incompatible with it,
and even the imagination cannot attribute it to them.”

  [49] Book i., Part iv., Section 5.

A little reflection will show that knowledge in the highest perfection
would consist in the *simultaneous* possession of a multitude of
facts. To comprehend a science perfectly we should have every fact
present with every other fact. We must write a book and we must read
it successively word by word, but how infinitely higher would be
our powers of thought if we could grasp the whole in one collective
act of consciousness! Compared with the brutes we do possess some
slight approximation to such power, and it is conceivable that in the
indefinite future mind may acquire an increase of capacity, and be less
restricted to the piecemeal examination of a subject. But I wish here
to make plain that there is no logical foundation for the successive
character of thought and reasoning unavoidable under our present mental
conditions. *We are logically weak and imperfect in respect of the
fact that we are obliged to think of one thing after another.* We must
describe metal as “hard and opaque,” or “opaque and hard,” but in the
metal itself there is no such difference of order; the properties are
simultaneous and coextensive in existence.

Setting aside all grammatical peculiarities which render a substantive
less moveable than an adjective, and disregarding any meaning indicated
by emphasis or marked order of words, we may state, as a general law of
logic, that AB is identical with BA, or AB = BA. Similarly, ABC = ACB =
BCA = &c.

Boole first drew attention in recent years to this property of logical
terms, and he called it the property of Commutativeness.[50] He not
only stated the law with the utmost clearness, but pointed out that
it is a Law of Thought rather than a Law of Things. I shall have in
various parts of this work to show how the necessary imperfection of
our symbols expressed in this law clings to our modes of expression,
and introduces complication into the whole body of mathematical
formulæ, which are really founded on a logical basis.

  [50] *Laws of Thought*, p. 29. It is pointed out in the preface to
  this Second Edition that Leibnitz was acquainted with the Laws of
  Simplicity and of Commutativeness.

It is of course apparent that the power of commutation belongs only
to terms related in the simple logical mode of synthesis. No one can
confuse “a house of bricks” with “bricks of a house,” “twelve square
feet” with “twelve feet square,” “the water of crystallization” with
“the crystallization of water.” All relations which involve differences
of time and space are inconvertible; the higher must not be made to
change places with the lower, nor the first with the last. For the
parties concerned there is all the difference in the world between A
killing B and B killing A. The law of commutativeness simply asserts
that difference of order does not attach to the connection between the
properties and circumstances of a thing--to what I call *simple logical
relation*.




CHAPTER III.

PROPOSITIONS.


We now proceed to consider the variety of forms of propositions in
which the truths of science must be expressed. I shall endeavour to
show that, however diverse these forms may be, they all admit the
application of the one same principle of inference that what is true of
a thing is true of the like or same. This principle holds true whatever
be the kind or manner of the likeness, provided proper regard be had to
its nature. Propositions may assert an identity of time, space, manner,
quantity, degree, or any other circumstance in which things may agree
or differ.

We find an instance of a proposition concerning time in the
following:--“The year in which Newton was born, was the year in which
Galileo died.” This proposition expresses an approximate identity of
time between two events; hence whatever is true of the year in which
Galileo died is true of that in which Newton was born, and *vice
versâ*. “Tower Hill is the place where Raleigh was executed” expresses
an identity of place; and whatever is true of the one spot is true
of the spot otherwise defined, but in reality the same. In ordinary
language we have many propositions obscurely expressing identities
of number, quantity, or degree. “So many men, so many minds,” is a
proposition concerning number, that is to say, an equation; whatever
is true of the number of men is true of the number of minds, and
*vice versâ*. “The density of Mars is (nearly) the same as that of
the Earth,” “The force of gravity is directly as the product of the
masses, and inversely as the square of the distance,” are propositions
concerning magnitude or degree. Logicians have not paid adequate
attention to the great variety of propositions which can be stated by
the use of the little conjunction *as*, together with *so*. “As the
home so the people,” is a proposition expressing identity of manner;
and a great number of similar propositions all indicating some kind of
resemblance might be quoted. Whatever be the special kind of identity,
all such expressions are subject to the great principle of inference;
but as we shall in later parts of this work treat more particularly of
inference in cases of number and magnitude, we will here confine our
attention to logical propositions which involve only notions of quality.


*Simple Identities.*

The most important class of propositions consists of those which fall
under the formula

  A = B,

and may be called *simple identities*. I may instance, in the first
place, those most elementary propositions which express the exact
similarity of a quality encountered in two or more objects. I may
compare the colour of the Pacific Ocean with that of the Atlantic, and
declare them identical. I may assert that “the smell of a rotten egg
is like that of hydrogen sulphide;” “the taste of silver hyposulphite
is like that of cane sugar;” “the sound of an earthquake resembles
that of distant artillery.” Such are propositions stating, accurately
or otherwise, the identity of simple physical sensations. Judgments of
this kind are necessarily pre-supposed in more complex judgments. If
I declare that “this coin is made of gold,” I must base the judgment
upon the exact likeness of the substance in several qualities to
other pieces of substance which are undoubtedly gold. I must make
judgments of the colour, the specific gravity, the hardness, and of
other mechanical and chemical properties; each of these judgments is
expressed in an elementary proposition, “the colour of this coin is the
colour of gold,” and so on. Even when we establish the identity of a
thing with itself under a different name or aspect, it is by distinct
judgments concerning single circumstances. To prove that the Homeric
χαλκός is copper we must show the identity of each quality recorded of
χαλκός with a quality of copper. To establish Deal as the landing-place
of Cæsar all material circumstances must be shown to agree. If the
modern Wroxeter is the ancient Uriconium, there must be the like
agreement of all features of the country not subject to alteration by
time.

Such identities must be expressed in the form A = B. We may say

  Colour of Pacific Ocean = Colour of Atlantic Ocean.
  Smell of rotten egg = Smell of hydrogen sulphide.

In these and similar propositions we assert identity of single
qualities or causes of sensation. In the same form we may also express
identity of any group of qualities, as in

  χαλκός = Copper.
  Deal = Landing-place of Cæsar.

A multitude of propositions involving singular terms fall into the same
form, as in

  The Pole star = The slowest-moving star.
  Jupiter = The greatest of the planets.
  The ringed planet = The planet having seven satellites.
  The Queen of England = The Empress of India.
  The number two = The even prime number.
  Honesty = The best policy.

In mathematical and scientific theories we often meet with simple
identities capable of expression in the same form. Thus in mechanical
science “The process for finding the resultant of forces = the process
for finding the resultant of simultaneous velocities.” Theorems in
geometry often give results in this form, as

  Equilateral triangles = Equiangular triangles.
  Circle = Finite plane curve of constant curvature.
  Circle = Curve of least perimeter.

The more profound and important laws of nature are often expressible in
the form of simple identities; in addition to some instances which have
already been given, I may suggest,

  Crystals of cubical system = Crystals not possessing the power of
  double refraction.

All definitions are necessarily of this form, whether the objects
defined be many, few, or singular. Thus we may say,

  Common salt = Sodium chloride.
  Chlorophyl = Green colouring matter of leaves.
  Square = Equal-sided rectangle.

It is an extraordinary fact that propositions of this elementary form,
all-important and very numerous as they are, had no recognised place
in Aristotle’s system of Logic. Accordingly their importance was
overlooked until very recent times, and logic was the most deformed
of sciences. But it is impossible that Aristotle or any other person
should avoid constantly using them; not a term could be defined
without their use. In one place at least Aristotle actually notices a
proposition of the kind. He observes: “We sometimes say that that white
thing is Socrates, or that the object approaching is Callias.”[51] Here
we certainly have simple identity of terms; but he considered such
propositions purely accidental, and came to the unfortunate conclusion,
that “Singulars cannot be predicated of other terms.”

  [51] *Prior Analytics*, i. cap. xxvii. 3.

Propositions may also express the identity of extensive groups of
objects taken collectively or in one connected whole; as when we say,

  The Queen, Lords, and Commons = The Legislature of the United Kingdom.

When Blackstone asserts that “The only true and natural foundation of
society are the wants and fears of individuals,” we must interpret him
as meaning that the whole of the wants and fears of individuals in the
aggregate form the foundation of society. But many propositions which
might seem to be collective are but groups of singular propositions or
identities. When we say “Potassium and sodium are the metallic bases of
potash and soda,” we obviously mean,

  Potassium = Metallic base of potash;
  Sodium = Metallic base of soda.

It is the work of grammatical analysis to separate the various
propositions often combined into a single sentence. Logic cannot be
properly required to interpret the forms and devices of language, but
only to treat the meaning when clearly exhibited.


*Partial Identities.*

A second highly important kind of proposition is that which I propose
to call *a partial identity*. When we say that “All mammalia are
vertebrata,” we do not mean that mammalian animals are identical with
vertebrate animals, but only that the mammalia form a *part of the
class vertebrata*. Such a proposition was regarded in the old logic as
asserting the inclusion of one class in another, or of an object in a
class. It was called a universal affirmative proposition, because the
attribute *vertebrate* was affirmed of the whole subject *mammalia*;
but the attribute was said to be *undistributed*, because not all
vertebrata were of necessity involved in the proposition. Aristotle,
overlooking the importance of simple identities, and indeed almost
denying their existence, unfortunately founded his system upon the
notion of inclusion in a class, instead of adopting the basis of
identity. He regarded inference as resting upon the rule that what is
true of the containing class is true of the contained, in place of the
vastly more general rule that what is true of a class or thing is true
of the like. Thus he not only reduced logic to a fragment of its proper
self, but destroyed the deep analogies which bind together logical and
mathematical reasoning. Hence a crowd of defects, difficulties and
errors which will long disfigure the first and simplest of the sciences.

It is surely evident that the relation of inclusion rests upon the
relation of identity. Mammalian animals cannot be included among
vertebrates unless they be identical with part of the vertebrates.
Cabinet Ministers are included almost always in the class Members of
Parliament, because they are identical with some who sit in Parliament.
We may indicate this identity with a part of the larger class in
various ways; as for instance,

  Mammalia = part of the vertebrata.
  Diatomaceæ = a class of plants.
  Cabinet Ministers = some members of Parliament.
  Iron = a metal.

In ordinary language the verbs *is* and *are* express mere inclusion
more often than not. *Men are mortals*, means that *men* form a part
of the class *mortal*; but great confusion exists between this sense
of the verb and that in which it expresses identity, as in “The sun is
the centre of the planetary system.” The introduction of the indefinite
article *a* often expresses partiality; when we say “Iron is a metal”
we clearly mean that iron is *one only* of several metals.

Certain recent logicians have proposed to avoid the indefiniteness
in question by what is called the Quantification of the Predicate,
and they have generally used the little word *some* to show that only
a part of the predicate is identical with the subject. *Some* is an
*indeterminate adjective*; it implies unknown qualities by which we
might select the part in question if the qualities were known, but
it gives no hint as to their nature. I might make use of such an
indeterminate sign to express partial identities in this work. Thus,
taking the special symbol V = Some, the general form of a partial
identity would be A = VB, and in Boole’s Logic expressions of the
kind were much used. But I believe that indeterminate symbols only
introduce complexity, and destroy the beauty and simple universality
of the system which may be created without their use. A vague word
like *some* is only used in ordinary language by *ellipsis*, and to
avoid the trouble of attaining accuracy. We can always employ more
definite expressions if we like; but when once the indefinite *some* is
introduced we cannot replace it by the special description. We do not
know whether *some* colour is red, yellow, blue, or what it is; but on
the other hand *red* colour is certainly *some* colour.

Throughout this system of logic I shall dispense with such indefinite
expressions; and this can readily be done by substituting one of the
other terms. To express the proposition “All A’s are some B’s” I shall
not use the form A = VB, but

  A = AB.

This formula states that the class A is identical with the class AB;
and as the latter must be a part at least of the class B, it implies
the inclusion of the class A in that of B. We might represent our
former example thus,

  Mammalia = Mammalian vertebrata.

This proposition asserts identity between a part (or it may be the
whole) of the vertebrata and the mammalia. If it is asked What part?
the proposition affords no answer, except that it is the part which is
mammalian; but the assertion “mammalia = some vertebrata” tells us no
more.

It is quite likely that some readers will think this mode of
representing the universal affirmative proposition artificial and
complicated. I will not undertake to convince them of the opposite
at this point of my exposition. Justification for it will be found,
not so much in the immediate treatment of this proposition, as in the
general harmony which it will enable us to disclose between all parts
of reasoning. I have no doubt that this is the critical difficulty in
the relation of logical to other forms of reasoning. Grant this mode of
denoting that “all A’s are B’s,” and I fear no further difficulties;
refuse it, and we find want of analogy and endless anomaly in every
direction. It is on general grounds that I hope to show overwhelming
reasons for seeking to reduce every kind of proposition to the form of
an identity.

I may add that not a few logicians have accepted this view of the
universal affirmative proposition. Leibnitz, in his *Difficultates
Quædam Logicæ*, adopts it, saying, “Omne A est B; id est æquivalent AB
et A, seu A non B est nonens.” Boole employed the logical equation *x*
= *xy* concurrently with *x* = *vy*; and Spalding[52] distinctly
says that the proposition “all metals are minerals” might be described
as an assertion of *partial identity* between the two classes. Hence
the name which I have adopted for the proposition.

  [52] *Encyclopædia Britannica*, Eighth Ed. art. Logic, sect. 37,
  note. 8vo. reprint, p. 79.


*Limited Identities.*

An important class of propositions have the form

  AB = AC,

expressing the identity of the class AB with the class AC. In other
words, “Within the sphere of the class A, all the B’s are all the
C’s;” or again, “The B’s and C’s, which are A’s, are identical.” But
it will be observed that nothing is asserted concerning things which
are outside of the class A; and thus the identity is of limited extent.
It is the proposition B = C limited to the sphere of things called A.
Thus we may say, with some approximation to truth, that “Large plants
are plants devoid of locomotive power.”

A barrister may make numbers of most general statements concerning
the relations of persons and things in the course of an argument, but
it is of course to be understood that he speaks only of persons and
things under the English Law. Even mathematicians make statements which
are not true with absolute generality. They say that imaginary roots
enter into equations by pairs; but this is only true under the tacit
condition that the equations in question shall not have imaginary
coefficients.[53] The universe, in short, within which they habitually
discourse is that of equations with real coefficients. These implied
limitations form part of that great mass of tacit knowledge which
accompanies all special arguments.

  [53] De Morgan, *On the Root of any Function*. Cambridge
  Philosophical Transactions, 1867, vol. xi. p. 25.

To De Morgan is due the remark, that we do usually think and argue in
a limited universe or sphere of notions, even when it is not expressly
stated.[54]

  [54] *Syllabus of a proposed System of Logic*, §§ 122, 123.

It is worthy of inquiry whether all identities are not really limited
to an implied sphere of meaning. When we make such a plain statement as
“Gold is malleable” we obviously speak of gold only in its solid state;
when we say that “Mercury is a liquid metal” we must be understood to
exclude the frozen condition to which it may be reduced in the Arctic
regions. Even when we take such a fundamental law of nature as “All
substances gravitate,” we must mean by substance, material substance,
not including that basis of heat, light, and electrical undulations
which occupies space and possesses many wonderful mechanical
properties, but not gravity. The proposition then is really of the form

  Material substance = Material gravitating substance.


*Negative Propositions.*

In every act of intellect we are engaged with a certain identity or
difference between things or sensations compared together. Hitherto
I have treated only of identities; and yet it might seem that the
relation of difference must be infinitely more common than that of
likeness. One thing may resemble a great many other things, but then it
differs from all remaining things in the world. Diversity may almost be
said to constitute life, being to thought what motion is to a river.
The perception of an object involves its discrimination from all other
objects. But we may nevertheless be said to detect resemblance as often
as we detect difference. We cannot, in fact, assert the existence of
a difference, without at the same time implying the existence of an
agreement.

If I compare mercury, for instance, with other metals, and decide that
it is *not solid*, here is a difference between mercury and solid
things, expressed in a negative proposition; but there must be implied,
at the same time, an agreement between mercury and the other substances
which are not solid. As it is impossible to separate the vowels of the
alphabet from the consonants without at the same time separating the
consonants from the vowels, so I cannot select as the object of thought
*solid things*, without thereby throwing together into another class
all things which are *not solid*. The very fact of not possessing a
quality, constitutes a new quality which may be the ground of judgment
and classification. In this point of view, agreement and difference are
ever the two sides of the same act of intellect, and it becomes equally
possible to express the same judgment in the one or other aspect.

Between affirmation and negation there is accordingly a perfect
equilibrium. Every affirmative proposition implies a negative one, and
*vice versâ*. It is even a matter of indifference, in a logical point
of view, whether a positive or negative term be used to denote a given
quality and the class of things possessing it. If the ordinary state
of a man’s body be called *good health*, then in other circumstances
he is said *not to be in good health*; but we might equally describe
him in the latter state as *sickly*, and in his normal condition he
would be *not sickly*. Animal and vegetable substances are now called
*organic*, so that the other substances, forming an immensely greater
part of the globe, are described negatively as *inorganic*. But we
might, with at least equal logical correctness, have described the
preponderating class of substances as *mineral*, and then vegetable and
animal substances would have been *non-mineral*.

It is plain that any positive term and its corresponding negative
divide between them the whole universe of thought: whatever does not
fall into one must fall into the other, by the third fundamental Law
of Thought, the Law of Duality. It follows at once that there are
two modes of representing a difference. Supposing that the things
represented by A and B are found to differ, we may indicate (see p. 17)
the result of the judgment by the notation

  A ~ B.

We may now represent the same judgment by the assertion that A agrees
with those things which differ from B, or that A agrees with the
not-B’s. Using our notation for negative terms (see p. 14), we obtain

  A = A*b*

as the expression of the ordinary negative proposition. Thus if we
take A to mean quicksilver, and B solid, then we have the following
proposition:--

  Quicksilver = Quicksilver not-solid.

There may also be several other classes of negative propositions, of
which no notice was taken in the old logic. We may have cases where
all A’s are not-B’s, and at the same time all not-B’s are A’s; there
may, in short, be a simple identity between A and not-B, which may be
expressed in the form

  A = *b*.

An example of this form would be

  Conductors of electricity = non-electrics.

We shall also frequently have to deal as results of deduction, with
simple, partial, or limited identities between negative terms, as in
the forms

  *a* = *b*,   *a* = *a**b*,   *a*C = *b*C, etc.

It would be possible to represent affirmative propositions in the
negative form. Thus “Iron is solid,” might be expressed as “Iron is not
not-solid,” or “Iron is not fluid;” or, taking A and *b* for the terms
“iron,” and “not-solid,” the form would be A ~ *b*.

But there are very strong reasons why we should employ all propositions
in their affirmative form. All inference proceeds by the substitution
of equivalents, and a proposition expressed in the form of an identity
is ready to yield all its consequences in the most direct manner. As
will be more fully shown, we can infer *in* a negative proposition,
but not *by* it. Difference is incapable of becoming the ground of
inference; it is only the implied agreement with other differing
objects which admits of deductive reasoning; and it will always be
found advantageous to employ propositions in the form which exhibits
clearly the implied agreements.


*Conversion of Propositions.*

The old books of logic contain many rules concerning the conversion of
propositions, that is, the transposition of the subject and predicate
in such a way as to obtain a new proposition which will be true when
the original proposition is true. The reduction of every proposition to
the form of an identity renders all such rules and processes needless.
Identity is essentially reciprocal. If the colour of the Atlantic Ocean
is the same as that of the Pacific Ocean, that of the Pacific must
be the same as that of the Atlantic. Sodium chloride being identical
with common salt, common salt must be identical with sodium chloride.
If the number of windows in Salisbury Cathedral equals the number of
days in the year, the number of days in the year must equal the number
of the windows. Lord Chesterfield was not wrong when he said, “I will
give anybody their choice of these two truths, which amount to the
same thing; He who loves himself best is the honestest man; or, The
honestest man loves himself best.” Scotus Erigena exactly expresses
this reciprocal character of identity in saying, “There are not two
studies, one of philosophy and the other of religion; true philosophy
is true religion, and true religion is true philosophy.”

A mathematician would not think it worth while to mention that if
*x* = *y* then also *y* = *x*. He would not consider these to be
two equations at all, but one equation accidentally written in two
different manners. In written symbols one of two names must come first,
and the other second, and a like succession must perhaps be observed
in our thoughts: but in the relation of identity there is no need for
succession in order (see p. 33), each is simultaneously equal and
identical to the other. These remarks will hold true both of logical
and mathematical identity; so that I shall consider the two forms

  A = B and B = A

to express exactly the same identity differently written. All need for
rules of conversion disappears, and there will be no single proposition
in the system which may not be written with either end foremost. Thus A
= AB is the same as AB = A, *a*C = *b*C is the same as *b*C = *a*C, and
so forth.

The same remarks are partially true of differences and inequalities,
which are also reciprocal to the extent that one thing cannot differ
from a second without the second differing from the first. Mars differs
in colour from Venus, and Venus must differ from Mars. The Earth
differs from Jupiter in density; therefore Jupiter must differ from the
Earth. Speaking generally, if A ~ B we shall also have B ~ A, and these
two forms may be considered expressions of the same difference. But
the relation of differing things is not wholly reciprocal. The density
of Jupiter does not differ from that of the Earth in the same way that
that of the Earth differs from that of Jupiter. The change of sensation
which we experience in passing from Venus to Mars is not the same as
what we experience in passing back to Venus, but just the opposite
in nature. The colour of the sky is lighter than that of the ocean;
therefore that of the ocean cannot be lighter than that of the sky, but
darker. In these and all similar cases we gain a notion of *direction*
or character of change, and results of immense importance may be shown
to rest on this notion. For the present we shall be concerned with the
mere fact of identity existing or not existing.


*Twofold Interpretation of Propositions.*

Terms, as we have seen (p. 25), may have a meaning either in extension
or intension; and according as one or the other meaning is attributed
to the terms of a proposition, so may a different interpretation be
assigned to the proposition itself. When the terms are abstract we
must read them in intension, and a proposition connecting such terms
must denote the identity or non-identity of the qualities respectively
denoted by the terms. Thus if we say

  Equality = Identity of magnitude,

the assertion means that the circumstance of being equal exactly
corresponds with the circumstance of being identical in magnitude.
Similarly in

  Opacity = Incapability of transmitting light,

the quality of being incapable of transmitting light is declared to be
the same as the intended meaning of the word opacity.

When general names form the terms of a proposition we may apply a
double interpretation. Thus

  Exogens = Dicotyledons

means either that the qualities which belong to all exogens are the
same as those which belong to all dicotyledons, or else that every
individual falling under one name falls equally under the other.
Hence it may be said that there are two distinct fields of logical
thought. We may argue either by the qualitative meaning of names or
by the quantitative, that is, the extensive meaning. Every argument
involving concrete plural terms might be converted into one involving
only abstract singular terms, and *vice versâ*. But there are reasons
for believing that the intensive or qualitative form of reasoning is
the primary and fundamental one. It is sufficient to point out that the
extensive meaning of a name is a changeable and fleeting thing, while
the intensive meaning may nevertheless remain fixed. Very numerous
additions have been lately made to the extensive meanings both of
planet and element. Every iron steam-ship which is made or destroyed
adds to or subtracts from the extensive meaning of the name steam-ship,
without necessarily affecting the intensive meaning. Stage coach means
as much as ever in one way, but in extension the class is nearly
extinct. Chinese railway, on the other hand, is a term represented only
by a single instance; in twenty years it may be the name of a large
class.




CHAPTER IV.

DEDUCTIVE REASONING.


The general principle of inference having been explained in the
previous chapters, and a suitable system of symbols provided, we have
now before us the comparatively easy task of tracing out the most
common and important forms of deductive reasoning. The general problem
of deduction is as follows:--*From one or more propositions called
premises to draw such other propositions as will necessarily be true
when the premises are true.* By deduction we investigate and unfold the
information contained in the premises; and this we can do by one single
rule--*For any term occurring in any proposition substitute the term
which is asserted in any premise to be identical with it.* To obtain
certain deductions, especially those involving negative conclusions, we
shall require to bring into use the second and third Laws of Thought,
and the process of reasoning will then be called *Indirect Deduction*.
In the present chapter, however, I shall confine my attention to
those results which can be obtained by the process of *Direct
Deduction*, that is, by applying to the premises themselves the rule of
substitution. It will be found that we can combine into one harmonious
system, not only the various moods of the ancient syllogism but a great
number of equally important forms of reasoning, which had no recognised
place in the old logic. We can at the same time dispense entirely with
the elaborate apparatus of logical rules and mnemonic lines, which were
requisite so long as the vital principle of reasoning was not clearly
expressed.


*Immediate Inference.*

Probably the simplest of all forms of inference is that which has been
called *Immediate Inference*, because it can be performed upon a single
proposition. It consists in joining an adjective, or other qualifying
clause of the same nature, to both sides of an identity, and asserting
the equivalence of the terms thus produced. For instance, since

  Conductors of electricity = Non-electrics,

it follows that

  Liquid conductors of electricity = Liquid non-electrics.

If we suppose that

  Plants = Bodies decomposing carbonic acid,

it follows that

  Microscopic plants = Microscopic bodies decomposing
    carbonic acid.

In general terms, from the identity

  A = B

we can infer the identity

  AC = BC.

This is but a case of plain substitution; for by the first Law of
Thought it must be admitted that

  AC = AC,

and if, in the second side of this identity, we substitute for A its
equivalent B, we obtain

  AC = BC.

In like manner from the partial identity

  A = AB

we may obtain

  AC = ABC

by an exactly similar act of substitution; and in every other case
the rule will be found capable of verification by the principle of
inference. The process when performed as here described will be quite
free from the liability to error which I have shown[55] to exist in
“Immediate Inference by added Determinants,” as described by Dr.
Thomson.[56]

  [55] *Elementary Lessons in Logic*, p. 86.

  [56] *Outline of the Laws of Thought*, § 87.


*Inference with Two Simple Identities.*

One of the most common forms of inference, and one to which I shall
especially direct attention, is practised with two simple identities.
From the two statements that “London is the capital of England” and
“London is the most populous city in the world,” we instantaneously
draw the conclusion that “The capital of England is the most populous
city in the world.” Similarly, from the identities

  Hydrogen = Substance of least density,
  Hydrogen = Substance of least atomic weight,

we infer

  Substance of least density = Substance of least atomic weight.

The general form of the argument is exhibited in the symbols

           B = A         (1)
           B = C         (2)
  hence    A = C.        (3)

We may describe the result by saying that terms identical with the
same term are identical with each other; and it is impossible to
overlook the analogy to the first axiom of Euclid that “things equal
to the same thing are equal to each other.” It has been very commonly
supposed that this is a fundamental principle of thought, incapable of
reduction to anything simpler. But I entertain no doubt that this form
of reasoning is only one case of the general rule of inference. We have
two propositions, A = B and B = C, and we may for a moment consider
the second one as affirming a truth concerning B, while the former one
informs us that B is identical with A; hence by substitution we may
affirm the same truth of A. It happens in this particular case that the
truth affirmed is identity to C, and we might, if we preferred it, have
considered the substitution as made by means of the second identity in
the first. Having two identities we have a choice of the mode in which
we will make the substitution, though the result is exactly the same in
either case.

Now compare the three following formulæ,

  (1)   A = B = C, hence A = C
  (2)   A = B ~ C, hence A ~ C
  (3)   A ~ B ~ C, no inference.

In the second formula we have an identity and a difference, and we are
able to infer a difference; in the third we have two differences and
are unable to make any inference at all. Because A and C both differ
from B, we cannot tell whether they will or will not differ from each
other. The flowers and leaves of a plant may both differ in colour from
the earth in which the plant grows, and yet they may differ from each
other; in other cases the leaves and stem may both differ from the
soil and yet agree with each other. Where we have difference only we
can make no inference; where we have identity we can infer. This fact
gives great countenance to my assertion that inference proceeds always
through identity, but may be equally well effected in propositions
asserting difference or identity.

Deferring a more complete discussion of this point, I will only mention
now that arguments from double identity occur very frequently, and are
usually taken for granted, owing to their extreme simplicity. In regard
to the equivalence of words this form of inference must be constantly
employed. If the ancient Greek χαλκός is our *copper*, then it must
be the French *cuivre*, the German *kupfer*, the Latin *cuprum*,
because these are words, in one sense at least, equivalent to copper.
Whenever we can give two definitions or expressions for the same term,
the formula applies; thus Senior defined wealth as “All those things,
and those things only, which are transferable, are limited in supply,
and are directly or indirectly productive of pleasure or preventive
of pain.” Wealth is also equivalent to “things which have value in
exchange;” hence obviously, “things which have value in exchange = all
those things, and those things only, which are transferable, &c.” Two
expressions for the same term are often given in the same sentence,
and their equivalence implied. Thus Thomson and Tait say,[57] “The
naturalist may be content to know matter as that which can be perceived
by the senses, or as that which can be acted upon by or can exert
force.” I take this to mean--

  Matter = what can be perceived by the senses;
  Matter = what can be acted upon by or can exert force.

  [57] *Treatise on Natural Philosophy*, vol. i. p. 161.

For the term “matter” in either of these identities we may substitute
its equivalent given in the other definition. Elsewhere they often
employ sentences of the form exemplified in the following:[58] “The
integral curvature, or whole change of direction of an arc of a plane
curve, is the angle through which the tangent has turned as we pass
from one extremity to the other.” This sentence is certainly of the
form--

  The integral curvature = the whole change of direction, &c. = the
  angle through which the tangent has turned, &c.

  [58] *Treatise on Natural Philosophy*, vol. i. p. 6.

Disguised cases of the same kind of inference occur throughout all
sciences, and a remarkable instance is found in algebraic geometry.
Mathematicians readily show that every equation of the form *y* = *mx*
+ *c* corresponds to or represents a straight line; it is also easily
proved that the same equation is equivalent to one of the general form
A*x* + B*y* + C = 0, and *vice versâ*. Hence it follows that every
equation of the form in question, that is to say, every equation of the
first degree, corresponds to or represents a straight line.[59]

  [59] Todhunter’s *Plane Co-ordinate Geometry*, chap. ii. pp. 11–14.


*Inference with a Simple and a Partial Identity.*

A form of reasoning somewhat different from that last considered
consists in inference-between a simple and a partial identity. If we
have two propositions of the forms

  A = B,
  B = BC,

we may then substitute for B in either proposition its equivalent in
the other, getting in both cases A = BC; in this we may if we like make
a second substitution for B, getting

  A = AC.

Thus, since “The Mont Blanc is the highest mountain in Europe, and
the Mont Blanc is deeply covered with snow,” we infer by an obvious
substitution that “The highest mountain in Europe is deeply covered
with snow.” These propositions when rigorously stated fall into the
forms above exhibited.

This mode of inference is constantly employed when for a term we
substitute its definition, or *vice versâ*. The very purpose of a
definition is to allow a single noun to be employed in place of a long
descriptive phrase. Thus, when we say “A circle is a curve of the
second degree,” we may substitute a definition of the circle, getting
“A curve, all points of which are at equal distances from one point, is
a curve of the second degree.” The real forms of the propositions here
given are exactly those shown in the symbolic statement, but in this
and many other cases it will be sufficient to state them in ordinary
elliptical language for sake of brevity. In scientific treatises a
term and its definition are often both given in the same sentence,
as in “The weight of a body in any given locality, or the force
with which the earth attracts it, is proportional to its mass.” The
conjunction *or* in this statement gives the force of equivalence to
the parenthetic phrase, so that the propositions really are

  Weight of a body = force with which the earth attracts it.
  Weight of a body = weight, &c. proportional to its mass.

A slightly different case of inference consists in substituting in a
proposition of the form A = AB, a definition of the term B. Thus from A
= AB and B = C we get A = AC. For instance, we may say that “Metals are
elements” and “Elements are incapable of decomposition.”

  Metal = metal element.
  Element = what is incapable of decomposition.

Hence

  Metal = metal incapable of decomposition.

It is almost needless to point out that the form of these arguments
does not suffer any real modification if some of the terms happen to be
negative; indeed in the last example “incapable of decomposition” may
be treated as a negative term. Taking

  A = metal
  B = element
  C = capable of decomposition
  *c* = incapable of decomposition;

the propositions are of the forms

  A = AB
  B = *c*

whence, by substitution,

  A = A*c*.


*Inference of a Partial from Two Partial Identities.*

However common be the cases of inference already noticed, there is
a form occurring almost more frequently, and which deserves much
attention, because it occupied a prominent place in the ancient
syllogistic system. That system strangely overlooked all the kinds of
argument we have as yet considered, and selected, as the type of all
reasoning, one which employs two partial identities as premises. Thus
from the propositions

  Sodium is a metal               (1)
  Metals conduct electricity,     (2)

we may conclude that

  Sodium conducts electricity.    (3)

Taking A, B, C to represent the three terms respectively, the premises
are of the forms

  A = AB         (1)
  B = BC.        (2)

Now for B in (1) we can substitute its expression as given in (2),
obtaining

  A = ABC,       (3)

or, in words, from

  Sodium = sodium metal,                        (1)
  Metal = metal conducting electricity,         (2)

we infer

  Sodium = sodium metal conducting electricity, (3)

which, in the elliptical language of common life, becomes

  “Sodium conducts electricity.”

The above is a syllogism in the mood called Barbara[60] in the truly
barbarous language of ancient logicians; and the first figure of the
syllogism contained Barbara and three other moods which were esteemed
distinct forms of argument. But it is worthy of notice that, without
any real change in our form of inference, we readily include these
three other moods under Barbara. The negative mood Celarent will be
represented by the example

  [60] An explanation of this and other technical terms of the old
  logic will be found in my *Elementary Lessons in Logic*, Sixth
  Edition, 1876; Macmillan.

           Neptune is a planet,                  (1)
           No planet has retrograde motion;      (2)
  Hence    Neptune has not retrograde motion.    (3)

If we put A for Neptune, B for planet, and C for “having retrograde
motion,” then by the corresponding negative term c, we denote “not
having retrograde motion.” The premises now fall into the forms

  A = AB            (1)
  B = B*c*,         (2)

and by substitution for B, exactly as before, we obtain

  A = AB*c*.        (3)

What is called in the old logic a particular conclusion may be deduced
without any real variation in the symbols. Particular quantity is
indicated, as before mentioned (p. 41), by joining to the term an
indefinite adjective of quantity, such as *some*, *a part of*,
*certain*, &c., meaning that an unknown part of the term enters into
the proposition as subject. Considerable doubt and ambiguity arise out
of the question whether the part may not in some cases be the whole,
and in the syllogism at least it must be understood in this sense.[61]
Now, if we take a letter to represent this indefinite part, we need
make no change in our formulæ to express the syllogisms Darii and
Ferio. Consider the example--

  [61] *Elementary Lessons in Logic*, pp. 67, 79.

  Some metals are of less density than water,      (1)

  All bodies of less density than water will float
  upon the surface of water; hence                 (2)

  Some metals will float upon the surface of
  water.                                           (3)

Let

  A = some metals,
  B = body of less density than water,
  C = floating on the surface of water

then the propositions are evidently as before,

           A = AB,        (1)
           B = BC;        (2)
  hence    A = ABC,       (3)

Thus the syllogism Darii does not really differ from Barbara. If the
reader prefer it, we can readily employ a distinct symbol for the
indefinite sign of quantity.

  Let    P = some,
         Q = metal,

B and C having the same meanings as before. Then the premises become

  PQ = PQB,       (1)
   B = BC;        (2)

hence, by substitution, as before,

  PQ = PQBC.      (3)

Except that the formulæ look a little more complicated there is no
difference whatever.

The mood Ferio is of exactly the same character as Darii or Barbara,
except that it involves the use of a negative term. Take the example,

  Bodies which are equally elastic in all directions do not doubly
  refract light;

  Some crystals are bodies equally elastic in all directions;
  therefore, some crystals do not doubly refract light.

Assigning the letters as follows:--

   A  = some crystals,
   B  = bodies equally elastic in all directions,
   C  = doubly refracting light,
  *c* = not doubly refracting light.

Our argument is of the same form as before, and may be concisely stated
in one line,

  A = AB = AB*c*.

If it is preferred to put PQ for the indefinite *some crystals*, we have

  PQ = PQB = PQB*c*.

The only difference is that the negative term c takes the place of C in
the mood Darii.


*Ellipsis of Terms in Partial Identities.*

The reader will probably have noticed that the conclusion which we
obtain from premises is often more full than that drawn by the old
Aristotelian processes. Thus from “Sodium is a metal,” and “Metals
conduct electricity,” we inferred (p. 55) that “Sodium = sodium, metal,
conducting electricity,” whereas the old logic simply concludes that
“Sodium conducts electricity.” Symbolically, from A = AB, and B = BC,
we get A = ABC, whereas the old logic gets at the most A = AC. It is
therefore well to show that without employing any other principles of
inference than those already described, we may infer A = AC from A =
ABC, though we cannot infer the latter more full and accurate result
from the former. We may show this most simply as follows:--

By the first Law of Thought it is evident that

  AA = AA;

and if we have given the proposition A = ABC, we may substitute for
both the A’s in the second side of the above, obtaining

  AA = ABC . ABC.

But from the property of logical symbols expressed in the Law of
Simplicity (p. 33) some of the repeated letters may be made to
coalesce, and we have

  A = ABC . C.

Substituting again for ABC its equivalent A, we obtain

  A = AC,

the desired result.

By a similar process of reasoning it may be shown that we can always
drop out any term appearing in one member of a proposition, provided
that we substitute for it the whole of the other member. This
process was described in my first logical Essay,[62] as *Intrinsic
Elimination*, but it might perhaps be better entitled the *Ellipsis
of Terms*. It enables us to get rid of needless terms by strict
substitutive reasoning.

  [62] *Pure Logic*, p. 19.


*Inference of a Simple from Two Partial Identities.*

Two terms may be connected together by two partial identities in yet
another manner, and a case of inference then arises which is of the
highest importance. In the two premises

  A = AB      (1)
  B = AB      (2)

the second member of each is the same; so that we can by obvious
substitution obtain

  A = B.

Thus, in plain geometry we readily prove that “Every equilateral
triangle is also an equiangular triangle,” and we can with equal ease
prove that “Every equiangular triangle is an equilateral triangle.”
Thence by substitution, as explained above, we pass to the simple
identity,

  Equilateral triangle = equiangular triangle.

We thus prove that one class of triangles is entirely identical with
another class; that is to say, they differ only in our way of naming
and regarding them.

The great importance of this process of inference arises from the
fact that the conclusion is more simple and general than either of
the premises, and contains as much information as both of them put
together. It is on this account constantly employed in inductive
investigation, as will afterwards be more fully explained, and it is
the natural mode by which we arrive at a conviction of the truth of
simple identities as existing between classes of numerous objects.


*Inference of a Limited from Two Partial Identities.*

We have considered some arguments which are of the type treated by
Aristotle in the first figure of the syllogism. But there exist two
other types of argument which employ a pair of partial identities. If
our premises are as shown in these symbols,

  B = AB       (1)
  B = CB,      (2)

we may substitute for B either by (1) in (2) or by (2) in (1), and by
both modes we obtain the conclusion

  AB = CB,      (3)

a proposition of the kind which we have called a limited identity
(p. 42). Thus, for example,

  Potassium = potassium metal                               (1)
  Potassium = potassium capable of floating on water;       (2)

hence

  Potassium metal = potassium capable of floating on water. (3)

This is really a syllogism of the mood Darapti in the third figure,
except that we obtain a conclusion of a more exact character than
the old syllogism gives. From the premises “Potassium is a metal”
and “Potassium floats on water,” Aristotle would have inferred that
“Some metals float on water.” But if inquiry were made what the “some
metals” are, the answer would certainly be “Metal which is potassium.”
Hence Aristotle’s conclusion simply leaves out some of the information
afforded in the premises. It even leaves us open to interpret the
*some metals* in a wider sense than we are warranted in doing. From
these distinct defects of the old syllogism the process of substitution
is free, and the new process only incurs the possible objection of
being tediously minute and accurate.


*Miscellaneous Forms of Deductive Inference.*

The more common forms of deductive reasoning having been exhibited
and demonstrated on the principle of substitution, there still remain
many, in fact an indefinite number, which may be explained with nearly
equal ease. Such as involve the use of disjunctive propositions will
be described in a later chapter, and several of the syllogistic moods
which include negative terms will be more conveniently treated after
we have introduced the symbolic use of the second and third laws of
thought.

We sometimes meet with a chain of propositions which allow of repeated
substitution, and form an argument called in the old logic a Sorites.
Take, for instance, the premises

  Iron is a metal,                                  (1)
  Metals are good conductors of electricity,        (2)
  Good conductors of electricity are useful for
    telegraphic purposes.                           (3)

It obviously follows that

  Iron is useful for telegraphic purposes.          (4)

Now if we take our letters thus,

  A = Iron, B = metal, C = good conductor of electricity, D = useful
  for telegraphic purposes,

the premises will assume the forms

  A = AB,             (1)
  B = BC,             (2)
  C = CD.             (3)

For B in (1) we can substitute its equivalent in (2) obtaining, as
before,

  A = ABC.

Substituting for C in this intermediate result its equivalent as given
in (3), we obtain the complete conclusion

  A = ABCD.           (4)

The full interpretation is that *Iron is iron, metal, good conductor of
electricity, useful for telegraphic purposes*, which is abridged in
common language by the ellipsis of the circumstances which are not of
immediate importance.

Instead of all the propositions being exactly of the same kind as
in the last example, we may have a series of premises of various
character; for instance,

Common salt is sodium chloride,                               (1)

Sodium chloride crystallizes in a cubical form,               (2)

What crystallizes in a cubical form does not possess the power of
double refraction;                                            (3)

it will follow that

Common salt does not possess the power of double refraction.  (4)

Taking our letter-terms thus,

  A = Common salt,
  B = Sodium chloride,
  C = Crystallizing in a cubical form,
  D = Possessing the power of double refraction,

we may state the premises in the forms

  A = B,              (1)
  B = BC,             (2)
  C = C*d*.           (3)

Substituting by (3) in (2) and then by (2) as thus altered in (1) we
obtain

  A = BC*d*,          (4)

which is a more precise version of the common conclusion.

We often meet with a series of propositions describing the qualities or
circumstances of the one same thing, and we may combine them all into
one proposition by the process of substitution. This case is, in fact,
that which Dr. Thomson has called “Immediate Inference by the sum of
several predicates,” and his example will serve my purpose well.[63]
He describes copper as “A metal--of a red colour--and disagreeable
smell--and taste--all the preparations of which are poisonous--which is
highly malleable--ductile--and tenacious--with a specific gravity of
about 8.83.” If we assign the letter A to copper, and the succeeding
letters of the alphabet in succession to the series of predicates, we
have nine distinct statements, of the form A = AB (1) A = AC (2) A = AD
(3) ... A = AK (9). We can readily combine these propositions into one
by substituting for A in the second side of (1) its expression in (2).
We thus get

  [63] *An Outline of the Necessary Laws of Thought*, Fifth Ed. p. 161.

  A = ABC,

and by repeating the process over and over again we obviously get the
single proposition

  A = ABCD ... JK.

But Dr. Thomson is mistaken in supposing that we can obtain in
this manner a *definition* of copper. Strictly speaking, the above
proposition is only a *description* of copper, and all the ordinary descriptions
of substances in scientific works may be summed up in this form. Thus
we may assert of the organic substances called Paraffins that they are
all saturated hydrocarbons, incapable of uniting with other substances,
produced by heating the alcoholic iodides with zinc, and so on. It may
be shown that no amount of ordinary description can be equivalent to a
definition of any substance.


*Fallacies.*

I have hitherto been engaged in showing that all the forms of
reasoning of the old syllogistic logic, and an indefinite number of
other forms in addition, may be readily and clearly explained on the
single principle of substitution. It is now desirable to show that the
same principle will prevent us falling into fallacies. So long as we
exactly observe the one rule of substitution of equivalents it will
be impossible to commit a *paralogism*, that is to break any one of
the elaborate rules of the ancient system. The one new rule is thus
proved to be as powerful as the six, eight, or more rules by which the
correctness of syllogistic reasoning was guarded.

It was a fundamental rule, for instance, that two negative premises
could give no conclusion. If we take the propositions

  Granite is not a sedimentary rock,    (1)
  Basalt is not a sedimentary rock,     (2)

we ought not to be able to draw any inference concerning the relation
between granite and basalt. Taking our letter-terms thus:

  A = granite,  B = sedimentary rock,  C = basalt,

the premises may be expressed in the forms

  A ~ B,          (1)
  C ~ B.          (2)

We have in this form two statements of difference; but the principle
of inference can only work with a statement of agreement or identity
(p. 63). Thus our rule gives us no power whatever of drawing any
inference; this is exactly in accordance with the fifth rule of the
syllogism.

It is to be remembered, indeed, that we claim the power of always
turning a negative proposition into an affirmative one (p. 45); and it
might seem that the old rule against negative premises would thus be
circumvented. Let us try. The premises (1) and (2) when affirmatively
stated take the forms

  A = A*b*        (1)
  C = C*b*.       (2)

The reader will find it impossible by the rule of substitution to
discover a relation between A and C. Three terms occur in the above
premises, namely A, *b*, and C; but they are so combined that no term
occurring in one has its exact equivalent stated in the other. No
substitution can therefore be made, and the principle of the fifth rule
of the syllogism holds true. Fallacy is impossible.

It would be a mistake, however, to suppose that the mere occurrence of
negative terms in both premises of a syllogism renders them incapable
of yielding a conclusion. The old rule informed us that from two
negative premises no conclusion could be drawn, but it is a fact that
the rule in this bare form does not hold universally true; and I am not
aware that any precise explanation has been given of the conditions
under which it is or is not imperative. Consider the following example:

  Whatever is not metallic is not capable of powerful
    magnetic influence,                                  (1)
  Carbon is not metallic,                                (2)
  Therefore, carbon is not capable of powerful magnetic
    influence.                                           (3)

Here we have two distinctly negative premises (1) and (2), and yet they
yield a perfectly valid negative conclusion (3). The syllogistic rule
is actually falsified in its bare and general statement. In this and
many other cases we can convert the propositions into affirmative ones
which will yield a conclusion by substitution without any difficulty.
To show this let

  A = carbon,                B = metallic,
  C = capable of powerful magnetic influence.

The premises readily take the forms

  *b* = *bc*,      (1)
   A  =  A*b*,     (2)

and substitution for *b* in (2) by means of (1) gives the conclusion

  A = A*bc*.       (3)

Our principle of inference then includes the rule of negative premises
whenever it is true, and discriminates correctly between the cases
where it does and does not hold true.

The paralogism, anciently called *the Fallacy of Undistributed Middle*,
is also easily exhibited and infallibly avoided by our system. Let the
premises be

  Hydrogen is an element,       (1)
  All metals are elements.      (2)

According to the syllogistic rules the middle term “element” is here
undistributed, and no conclusion can be obtained; we cannot tell then
whether hydrogen is or is not a metal. Represent the terms as follows

  A = hydrogen,
  B = element,
  C = metal.

The premises then become

  A = AB,          (1)
  C = CB.          (2)

The reader will here, as in a former page (p. 62), find it impossible
to make any substitution. The only term which occurs in both premises
is B, but it is differently combined in the two premises. For B we
must not substitute A, which is equivalent to AB, not to B. Nor must
we confuse together CB and AB, which, though they contain one common
letter, are different aggregate terms. The rule of substitution gives
us no right to decompose combinations; and if we adhere rigidly to the
rule, that if two terms are stated to be equivalent we may substitute
one for the other, we cannot commit the fallacy. It is apparent that
the form of premises stated above is the same as that which we obtained
by translating two negative premises into the affirmative form.

The old fallacy, technically called the *Illicit Process of the Major
Term*, is more easy to commit and more difficult to detect than any
other breach of the syllogistic rules. In our system it could hardly
occur. From the premises

  All planets are subject to gravity,    (1)
  Fixed stars are not planets,           (2)

we might inadvertently but fallaciously infer that, “Fixed stars are
not subject to gravity.” To reduce the premises to symbolic form, let

  A = planet
  B = fixed star
  C = subject to gravity;

then we have the propositions

  A = AC           (1)
  B = B*a*.        (2)

The reader will try in vain to produce from these premises by
legitimate substitution any relation between B and C; he could not then
commit the fallacy of asserting that B is not C.

There remain two other kinds of paralogism, commonly known as the
fallacy of Four Terms and the Illicit Process of the Minor Term. They
are so evidently impossible while we obey the rule of the substitution
of equivalents, that it is not necessary to give any illustrations.
When there are four distinct terms in two propositions as in A = B
and C = D, there could evidently be no opening for substitution. As
to the Illicit Process of the Minor Term it consists in a flagrant
substitution for a term of another wider term which is not known to be
equivalent to it, and which is therefore not allowed by our rule to be
substituted for it.




CHAPTER V.

DISJUNCTIVE PROPOSITIONS.


In the previous chapter I have exhibited various cases of deductive
reasoning by the process of substitution, avoiding the introduction of
disjunctive propositions; but we cannot long defer the consideration of
this more complex class of identities. General terms arise, as we have
seen (p. 24), from classifying or mentally uniting together all objects
which agree in certain qualities, the value of this union consisting in
the fact that the power of knowledge is multiplied thereby. In forming
such classes or general notions, we overlook or abstract the points of
difference which exist between the objects joined together, and fix our
attention only on the points of agreement. But every process of thought
may be said to have its inverse process, which consists in undoing the
effects of the direct process. Just as division undoes multiplication,
and evolution undoes involution, so we must have a process which undoes
generalization, or the operation of forming general notions. This
inverse process will consist in distinguishing the separate objects or
minor classes which are the constituent parts of any wider class. If
we mentally unite together certain objects visible in the sky and call
them planets, we shall afterwards need to distinguish the contents of
this general notion, which we do in the disjunctive proposition--

  A planet is either Mercury or Venus or the Earth or ... or Neptune.

Having formed the very wide class “vertebrate animal,” we may specify
its subordinate classes thus:--“A vertebrate animal is either a
mammal, bird, reptile, or fish.” Nor is there any limit to the
number of possible alternatives. “An exogenous plant is either a
ranunculus, a poppy, a crucifer, a rose, or it belongs to some one
of the other seventy natural orders of exogens at present recognized
by botanists.” A cathedral church in England must be either that of
London, Canterbury, Winchester, Salisbury, Manchester, or of one of
about twenty-four cities possessing such churches. And if we were to
attempt to specify the meaning of the term “star,” we should require
to enumerate as alternatives, not only the many thousands of stars
recorded in catalogues, but the many millions unnamed.

Whenever we thus distinguish the parts of a general notion we employ
a disjunctive proposition, in at least one side of which are several
alternatives joined by the so-called disjunctive conjunction or,
a contracted form of *other*. There must be some relation between
the parts thus connected in one proposition; we may call it the
*disjunctive* or *alternative* relation, and we must carefully inquire
into its nature. This relation is that of ignorance and doubt, giving
rise to choice. Whenever we classify and abstract we must open the way
to such uncertainty. By fixing our attention on certain attributes to
the exclusion of others, we necessarily leave it doubtful what those
other attributes are. The term “molar tooth” bears upon the face of
it that it is a part of the wider term “tooth.” But if we meet with
the simple term “tooth” there is nothing to indicate whether it is
an incisor, a canine, or a molar tooth. This doubt, however, may be
resolved by further information, and we have to consider what are the
appropriate logical processes for treating disjunctive propositions in
connection with other propositions disjunctive or otherwise.


*Expression of the Alternative Relation.*

In order to represent disjunctive propositions with convenience we
require a sign of the alternative relation, equivalent to one meaning
at least of the little conjunction *or* so frequently used in common
language. I propose to use for this purpose the symbol ꖌ. In my first
logical essay I followed the practice of Boole and adopted the sign
+; but this sign should not be employed unless there exists exact
analogy between mathematical addition and logical alternation. We shall
find that the analogy is imperfect, and that there is such profound
difference between logical and mathematical terms as should prevent
our uniting them by the same symbol. Accordingly I have chosen a sign
ꖌ, which seems aptly to suggest whatever degree of analogy may exist
without implying more. The exact meaning of the symbol we will now
proceed to investigate.


*Nature of the Alternative Relation.*

Before treating disjunctive propositions it is indispensable to decide
whether the alternatives must be considered exclusive or unexclusive.
By *exclusive alternatives* we mean those which cannot contain the same
things. If we say “Arches are circular or pointed,” it is certainly to
be understood that the same arch cannot be described as both circular
and pointed. Many examples, on the other hand, can readily be suggested
in which two or more alternatives may hold true of the same object. Thus

  Luminous bodies are self-luminous or luminous by reflection.

It is undoubtedly possible, by the laws of optics, that the same
surface may at one and the same moment give off light of its own and
reflect light from other bodies. We speak familiarly of *deaf or dumb*
persons, knowing that the majority of those who are deaf from birth are
also dumb.

There can be no doubt that in a great many cases, perhaps the greater
number of cases, alternatives are exclusive as a matter of fact. Any
one number is incompatible with any other; one point of time or place
is exclusive of all others. Roger Bacon died either in 1284 or 1292; it
is certain that he could not die in both years. Henry Fielding was born
either in Dublin or Somersetshire; he could not be born in both places.
There is so much more precision and clearness in the use of exclusive
alternatives that we ought doubtless to select them when possible. Old
works on logic accordingly contained a rule directing that the *Membra
dividentia*, the parts of a division or the constituent species of a
genus, should be exclusive of each other.

It is no doubt owing to the great prevalence and convenience of
exclusive divisions that the majority of logicians have held it
necessary to make every alternative in a disjunctive proposition
exclusive of every other one. Aquinas considered that when this was not
the case the proposition was actually *false*, and Kant adopted the
same opinion.[64] A multitude of statements to the same effect might
readily be quoted, and if the question were to be determined by the
weight of historical evidence, it would certainly go against my view.
Among recent logicians Hamilton, as well as Boole, took the exclusive
side. But there are authorities to the opposite effect. Whately,
Mansel, and J. S. Mill have all pointed out that we may often treat
alternatives as *Compossible*, or true at the same time. Whately gives
us an example,[65] “Virtue tends to procure us either the esteem of
mankind, or the favour of God,” and he adds--“Here both members are
true, and consequently from one being affirmed we are not authorized to
deny the other. Of course we are left to conjecture in each case, from
the context, whether it is meant to be implied that the members are
or are not exclusive.” Mansel says,[66] “*We may happen to know* that
two alternatives cannot be true together, so that the affirmation of
the second necessitates the denial of the first; but this, as Boethius
observes, is a *material*, not a *formal* consequence.” Mill has also
pointed out the absurdities which would arise from always interpreting
alternatives as exclusive. “If we assert,” he says,[67] “that a man
who has acted in some particular way must be either a knave or a fool,
we by no means assert, or intend to assert, that he cannot be both.”
Again, “to make an entirely unselfish use of despotic power, a man must
be either a saint or a philosopher.... Does the disjunctive premise
necessarily imply, or must it be construed as supposing, that the same
person cannot be both a saint and a philosopher? Such a construction
would be ridiculous.”

  [64] Mansel’s *Aldrich*, p. 103, and *Prolegomena Logica*, p. 221.

  [65] *Elements of Logic*, Book II. chap. iv. sect. 4.

  [66] Aldrich, *Artis Logicæ Rudimenta*, p. 104.

  [67] *Examination of Sir W. Hamilton’s Philosophy*, pp. 452–454.

I discuss this subject fully because it is really the point which
separates my logical system from that of Boole. In his *Laws of
Thought* (p. 32) he expressly says, “In strictness, the words ‘and,’
‘or,’ interposed between the terms descriptive of two or more classes
of objects, imply that those classes are quite distinct, so that no
member of one is found in another.” This I altogether dispute. In the
ordinary use of these conjunctions we do not join distinct terms only;
and when terms so joined do prove to be logically distinct, it is by
virtue of a *tacit premise*, something in the meaning of the names and
our knowledge of them, which teaches us that they are distinct. If our
knowledge of the meanings of the words joined is defective it will
often be impossible to decide whether terms joined by conjunctions are
exclusive or not.

In the sentence “Repentance is not a single act, but a habit or
virtue,” it cannot be implied that a virtue is not a habit; by
Aristotle’s definition it is. Milton has the expression in one of
his sonnets, “Unstain’d by gold or fee,” where it is obvious that if
the fee is not always gold, the gold is meant to be a fee or bribe.
Tennyson has the expression “wreath or anadem.” Most readers would
be quite uncertain whether a wreath may be an anadem, or an anadem a
wreath, or whether they are quite distinct or quite the same. From
Darwin’s *Origin of Species*, I take the expression, “When we see any
*part or organ* developed in a remarkable *degree or manner*.” In this,
*or* is used twice, and neither time exclusively. For if *part* and
*organ* are not synonymous, at any rate an organ is a part. And it
is obvious that a part may be developed at the same time both in an
extraordinary degree and an extraordinary manner, although such cases
may be comparatively rare.

From a careful examination of ordinary writings, it will thus be found
that the meanings of terms joined by “and,” “or” vary from absolute
identity up to absolute contrariety. There is no logical condition of
distinctness at all, and when we do choose exclusive alternatives, it
is because our subject demands it. The matter, not the form of an
expression, points out whether terms are exclusive or not.[68] In
bills, policies, and other kinds of legal documents, it is sometimes
necessary to express very distinctly that alternatives are not
exclusive. The form and/or is then used, and, as Mr. J. J. Murphy has
remarked, this form coincides exactly in meaning with the symbol ꖌ.

  [68] *Pure Logic*, pp 76, 77.

In the first edition of this work (vol. i., p. 81), I took the
disjunctive proposition “Matter is solid, or liquid, or gaseous,” and
treated it as an instance of exclusive alternatives, remarking that the
same portion of matter cannot be at once solid and liquid, properly
speaking, and that still less can we suppose it to be solid and
gaseous, or solid, liquid, and gaseous all at the same time. But the
experiments of Professor Andrews show that, under certain conditions
of temperature and pressure, there is no abrupt change from the liquid
to the gaseous state. The same substance may be in such a state as to
be indifferently described as liquid and gaseous. In many cases, too,
the transition from solid to liquid is gradual, so that the properties
of solidity are at least partially joined with those of liquidity.
The proposition then, instead of being an instance of exclusive
alternatives, seems to afford an excellent instance to the opposite
effect. When such doubts can arise, it is evidently impossible to treat
alternatives as absolutely exclusive by the logical nature of the
relation. It becomes purely a question of the matter of the proposition.

The question, as we shall afterwards see more fully, is one of
the greatest theoretical importance, because it concerns the true
distinction between the sciences of Logic and Mathematics. It is the
foundation of number that every unit shall be distinct from every other
unit; but Boole imported the conditions of number into the science of
Logic, and produced a system which, though wonderful in its results,
was not a system of logic at all.


*Laws of the Disjunctive Relation.*

In considering the combination or synthesis of terms (p. 30), we found
that certain laws, those of Simplicity and Commutativeness, must be
observed. In uniting terms by the disjunctive symbol we shall find that
the same or closely similar laws hold true. The alternatives of either
member of a disjunctive proposition are certainly commutative. Just as
we cannot properly distinguish between *rich and rare gems* and *rare
and rich gems*, so we must consider as identical the expression *rich
or rare gems*, and *rare or rich gems*. In our symbolic language we may
say

  A ꖌ B = B ꖌ A.

The order of statement, in short, has no effect upon the meaning of an
aggregate of alternatives, so that the Law of Commutativeness holds
true of the disjunctive symbol.

As we have admitted the possibility of joining as alternatives terms
which are not really different, the question arises, How shall we treat
two or more alternatives when they are clearly shown to be the same?
If we have it asserted that P is Q or R, and it is afterwards proved
that Q is but another name for R, the result is that P is either R or
R. How shall we interpret such a statement? What would be the meaning,
for instance, of “wreath or anadem” if, on referring to a dictionary,
we found *anadem* described as a wreath? I take it to be self-evident
that the meaning would then become simply “wreath.” Accordingly we may
affirm the general law

  A ꖌ A = A.

Any number of identical alternatives may always be reduced to, and are
logically equivalent to, any one of those alternatives. This is a law
which distinguishes mathematical terms from logical terms, because
it obviously does not apply to the former. I propose to call it the
*Law of Unity*, because it must really be involved in any definition
of a mathematical unit. This law is closely analogous to the Law of
Simplicity, AA = A; and the nature of the connection is worthy of
attention.

Few or no logicians except De Morgan have adequately noticed the close
relation between combined and disjunctive terms, namely, that every
disjunctive term is the negative of a corresponding combined term, and
*vice versâ*. Consider the term

  Malleable dense metal.

How shall we describe the class of things which are not
malleable-dense-metals? Whatever is included under that term must have
all the qualities of malleability, denseness, and metallicity. Wherever
any one or more of the qualities is wanting, the combined term will not
apply. Hence the negative of the whole term is

  Not-malleable or not-dense or not-metallic.

In the above the conjunction *or* must clearly be interpreted
as unexclusive; for there may readily be objects which are both
not-malleable, and not-dense, and perhaps not-metallic at the same
time. If in fact we were required to use *or* in a strictly exclusive
manner, it would be requisite to specify seven distinct alternatives
in order to describe the negative of a combination of three terms. The
negatives of four or five terms would consist of fifteen or thirty-one
alternatives. This consideration alone is sufficient to prove that the
meaning of *or* cannot be always exclusive in common language.

Expressed symbolically, we may say that the negative of

                         ABC
  is           not-A or not-B or not-C;
  that is,     *a* ꖌ *b* ꖌ *c*.

Reciprocally the negative of

                    P ꖌ Q ꖌ R
  is                  *pqr*.

Every disjunctive term, then, is the negative of a combined term, and
*vice versâ*.

Apply this result to the combined term AAA, and its negative is

  *a* ꖌ *a* ꖌ *a*.

Since AAA is by the Law of Simplicity equivalent to A, so *a* ꖌ *a* ꖌ
*a* must be equivalent to *a*, and the Law of Unity holds true. Each
law thus necessarily presupposes the other.


*Symbolic expression of the Law of Duality.*

We may now employ our symbol of alternation to express in a clear and
formal manner the third Fundamental Law of Thought, which I have called
the Law of Duality (p. 6). Taking A to represent any class or object
or quality, and B any other class, object or quality, we may always
assert that A either agrees with B, or does not agree. Thus we may say

  A = AB ꖌ A*b*.

This is a formula which will henceforth be constantly employed, and it
lies at the basis of reasoning.

The reader may perhaps wish to know why A is inserted in both
alternatives of the second member of the identity, and why the law is
not stated in the form

  A = B ꖌ *b*.

But if he will consider the contents of the last section (p. 73), he
will see that the latter expression cannot be correct, otherwise no
term could have a corresponding negative term. For the negative of B
ꖌ *b* is *b*B, or a self-contradictory term; thus if A were identical
with B ꖌ *b*, its negative *a* would be non-existent. To say the least,
this result would in most cases be an absurd one, and I see much reason
to think that in a strictly logical point of view it would always be
absurd. In all probability we ought to assume as a fundamental logical
axiom that *every term has its negative in thought*. We cannot think at
all without separating what we think about from other things, and these
things necessarily form the negative notion.[69] It follows that any
proposition of the form A = B ꖌ *b* is just as self-contradictory as
one of the form A = B*b*.

  [69] *Pure Logic*, p. 65. See also the criticism of this point by De
  Morgan in the *Athenæum*, No. 1892, 30th January, 1864; p. 155.

It is convenient to recapitulate in this place the three Laws of
Thought in their symbolic form, thus

  Law of Identity            A = A.
  Law of Contradiction    A*a* = 0.
  Law of Duality             A = AB ꖌ A*b*.


*Various Forms of the Disjunctive Proposition.*

Disjunctive propositions may occur in a great variety of forms, of
which the old logicians took insufficient notice. There may be any
number of alternatives, each of which may be a combination of any
number of simple terms. A proposition, again, may be disjunctive in one
or both members. The proposition

  Solids or liquids or gases are electrics or conductors of electricity

is an example of the doubly disjunctive form. The meaning of such a
proposition is that whatever falls under any one or more alternatives
on one side must fall under one or more alternatives on the other side.
From what has been said before, it is apparent that the proposition

  A ꖌ B = C ꖌ D

will correspond to

  *ab* = *cd*,

each member of the latter being the negative of a member of the former
proposition.

As an instance of a complex disjunctive proposition I may give Senior’s
definition of wealth, which, briefly stated, amounts to the proposition
“Wealth is what is transferable, limited in supply, and either
productive of pleasure or preventive of pain.”[70]

  [70] Boole’s *Laws of Thought*, p. 106. Jevons’ *Pure Logic*, p. 69.

  Let A = wealth
      B = transferable
      C = limited in supply
      D = productive of pleasure
      E = preventive of pain.

The definition takes the form

  A = BC(D ꖌ E);

but if we develop the alternatives by a method to be afterwards more
fully considered, it becomes

  A = BCDE ꖌ BCD*e* ꖌ BC*d*E.

An example of a still more complex proposition is found in De Morgan’s
writings,[71] as follows:--“He must have been rich, and if not
absolutely mad was weakness itself, subjected either to bad advice or
to most unfavourable circumstances.”

  [71] *On the Syllogism*, No. iii. p. 12. Camb. Phil. Trans. vol. x,
  part i.

If we assign the letters of the alphabet in succession, thus,

  A = he
  B = rich
  C = absolutely mad
  D = weakness itself
  E = subjected to bad advice
  F = subjected to most unfavourable circumstances,
        the proposition will take the form

  A = AB{C ꖌ D (E ꖌ F)},

and if we develop the alternatives, expressing some of the different
cases which may happen, we obtain

  A = ABC ꖌ AB*c*DEF ꖌ AB*c*DE*f* ꖌ AB*c*D*e*F.

The above gives the strict logical interpretation of the sentence, and
the first alternative ABC is capable of development into eight cases,
according as D, E and F are or are not present. Although from our
knowledge of the matter, we may infer that weakness of character cannot
be asserted of a person absolutely mad, there is no explicit statement
to this effect.


*Inference by Disjunctive Propositions.*

Before we can make a free use of disjunctive propositions in the
processes of inference we must consider how disjunctive terms can be
combined together or with simple terms. In the first place, to combine
a simple term with a disjunctive one, we must combine it with every
alternative of the disjunctive term. A vegetable, for instance, is
either a herb, a shrub, or a tree. Hence an exogenous vegetable is
either an exogenous herb, or an exogenous shrub, or an exogenous tree.
Symbolically stated, this process of combination is as follows,

  A(B ꖌ C) = AB ꖌ AC.

Secondly, to combine two disjunctive terms with each other, combine
each alternative of one with each alternative of the other. Since
flowering plants are either exogens or endogens, and are at the
same time either herbs, shrubs or trees, it follows that there are
altogether six alternatives--namely, exogenous herbs, exogenous shrubs,
exogenous trees, endogenous herbs, endogenous shrubs, endogenous trees.
This process of combination is shown in the general form

  (A ꖌ B) (C ꖌ D ꖌ E) = AC ꖌ AD ꖌ AE ꖌ BC ꖌ BD ꖌ BE.

It is hardly necessary to point out that, however numerous the
terms combined, or the alternatives in those terms, we may effect
the combination, provided each alternative is combined with each
alternative of the other terms, as in the algebraic process of
multiplication.

Some processes of deduction may be at once exhibited. We may
always, for instance, unite the same qualifying term to each side
of an identity even though one or both members of the identity be
disjunctive. Thus let

  A = B ꖌ C.

Now it is self-evident that

  AD = AD,

and in one side of this identity we may for A substitute its equivalent
B ꖌ C, obtaining

  AD = BD ꖌ CD.

Since “a gaseous element is either hydrogen, or oxygen, or nitrogen,
or chlorine, or fluorine,” it follows that “a free gaseous element
is either free hydrogen, or free oxygen, or free nitrogen, or free
chlorine, or free fluorine.”

This process of combination will lead to most useful inferences when
the qualifying adjective combined with both sides of the proposition is
a negative of one or more alternatives. Since chlorine is a coloured
gas, we may infer that “a colourless gaseous element is either
(colourless) hydrogen, oxygen, nitrogen, or fluorine.” The alternative
chlorine disappears because colourless chlorine does not exist. Again,
since “a tooth is either an incisor, canine, bicuspid, or molar,”
it follows that “a not-incisor tooth is either canine, bicuspid,
or molar.” The general rule is that from the denial of any of the
alternatives the affirmation of the remainder can be inferred. Now this
result clearly follows from our process of substitution; for if we have
the proposition

  A = B ꖌ C ꖌ D,

and we insert this expression for A on one side of the self-evident
identity

  A*b* = A*b*,

we obtain A*b* = AB*b* ꖌ A*b*C ꖌ A*b*D;

and, as the first of the three alternatives is self-contradictory, we
strike it out according to the law of contradiction: there remains

  A*b* = A*b*C ꖌ A*b*D.

Thus our system fully includes and explains that mood of the
Disjunctive Syllogism technically called the *modus tollendo ponens*.

But the reader must carefully observe that the Disjunctive Syllogism of
the mood *ponendo tollens*, which affirms one alternative, and thence
infers the denial of the rest, cannot be held true in this system. If I
say, indeed, that

  Water is either salt or fresh water,

it seems evident that “water which is salt is not fresh.” But this
inference really proceeds from our knowledge that water cannot be at
once salt and fresh. This inconsistency of the alternatives, as I have
fully shown, will not always hold. Thus, if I say

  Gems are either rare stones or beautiful stones,       (1)

it will obviously not follow that

  A rare gem is not a beautiful stone,                   (2)

nor that

  A beautiful gem is not a rare stone.                   (3)

Our symbolic method gives only true conclusions; for if we take

  A = gem
  B = rare stone
  C = beautiful stone,

the proposition (1) is of the form

             A = B ꖌ C
  hence     AB = B ꖌ BC
  and       AC = BC ꖌ C;

but these inferences are not equivalent to the false ones (2) and (3).


We can readily represent disjunctive reasoning by the *modus ponendo
tollens*, when it is valid, by expressing the inconsistency of the
alternatives explicitly. Thus if we resort to our instance of

  Water is either salt or fresh,

and take

  A = Water  B = salt  C = fresh,

then the premise is apparently of the form

  A = AB ꖌ AC;

but in reality there is an unexpressed condition that “what is salt
is not fresh,” from which follows, by a process of inference to be
afterwards described, that “what is fresh is not salt.” We have then,
in letter-terms, the two propositions

  B = B*c*
  C = *b*C.

If we substitute these descriptions in the original proposition, we
obtain /* A = AB*c* ꖌ A*b*C; */

uniting B to each side we infer

       AB = AB*c* ꖌ AB*b*C
  or   AB = AB*c*;

that is,

  Water which is salt is water salt and not fresh.

I should weary the reader if I attempted to illustrate the multitude of
forms which disjunctive reasoning may take; and as in the next chapter
we shall be constantly treating the subject, I must here restrict
myself to a single instance. A very common process of reasoning
consists in the determination of the name of a thing by the successive
exclusion of alternatives, a process called by the old name *abscissio
infiniti*. Take the case:

  Red-coloured metal is either copper or gold    (1)
  Copper is dissolved by nitric acid             (2)
  This specimen is red-coloured metal            (3)
  This specimen is not dissolved by nitric acid  (4)
  Therefore, this specimen consists of gold      (5)

Let us assign the letter-symbols thus--

  A = this specimen
  B = red-coloured metal
  C = copper
  D = gold
  E = dissolved by nitric acid.

Assuming that the alternatives copper or gold are intended to be
exclusive, as just explained in the case of fresh and salt water, the
premises may be stated in the forms

  B = BC*d* ꖌ B*c*D            (1)
  C = CE                       (2)
  A = AB                       (3)
  A = A*e*                     (4)

Substituting for C in (1) by means of (2) we get

  B = BC*d*E ꖌ B*c*D

From (3) and (4) we may infer likewise

  A = AB*e*

and if in this we substitute for B its equivalent just stated, it
follows that

  A = ABC*d*E*e* ꖌ AB*c*D*e*

The first of the alternatives being contradictory the result is

  A = AB*c*D*e*

which contains a full description of “this specimen,” as furnished
in the premises, but by ellipsis asserts that it is gold. It will be
observed that in the symbolic expression (1) I have explicitly stated
what is certainly implied, that copper is not gold, and gold not
copper, without which condition the inference would not hold good.




CHAPTER VI.

THE INDIRECT METHOD OF INFERENCE.


The forms of deductive reasoning as yet considered, are mostly cases
of Direct Deduction as distinguished from those which we are now about
to treat. The method of Indirect Deduction may be described as that
which points out what a thing is, by showing that it cannot be anything
else. We can define a certain space upon a map, either by colouring
that space, or by colouring all except the space; the first mode is
positive, the second negative. The difference, it will be readily seen,
is exactly analogous to that between the direct and indirect modes
of proof in geometry. Euclid often shows that two lines are equal,
by showing that they cannot be unequal, and the proof rests upon the
known number of alternatives, greater, equal or less, which are alone
conceivable. In other cases, as for instance in the seventh proposition
of the first book, he shows that two lines must meet in a particular
point, by showing that they cannot meet elsewhere.

In logic we can always define with certainty the utmost number of
alternatives which are conceivable. The Law of Duality (pp. 6, 74)
enables us always to assert that any quality or circumstance whatsoever
is either present or absent. Whatever may be the meaning of the terms A
and B it is certainly true that

  A = AB ꖌ A*b*
  B = AB ꖌ *a*B.

These are universal tacit premises which may be employed in the
solution of every problem, and which are such invariable and necessary
conditions of all thought, that they need not be specially laid down.
The Law of Contradiction is a further condition of all thought and of
all logical symbols; it enables, and in fact obliges, us to reject from
further consideration all terms which imply the presence and absence
of the same quality. Now, whenever we bring both these Laws of Thought
into explicit action by the method of substitution, we employ the
Indirect Method of Inference. It will be found that we can treat not
only those arguments already exhibited according to the direct method,
but we can include an infinite multitude of other arguments which are
incapable of solution by any other means.

Some philosophers, especially those of France, have held that the
Indirect Method of Proof has a certain inferiority to the direct
method, which should prevent our using it except when obliged. But
there are many truths which we can prove only indirectly. We can
prove that a number is a prime only by the purely indirect method of
showing that it is not any of the numbers which have divisors, and the
remarkable process known as Eratosthenes’ Sieve is the only mode by
which we can select the prime numbers.[72] It bears a strong analogy to
the indirect method here to be described. We can prove that the side
and diameter of a square are incommensurable, but only in the negative
or indirect manner, by showing that the contrary supposition inevitably
leads to contradiction.[73] Many other demonstrations in various
branches of the mathematical sciences proceed upon a like method.
Now, if there is only one important truth which must be, and can only
be, proved indirectly, we may say that the process is a necessary and
sufficient one, and the question of its comparative excellence or
usefulness is not worth discussion. As a matter of fact I believe that
nearly half our logical conclusions rest upon its employment.

  [72] See Horsley, *Philosophical Transactions*, 1772; vol. lxii.
  p. 327. Montucla, *Histoire des Mathematiques*, vol. i. p. 239.
  *Penny Cyclopædia*, article “Eratosthenes.”

  [73] Euclid, Book x. Prop. 117.


*Simple Illustrations.*

In tracing out the powers and results of this method, we will begin
with the simplest possible instance. Let us take a proposition of the
common form, A = AB, say,

  *A Metal is an Element,*

and let us investigate its full meaning. Any person who has had the
least logical training, is aware that we can draw from the above
proposition an apparently different one, namely,

  *A Not-element is a Not-metal.*

While some logicians, as for instance De Morgan,[74] have considered
the relation of these two propositions to be purely self-evident, and
neither needing nor allowing analysis, a great many more persons, as
I have observed while teaching logic, are at first unable to perceive
the close connection between them. I believe that a true and complete
system of logic will furnish a clear analysis of this process, which
has been called *Contrapositive Conversion*; the full process is as
follows:--

  [74] *Philosophical Magazine*, December 1852; Fourth Series, vol. iv.
  p. 435, “On Indirect Demonstration.”

Firstly, by the Law of Duality we know that

  *Not-element is either Metal or Not-metal.*

If it be metal, we know that it is by the premise *an element*; we
should thus be supposing that the same thing is an element and a
not-element, which is in opposition to the Law of Contradiction.
According to the only other alternative, then, the not-element must be
a not-metal.

To represent this process of inference symbolically we take the premise
in the form

  A = AB.                  (1)

We observe that by the Law of Duality the term not-B is thus described

  *b* = A*b* ꖌ *ab*.       (2)

For A in this proposition we substitute its description as given in
(1), obtaining

  *b* = AB*b* ꖌ *ab*.

But according to the Law of Contradiction the term AB*b* must be
excluded from thought, or

  AB*b* = 0.

Hence it results that *b* is either nothing at all, or it is *ab*; and
the conclusion is

  *b* = *ab*.

As it will often be necessary to refer to a conclusion of this kind I
shall call it, as is usual, the *Contrapositive Proposition* of the
original. The reader need hardly be cautioned to observe that from all
A’s are B’s it does not follow that all not-A’s are not-B’s. For by the
Law of Duality we have

  *a* = *a*B ꖌ *ab*,

and it will not be found possible to make any substitution in this by
our original premise A = AB. It still remains doubtful, therefore,
whether not-metal is element or not-element.

The proof of the Contrapositive Proposition given above is exactly the
same as that which Euclid applies in the case of geometrical notions.
De Morgan describes Euclid’s process as follows[75]:--“From every not-B
is not-A he produces Every A is B, thus: If it be possible, let this A
be not-B, but every not-B is not-A, therefore this A is not-A, which
is absurd: whence every A is B.” Now De Morgan thinks that this proof
is entirely needless, because common logic gives the inference without
the use of any geometrical reasoning. I conceive however that logic
gives the inference only by an indirect process. De Morgan claims “to
see identity in Every A is B and every not-B is not-A, by a process
of thought prior to syllogism.” Whether prior to syllogism or not, I
claim that it is not prior to the laws of thought and the process of
substitutive inference, by which it may be undoubtedly demonstrated.

  [75] *Philosophical Magazine*, Dec. 1852; p. 437.


*Employment of the Contrapositive Proposition.*

We can frequently employ the contrapositive form of a proposition by
the method of substitution; and certain moods of the ancient syllogism,
which we have hitherto passed over, may thus be satisfactorily
comprehended in our system. Take for instance the following syllogism
in the mood Camestres:--

  “Whales are not true fish; for they do not respire water,
     whereas true fish do respire water.”

Let us take

  A = whale
  B = true fish
  C = respiring water

The premises are of the forms

  A = A*c*        (1)
  B = BC          (2)

Now, by the process of contraposition we obtain from the second premise

  *c* = *bc*

and we can substitute this expression for *c* in (1), obtaining

  A = A*bc*

or “Whales are not true fish, not respiring water.”

The mood Cesare does not really differ from Camestres except in the
order of the premises, and it could be exhibited in an exactly similar
manner.

The mood Baroko gave much trouble to the old logicians, who could
not *reduce* it to the first figure in the same manner as the other
moods, and were obliged to invent, specially for it and for Bokardo, a
method of Indirect Reduction closely analogous to the indirect proof
of Euclid. Now these moods require no exceptional treatment in this
system. Let us take as an instance of Baroko, the argument

  All heated solids give continuous spectra        (1)
  Some nebulæ do not give continuous spectra       (2)
  Therefore, some nebulæ are not heated solids     (3)

Treating the little word some as an indeterminate adjective of
selection, to which we assign a symbol like any other adjective, let

  A = some
  B = nebulæ
  C = giving continuous spectra
  D = heated solids

The premises then become

  D = DC                        (1)
  AB = AB*c*                    (2)

Now from (1) we obtain by the indirect method the contrapositive
proposition

  *c* = *cd*

and if we substitute this expression for *c* in (2) we have

  AB = AB*cd*

the full meaning of which is that “some nebulæ do not give continuous
spectra and are not heated solids.”

We might similarly apply the contrapositive in many other instances.
Take the argument, “All fixed stars are self-luminous; but some of the
heavenly bodies are not self-luminous, and are therefore not fixed
stars.” Taking our terms

  A = fixed stars
  B = self-luminous
  C = some
  D = heavenly bodies

we have the premises

   A = AB,                      (1)
  CD = *b*CD                    (2)

Now from (1) we can draw the contrapositive

  *b* = *ab*

and substituting this expression for *b* in (2) we obtain

  CD = *ab*CD

which expresses the conclusion of the argument that some heavenly
bodies are not fixed stars.


*Contrapositive of a Simple Identity.*

The reader should carefully note that when we apply the process of
Indirect Inference to a simple identity of the form

  A = B

we may obtain further results. If we wish to know what is the term
not-B, we have as before, by the Law of Duality,

  *b* = A*b* ꖌ *ab*

and substituting for A we obtain

  *b* = B*b* ꖌ *ab* = *ab*.

But we may now also draw a second contrapositive; for we have

  *a* = *a*B ꖌ *ab*,

and substituting for B its equivalent A we have

  *a* = *a*A ꖌ *ab* = *ab*.

Hence from the single identity A = B we can draw the two propositions

  *a* = *ab*
  *b* = *ab*,

and observing that these propositions have a common term *ab* we can
make a new substitution, getting

  *a* = *b*.

This result is in strict accordance with the fundamental principles of
inference, and it may be a question whether it is not a self-evident
result, independent of the steps of deduction by which we have reached
it. For where two classes are coincident like A and B, whatever is true
of the one is true of the other; what is excluded from the one must be
excluded from the other similarly. Now as *a* bears to A exactly the
same relation that *b* bears to B, the identity of either pair follows
from the identity of the other pair. In every identity, equality, or
similarity, we may argue from the negative of the one side to the
negative of the other. Thus at ordinary temperatures

  Mercury = liquid-metal,

hence obviously

  Not-mercury = not liquid-metal;

or since

  Sirius = brightest fixed star,

it follows that whatever star is not the brightest is not Sirius, and
*vice versâ*. Every correct definition is of the form A = B, and may
often require to be applied in the equivalent negative form.

Let us take as an illustration of the mode of using this result the
argument following:

  Vowels are letters which can be sounded alone,     (1)
  The letter *w* cannot be sounded alone;            (2)
  Therefore the letter *w* is not a vowel.           (3)

Here we have a definition (1), and a comparison of a thing with that
definition (2), leading to exclusion of the thing from the class
defined.

Taking the terms

  A = vowel,
  B = letter which can be sounded alone,
  C = letter *w*,

the premises are plainly of the forms

  A = B,                          (1)
  C = *b*C.                       (2)

Now by the Indirect method we obtain from (1) the Contrapositive

  *b* = *a*,

and inserting in (2) the equivalent for *b* we have

  C = *a*C,                       (3)

or “the letter *w* is not a vowel.”


*Miscellaneous Examples of the Method.*

We can apply the Indirect Method of Inference however many may be the
terms involved or the premises containing those terms. As the working
of the method is best learnt from examples, I will take a case of two
premises forming the syllogism Barbara: thus

  Iron is metal                   (1)
  Metal is element.               (2)

If we want to ascertain what inference is possible concerning the
term *Iron*, we develop the term by the Law of Duality. Iron must be
either metal or not-metal; iron which is metal must be either element
or not-element; and similarly iron which is not-metal must be either
element or not-element. There are then altogether four alternatives
among which the description of iron must be contained; thus

  Iron, metal, element,           (α)
  Iron, metal, not-element,       (β)
  Iron, not-metal, element,       (γ)
  Iron, not-metal, not-element.   (δ)

Our first premise informs us that iron is a metal, and if we substitute
this description in (γ) and (δ) we shall have self-contradictory
combinations. Our second premise likewise informs us that metal
is element, and applying this description to (β) we again have
self-contradiction, so that there remains only (α) as a description of
iron--our inference is

  Iron = iron, metal, element.

To represent this process of reasoning in general symbols, let

  A = iron
  B = metal
  C = element,

The premises of the problem take the forms

  A = AB                   (1)
  B = BC.                  (2)

By the Law of Duality we have

  A = AB ꖌ A*b*            (3)
  A = AC ꖌ A*c*.           (4)

Now, if we insert for A in the second side of (3) its description in
(4), we obtain what I shall call the *development of A with respect to
B and C*, namely

  A = ABC ꖌ AB*c* ꖌ A*b*C ꖌ A*bc*.      (5)

Wherever the letters A or B appear in the second side of (5) substitute
their equivalents given in (1) and (2), and the results stated at full
length are

  A = ABC ꖌ ABC*c* ꖌ AB*b*C ꖌ AB*b*C*c*.

The last three alternatives break the Law of Contradiction, so that

  A = ABC ꖌ 0 ꖌ 0 ꖌ 0 = ABC.

This conclusion is, indeed, no more than we could obtain by the
direct process of substitution, that is by substituting for B in (1),
its description in (2) as in p. 55; it is the characteristic of the
Indirect process that it gives all possible logical conclusions, both
those which we have previously obtained, and an immense number of
others or which the ancient logic took little or no account. From the
same premises, for instance, we can obtain a description of the class
*not-element* or *c*. By the Law of Duality we can develop *c* into
four alternatives, thus

  *c* = AB*c* ꖌ A*bc* ꖌ *a*B*c* ꖌ *abc*.

If we substitute for A and B as before, we get

  *c* = ABC*c* ꖌ AB*bc* ꖌ *a*BC*c* ꖌ *abc*,

and, striking out the terms which break the Law of Contradiction, there
remains

  *c* = *abc*,

or what is not element is also not iron and not metal. This Indirect
Method of Inference thus furnishes a complete solution of the following
problem--*Given any number of logical premises or conditions, required
the description of any class of objects, or of any term, as governed by
those conditions.*

The steps of the process of inference may thus be concisely stated--

1. By the Law of Duality develop the utmost number of alternatives
which may exist in the description of the required class or term as
regards the terms involved in the premises.

2. For each term in these alternatives substitute its description as
given in the premises.

3. Strike out every alternative which is then found to break the Law of
Contradiction.

4. The remaining terms may be equated to the term in question as the
desired description.


*Mr. Venn’s Problem.*

The need of some logical method more powerful and comprehensive than
the old logic of Aristotle is strikingly illustrated by Mr. Venn
in his most interesting and able article on Boole’s logic.[76] An
easy example, originally got, as he says, by the aid of my method as
simply described in the *Elementary Lessons in Logic*, was proposed in
examination and lecture-rooms to some hundred and fifty students as a
problem in ordinary logic. It was answered by, at most, five or six
of them. It was afterwards set, as an example on Boole’s method, to
a small class who had attended a few lectures on the nature of these
symbolic methods. It was readily answered by half or more of their
number.

  [76] *Mind*; a Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy;
  October, 1876, vol. i. p. 487.

The problem was as follows:--“The members of a board were all of them
either bondholders, or shareholders, but not both; and the bondholders
as it happened, were all on the board. What conclusion can be drawn?”
The conclusion wanted is, “No shareholders are bondholders.” Now, as
Mr. Venn says, nothing can look simpler than the following reasoning,
*when stated*:--“There can be no bondholders who are shareholders; for
if there were they must be either on the board, or off it. But they
are not on it, by the first of the given statements; nor off it, by
the second.” Yet from the want of any systematic mode of treating such
a question only five or six of some hundred and fifty students could
succeed in so simple a problem.

By symbolic statement the problem is instantly solved. Taking

  A = member of board
  B = bondholder
  C = shareholder

the premises are evidently

  A = AB*c* ꖌ A*b*C
  B = AB.

The class C or shareholders may in respect of A and B be developed into
four alternatives,

  C = ABC ꖌ A*b*C ꖌ *a*BC ꖌ *ab*C.

But substituting for A in the first and for B in the third alternative
we get

  C = ABC*c* ꖌ AB*b*C ꖌ A*b*C ꖌ *a*ABC ꖌ *ab*C.

The first, second, and fourth alternatives in the above are
self-contradictory combinations, and only these; striking them out
there remain

  C = A*b*C ꖌ *ab*C = *b*C,

the required answer. This symbolic reasoning is, I believe, the exact
equivalent of Mr. Venn’s reasoning, and I do not believe that the
result can be attained in a simpler manner. Mr. Venn adds that he
could adduce other similar instances, that is, instances showing the
necessity of a better logical method.


*Abbreviation of the Process.*

Before proceeding to further illustrations of the use of this method,
I must point out how much its practical employment can be simplified,
and how much more easy it is than would appear from the description.
When we want to effect at all a thorough solution of a logical problem
it is best to form, in the first place, a complete series of all the
combinations of terms involved in it. If there be two terms A and B,
the utmost variety of combinations in which they can appear are

  AB          *a*B
  A*b*        *ab*.

The term A appears in the first and second; B in the first and third;
*a* in the third and fourth; and *b* in the second and fourth. Now if
we have any premise, say

  A = B,

we must ascertain which of these combinations will be rendered
self-contradictory by substitution; the second and third will have to
be struck out, and there will remain only

   AB
  *ba*.

Hence we draw the following inferences

  A = AB, B = AB, *a* = *ab*, *b* = *ab*.

Exactly the same method must be followed when a question involves a
greater number of terms. Thus by the Law of Duality the three terms A,
B, C, give rise to eight conceivable combinations, namely

  ABC        (α)         *a*BC       (ε)
  AB*c*      (β)         *a*B*c*     (ζ)
  A*b*C      (γ)         *ab*C       (η)
  A*bc*      (δ)         *abc*.      (θ)

The development of the term A is formed by the first four of these; for
B we must select (α), (β), (ε), (ζ); C consists of (α), (γ), (ε), (η);
*b* of (γ), (δ), (η), (θ), and so on.

Now if we want to investigate completely the meaning of the premises

  A = AB      (1)
  B = BC      (2)

we examine each of the eight combinations as regards each premise; (γ)
and (δ) are contradicted by (1), and (β) and (ζ) by (2), so that there
remain only

   ABC        (α)
  *a*BC       (ε)
  *ab*C       (η)
  *abc*.      (θ)

To describe any term under the conditions of the premises (1) and (2),
we have simply to draw out the proper combinations from this list;
thus, A is represented only by ABC, that is to say

                  A  =  ABC,
  similarly      *c* = *abc*.

For B we have two alternatives thus stated,

  B = ABC ꖌ *a*BC;

and for *b* we have

  *b* = *ab*C ꖌ *abc*.

When we have a problem involving four distinct terms we need to
double the number of combinations, and as we add each new term the
combinations become twice as numerous. Thus

  A, B              produce four       combinations
  A, B, C,             "    eight           "
  A, B, C, D           "    sixteen         "
  A, B, C, D, E        "    thirty-two      "
  A, B, C, D, E, F     "    sixty-four      "

and so on.

I propose to call any such series of combinations the *Logical
Alphabet*. It holds in logical science a position the importance
of which cannot be exaggerated, and as we proceed from logical to
mathematical considerations, it will become apparent that there is
a close connection between these combinations and the fundamental
theorems of mathematical science. For the convenience of the reader
who may wish to employ the *Alphabet* in logical questions, I have
had printed on the next page a complete series of the combinations up
to those of six terms. At the very commencement, in the first column,
is placed a single letter X, which might seem to be superfluous. This
letter serves to denote that it is always some higher class which is
divided up. Thus the combination AB really means ABX, or that part of
some larger class, say X, which has the qualities of A and B present.
The letter X is omitted in the greater part of the table merely for
the sake of brevity and clearness. In a later chapter on Combinations
it will become apparent that the introduction of this unit class is
requisite in order to complete the analogy with the Arithmetical
Triangle there described.

The reader ought to bear in mind that though the Logical Alphabet seems
to give mere lists of combinations, these combinations are intended in
every case to constitute the development of a term of a proposition.
Thus the four combinations AB, A*b*, *a*B, *ab* really mean that any
class X is described by the following proposition,

  X = XAB ꖌ XA*b* ꖌ X*a*B ꖌ X*ab*.

If we select the A’s, we obtain the following proposition

  AX = XAB ꖌ XA*b*.

Thus whatever group of combinations we treat must be conceived as part
of a higher class, *summum genus* or universe symbolised in the term
X; but, bearing this in mind, it is needless to complicate our formulæ
by always introducing the letter. All inference consists in passing
from propositions to propositions, and combinations *per se* have no
meaning. They are consequently to be regarded in all cases as forming
parts of propositions.


THE LOGICAL ALPHABET.

  I.   II.    III.    IV.     V.        VI.         VII.
  X    AX     AB      ABC     ABCD      ABCDE       ABCDEF
      *a*X    A*b*    AB*c*   ABC*d*    ABCD*e*     ABCDE*f*
             *a*B     A*b*C   AB*c*D    ABC*d*E     ABCD*e*F
             *ab*     A*bc*   AB*cd*    ABC*de*     ABCD*ef*
                     *a*BC    A*b*CD    AB*c*DE     ABC*d*EF
                     *a*B*c*  A*b*C*d*  AB*c*D*e*   ABC*d*E*f*
                     *ab*C    A*bc*D    AB*cd*E     ABC*de*F
                     *abc*    Ab*cd*    AB*cde*     ABC*def*
                             *a*BCD     A*b*CDE     AB*c*DEF
                             *a*BC*d*   A*b*CD*e*   AB*c*DE*f*
                             *a*B*c*D   A*b*C*d*E   AB*c*D*e*F
                             *a*B*cd*   A*b*C*de*   AB*c*D*ef*
                             *ab*CD     A*bc*DE     AB*cd*EF
                             *ab*C*d*   A*bc*D*e*   AB*cd*E*f*
                             *abc*D     A*bcd*E     AB*cde*F
                             *abcd*     A*bcde*     AB*cdef*
                                       *a*BCDE      A*b*CDEF
                                       *a*BCD*e*    A*b*CDE*f*
                                       *a*BC*d*E    A*b*CD*e*F
                                       *a*BC*de*    A*b*CD*ef*
                                       *a*B*c*DE    A*b*C*d*EF
                                       *a*B*c*D*e*  A*b*C*d*E*f*
                                       *a*B*cd*E    A*b*C*de*F
                                       *a*B*cde*    A*b*C*def*
                                       *ab*CDE      A*bc*DEF
                                       *ab*CD*e*    A*bc*DE*f*
                                       *ab*C*d*E    A*bc*D*e*F
                                       *ab*Cd*e*    A*bc*D*ef*
                                       *abc*DE      A*bcd*EF
                                       *abc*D*e*    A*bcd*E*f*
                                       *abcd*E      A*bcde*F
                                       *abcde*      A*bcdef*
                                                   *a*BCDEF
                                                   *a*BCDE*f*
                                                   *a*BCD*e*F
                                                   *a*BCD*ef*
                                                   *a*BC*d*EF
                                                   *a*BC*d*E*f*
                                                   *a*BC*de*F
                                                   *a*BC*def*
                                                   *a*B*c*DEF
                                                   *a*B*c*DE*f*
                                                   *a*B*c*D*e*F
                                                   *a*B*c*D*ef*
                                                   *a*B*cd*EF
                                                   *a*B*cd*E*f*
                                                   *a*B*cde*F
                                                   *a*B*cdef*
                                                   *ab*CDEF
                                                   *ab*CDE*f*
                                                   *ab*CD*e*F
                                                   *ab*CD*ef*
                                                   *ab*C*d*EF
                                                   *ab*C*d*E*f*
                                                   *ab*C*de*F
                                                   *ab*C*def*
                                                   *abc*DEF
                                                   *abc*DE*f*
                                                   *abc*D*e*F
                                                   *abc*D*ef*
                                                   *abcd*EF
                                                   *abcd*E*f*
                                                   *abcde*F
                                                   *abcdef*

In a theoretical point of view we may conceive that the Logical
Alphabet is infinitely extended. Every new quality or circumstance
which can belong to an object, subdivides each combination or class,
so that the number of such combinations, when unrestricted by logical
conditions, is represented by an infinitely high power of two. The
extremely rapid increase in the number of subdivisions obliges us to
confine our attention to a few qualities at a time.

When contemplating the properties of this Alphabet I am often inclined
to think that Pythagoras perceived the deep logical importance of
duality; for while unity was the symbol of identity and harmony, he
described the number two as the origin of contrasts, or the symbol
of diversity, division and separation. The number four, or the
*Tetractys*, was also regarded by him as one of the chief elements of
existence, for it represented the generating virtue whence come all
combinations. In one of the golden verses ascribed to Pythagoras, he
conjures his pupil to be virtuous:[77]

  “By him who stampt *The Four* upon the Mind,
  *The Four*, the fount of Nature’s endless stream.”

  [77] Whewell, *History of the Inductive Sciences*, vol. i. p. 222.

Now four and the higher powers of duality do represent in this logical
system the numbers of combinations which can be generated in the
absence of logical restrictions. The followers of Pythagoras may have
shrouded their master’s doctrines in mysterious and superstitious
notions, but in many points these doctrines seem to have some basis in
logical philosophy.


*The Logical Slate.*

To a person who has once comprehended the extreme significance and
utility of the Logical Alphabet the indirect process of inference
becomes reduced to the repetition of a few uniform operations of
classification, selection, and elimination of contradictories. Logical
deduction, even in the most complicated questions, becomes a matter
of mere routine, and the amount of labour required is the only
impediment, when once the meaning of the premises is rendered clear.
But the amount of labour is often found to be considerable. The mere
writing down of sixty-four combinations of six letters each is no small
task, and, if we had a problem of five premises, each of the sixty-four
combinations would have to be examined in connection with each premise.
The requisite comparison is often of a very tedious character, and
considerable chance of error intervenes.

I have given much attention, therefore, to lessening both the manual
and mental labour of the process, and I shall describe several devices
which may be adopted for saving trouble and risk of mistake.

In the first place, as the same sets of combinations occur over and
over again in different problems, we may avoid the labour of writing
them out by having the sets of letters ready printed upon small sheets
of writing-paper. It has also been suggested by a correspondent that,
if any one series of combinations were marked upon the margin of a
sheet of paper, and a slit cut between each pair of combinations, it
would be easy to fold down any particular combination, and thus strike
it out of view. The combinations consistent with the premises would
then remain in a broken series. This method answers sufficiently well
for occasional use.

A more convenient mode, however, is to have the series of letters shown
on p. 94, engraved upon a common school writing slate, of such a size,
that the letters may occupy only about a third of the space on the
left hand side of the slate. The conditions of the problem can then be
written down on the unoccupied part of the slate, and the proper series
of combinations being chosen, the contradictory combinations can be
struck out with the pencil. I have used a slate of this kind, which I
call a *Logical Slate*, for more than twelve years, and it has saved me
much trouble. It is hardly possible to apply this process to problems
of more than six terms, owing to the large number of combinations which
would require examination.


*Abstraction of Indifferent Circumstances.*

There is a simple but highly important process of inference which
enables us to abstract, eliminate or disregard all circumstances
indifferently present and absent. Thus if I were to state that “a
triangle is a three-sided rectilinear figure, either large or not
large,” these two alternatives would be superfluous, because, by the
Law of Duality, I know that everything must be either large or not
large. To add the qualification gives no new knowledge, since the
existence of the two alternatives will be understood in the absence of
any information to the contrary. Accordingly, when two alternatives
differ only as regards a single component term which is positive in one
and negative in the other, we may reduce them to one term by striking
out their indifferent part. It is really a process of substitution
which enables us to do this; for having any proposition of the form

  A = ABC ꖌ AB*c*,      (1)

we know by the Law of Duality that

  AB = ABC ꖌ AB*c*.     (2)

As the second member of this is identical with the second member of (1)
we may substitute, obtaining

  A = AB.

This process of reducing useless alternatives may be applied again and
again; for it is plain that

  A = AB (CD ꖌ C*d* ꖌ *c*D ꖌ *cd*)

communicates no more information than that A is B. Abstraction
of indifferent terms is in fact the converse process to that of
development described in p. 89; and it is one of the most important
operations in the whole sphere of reasoning.

The reader should observe that in the proposition

  AC = BC

we cannot abstract C and infer

  A = B;

but from

  AC ꖌ A*c* = BC ꖌ B*c*

we may abstract all reference to the term C.

It ought to be carefully remarked, however, that alternatives which
seem to be without meaning often imply important knowledge. Thus if
I say that “a triangle is a three-sided rectilinear figure, with or
without three equal angles,” the last alternatives really express a
property of triangles, namely, that some triangles have three equal
angles, and some do not have them. If we put P = “Some,” meaning by the
indefinite adjective “Some,” one or more of the undefined properties of
triangles with three equal angles, and take

  A = triangle
  B = three-sided rectilinear figure
  C = with three equal angles,

then the knowledge implied is expressed in the two propositions

   PA = PBC
  *p*A = *p*B*c*.

These may also be thrown into the form of one proposition, namely,

  A = PBC ꖌ *p*B*c*;

but these alternatives cannot be reduced, and the proposition is quite
different from

  A = BC ꖌ B*c*.


*Illustrations of the Indirect Method.*

A great variety of arguments and logical problems might be introduced
here to show the comprehensive character and powers of the Indirect
Method. We can treat either a single premise or a series of premises.

Take in the first place a simple definition, such as “a triangle is a
three-sided rectilinear figure.” Let

  A = triangle
  B = three-sided
  C = rectilinear figure,

then the definition is of the form

  A = BC.

If we take the series of eight combinations of three letters in the
Logical Alphabet (p. 94) and strike out those which are inconsistent
with the definition, we have the following result:--

   ABC
  *a*B*c*
  *ab*C
  *abc.*

For the description of the class C we have

  C = ABC ꖌ *ab*C,

that is, “a rectilinear figure is either a triangle and three-sided, or
not a triangle and not three-sided.”

For the class *b* we have

  *b* = *ab*C ꖌ *abc*.

To the second side of this we may apply the process of simplification
by abstraction described in the last section; for by the Law of Duality

  *ab* = *ab*C ꖌ *abc*;

and as we have two propositions identical in the second side of each we
may substitute, getting

  *b* = *ab*,

or what is not three-sided is not a triangle (whether it be rectilinear
or not).


*Second Example.*

Let us treat by this method the following argument:--

  “Blende is not an elementary substance; elementary substances
     are those which are undecomposable; blende, therefore, is
     decomposable.”

Taking our letters thus--

  A = blende,
  B = elementary substance,
  C = undecomposable,

the premises are of the forms

  A = A*b*,              (1)
  B = C.                 (2)

No immediate substitution can be made; but if we take the
contrapositive of (2) (see p. 86), namely

  *b* = *c*,             (3)

we can substitute in (1) obtaining the conclusion

  A = A*c*.

But the same result may be obtained by taking the eight combinations
of A, B, C, of the Logical Alphabet; it will be found that only three
combinations, namely,

   A*bc*
  *a*BC
  *abc*,

are consistent with the premises, whence it results that

  A = A*bc*,

or by the process of Ellipsis before described (p. 57)

  A = A*c*.


*Third Example.*

As a somewhat more complex example I take the argument thus stated, one
which could not be thrown into the syllogistic form:--

  “All metals except gold and silver are opaque; therefore what is not
     opaque is either gold or silver or is not-metal.”

There is more implied in this statement than is distinctly asserted,
the full meaning being as follows:

  All metals not gold or silver are opaque,      (1)
  Gold is not opaque but is a metal,             (2)
  Silver is not opaque but is a metal,           (3)
  Gold is not silver.                            (4)

Taking our letters thus--

  A = metal      C = silver
  B = gold       D = opaque,

we may state the premises in the forms

  A*bc* = A*bc*D        (1)
  B = AB*d*             (2)
  C = AC*d*             (3)
  B = B*c*.             (4)

To obtain a complete solution of the question we take the sixteen
combinations of A, B, C, D, and striking out those which are
inconsistent with the premises, there remain only

   AB*cd*
   A*b*C*d*
   A*bc*D
  *abc*D
  *abcd*.

The expression for not-opaque things consists of the three combinations
containing *d*, thus

       *d* = AB*cd* ꖌ A*b*C*d* ꖌ *abcd*,
  or   *d* = A*d* (B*c* ꖌ *b*C) ꖌ *abcd*.

In ordinary language, what is not-opaque is either metal which is
gold, and then not-silver, or silver and then not-gold, or else it is
not-metal and neither gold nor silver.


*Fourth Example.*

A good example for the illustration of the Indirect Method is to be
found in De Morgan’s *Formal Logic* (p. 123), the premises being
substantially as follows:--

From A follows B, and from C follows D; but B and D are inconsistent
with each other; therefore A and C are inconsistent.

The meaning no doubt is that where A is, B will be found, or that
every A is a B, and similarly every C is a D; but B and D cannot occur
together. The premises therefore appear to be of the forms

  A = AB,          (1)
  C = CD,          (2)
  B = B*d*.        (3)

On examining the series of sixteen combinations, only five are found to
be consistent with the above conditions, namely,

   AB*cd*
  *a*B*cd*
  *ab*CD
  *abc*D
  *abcd*.

In these combinations the only A which appears is joined to *c*, and
similarly C is joined to *a*, or A is inconsistent with C.


*Fifth Example.*

A more complex argument, also given by De Morgan,[78] contains five
terms, and is as stated below, except that the letters are altered.

  Every A is one only of the two B or C; D is both B and C, except
    when B is E, and then it is neither; therefore no A is D.

  [78] *Formal Logic*, p. 124. As Professor Croom Robertson has pointed
  out to me, the second and third premises may be thrown into a single
  proposition, D = D*e*BC ꖌ DE*bc*.

The meaning of the above premises is difficult to interpret, but seems
to be capable of expression in the following symbolic forms--

   A = AB*c* ꖌ A*b*C,      (1)
  De = D*e*BC,             (2)
  DE = DE*bc*.             (3)

As five terms enter into these premises it is requisite to treat their
thirty-two combinations, and it will be found that fourteen of them
remain consistent with the premises, namely

  AB*cd*E      *a*BCD*e*     *ab*C*d*E
  AB*cde*      *a*BC*d*E     *ab*C*de*
  A*b*C*d*E    *a*BC*de*     *abc*DE
  A*b*C*de*    *a*B*cd*E     *abcd*E
               *a*B*cde*     *abcde*.

If we examine the first four combinations, all of which contain A, we
find that they none of them contain D; or again, if we select those
which contain D, we have only two, thus--

  D = *a*BCD*e* ꖌ *abc*DE.

Hence it is clear that no A is D, and *vice versâ* no D is A. We might
draw many other conclusions from the same premises; for instance--

  DE = *abc*DE,

or D and E never meet but in the absence of A, B, and C.


*Fallacies analysed by the Indirect Method.*

It has been sufficiently shown, perhaps, that we can by the Indirect
Method of Inference extract the whole truth from a series of
propositions, and exhibit it anew in any required form of conclusion.
But it may also need to be shown by examples that so long as we follow
correctly the almost mechanical rules of the method, we cannot fall
into any of the fallacies or paralogisms which are often committed in
ordinary discussion. Let us take the example of a fallacious argument,
previously treated by the Method of Direct Inference (p. 62),

  Granite is not a sedimentary rock,    (1)
  Basalt is not a sedimentary rock,     (2)

and let us ascertain whether any precise conclusion can be drawn
concerning the relation of granite and basalt. Taking as before

  A = granite,
  B = sedimentary rock,
  C = basalt,

the premises become

  A = A*b*,       (1)
  C = C*b*.       (2)

Of the eight conceivable combinations of A, B, C, five agree with these
conditions, namely

  A*b*C     *a*B*c*
  A*bc*     *ab*C
            *abc*.

Selecting the combinations which contain A, we find the description of
granite to be

  A = A*b*C ꖌ A*bc* = A*b*(C ꖌ *c*),

that is, granite is not a sedimentary rock, and is either basalt or
not-basalt. If we want a description of basalt the answer is of like
form

  C = A*b*C ꖌ *ab*C = *b*C(A ꖌ *a*),

that is basalt is not a sedimentary rock, and is either granite or
not-granite. As it is already perfectly evident that basalt must be
either granite or not, and *vice versâ*, the premises fail to give us
any information on the point, that is to say the Method of Indirect
Inference saves us from falling into any fallacious conclusions. This
example sufficiently illustrates both the fallacy of Negative premises
and that of Undistributed Middle of the old logic.

The fallacy called the Illicit Process of the Major Term is also
incapable of commission in following the rules of the method. Our
example was (p. 65)

  All planets are subject to gravity,    (1)
  Fixed stars are not planets.           (2)

The false conclusion is that “fixed stars are not subject to gravity.”
The terms are

  A = planet
  B = fixed star
  C = subject to gravity.

And the premises are A = AC, (1) B = *a*B. (2)

The combinations which remain uncontradicted on comparison with these
premises are

   A*b*C     *a*B*c*
  *a*BC      *ab*C
             *abc*.

For fixed star we have the description

  B = *a*BC ꖌ *a*B*c*,

that is, “a fixed star is not a planet, but is either subject or not,
as the case may be, to gravity.” Here we have no conclusion concerning
the connection of fixed stars and gravity.


*The Logical Abacus.*

The Indirect Method of Inference has now been sufficiently described,
and a careful examination of its powers will show that it is capable of
giving a full analysis and solution of every question involving only
logical relations. The chief difficulty of the method consists in the
great number of combinations which may have to be examined; not only
may the requisite labour become formidable, but a considerable chance
of mistake arises. I have therefore given much attention to modes
of facilitating the work, and have succeeded in reducing the method
to an almost mechanical form. It soon appeared obvious that if the
conceivable combinations of the Logical Alphabet, for any number of
letters, instead of being printed in fixed order on a piece of paper
or slate, were marked upon light movable pieces of wood, mechanical
arrangements could readily be devised for selecting any required class
of the combinations. The labour of comparison and rejection might thus
be immensely reduced. This idea was first carried out in the Logical
Abacus, which I have found useful in the lecture-room for exhibiting
the complete solution of logical problems. A minute description of
the construction and use of the Abacus, together with figures of the
parts, has already been given in my essay called *The Substitution of
Similars*,[79] and I will here give only a general description.

  [79] Pp. 55–59, 81–86.

The Logical Abacus consists of a common school black-board placed in a
sloping position and furnished with four horizontal and equi-distant
ledges. The combinations of the letters shown in the first four columns
of the Logical Alphabet are printed in somewhat large type, so that
each letter is about an inch from the neighbouring one, but the letters
are placed one above the other instead of being in horizontal lines
as in p. 94. Each combination of letters is separately fixed to the
surface of a thin slip of wood one inch broad and about one-eighth
inch thick. Short steel pins are then driven in an inclined position
into the wood. When a letter is a large capital representing a positive
term, the pin is fixed in the upper part of its space; when the letter
is a small italic representing a negative term, the pin is fixed in
the lower part of the space. Now, if one of the series of combinations
be ranged upon a ledge of the black-board, the sharp edge of a flat
rule can be inserted beneath the pins belonging to any one letter--say
A, so that all the combinations marked A can be lifted out and placed
upon a separate ledge. Thus we have represented the act of thought
which separates the class A from what is not-A. The operation can be
repeated; out of the A’s we can in like manner select those which are
B’s, obtaining the AB’s; and in like manner we may select any other
classes such as the *a*B’s, the *ab*’s, or the *abc*’s.

If now we take the series of eight combinations of the letters A, B,
C, *a*, *b*, *c*, and wish to analyse the argument anciently called
Barbara, having the premises

  A = AB         (1)
  B = BC,        (2)

we proceed as follows--We raise the combinations marked *a*, leaving
the A’s behind; out of these A’s we move to a lower ledge such as
are *b*’s, and to the remaining AB’s we join the *a*’s which have
been raised. The result is that we have divided all the combinations
into two classes, namely, the A*b*’s which are incapable of existing
consistently with premise (1), and the combinations which are
consistent with the premise. Turning now to the second premise, we
raise out of those which agree with (1) the *b*’s, then we lower
the B*c*’s; lastly we join the *b*’s to the BC’s. We now find our
combinations arranged as below.

  +---+-----+-----+-----+-----+-----+-----+-----+
  | A |     |     |     | *a* |     | *a* | *a* |
  | B |     |     |     |  B  |     | *b* | *b* |
  | C |     |     |     |  C  |     |  C  | *c* |
  +---+-----+-----+-----+-----+-----+-----+-----+
  |   |  A  |  A  |  A  |     | *a* |     |     |
  |   |  B  | *b* | *b* |     |  B  |     |     |
  |   | *c* |  C  | *c* |     | *c* |     |     |
  +---+-----+-----+-----+-----+-----+-----+-----+

The lower line contains all the combinations which are inconsistent
with either premise; we have carried out in a mechanical manner that
exclusion of self-contradictories which was formerly done upon the
slate or upon paper. Accordingly, from the combinations remaining in
the upper line we can draw any inference which the premises yield. If
we raise the A’s we find only one, and that is C, so that A must be C.
If we select the *c*’s we again find only one, which is *a* and also
*b*; thus we prove that not-C is not-A and not-B.

When a disjunctive proposition occurs among the premises the requisite
movements become rather more complicated. Take the disjunctive argument

  A is either B or C or D,
  A is not C and not D,
  Therefore A is B.

The premises are represented accurately as follows:--

  A = AB ꖌ AC ꖌ AD       (1)
  A = A*c*               (2)
  A = A*d*.              (3)

As there are four terms, we choose the series of sixteen combinations
and place them on the highest ledge of the board but one. We raise
the *a*’s and out of the A’s, which remain, we lower the *b*’s. But
we are not to reject all the A*b*’s as contradictory, because by the
first premise A’s may be either B’s or C’s or D’s. Accordingly out
of the A*b*’s we must select the *c*’s, and out of these again the
*d*’s, so that only A*bcd* will remain to be rejected finally. Joining
all the other fifteen combinations together again, and proceeding to
premise (2), we raise the *a*’s and lower the AC’s, and thus reject
the combinations inconsistent with (2); similarly we reject the AD’s
which are inconsistent with (3). It will be found that there remain,
in addition to all the eight combinations containing *a*, only one
containing A, namely

  AB*cd*,

whence it is apparent that A must be B, the ordinary conclusion of the
argument.

In my “Substitution of Similars” (pp. 56–59) I have described the
working upon the Abacus of two other logical problems, which it would
be tedious to repeat in this place.


*The Logical Machine.*

Although the Logical Abacus considerably reduced the labour of using
the Indirect Method, it was not free from the possibility of error.
I thought moreover that it would afford a conspicuous proof of the
generality and power of the method if I could reduce it to a purely
mechanical form. Logicians had long been accustomed to speak of Logic
as an Organon or Instrument, and even Lord Bacon, while he rejected
the old syllogistic logic, had insisted, in the second aphorism of his
“New Instrument,” that the mind required some kind of systematic aid.
In the kindred science of mathematics mechanical assistance of one kind
or another had long been employed. Orreries, globes, mechanical clocks,
and such like instruments, are really aids to calculation and are of
considerable antiquity. The Arithmetical Abacus is still in common use
in Russia and China. The calculating machine of Pascal is more than two
centuries old, having been constructed in 1642–45. M. Thomas of Colmar
manufactures an arithmetical machine on Pascal’s principles which
is employed by engineers and others who need frequently to multiply
or divide. To Babbage and Scheutz is due the merit of embodying the
Calculus of Differences in a machine, which thus became capable of
calculating the most complicated tables of figures. It seemed strange
that in the more intricate science of quantity mechanism should be
applicable, whereas in the simple science of qualitative reasoning, the
syllogism was only called an instrument by a figure of speech. It is
true that Swift satirically described the Professors of Laputa as in
possession of a thinking machine, and in 1851 Mr. Alfred Smee actually
proposed the construction of a Relational machine and a Differential
machine, the first of which would be a mechanical dictionary and the
second a mode of comparing ideas; but with these exceptions I have not
yet met with so much as a suggestion of a reasoning machine. It may be
added that Mr. Smee’s designs, though highly ingenious, appear to be
impracticable, and in any case they do not attempt the performance of
logical inference.[80]

  [80] See his work called *The Process of Thought adapted to Words
  and Language, together with a Description of the Relational and
  Differential Machines*. Also *Philosophical Transactions*, [1870]
  vol. 160, p. 518.

The Logical Abacus soon suggested the notion of a Logical Machine,
which, after two unsuccessful attempts, I succeeded in constructing
in a comparatively simple and effective form. The details of the
Logical Machine have been fully described by the aid of plates in the
Philosophical Transactions,[81] and it would be needless to repeat the
account of the somewhat intricate movements of the machine in this
place.

  [81] *Philosophical Transactions* [1870], vol. 160, p. 497.
  *Proceedings of the Royal Society*, vol. xviii. p. 166, Jan. 20,
  1870. *Nature*, vol, i. p. 343.

The general appearance of the machine is shown in a plate facing
the title-page of this volume. It somewhat resembles a very small
upright piano or organ, and has a keyboard containing twenty-one keys.
These keys are of two kinds, sixteen of them representing the terms
or letters A, *a*, B, *b*, C, *c*, D, *d*, which have so often been
employed in our logical notation. When letters occur on the left-hand
side of a proposition, formerly called the subject, each is represented
by a key on the left-hand half of the keyboard; but when they occur on
the right-hand side, or as it used to be called the predicate of the
proposition, the letter-keys on the right-hand side of the keyboard are
the proper representatives. The five other keys may be called operation
keys, to distinguish them from the letter or term keys. They stand for
the stops, copula, and disjunctive conjunctions of a proposition. The
middle key of all is the copula, to be pressed when the verb *is* or
the sign = is met. The key to the extreme right-hand is called the Full
Stop, because it should be pressed when a proposition is completed,
in fact in the proper place of the full stop. The key to the extreme
left-hand is used to terminate an argument or to restore the machine to
its initial condition; it is called the Finis key. The last keys but
one on the right and left complete the whole series, and represent the
conjunction *or* in its unexclusive meaning, or the sign ꖌ which I have
employed, according as it occurs in the right or left hand side of the
proposition. The whole keyboard is arranged as shown on the next page--

  +-+-----------------------------------+-+-----------------------------------+---+
  | |                                   |C|                                   |   |
  |F|   Left-hand side of Proposition.  |o|  Right-hand side of Proposition.  |F S|
  |i|                                   |p|                                   |u t|
  |n+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+u+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+l o|
  |i|   |   |   |   |   |   |   |   |   |l|   |   |   |   |   |   |   |   |   |l p|
  |s|ꖌ|*d*| D |*c*| C |*b*| B |*a*| A |a| A |*a*| B |*b*| C |*c*| D |*d*|ꖌ|  .|
  |.|Or |   |   |   |   |   |   |   |   |.|   |   |   |   |   |   |   |   | Or|   |
  +-+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+-+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+---+

To work the machine it is only requisite to press the keys in
succession as indicated by the letters and signs of a symbolical
proposition. All the premises of an argument are supposed to be reduced
to the simple notation which has been employed in the previous pages.
Taking then such a simple proposition as

  A = AB,

we press the keys A (left), copula, A (right), B (right), and full stop.

If there be a second premise, for instance

  B = BC,

we press in like manner the keys--

  B (left), copula, B (right), C (right), full stop.

The process is exactly the same however numerous the premises may be.
When they are completed the operator will see indicated on the face of
the machine the exact combinations of letters which are consistent with
the premises according to the principles of thought.

As shown in the figure opposite the title-page, the machine exhibits in
front a Logical Alphabet of sixteen combinations, exactly like that of
the Abacus, except that the letters of each combination are separated
by a certain interval. After the above problem has been worked upon the
machine the Logical Alphabet will have been modified so as to present
the following appearance--

  +-------------------------------------------------------+
  |                                                       |
  +---+---+--+--+--+--+--+--+---+---+--+--+---+---+---+---+
  | A | A |  |  |  |  |  |  |*a*|*a*|  |  |*a*|*a*|*a*|*a*|
  +---+---+--+--+--+--+--+--+---+---+--+--+---+---+---+---+
  |                                                       |
  +---+---+--+--+--+--+--+--+---+---+--+--+---+---+---+---+
  | B | B |  |  |  |  |  |  | B | B |  |  |*b*|*b*|*b*|*b*|
  +---+---+--+--+--+--+--+--+---+---+--+--+---+---+---+---+
  |                                                       |
  +---+---+--+--+--+--+--+--+---+---+--+--+---+---+---+---+
  | C | C |  |  |  |  |  |  | C | C |  |  | C | C |*c*|*c*|
  +---+---+--+--+--+--+--+--+---+---+--+--+---+---+---+---+
  |                                                       |
  +---+---+--+--+--+--+--+--+---+---+--+--+---+---+---+---+
  | D |*d*|  |  |  |  |  |  | D |*d*|  |  | D |*d*| D |*d*|
  +---+---+--+--+--+--+--+--+---+---+--+--+---+---+---+---+
  |                                                       |
  +-------------------------------------------------------+

The operator will readily collect the various conclusions in the manner
described in previous pages, as, for instance that A is always C, that
not-C is not-B and not-A; and not-B is not-A but either C or not-C. The
results are thus to be read off exactly as in the case of the Logical
Slate, or the Logical Abacus.

Disjunctive propositions are to be treated in an exactly similar
manner. Thus, to work the premises

  A = AB ꖌ AC
  B ꖌ C = BD ꖌ CD,

it is only necessary to press in succession the keys

  A (left), copula, A (right), B, ꖌ, A, C, full stop.
  B (left), ꖌ, C, copula, B (right), D, ꖌ, C, D, full stop.

The combinations then remaining will be as follows

  ABCD        *a*BCD        *abc*D
  AB*c*D      *a*B*c*D      *abcd.*
  A*c*CD      *ab*CD

On pressing the left-hand key A, all the possible combinations which do
not contain A will disappear, and the description of A may be gathered
from what remain, namely that it is always D. The full-stop key
restores all combinations consistent with the premises and any other
selection may be made, as say not-D, which will be found to be always
not-A, not-B, and not-C.

At the end of every problem, when no further questions need be
addressed to the machine, we press the Finis key, which has the effect
of bringing into view the whole of the conceivable combinations of
the alphabet. This key in fact obliterates the conditions impressed
upon the machine by moving back into their ordinary places those
combinations which had been rejected as inconsistent with the premises.
Before beginning any new problem it is requisite to observe that the
whole sixteen combinations are visible. After the Finis key has been
used the machine represents a mind endowed with powers of thought,
but wholly devoid of knowledge. It would not in that condition give
any answer but such as would consist in the primary laws of thought
themselves. But when any proposition is worked upon the keys, the
machine analyses and digests the meaning of it and becomes charged with
the knowledge embodied in that proposition. Accordingly it is able
to return as an answer any description of a term or class so far as
furnished by that proposition in accordance with the Laws of Thought.
The machine is thus the embodiment of a true logical system. The
combinations are classified, selected or rejected, just as they should
be by a reasoning mind, so that at each step in a problem, the Logical
Alphabet represents the proper condition of a mind exempt from mistake.
It cannot be asserted indeed that the machine entirely supersedes the
agency of conscious thought; mental labour is required in interpreting
the meaning of grammatical expressions, and in correctly impressing
that meaning on the machine; it is further required in gathering
the conclusion from the remaining combinations. Nevertheless the
true process of logical inference is really accomplished in a purely
mechanical manner.

It is worthy of remark that the machine can detect any
self-contradiction existing between the premises presented to it;
should the premises be self-contradictory it will be found that one or
more of the letter-terms disappears entirely from the Logical Alphabet.
Thus if we work the two propositions, A is B, and A is not-B, and then
inquire for a description of A, the machine will refuse to give it
by exhibiting no combination at all containing A. This result is in
agreement with the law, which I have explained, that every term must
have its negative (p. 74). Accordingly, whenever any one of the letters
A, B, C, D, *a*, *b*, *c*, *d*, wholly disappears from the alphabet,
it may be safely inferred that some act of self-contradiction has been
committed.

It ought to be carefully observed that the logical machine cannot
receive a simple identity of the form A = B except in the double form
of A = B and B = A. To work the proposition A = B, it is therefore
necessary to press the keys--

  A (left), copula, B (right), full stop;
  B (left), copula, A (right), full stop.

The same double operation will be necessary whenever the proposition is
not of the kind called a partial identity (p. 40). Thus AB = CD, AB =
AC, A = B ꖌ C, A ꖌ B = C ꖌ D, all require to be read from both ends
separately.

The proper rule for using the machine may in fact be given in the
following way:--(1) *Read each proposition as it stands, and play
the corresponding keys*: (2) *Convert the proposition and read and
play the keys again in the transposed order of the terms.* So long
as this rule is observed the true result must always be obtained.
There can be no mistake. But it will be found that in the case of
partial identities, and some other similar forms of propositions, the
transposed reading has no effect upon the combinations of the Logical
Alphabet. One reading is in such cases all that is practically needful.
After some experience has been gained in the use of the machine, the
worker naturally saves himself the trouble of the second reading when
possible.

It is no doubt a remarkable fact that a simple identity cannot
be impressed upon the machine except in the form of two partial
identities, and this may be thought by some logicians to militate
against the equational mode of representing propositions.

Before leaving the subject I may remark that these mechanical devices
are not likely to possess much practical utility. We do not require in
common life to be constantly solving complex logical questions. Even in
mathematical calculation the ordinary rules of arithmetic are generally
sufficient, and a calculating machine can only be used with advantage
in peculiar cases. But the machine and abacus have nevertheless two
important uses.

In the first place I hope that the time is not very far distant when
the predominance of the ancient Aristotelian Logic will be a matter
of history only, and when the teaching of logic will be placed on a
footing more worthy of its supreme importance. It will then be found
that the solution of logical questions is an exercise of mind at least
as valuable and necessary as mathematical calculation. I believe that
these mechanical devices, or something of the same kind, will then
become useful for exhibiting to a class of students a clear and visible
analysis of logical problems of any degree of complexity, the nature
of each step being rendered plain to the eyes of the students. I often
used the machine or abacus for this purpose in my class lectures while
I was Professor of Logic at Owens College.

Secondly, the more immediate importance of the machine seems to consist
in the unquestionable proof which it affords that correct views of the
fundamental principles of reasoning have now been attained, although
they were unknown to Aristotle and his followers. The time must come
when the inevitable results of the admirable investigations of the late
Dr. Boole must be recognised at their true value, and the plain and
palpable form in which the machine presents those results will, I hope,
hasten the time. Undoubtedly Boole’s life marks an era in the science
of human reason. It may seem strange that it had remained for him first
to set forth in its full extent the problem of logic, but I am not
aware that anyone before him had treated logic as a symbolic method
for evolving from any premises the description of any class whatsoever
as defined by those premises. In spite of several serious errors into
which he fell, it will probably be allowed that Boole discovered the
true and general form of logic, and put the science substantially into
the form which it must hold for evermore. He thus effected a reform
with which there is hardly anything comparable in the history of logic
between his time and the remote age of Aristotle.

Nevertheless, Boole’s quasi-mathematical system could hardly be
regarded as a final and unexceptionable solution of the problem. Not
only did it require the manipulation of mathematical symbols in a very
intricate and perplexing manner, but the results when obtained were
devoid of demonstrative force, because they turned upon the employment
of unintelligible symbols, acquiring meaning only by analogy. I
have also pointed out that he imported into his system a condition
concerning the exclusive nature of alternatives (p. 70), which is
not necessarily true of logical terms. I shall have to show in the
next chapter that logic is really the basis of the whole science of
mathematical reasoning, so that Boole inverted the true order of proof
when he proposed to infer logical truths by algebraic processes. It is
wonderful evidence of his mental power that by methods fundamentally
false he should have succeeded in reaching true conclusions and
widening the sphere of reason.

The mechanical performance of logical inference affords a demonstration
both of the truth of Boole’s results and of the mistaken nature of his
mode of deducing them. Conclusions which he could obtain only by pages
of intricate calculation, are exhibited by the machine after one or
two minutes of manipulation. And not only are those conclusions easily
reached, but they are demonstratively true, because every step of the
process involves nothing more obscure than the three fundamental Laws
of Thought.


*The Order of Premises.*

Before quitting the subject of deductive reasoning, I may remark that
the order in which the premises of an argument are placed is a matter
of logical indifference. Much discussion has taken place at various
times concerning the arrangement of the premises of a syllogism; and it
has been generally held, in accordance with the opinion of Aristotle,
that the so-called major premise, containing the major term, or the
predicate of the conclusion, should stand first. This distinction
however falls to the ground in our system, since the proposition is
reduced to an identical form, in which there is no distinction of
subject and predicate. In a strictly logical point of view the order
of statement is wholly devoid of significance. The premises are
simultaneously coexistent, and are not related to each other according
to the properties of space and time. Just as the qualities of the same
object are neither before nor after each other in nature (p. 33), and
are only thought of in some one order owing to the limited capacity of
mind, so the premises of an argument are neither before nor after each
other, and are only thought of in succession because the mind cannot
grasp many ideas at once. The combinations of the logical alphabet
are exactly the same in whatever order the premises be treated on
the logical slate or machine. Some difference may doubtless exist as
regards convenience to human memory. The mind may take in the results
of an argument more easily in one mode of statement than another,
although there is no real difference in the logical results. But in
this point of view I think that Aristotle and the old logicians were
clearly wrong. It is more easy to gather the conclusion that “all A’s
are C’s” from “all A’s are B’s and all B’s are C’s,” than from the same
propositions in inverted order, “all B’s are C’s and all A’s are B’s.”


*The Equivalence of Propositions*.

One great advantage which arises from the study of this Indirect
Method of Inference consists in the clear notion which we gain of
the Equivalence of Propositions. The older logicians showed how from
certain simple premises we might draw an inference, but they failed
to point out whether that inference contained the whole, or only a
part, of the information embodied in the premises. Any one proposition
or group of propositions may be classed with respect to another
proposition or group of propositions, as

  1. Equivalent,
  2. Inferrible,
  3. Consistent,
  4. Contradictory.

Taking the proposition “All men are mortals” as the original, then
“All immortals are not men” is its equivalent; “Some mortals are men”
is inferrible, or capable of inference, but is not equivalent; “All
not-men are not mortals” cannot be inferred, but is consistent, that
is, may be true at the same time; “All men are immortals” is of course
contradictory.

One sufficient test of equivalence is capability of mutual inference.
Thus from

  All electrics = all non-conductors,

I can infer

  All non-electrics = all conductors,

and *vice versâ* from the latter I can pass back to the former. In
short, A = B is equivalent to *a* = *b*. Again, from the union of the
two propositions, A = AB and B = AB, I get A = B, and from this I
might as easily deduce the two with which I started. In this case one
proposition is equivalent to two other propositions. There are in fact
no less than four modes in which we may express the identity of two
classes A and B, namely,

  FIRST MODE.    SECOND MODE.    THIRD MODE.    FOURTH MODE.

    A = B         *a* = *b*       A = AB }      *a* = *ab* }
                                  B = AB }      *b* = *ab* }

The Indirect Method of Inference furnishes a universal and clear
criterion as to the relationship of propositions. The import of a
statement is always to be measured by the combinations of terms which
it destroys. Hence two propositions are equivalent when they remove
the same combinations from the Logical Alphabet, and neither more nor
less. A proposition is inferrible but not equivalent to another when
it removes some but not all the combinations which the other removes,
and none except what this other removes. Again, propositions are
consistent provided that they jointly allow each term and the negative
of each term to remain somewhere in the Logical Alphabet. If after all
the combinations inconsistent with two propositions are struck out,
there still appears each of the letters A, *a*, B, *b*, C, *c*, D, *d*,
which were there before, then no inconsistency between the propositions
exists, although they may not be equivalent or even inferrible.
Finally, contradictory propositions are those which taken together
remove any one or more letter-terms from the Logical Alphabet.

What is true of single propositions applies also to groups of
propositions, however large or complicated; that is to say, one group
may be equivalent, inferrible, consistent, or contradictory as regards
another, and we may similarly compare one proposition with a group of
propositions.

To give in this place illustrations of all the four kinds of relation
would require much space: as the examples given in previous sections or
chapters may serve more or less to explain the relations of inference,
consistency, and contradiction, I will only add a few instances of
equivalent propositions or groups.

In the following list each proposition or group of propositions is
exactly equivalent in meaning to the corresponding one in the other
column, and the truth of this statement may be tested by working out
the combinations of the alphabet, which ought to be found exactly the
same in the case of each pair of equivalents.

         A  =  A*b*  . . . . . . .  B   = *a*B
         A  = *b*  . . . . . . . . *a*  =  B
         A  =  BC  . . . . . . . . *a*  = *b* ꖌ *c*
         A  =  AB ꖌ AC . . . . . . *b*  = *ab* ꖌ A*b*C
      A ꖌB  =  C ꖌ D . . . . . . . *ab* = *cd*
    A ꖌ *c* =  B ꖌ *d* . . . . . . *a*C = *b*D
         A  =  AB*c* ꖌ A*b*C . . .{ A   =  AB ꖌ AC
                                  { AB  =  AB*c*

          A = B }                   { A = B
          B = C } . . . . . . . . . { A = C

          A = AB }                  { A = AC
          B = BC }. . . . . . . . . { B = A ꖌ *a*BC

Although in these and many other cases the equivalents of certain
propositions can readily be given, yet I believe that no uniform and
infallible process can be pointed out by which the exact equivalents
of premises can be ascertained. Ordinary deductive inference usually
gives us only a portion of the contained information. It is true that
the combinations consistent with a set of premises may always be thrown
into the form of a proposition which must be logically equivalent to
those premises; but the difficulty consists in detecting the other
forms of propositions which will be equivalent to the premises. The
task is here of a different character from any which we have yet
attempted. It is in reality an inverse process, and is just as much
more troublesome and uncertain than the direct process, as seeking is
compared with hiding. Not only may several different answers equally
apply, but there is no method of discovering any of those answers
except by repeated trial. The problem which we have here met is really
that of induction, the inverse of deduction; and, as I shall soon show,
induction is always tentative, and, unless conducted with peculiar
skill and insight, must be exceedingly laborious in cases of complexity.

De Morgan was unfortunately led by this equivalence of propositions
into the most serious error of his ingenious system of Logic. He held
that because the proposition “All A’s are all B’s,” is but another
expression for the two propositions “All A’s are B’s” and “All B’s
are A’s,” it must be a composite and not really an elementary form
of proposition.[82] But on taking a general view of the equivalence
of propositions such an objection seems to have no weight. Logicians
have, with few exceptions, persistently upheld the original error of
Aristotle in rejecting from their science the one simple relation of
identity on which all more complex logical relations must really rest.

  [82] *Syllabus of a proposed system of Logic*, §§ 57, 121, &c.
  *Formal Logic*, p. 66.


*The Nature of Inference.*

The question, What is Inference? is involved, even to the present day,
in as much uncertainty as that ancient question, What is Truth? I shall
in more than one part of this work endeavour to show that inference
never does more than explicate, unfold, or develop the information
contained in certain premises or facts. Neither in deductive nor
inductive reasoning can we add a tittle to our implicit knowledge,
which is like that contained in an unread book or a sealed letter. Sir
W. Hamilton has well said, “Reasoning is the showing out explicitly
that a proposition not granted or supposed, is implicitly contained in
something different, which is granted or supposed.”[83]

  [83] Lectures on Metaphysics, vol. iv. p. 369.

Professor Bowen has explained[84] with much clearness that the
conclusion of an argument states explicitly what is virtually or
implicitly thought. “The process of reasoning is not so much a mode of
evolving a new truth, as it is of establishing or proving an old one,
by showing how much was admitted in the concession of the two premises
taken together.” It is true that the whole meaning of these statements
rests upon that of such words as “explicit,” “implicit,” “virtual.”
That is implicit which is wrapped up, and we render it explicit when
we unfold it. Just as the conception of a circle involves a hundred
important geometrical properties, all following from what we know, if
we have acuteness to unfold the results, so every fact and statement
involves more meaning than seems at first sight. Reasoning explicates
or brings to conscious possession what was before unconscious. It does
not create, nor does it destroy, but it transmutes and throws the same
matter into a new form.

  [84] Bowen, *Treatise on Logic*, Cambridge, U.S., 1866; p. 362.

The difficult question still remains, Where does novelty of form begin?
Is it a case of inference when we pass from “Sincerity is the parent of
truth” to “The parent of truth is sincerity?” The old logicians would
have called this change *conversion*, one case of immediate inference.
But as all identity is necessarily reciprocal, and the very meaning
of such a proposition is that the two terms are identical in their
signification, I fail to see any difference between the statements
whatever. As well might we say that *x* = *y* and *y* = *x* are
different equations.

Another point of difficulty is to decide when a change is merely
grammatical and when it involves a real logical transformation. Between
a *table of wood* and a *wooden table* there is no logical difference
(p. 31), the adjective being merely a convenient substitute for the
prepositional phrase. But it is uncertain to my mind whether the
change from “All men are mortal” to “No men are not mortal” is purely
grammatical. Logical change may perhaps be best described as consisting
in the determination of a relation between certain classes of objects
from a relation between certain other classes. Thus I consider it a
truly logical inference when we pass from “All men are mortal” to “All
immortals are not-men,” because the classes *immortals* and *not-men*
are different from *mortals* and *men*, and yet the propositions
contain at the bottom the very same truth, as shown in the combinations
of the Logical Alphabet.

The passage from the qualitative to the quantitative mode of expressing
a proposition is another kind of change which we must discriminate
from true logical inference. We state the same truth when we say that
“mortality belongs to all men,” as when we assert that “all men are
mortals.” Here we do not pass from class to class, but from one kind
of term, the abstract, to another kind, the concrete. But inference
probably enters when we pass from either of the above propositions to
the assertion that the class of immortal men is zero, or contains no
objects.

It is of course a question of words to what processes we shall or shall
not apply the name “inference,” and I have no wish to continue the
trifling discussions which have already taken place upon the subject.
What we need to do is to define accurately the sense in which we use
the word “inference,” and to distinguish the relation of inferrible
propositions from other possible relations. It seems to be sufficient
to recognise four modes in which two apparently different propositions
may be related. Thus two propositions may be--

1. *Tautologous* or *identical*, involving the same relation between
the same terms and classes, and only differing in the order of
statement; thus “Victoria is the Queen of England” is tautologous with
“The Queen of England is Victoria.”

2. *Grammatically related*, when the classes or objects are the same
and similarly related, and the only difference is in the words; thus
“Victoria is the Queen of England” is grammatically equivalent to
“Victoria is England’s Queen.”

3. *Equivalents* in qualitative and quantitative form, the classes
being the same, but viewed in a different manner.

4. *Logically inferrible*, one from the other, or it may be
*equivalent*, when the classes and relations are different, but involve
the same knowledge of the possible combinations.




CHAPTER VII.

INDUCTION.


We enter in this chapter upon the second great department of logical
method, that of Induction or the Inference of general from particular
truths. It cannot be said that the Inductive process is of greater
importance than the Deductive process already considered, because the
latter process is absolutely essential to the existence of the former.
Each is the complement and counterpart of the other. The principles
of thought and existence which underlie them are at the bottom the
same, just as subtraction of numbers necessarily rests upon the same
principles as addition. Induction is, in fact, the inverse operation of
deduction, and cannot be conceived to exist without the corresponding
operation, so that the question of relative importance cannot arise.
Who thinks of asking whether addition or subtraction is the more
important process in arithmetic? But at the same time much difference
in difficulty may exist between a direct and inverse operation; the
integral calculus, for instance, is infinitely more difficult than the
differential calculus of which it is the inverse. Similarly, it must
be allowed that inductive investigations are of a far higher degree of
difficulty and complexity than any questions of deduction; and it is
this fact no doubt which led some logicians, such as Francis Bacon,
Locke, and J. S. Mill, to erroneous opinions concerning the exclusive
importance of induction.

Hitherto we have been engaged in considering how from certain
conditions, laws, or identities governing the combinations of
qualities, we may deduce the nature of the combinations agreeing
with those conditions. Our work has been to unfold the results of
what is contained in any statements, and the process has been one of
*Synthesis*. The terms or combinations of which the character has been
determined have usually, though by no means always, involved more
qualities, and therefore, by the relation of extension and intension,
fewer objects than the terms in which they were described. The truths
inferred were thus usually less general than the truths from which they
were inferred.

In induction all is inverted. The truths to be ascertained are more
general than the data from which they are drawn. The process by which
they are reached is *analytical*, and consists in separating the
complex combinations in which natural phenomena are presented to us,
and determining the relations of separate qualities. Given events
obeying certain unknown laws, we have to discover the laws obeyed.
Instead of the comparatively easy task of finding what effects will
follow from a given law, the effects are now given and the law is
required. We have to interpret the will by which the conditions of
creation were laid down.


*Induction an Inverse Operation*

I have already asserted that induction is the inverse operation of
deduction, but the difference is one of such great importance that I
must dwell upon it. There are many cases in which we can easily and
infallibly do a certain thing but may have much trouble in undoing
it. A person may walk into the most complicated labyrinth or the
most extensive catacombs, and turn hither and thither at his will;
it is when he wishes to return that doubt and difficulty commence.
In entering, any path served him; in leaving, he must select certain
definite paths, and in this selection he must either trust to memory
of the way he entered or else make an exhaustive trial of all possible
ways. The explorer entering a new country makes sure his line of return
by barking the trees.

The same difficulty arises in many scientific processes. Given any
two numbers, we may by a simple and infallible process obtain their
product; but when a large number is given it is quite another
matter to determine its factors. Can the reader say what two numbers
multiplied together will produce the number 8,616,460,799? I think it
unlikely that anyone but myself will ever know; for they are two large
prime numbers, and can only be rediscovered by trying in succession
a long series of prime divisors until the right one be fallen upon.
The work would probably occupy a good computer for many weeks, but it
did not occupy me many minutes to multiply the two factors together.
Similarly there is no direct process for discovering whether any number
is a prime or not; it is only by exhaustively trying all inferior
numbers which could be divisors, that we can show there is none, and
the labour of the process would be intolerable were it not performed
systematically once for all in the process known as the Sieve of
Eratosthenes, the results being registered in tables of prime numbers.

The immense difficulties which are encountered in the solution of
algebraic equations afford another illustration. Given any algebraic
factors, we can easily and infallibly arrive at the product; but given
a product it is a matter of infinite difficulty to resolve it into
factors. Given any series of quantities however numerous, there is very
little trouble in making an equation which shall have those quantities
as roots. Let *a*, *b*, *c*, *d*, &c., be the quantities; then

  (*x* - *a*)(*x* - *b*)(*x* - *c*)(*x* - d) ... = 0

is the equation required, and we only need to multiply out the
expression on the left hand by ordinary rules. But having given a
complex algebraic expression equated to zero, it is a matter of
exceeding difficulty to discover all the roots. Mathematicians have
exhausted their highest powers in carrying the complete solution up to
the fourth degree. In every other mathematical operation the inverse
process is far more difficult than the direct process, subtraction than
addition, division than multiplication, evolution than involution;
but the difficulty increases vastly as the process becomes more
complex. Differentiation, the direct process, is always capable of
performance by fixed rules, but as these rules produce considerable
variety of results, the inverse process of integration presents
immense difficulties, and in an infinite majority of cases surpasses
the present resources of mathematicians. There are no infallible and
general rules for its accomplishment; it must be done by trial, by
guesswork, or by remembering the results of differentiation, and using
them as a guide.

Coming more nearly to our own immediate subject, exactly the same
difficulty exists in determining the law which certain things obey.
Given a general mathematical expression, we can infallibly ascertain
its value for any required value of the variable. But I am not aware
that mathematicians have ever attempted to lay down the rules of a
process by which, having given certain numbers, one might discover a
rational or precise formula from which they proceed. The reader may
test his power of detecting a law, by contemplation of its results, if
he, not being a mathematician, will attempt to point out the law obeyed
by the following numbers:

  1/6, 1/30, 1/42, 1/30, 5/66, 691/2730, 7/6, 3617/510, 43867/798, etc.

These numbers are sometimes in low terms, but unexpectedly spring up
to high terms; in absolute magnitude they are very variable. They seem
to set all regularity and method at defiance, and it is hardly to be
supposed that anyone could, from contemplation of the numbers, have
detected the relations between them. Yet they are derived from the
most regular and symmetrical laws of relation, and are of the highest
importance in mathematical analysis, being known as the numbers of
Bernoulli.

Compare again the difficulty of decyphering with that of cyphering.
Anyone can invent a secret language, and with a little steady labour
can translate the longest letter into the character. But to decypher
the letter, having no key to the signs adopted, is a wholly different
matter. As the possible modes of secret writing are infinite in number
and exceedingly various in kind, there is no direct mode of discovery
whatever. Repeated trial, guided more or less by knowledge of the
customary form of cypher, and resting entirely on the principles of
probability and logical induction, is the only resource. A peculiar
tact or skill is requisite for the process, and a few men, such as
Wallis or Wheatstone, have attained great success.

Induction is the decyphering of the hidden meaning of natural
phenomena. Given events which happen in certain definite combinations,
we are required to point out the laws which govern those combinations.
Any laws being supposed, we can, with ease and certainty, decide
whether the phenomena obey those laws. But the laws which may exist
are infinite in variety, so that the chances are immensely against
mere random guessing. The difficulty is much increased by the fact
that several laws will usually be in operation at the same time, the
effects of which are complicated together. The only modes of discovery
consist either in exhaustively trying a great number of supposed laws,
a process which is exhaustive in more senses than one, or else in
carefully contemplating the effects, endeavouring to remember cases
in which like effects followed from known laws. In whatever manner we
accomplish the discovery, it must be done by the more or less conscious
application of the direct process of deduction.

The Logical Alphabet illustrates induction as well as deduction. In
considering the Indirect Process of Inference we found that from
certain propositions we could infallibly determine the combinations
of terms agreeing with those premises. The inductive problem is just
the inverse. Having given certain combinations of terms, we need to
ascertain the propositions with which the combinations are consistent,
and from which they may have proceeded. Now, if the reader contemplates
the following combinations,

   ABC       *ab*C
  *a*BC      *abc*,

he will probably remember at once that they belong to the premises
A = AB, B = BC (p. 92). If not, he will require a few trials before he
meets with the right answer, and every trial will consist in assuming
certain laws and observing whether the deduced results agree with the
data. To test the facility with which he can solve this inductive
problem, let him casually strike out any of the combinations of the
fourth column of the Logical Alphabet, (p. 94), and say what laws
the remaining combinations obey, observing that every one of the
letter-terms and their negatives ought to appear in order to avoid
self-contradiction in the premises (pp. 74, 111). Let him say, for
instance, what laws are embodied in the combinations

  ABC       *a*BC
  A*bc*     *ab*C.

The difficulty becomes much greater when more terms enter into the
combinations. It would require some little examination to ascertain the
complete conditions fulfilled in the combinations

   AC*e*      *ab*C*e*
  *a*BC*e*    *abc*E.
  *a*B*cd*E

The reader may discover easily enough that the principal laws are
C = *e*, and A = A*e*; but he would hardly discover without some
trouble the remaining law, namely, that BD = BD*e*.

The difficulties encountered in the inductive investigations of
nature, are of an exactly similar kind. We seldom observe any law in
uninterrupted and undisguised operation. The acuteness of Aristotle and
the ancient Greeks did not enable them to detect that all terrestrial
bodies tend to fall towards the centre of the earth. A few nights of
observation might have convinced an astronomer viewing the solar system
from its centre, that the planets travelled round the sun; but the
fact that our place of observation is one of the travelling planets,
so complicates the apparent motions of the other bodies, that it
required all the sagacity of Copernicus to prove the real simplicity of
the planetary system. It is the same throughout nature; the laws may
be simple, but their combined effects are not simple, and we have no
clue to guide us through their intricacies. “It is the glory of God,”
said Solomon, “to conceal a thing, but the glory of a king to search
it out.” The laws of nature are the invaluable secrets which God has
hidden, and it is the kingly prerogative of the philosopher to search
them out by industry and sagacity.


*Inductive Problems for Solution by the Reader.*

In the first edition (vol. ii. p. 370) I gave a logical problem
involving six terms, and requested readers to discover the laws
governing the combinations given. I received satisfactory replies
from readers both in the United States and in England. I formed
the combinations deductively from four laws of correction, but my
correspondents found that three simpler laws, equivalent to the four
more complex ones, were the best answer; these laws are as follows:
*a* = *ac*, *b* = *cd*, *d* = E*f*.

In case other readers should like to test their skill in the inductive
or inverse problem, I give below several series of combinations forming
problems of graduated difficulty.

  PROBLEM I.

       A  B *c*
       A *b* C
      *a* B  C

  PROBLEM II.

       A  B  C
       A *b* C
      *a* B  C
      *a* B *c*

  PROBLEM III.

       A   B   C
       A  *b*  C
      *a*  B   C
      *a*  B  *c*
      *a* *b* *c*

  PROBLEM IV.

       A   B   C   D
       A  *b* *c*  D
      *a*  B  *c* *d*
      *a* *b*  C  *d*

  PROBLEM V.

       A   B   C   D
       A   B   C  *d*
       A   B  *c* *d*
       A  *b*  C   D
       A  *b* *c*  D
      *a*  B   C   D
      *a*  B  *c*  D
      *a*  B  *c* *d*
      *a* *b*  C  *d*

  PROBLEM VI.

       A   B   C   D   E
       A   B   C  *d* *e*
       A   B  *c*  D   E
       A   B  *c* *d* *e*
       A  *b*  C   D   E
      *a*  B   C   D   E
      *a*  B   C  *d* *e*
      *a* *b*  C   D   E
      *a* *b* *c* *d* *e*

  PROBLEM VII.

       A  *b* *c*  D  *e*
      *a*  B   C  *d*  E
      *a* *b*  C  *d*  E

  PROBLEM VIII.

       A   B   C   D   E
       A   B   C   D  *e*
       A   B   C  *d* *e*
       A   B  *c* *d* *e*
       A  *b*  C   D   E
       A  *b* *c* *d*  E
       A  *b* *c* *d* *e*
      *a*  B   C   D  *e*
      *a*  B   C  *d* *e*
      *a*  B  *c*  D  *e*
      *a* *b*  C   D  *e*
      *a* *b*  C  *d*  E
      *a* *b* *c*  D  *e*
      *a* *b* *c* *d*  E

  PROBLEM IX.

       A   B  *c*  D   E   F
       A   B  *c*  D  *e*  F
       A  *b*  C   D  *e* *f*
       A  *b* *c*  D   E  *f*
       A  *b* *c*  D  *e* *f*
       A  *b* *c* *d*  E   F
       A  *b* *c* *d* *e*  F
      *a*  B  *c*  D   E   F
      *a*  B  *c*  D  *e*  F
      *a*  B  *c* *d*  E   F
      *a* *b*  C   D   E   F
      *a* *b*  C   D  *e*  F
      *a* *b*  C   D  *e* *f*
      *a* *b* *c*  D  *e* *f*
      *a* *b* *c*  D   E  *f*
      *a* *b* *c* *d* *e*  F

  PROBLEM X.

       A   B   C   D  *e*  F
       A   B  *c*  D   E  *f*
       A  *b*  C   D   E   F
       A  *b*  C   D  *e*  F
       A  *b* *c*  D  *e*  F
      *a*  B   C   D   E  *f*
      *a*  B  *c*  D   E  *f*
      *a* *b*  C   D  *e*  F
      *a* *b*  C  *d* *e*  F
      *a* *b* *c*  D  *e* *f*
      *a* *b* *c* *d* *e* *f*


*Induction of Simple Identities*.

Many important laws of nature are expressible in the form of simple
identities, and I can at once adduce them as examples to illustrate
what I have said of the difficulty of the inverse process of induction.
Two phenomena are conjoined. Thus all gravitating matter is exactly
coincident with all matter possessing inertia; where one property
appears, the other likewise appears. All crystals of the cubical
system, are all the crystals which do not doubly refract light. All
exogenous plants are, with some exceptions, those which have two
cotyledons or seed-leaves.

A little reflection will show that there is no direct and infallible
process by which such complete coincidences may be discovered.
Natural objects are aggregates of many qualities, and any one of
those qualities may prove to be in close connection with some others.
If each of a numerous group of objects is endowed with a hundred
distinct physical or chemical qualities, there will be no less than
(1/2)(100 × 99) or 4950 pairs of qualities, which may be connected,
and it will evidently be a matter of great intricacy and labour to
ascertain exactly which qualities are connected by any simple law.

One principal source of difficulty is that the finite powers of the
human mind are not sufficient to compare by a single act any large
group of objects with another large group. We cannot hold in the
conscious possession of the mind at any one moment more than five or
six different ideas. Hence we must treat any more complex group by
successive acts of attention. The reader will perceive by an almost
individual act of comparison that the words *Roma* and *Mora* contain
the same letters. He may perhaps see at a glance whether the same is
true of *Causal* and *Casual*, and of *Logica* and *Caligo*. To assure
himself that the letters in *Astronomers* make *No more stars*, that
*Serpens in akuleo* is an anagram of *Joannes Keplerus*, or *Great gun
do us a sum* an anagram of *Augustus de Morgan*, it will certainly be
necessary to break up the act of comparison into several successive
acts. The process will acquire a double character, and will consist in
ascertaining that each letter of the first group is among the letters
of the second group, and *vice versâ*, that each letter of the second
is among those of the first group. In the same way we can only prove
that two long lists of names are identical, by showing that each name
in one list occurs in the other, and *vice versâ*.

This process of comparison really consists in establishing two partial
identities, which are, as already shown (p. 58), equivalent in
conjunction to one simple identity. We first ascertain the truth of the
two propositions A = AB, B = AB, and we then rise by substitution to
the single law A = B.

There is another process, it is true, by which we may get to exactly
the same result; for the two propositions A = AB, *a* = *ab* are also
equivalent to the simple identity A = B. If then we can show that
all objects included under A are included under B, and also that all
objects not included under A are not included under B, our purpose is
effected. By this process we should usually compare two lists if we are
allowed to mark them. For each name in the first list we should strike
off one in the second, and if, when the first list is exhausted, the
second list is also exhausted, it follows that all names absent from
the first must be absent from the second, and the coincidence must be
complete.

These two modes of proving an identity are so closely allied that it
is doubtful how far we can detect any difference in their powers and
instances of application. The first method is perhaps more convenient
when the phenomena to be compared are rare. Thus we prove that all the
musical concords coincide with all the more simple numerical ratios, by
showing that each concord arises from a simple ratio of undulations,
and then showing that each simple ratio gives rise to one of the
concords. To examine all the possible cases of discord or complex ratio
of undulation would be impossible. By a happy stroke of induction Sir
John Herschel discovered that all crystals of quartz which cause the
plane of polarization of light to rotate are precisely those crystals
which have plagihedral faces, that is, oblique faces on the corners of
the prism unsymmetrical with the ordinary faces. This singular relation
would be proved by observing that all plagihedral crystals possessed
the power of rotation, and *vice versâ* all crystals possessing this
power were plagihedral. But it might at the same time be noticed that
all ordinary crystals were devoid of the power. There is no reason
why we should not detect any of the four propositions A = AB, B = AB,
*a* = *ab*, *b* = *ab*, all of which follow from A = B (p. 115).

Sometimes the terms of the identity may be singular objects; thus we
observe that diamond is a combustible gem, and being unable to discover
any other that is, we affirm--

  Diamond = combustible gem.

In a similar manner we ascertain that

  Mercury = metal liquid at ordinary temperatures,
  Substance of least density = substance of least atomic weight.

Two or three objects may occasionally enter into the induction, as when
we learn that

  Sodium ꖌ potassium = metal of less density than water,

  Venus ꖌ Mercury ꖌ Mars = major planet devoid of satellites.


*Induction of Partial Identities*.

We found in the last section that the complete identity of two classes
is almost always discovered not by direct observation of the fact,
but by first establishing two partial identities. There are also a
multitude of cases in which the partial identity of one class with
another is the only relation to be discovered. Thus the most common
of all inductive inferences consists in establishing the fact that
all objects having the properties of A have also those of B, or that
A = AB. To ascertain the truth of a proposition of this kind it is
merely necessary to assemble together, mentally or physically, all the
objects included under A, and then observe whether B is present in
each of them, or, which is the same, whether it would be impossible
to select from among them any not-B. Thus, if we mentally assemble
together all the heavenly bodies which move with apparent rapidity,
that is to say, the planets, we find that they all possess the property
of not scintillating. We cannot analyse any vegetable substance without
discovering that it contains carbon and hydrogen, but it is not true
that all substances containing carbon and hydrogen are vegetable
substances.

The great mass of scientific truths consists of propositions of
this form A = AB. Thus in astronomy we learn that all the planets
are spheroidal bodies; that they all revolve in one direction round
the sun; that they all shine by reflected light; that they all obey
the law of gravitation. But of course it is not to be asserted that
all bodies obeying the law of gravitation, or shining by reflected
light, or revolving in a particular direction, or being spheroidal
in form, are planets. In other sciences we have immense numbers of
propositions of the same form, as, for instance, all substances in
becoming gaseous absorb heat; all metals are elements; they are all
good conductors of heat and electricity; all the alkaline metals are
monad elements; all foraminifera are marine organisms; all parasitic
animals are non-mammalian; lightning never issues from stratous clouds;
pumice never occurs where only Labrador felspar is present; milkmaids
do not suffer from small-pox; and, in the works of Darwin, scientific
importance may attach even to such an apparently trifling observation
as that “white tom-cats having blue eyes are deaf.”

The process of inference by which all such truths are obtained may
readily be exhibited in a precise symbolic form. We must have one
premise specifying in a disjunctive form all the possible individuals
which belong to a class; we resolve the class, in short, into its
constituents. We then need a number of propositions, each of which
affirms that one of the individuals possesses a certain property. Thus
the premises must be of the forms

  A = B ꖌ C ꖌ D ꖌ .... ꖌ P ꖌ Q
                B = BX
                C = CX
                ... ...
                ... ...
                Q = QX.

Now, if we substitute for each alternative of the first premise its
description as found among the succeeding premises, we obtain

  A = BX ꖌ CX ꖌ .... ꖌ PX ꖌ QX

or

  A = (B ꖌ C ꖌ .... ꖌ Q)X

But for the aggregate of alternatives we may now substitute their
equivalent as given in the first premise, namely A, so that we get the
required result:

  A = AX.

We should have reached the same result if the first premise had been of
the form

  A = AB ꖌ AC ꖌ .... ꖌ AQ.

We can always prove a proposition, if we find it more convenient, by
proving its equivalent. To assert that all not-B’s are not-A’s, is
exactly the same as to assert that all A’s are B’s. Accordingly we may
ascertain that A = AB by first ascertaining that *b* = *ab*. If we
observe, for instance, that all substances which are not solids are
also not capable of double refraction, it follows necessarily that all
double refracting substances are solids. We may convince ourselves that
all electric substances are nonconductors of electricity, by reflecting
that all good conductors do not, and in fact cannot, retain electric
excitation. When we come to questions of probability it will be found
desirable to prove, as far as possible, both the original proposition
and its equivalent, as there is then an increased area of observation.

The number of alternatives which may arise in the division of a class
varies greatly, and may be any number from two upwards. Thus it is
probable that every substance is either magnetic or diamagnetic, and no
substance can be both at the same time. The division then must be made
in the form

  A = AB*c* ꖌ A*b*C.

If now we can prove that all magnetic substances are capable of
polarity, say B = BD, and also that all diamagnetic substances are
capable of polarity, C = CD, it follows by substitution that all
substances are capable of polarity, or A = AD. We commonly divide
the class substance into the three subclasses, solid, liquid, and
gas; and if we can show that in each of these forms it obeys Carnot’s
thermodynamic law, it follows that all substances obey that law.
Similarly we may show that all vertebrate animals possess red blood,
if we can show separately that fish, reptiles, birds, marsupials, and
mammals possess red blood, there being, as far as is known, only five
principal subclasses of vertebrata.

Our inductions will often be embarrassed by exceptions, real or
apparent. We might affirm that all gems are incombustible were not
diamonds undoubtedly combustible. Nothing seems more evident than that
all the metals are opaque until we examine them in fine films, when
gold and silver are found to be transparent. All plants absorb carbonic
acid except certain fungi; all the bodies of the planetary system
have a progressive motion from west to east, except the satellites of
Uranus and Neptune. Even some of the profoundest laws of matter are not
quite universal; all solids expand by heat except india-rubber, and
possibly a few other substances; all liquids which have been tested
expand by heat except water below 4° C. and fused bismuth; all gases
have a coefficient of expansion increasing with the temperature, except
hydrogen. In a later chapter I shall consider how such anomalous cases
may be regarded and classified; here we have only to express them in a
consistent manner by our notation.

Let us take the case of the transparency of metals, and assign the
terms thus:--

  A = metal    D = iron
  B = gold     E, F, &c. = copper, lead, &c.
  C = silver   X = opaque.

Our premises will be

  A = B ꖌ C ꖌ D ꖌ E, &c.
  B = B*x*
  C = C*x*
  D = DX
  E = EX,

and so on for the rest of the metals. Now evidently

  A*bc* = (D ꖌ E ꖌ F ꖌ ...)*bc*,

and by substitution as before we shall obtain

  A*bc* = A*bc*X,

or in words, “All metals not gold nor silver are opaque;” at the same
time we have

  A(B ꖌ C) = AB ꖌ AC = AB*x* ꖌ AC*x* = A(B ꖌ C)*x*,

or “Metals which are either gold or silver are not opaque.”

In some cases the problem of induction assumes a much higher degree of
complexity. If we examine the properties of crystallized substances
we may find some properties which are common to all, as cleavage or
fracture in definite planes; but it would soon become requisite to
break up the class into several minor ones. We should divide crystals
according to the seven accepted systems--and we should then find
that crystals of each system possess many common properties. Thus
crystals of the Regular or Cubical system expand equally by heat,
conduct heat and electricity with uniform rapidity, and are of like
elasticity in all directions; they have but one index of refraction
for light; and every facet is repeated in like relation to each of
the three axes. Crystals of the system having one principal axis
will be found to possess the various physical powers of conduction,
refraction, elasticity, &c., uniformly in directions perpendicular
to the principal axis; in other directions their properties vary
according to complicated laws. The remaining systems in which the
crystals possess three unequal axes, or have inclined axes, exhibit
still more complicated results, the effects of the crystal upon light,
heat, electricity, &c., varying in all directions. But when we pursue
induction into the intricacies of its application to nature we really
enter upon the subject of classification, which we must take up again
in a later part of this work.


*Solution of the Inverse or Inductive Problem, involving Two Classes*.

It is now plain that Induction consists in passing back from a series
of combinations to the laws by which such combinations are governed.
The natural law that all metals are conductors of electricity really
means that in nature we find three classes of objects, namely--

  1. Metals, conductors;
  2. Not-metals, conductors;
  3. Not-metals, not-conductors.

It comes to the same thing if we say that it excludes the existence
of the class, “metals not-conductors.” In the same way every other
law or group of laws will really mean the exclusion from existence
of certain combinations of the things, circumstances or phenomena
governed by those laws. Now in logic, strictly speaking, we treat not
the phenomena, nor the laws, but the general forms of the laws; and a
little consideration will show that for a finite number of things the
possible number of forms or kinds of law governing them must also be
finite. Using general terms, we know that A and B can be present or
absent in four ways and no more--thus:

  AB, A*b*, *a*B, *ab*;

therefore every possible law which can exist concerning the relation
of A and B must be marked by the exclusion of one or more of the above
combinations. The number of possible laws then cannot exceed the
number of selections which we can make from these four combinations.
Since each combination may be present or absent, the number of cases
to be considered is 2 × 2 × 2 × 2, or sixteen; and these cases are all
shown in the following table, in which the sign 0 indicates absence or
non-existence of the combination shown at the left-hand column in the
same line, and the mark 1 its presence:--

        1  2  3  4  5  6  7  8  9  10 11 12 13 14 15 16
                          *  *     *     *     *  *  *
   AB   0  0  0  0  0  0  0  0  1  1  1  1  1  1  1  1
   A*b* 0  0  0  0  1  1  1  1  0  0  0  0  1  1  1  1
  *a*B  0  0  1  1  0  0  1  1  0  0  1  1  0  0  1  1
  *ab*  0  1  0  1  0  1  0  1  0  1  0  1  0  1  0  1

Thus in column sixteen we find that all the conceivable combinations
are present, which means that there are no special laws in existence
in such a case, and that the combinations are governed only by the
universal Laws of Identity and Difference. The example of metals and
conductors of electricity would be represented by the twelfth column;
and every other mode in which two things or qualities might present
themselves is shown in one or other of the columns. More than half
the cases may indeed be at once rejected, because they involve the
entire absence of a term or its negative. It has been shown to be a
logical principle that every term must have its negative (p. 111),
and when this is not the case, inconsistency between the conditions
of combination must exist. Thus if we laid down the two following
propositions, “Graphite conducts electricity,” and “Graphite does not
conduct electricity,” it would amount to asserting the impossibility
of graphite existing at all; or in general terms, A is B and A is
not B result in destroying altogether the combinations containing A,
a case shown in the fourth column of the above table. We therefore
restrict our attention to those cases which may be represented in
natural phenomena when at least two combinations are present, and which
correspond to those columns of the table in which each of A, *a*,
B, *b* appears. These cases are shown in the columns marked with an
asterisk.

We find that seven cases remain for examination, thus characterised--

  Four cases exhibiting three combinations,
  Two cases exhibiting two combinations,
  One case exhibiting four combinations.

It has already been pointed out that a proposition of the form A =
AB destroys one combination, A*b*, so that this is the form of law
applying to the twelfth column. But by changing one or more of the
terms in A = AB into its negative, or by interchanging A and B, *a* and
*b*, we obtain no less than eight different varieties of the one form;
thus--

  12th case.    8th case.    15th case.    14th case.
   A  =  AB     A =  A*b*    *a* = *a*B    *a* = *ab*
  *b* = *ab*    B = *a*B     *b* =  A*b*    B  = AB

The reader of the preceding sections will see that each proposition
in the lower line is logically equivalent to, and is in fact the
contrapositive of, that above it (p. 83). Thus the propositions
A = A*b* and B = *a*B both give the same combinations, shown in the
eighth column of the table, and trial shows that the twelfth, eighth,
fifteenth and fourteenth columns are thus accounted for. We come to
this conclusion then--*The general form of proposition* A = AB *admits
of four logically distinct varieties, each capable of expression in two
modes*.

In two columns of the table, namely the seventh and tenth, we observe
that two combinations are missing. Now a simple identity A = B renders
impossible both A*b* and *a*B, accounting for the tenth case; and if we
change B into *b* the identity A = *b* accounts for the seventh case.
There may indeed be two other varieties of the simple identity, namely
*a* = *b* and *a* = B; but it has already been shown repeatedly that
these are equivalent respectively to A = B and A = *b* (p. 115). As
the sixteenth column has already been accounted for as governed by no
special conditions, we come to the following general conclusion:--The
laws governing the combinations of two terms must be capable of
expression either in a partial identity or a simple identity; the
partial identity is capable of only four logically distinct varieties,
and the simple identity of two. Every logical relation between two
terms must be expressed in one of these six forms of law, or must be
logically equivalent to one of them.

In short, we may conclude that in treating of partial and complete
identity, we have exhaustively treated the modes in which two terms or
classes of objects can be related. Of any two classes it can be said
that one must either be included in the other, or must be identical
with it, or a like relation must exist between one class and the
negative of the other. We have thus completely solved the inverse
logical problem concerning two terms.[85]

  [85] The contents of this and the following section nearly correspond
  with those of a paper read before the Manchester Literary and
  Philosophical Society on December 26th, 1871. See Proceedings of the
  Society, vol. xi. pp. 65–68, and Memoirs, Third Series, vol. v. pp.
  119–130.


*The Inverse Logical Problem involving Three Classes.*

No sooner do we introduce into the problem a third term C, than the
investigation assumes a far more complex character, so that some
readers may prefer to pass over this section. Three terms and their
negatives may be combined, as we have frequently seen, in eight
different combinations, and the effect of laws or logical conditions
is to destroy any one or more of these combinations. Now we may make
selections from eight things in 2^{8} or 256 ways; so that we have no
less than 256 different cases to treat, and the complete solution is
at least fifty times as troublesome as with two terms. Many series of
combinations, indeed, are contradictory, as in the simpler problem,
and may be passed over, the test of consistency being that each of the
letters A, B, C, *a*, *b*, *c*, shall appear somewhere in the series of
combinations.

My mode of solving the problem was as follows:--Having written out the
whole of the 256 series of combinations, I examined them separately and
struck out such as did not fulfil the test of consistency. I then chose
some form of proposition involving two or three terms, and varied it
in every possible manner, both by the circular interchange of letters
(A, B, C into B, C, A and then into C, A, B), and by the substitution
for any one or more of the terms of the corresponding negative terms.
For instance, the proposition AB = ABC can be first varied by circular
interchange so as to give BC = BCA and then CA = CAB. Each of these
three can then be thrown into eight varieties by negative change. Thus
AB = ABC gives *a*B = *a*BC, A*b* = A*b*C, AB = AB*c*, *ab* = *ab*C,
and so on. Thus there may possibly exist no less than twenty-four
varieties of the law having the general form AB = ABC, meaning that
whatever has the properties of A and B has those also of C. It by no
means follows that some of the varieties may not be equivalent to
others; and trial shows, in fact, that AB = ABC is exactly the same
in meaning as A*c* = A*bc* or B*c* = B*ca*. Thus the law in question
has but eight varieties of distinct logical meaning. I now ascertain
by actual deductive reasoning which of the 256 series of combinations
result from each of these distinct laws, and mark them off as soon as
found. I then proceed to some other form of law, for instance A = ABC,
meaning that whatever has the qualities of A has those also of B and
C. I find that it admits of twenty-four variations, all of which are
found to be logically distinct; the combinations being worked out, I am
able to mark off twenty-four more of the list of 256 series. I proceed
in this way to work out the results of every form of law which I can
find or invent. If in the course of this work I obtain any series of
combinations which had been previously marked off, I learn at once that
the law giving these combinations is logically equivalent to some law
previously treated. It may be safely inferred that every variety of the
apparently new law will coincide in meaning with some variety of the
former expression of the same law. I have sufficiently verified this
assumption in some cases, and have never found it lead to error. Thus
as AB = ABC is equivalent to A*c* = A*bc*, so we find that *ab* = *ab*C
is equivalent to *ac* = *ac*B.

Among the laws treated were the two A = AB and A = B which involve only
two terms, because it may of course happen that among three things two
only are in special logical relation, and the third independent; and
the series of combinations representing such cases of relation are sure
to occur in the complete enumeration. All single propositions which
I could invent having been treated, pairs of propositions were next
investigated. Thus we have the relations, “All A’s are B’s, and all
B’s are C’s,” of which the old logical syllogism is the development.
We may also have “all A’s are all B’s, and all B’s are C’s,” or even
“all A’s are all B’s, and all B’s are all C’s.” All such premises admit
of variations, greater or less in number, the logical distinctness
of which can only be determined by trial in detail. Disjunctive
propositions either singly or in pairs were also treated, but were
often found to be equivalent to other propositions of a simpler form;
thus A = ABC ꖌ A*bc* is exactly the same in meaning as AB = AC.

This mode of exhaustive trial bears some analogy to that ancient
mathematical process called the Sieve of Eratosthenes. Having taken
a long series of the natural numbers, Eratosthenes is said to have
calculated out in succession all the multiples of every number, and
to have marked them off, so that at last the prime numbers alone
remained, and the factors of every number were exhaustively discovered.
My problem of 256 series of combinations is the logical analogue, the
chief points of difference being that there is a limit to the number of
cases, and that prime numbers have no analogue in logic, since every
series of combinations corresponds to a law or group of conditions.
But the analogy is perfect in the point that they are both inverse
processes. There is no mode of ascertaining that a number is prime but
by showing that it is not the product of any assignable factors. So
there is no mode of ascertaining what laws are embodied in any series
of combinations but trying exhaustively the laws which would give them.
Just as the results of Eratosthenes’ method have been worked out to
a great extent and registered in tables for the convenience of other
mathematicians, I have endeavoured to work out the inverse logical
problem to the utmost extent which is at present practicable or useful.

I have thus found that there are altogether fifteen conditions or
series of conditions which may govern the combinations of three
terms, forming the premises of fifteen essentially different kinds
of arguments. The following table contains a statement of these
conditions, together with the numbers of combinations which are
contradicted or destroyed by each, and the numbers of logically
distinct variations of which the law is capable. There might be
also added, as a sixteenth case, that case where no special logical
condition exists, so that all the eight combinations remain.

  +---------+-------------------------------+-----------+------------+
  |         |                               | Number of |  Number of |
  |Reference|  Propositions expressing the  | distinct  |combinations|
  | Number. |  general type of the logical  |  logical  |contradicted|
  |         |         conditions.           |variations.|  by each.  |
  +---------+-------------------------------+-----------+------------+
  |     I.  |  A = B                        |      6    |     4      |
  |    II.  |  A = AB                       |     12    |     2      |
  |   III.  |  A = B, B = C                 |      4    |     6      |
  |    IV.  |  A = B, B = BC                |     24    |     5      |
  |     V.  |  A = AB, B = BC               |     24    |     4      |
  |    VI.  |  A = BC                       |     24    |     4      |
  |   VII.  |  A = ABC                      |     24    |     3      |
  |  VIII.  |  AB = ABC                     |      8    |     1      |
  |    IX.  |  A = AB, *a*B = *a*B*c*       |     24    |     3      |
  |     X.  |  A = ABC, *ab* = *ab*C        |      8    |     4      |
  |    XI.  |  AB = ABC, *ab* = *abc*       |      4    |     2      |
  |   XII.  |  AB = AC                      |     12    |     2      |
  |  XIII.  |  A = BC ꖌ A*bc*             |      8    |     3      |
  |   XIV.  |  A = BC ꖌ *bc*              |      2    |     4      |
  |    XV.  |  A = ABC, *a* = B*c* ꖌ *b*C |      8    |     5      |
  +---------+-------------------------------+-----------+------------+

There are sixty-three series of combinations derived from
self-contradictory premises, which with 192, the sum of the numbers of
distinct logical variations stated in the third column of the table,
and with the one case where there are no conditions or laws at all,
make up the whole conceivable number of 256 series.

We learn from this table, for instance, that two propositions of
the form A = AB, B = BC, which are such as constitute the premises
of the old syllogism Barbara, exclude as impossible four of the
eight combinations in which three terms may be united, and that
these propositions are capable of taking twenty-four variations by
transpositions of the terms or the introduction of negatives. This
table then presents the results of a complete analysis of all the
possible logical relations arising in the case of three terms, and the
old syllogism forms but one out of fifteen typical forms. Generally
speaking, every form can be converted into apparently different
propositions; thus the fourth type A = B, B = BC may appear in the
form A = ABC, *a* = *ab*, or again in the form of three propositions
A = AB, B = BC, *a*B = *a*B*c*; but all these sets of premises yield
identically the same series of combinations, and are therefore of
equivalent logical meaning. The fifth type, or Barbara, can also be
thrown into the equivalent forms A = ABC, *a*B = *a*BC and A = AC,
B = A ꖌ *a*BC. In other cases I have obtained the very same logical
conditions in four modes of statements. As regards mere appearance and
form of statement, the number of possible premises would be very great,
and difficult to exhibit exhaustively.

The most remarkable of all the types of logical condition is the
fourteenth, namely, A = BC ꖌ *bc*. It is that which expresses the
division of a genus into two doubly marked species, and might be
illustrated by the example--“Component of the physical universe =
matter, gravitating, or not-matter (ether), not-gravitating.” It is
capable of only two distinct logical variations, namely, A = BC ꖌ *bc*
and A = B*c* ꖌ *b*C. By transposition or negative change of the letters
we can indeed obtain six different expressions of each of these
propositions; but when their meanings are analysed, by working out the
combinations, they are found to be logically equivalent to one or other
of the above two. Thus the proposition A = BC ꖌ *bc* can be written in
any of the following five other modes,

  *a* = *b*C ꖌ B*c*, B = CA ꖌ *ca*, *b* = *c*A ꖌ C*a*,
          C = AB ꖌ *ab*, *c* = *a*B ꖌ A*b*.

I do not think it needful to publish at present the complete table of
193 series of combinations and the premises corresponding to each. Such
a table enables us by mere inspection to learn the laws obeyed by any
set of combinations of three things, and is to logic what a table of
factors and prime numbers is to the theory of numbers, or a table of
integrals to the higher mathematics. The table already given (p. 140)
would enable a person with but little labour to discover the law of any
combinations. If there be seven combinations (one contradicted) the law
must be of the eighth type, and the proper variety will be apparent.
If there be six combinations (two contradicted), either the second,
eleventh, or twelfth type applies, and a certain number of trials will
disclose the proper type and variety. If there be but two combinations
the law must be of the third type, and so on.

The above investigations are complete as regards the possible logical
relations of two or three terms. But when we attempt to apply the
same kind of method to the relations of four or more terms, the labour
becomes impracticably great. Four terms give sixteen combinations
compatible with the laws of thought, and the number of possible
selections of combinations is no less than 2^{16} or 65,536. The
following table shows the extraordinary manner in which the number of
possible logical relations increases with the number of terms involved.

  +---------+-------------+---------------------------------------+
  |Number of|  Number of  |Number of possible selections of combi-|
  |  terms. |  possible   |  nations corresponding to consistent  |
  |         |combinations.|   or inconsistent logical relations.  |
  +-----------------------+---------------------------------------+
  |    2    |       4     |                                    16 |
  |    3    |       8     |                                   256 |
  |    4    |      16     |                                65,536 |
  |    5    |      32     |                         4,294,967,296 |
  |    6    |      64     |            18,446,744,073,709,551,616 |
  +---------+-------------+---------------------------------------+

Some years of continuous labour would be required to ascertain the
types of laws which may govern the combinations of only four things,
and but a small part of such laws would be exemplified or capable of
practical application in science. The purely logical inverse problem,
whereby we pass from combinations to their laws, is solved in the
preceding pages, as far as it is likely to be for a long time to come;
and it is almost impossible that it should ever be carried more than a
single step further.

In the first edition, vol i. p. 158, I stated that I had not been
able to discover any mode of calculating the number of cases in which
inconsistency would be implied in the selection of combinations from
the Logical Alphabet. The logical complexity of the problem appeared
to be so great that the ordinary modes of calculating numbers of
combinations failed, in my opinion, to give any aid, and exhaustive
examination of the combinations in detail seemed to be the only method
applicable. This opinion, however, was mistaken, for both Mr. R. B.
Hayward, of Harrow, and Mr. W. H. Brewer have calculated the numbers
of inconsistent cases both for three and for four terms, without much
difficulty. In the case of four terms they find that there are 1761
inconsistent selections and 63,774 consistent, which with one case
where no condition exists, make up the total of 65,536 possible
selections.

The inconsistent cases are distributed in the manner shown in the
following table:--

  +--------------+---------------------------------------------------+
  |  Number of   |                                                   |
  | Combinations | 0   1    2    3    4    5    6   7  8  9  10, &c. |
  |  remaining.  |                                                   |
  +--------------+---------------------------------------------------+
  |  Number of   |                                                   |
  | Inconsistent | 1  16  112  352  536  448  224  64  8  0   0, &c. |
  |    Cases.    |                                                   |
  +--------------+---------------------------------------------------+

When more than eight combinations of the Logical Alphabet (p. 94,
column V.) remain unexcluded, there cannot be inconsistency. The whole
numbers of ways of selecting 0, 1, 2, &c., combinations out of 16 are
given in the 17th line of the Arithmetical Triangle given further on in
the Chapter on Combinations and Permutations, the sum of the numbers in
that line being 65,536.


*Professor Clifford on the Types of Compound Statement involving Four
Classes.*

In the first edition (vol. i. p. 163), I asserted that some years of
labour would be required to ascertain even the precise number of types
of law governing the combinations of four classes of things. Though I
still believe that some years’ labour would be required to work out the
types themselves, it is clearly a mistake to suppose that the *numbers*
of such types cannot be calculated with a reasonable amount of labour,
Professor W. K. Clifford having actually accomplished the task. His
solution of the numerical problem involves the use of a complete new
system of nomenclature and is far too intricate to be fully described
here. I can only give a brief abstract of the results, and refer
readers, who wish to follow out the reasoning, to the Proceedings of
the Literary and Philosophical Society of Manchester, for the 9th
January, 1877, vol. xvi., p. 88, where Professor Clifford’s paper is
printed in full.

By a *simple statement* Professor Clifford means the denial of the
existence of any single combination or *cross-division*, of the
classes, as in ABCD = 0, or A*b*C*d* = 0. The denial of two or more
such combinations is called a *compound statement*, and is further said
to be *twofold*, *threefold*, &c., according to the number denied. Thus
ABC = 0 is a twofold compound statement in regard to four classes,
because it involves both ABCD = 0 and ABC*d* = 0. When two compound
statements can be converted into one another by interchange of the
classes, A, B, C, D, with each other or with their complementary
classes, *a*, *b*, *c*, *d*, they are called *similar*, and all similar
statements are said to belong to the same *type*.

Two statements are called *complementary* when they deny between them
all the sixteen combinations without both denying any one; or, which
is the same thing, when each denies just those combinations which
the other permits to exist. It is obvious that when two statements
are similar, the complementary statements will also be similar,
and consequently for every type of *n*-fold statement, there is a
complementary type of (16--*n*)-fold statement. It follows that we need
only enumerate the types as far as the eighth order; for the types
of more-than-eight-fold statement will already have been given as
complementary to types of lower orders.

One combination, ABCD, may be converted into another A*b*C*d* by
interchanging one or more of the classes with the complementary
classes. The number of such changes is called the *distance*, which in
the above case is 2. In two similar compound statements the distances
of the combinations denied must be the same; but it does not follow
that when all the distances are the same, the statements are similar.
There is, however, only one example of two dissimilar statements having
the same distances. When the distance is 4, the two combinations
are said to be *obverse* to one another, and the statements denying
them are called *obverse statements*, as in ABCD = 0 and *abcd* = 0
or again A*b*C*d* = 0 and *a*B*c*D = 0. When any one combination is
given, called the *origin*, all the others may be grouped in respect
of their relations to it as follows:--Four are at distance *one* from
it, and may be called *proximates*; six are at distance *two*, and may
be called *mediates*; four are at distance *three*, and may be called
*ultimates*; finally the obverse is at distance *four*.

    Origin and               Six              Obverse and
  four proximates.        mediates.         four ultimates.
                           *ab*CD
                              |
        *a*BCD        A*bc*D  |  A*b*C*d*       A*bcd*
         |                 \  |  /                |
         |                  \ | /                 |
         |                   \|/                  |
  ABC*d*--ABCD--A*b*CD        +         *abc*D--*abcd*--*a*B*cd*
         |                   /|\                  |
         |                  / | \                 |
         |                 /  |  \                |
        AB*c*D      *a*B*c*D  |  *a*BC*d*      *ab*C*d*.
                              |
                            AB*cd*

It will be seen that the four proximates are respectively obverse to
the four ultimates, and that the mediates form three pairs of obverses.
Every proximate or ultimate is distant 1 and 3 respectively from such a
pair of mediates.

Aided by this system of nomenclature Professor Clifford proceeds to an
exhaustive enumeration of types, in which it is impossible to follow
him. The results are as follows:--

  1-fold statements         1 type }
  2   "      "              4 types}
  3   "      "              6   "  }
  4   "      "             19   "  } 159
  5   "      "             27   "  }
  6   "      "             47   "  }
  7   "      "             55   "  }
  8-fold statements        78   "

Now as each seven-fold or less-than-seven-fold statement is
complementary to a nine-fold or more-than-nine-fold statement, it
follows that the complete number of types will be 159 × 2 + 78 = 396.

It appears then that the types of statement concerning four classes
are only about 26 times as numerous as those concerning three classes,
fifteen in number, although the number of possible combinations is 256
times as great.

Professor Clifford informs me that the knowledge of the possible
groupings of subdivisions of classes which he obtained by this inquiry
has been of service to him in some applications of hyper-elliptic
functions to which he has subsequently been led. Professor Cayley has
since expressed his opinion that this line of investigation should
be followed out, owing to the bearing of the theory of compound
combinations upon the higher geometry.[86] It seems likely that many
unexpected points of connection will in time be disclosed between the
sciences of logic and mathematics.

  [86] *Proceedings of the Manchester Literary and Philosophical
  Society*, 6th February, 1877, vol. xvi., p. 113.


*Distinction between Perfect and Imperfect Induction.*

We cannot proceed with advantage before noticing the extreme difference
which exists between cases of perfect and those of imperfect induction.
We call an induction *perfect* when all the objects or events which
can possibly come under the class treated have been examined. But in
the majority of cases it is impossible to collect together, or in any
way to investigate, the properties of all portions of a substance or
of all the individuals of a race. The number of objects would often
be practically infinite, and the greater part of them might be beyond
our reach, in the interior of the earth, or in the most distant parts
of the Universe. In all such cases induction is *imperfect*, and is
affected by more or less uncertainty. As some writers have fallen into
much error concerning the functions and relative importance of these
two branches of reasoning, I shall have to point out that--

  1. Perfect Induction is a process absolutely requisite, both in the
  performance of imperfect induction and in the treatment of large
  bodies of facts of which our knowledge is complete.

  2. Imperfect Induction is founded on Perfect Induction, but involves
  another process of inference of a widely different character.

It is certain that if I can draw any inference at all concerning
objects not examined, it must be done on the data afforded by the
objects which have been examined. If I judge that a distant star obeys
the law of gravity, it must be because all other material objects
sufficiently known to me obey that law. If I venture to assert that
all ruminant animals have cloven hoofs, it is because all ruminant
animals which have come under my notice have cloven hoofs. On the
other hand, I cannot safely say that all cryptogamous plants possess
a purely cellular structure, because some cryptogamous plants, which
have been examined by botanists, have a partially vascular structure.
The probability that a new cryptogam will be cellular only can be
estimated, if at all, on the ground of the comparative numbers of
known cryptogams which are and are not cellular. Thus the first step
in every induction will consist in accurately summing up the number
of instances of a particular phenomenon which have fallen under our
observation. Adams and Leverrier, for instance, must have inferred
that the undiscovered planet Neptune would obey Bode’s law, because
*all the planets known at that time obeyed it*. On what principles the
passage from the known to the apparently unknown is warranted, must be
carefully discussed in the next section, and in various parts of this
work.

It would be a great mistake, however, to suppose that Perfect Induction
is in itself useless. Even when the enumeration of objects belonging
to any class is complete, and admits of no inference to unexamined
objects, the statement of our knowledge in a general proposition is a
process of so much importance that we may consider it necessary. In
many cases we may render our investigations exhaustive; all the teeth
or bones of an animal; all the cells in a minute vegetable organ; all
the caves in a mountain side; all the strata in a geological section;
all the coins in a newly found hoard, may be so completely scrutinized
that we may make some general assertion concerning them without fear
of mistake. Every bone might be proved to contain phosphate of lime;
every cell to enclose a nucleus; every cave to hide remains of extinct
animals; every stratum to exhibit signs of marine origin; every coin
to be of Roman manufacture. These are cases where our investigation
is limited to a definite portion of matter, or a definite area on the
earth’s surface.

There is another class of cases where induction is naturally and
necessarily limited to a definite number of alternatives. Of the
regular solids we can say without the least doubt that no one has
more than twenty faces, thirty edges, and twenty corners; for by the
principles of geometry we learn that there cannot exist more than five
regular solids, of each of which we easily observe that the above
statements are true. In the theory of numbers, an endless variety of
perfect inductions might be made; we can show that no number less than
sixty possesses so many divisors, and the like is true of 360; for it
does not require a great amount of labour to ascertain and count all
the divisors of numbers up to sixty or 360. I can assert that between
60,041 and 60,077 no prime number occurs, because the exhaustive
examination of those who have constructed tables of prime numbers
proves it to be so.

In matters of human appointment or history, we can frequently have
a complete limitation of the number of instances to be included in
an induction. We might show that the propositions of the third book
of Euclid treat only of circles; that no part of the works of Galen
mentions the fourth figure of the syllogism; that none of the other
kings of England reigned so long as George III.; that Magna Charta has
not been repealed by any subsequent statute; that the price of corn in
England has never been so high since 1847 as it was in that year; that
the price of the English funds has never been lower than it was on the
23rd of January, 1798, when it fell to 47-1/4.

It has been urged against this process of Perfect Induction that it
gives no new information, and is merely a summing up in a brief form
of a multitude of particulars. But mere abbreviation of mental labour
is one of the most important aids we can enjoy in the acquisition
of knowledge. The powers of the human mind are so limited that
multiplicity of detail is alone sufficient to prevent its progress
in many directions. Thought would be practically impossible if every
separate fact had to be separately thought and treated. Economy of
mental power may be considered one of the main conditions on which our
elevated intellectual position depends. Mathematical processes are for
the most part but abbreviations of the simpler acts of addition and
subtraction. The invention of logarithms was one of the most striking
additions ever made to human power: yet it was a mere abbreviation of
operations which could have been done before had a sufficient amount
of labour been available. Similar additions to our power will, it
is hoped, be made from time to time; for the number of mathematical
problems hitherto solved is but an indefinitely small fraction of those
which await solution, because the labour they have hitherto demanded
renders them impracticable. So it is throughout all regions of thought.
The amount of our knowledge depends upon our power of bringing it
within practicable compass. Unless we arrange and classify facts and
condense them into general truths, they soon surpass our powers of
memory, and serve but to confuse. Hence Perfect Induction, even as a
process of abbreviation, is absolutely essential to any high degree of
mental achievement.


*Transition from Perfect to Imperfect Induction.*

It is a question of profound difficulty on what grounds we are
warranted in inferring the future from the present, or the nature
of undiscovered objects from those which we have examined with our
senses. We pass from Perfect to Imperfect Induction when once we
allow our conclusion to apply, at all events apparently, beyond the
data on which it was founded. In making such a step we seem to gain
a net addition to our knowledge; for we learn the nature of what was
unknown. We reap where we have never sown. We appear to possess the
divine power of creating knowledge, and reaching with our mental arms
far beyond the sphere of our own observation. I shall have, indeed, to
point out certain methods of reasoning in which we do pass altogether
beyond the sphere of the senses, and acquire accurate knowledge which
observation could never have given; but it is not imperfect induction
that accomplishes such a task. Of imperfect induction itself, I venture
to assert that it never makes any real addition to our knowledge, in
the meaning of the expression sometimes accepted. As in other cases
of inference, it merely unfolds the information contained in past
observations; it merely renders explicit what was implicit in previous
experience. It transmutes, but certainly does not create knowledge.

There is no fact which I shall more constantly keep before the reader’s
mind in the following pages than that the results of imperfect
induction, however well authenticated and verified, are never more than
probable. We never can be sure that the future will be as the present.
We hang ever upon the will of the Creator: and it is only so far as He
has created two things alike, or maintains the framework of the world
unchanged from moment to moment, that our most careful inferences can
be fulfilled. All predictions, all inferences which reach beyond their
data, are purely hypothetical, and proceed on the assumption that new
events will conform to the conditions detected in our observation of
past events. No experience of finite duration can give an exhaustive
knowledge of the forces which are in operation. There is thus a
double uncertainty; even supposing the Universe as a whole to proceed
unchanged, we do not really know the Universe as a whole. We know only
a point in its infinite extent, and a moment in its infinite duration.
We cannot be sure, then, that our observations have not escaped some
fact, which will cause the future to be apparently different from the
past; nor can we be sure that the future really will be the outcome of
the past. We proceed then in all our inferences to unexamined objects
and times on the assumptions--

  1. That our past observation gives us a complete knowledge of what
  exists.

  2. That the conditions of things which did exist will continue to be
  the conditions which will exist.

We shall often need to illustrate the character of our knowledge of
nature by the simile of a ballot-box, so often employed by mathematical
writers in the theory of probability. Nature is to us like an infinite
ballot-box, the contents of which are being continually drawn, ball
after ball, and exhibited to us. Science is but the careful observation
of the succession in which balls of various character present
themselves; we register the combinations, notice those which seem to
be excluded from occurrence, and from the proportional frequency of
those which appear we infer the probable character of future drawings.
But under such circumstances certainty of prediction depends on two
conditions:--

  1. That we acquire a perfect knowledge of the comparative numbers of
  balls of each kind within the box.

  2. That the contents of the ballot-box remain unchanged.

Of the latter assumption, or rather that concerning the constitution
of the world which it illustrates, the logician or physicist can
have nothing to say. As the Creation of the Universe is necessarily
an act passing all experience and all conception, so any change in
that Universe, or, it may be, a termination of it, must likewise be
infinitely beyond the bounds of our mental faculties. No science
no reasoning upon the subject, can have any validity; for without
experience we are without the basis and materials of knowledge. It
is the fundamental postulate accordingly of all inference concerning
the future, that there shall be no arbitrary change in the subject
of inference; of the probability or improbability of such a change I
conceive that our faculties can give no estimate.

The other condition of inductive inference--that we acquire an
approximately complete knowledge of the combinations in which events
do occur, is in some degree within our power. There are branches
of science in which phenomena seem to be governed by conditions of
a most fixed and general character. We have ground in such cases
for believing that the future occurrence of such phenomena can be
calculated and predicted. But the whole question now becomes one
of probability and improbability. We seem to leave the region of
logic to enter one in which the number of events is the ground of
inference. We do not really leave the region of logic; we only leave
that where certainty, affirmative or negative, is the result, and the
agreement or disagreement of qualities the means of inference. For the
future, number and quantity will commonly enter into our processes of
reasoning; but then I hold that number and quantity are but portions
of the great logical domain. I venture to assert that number is wholly
logical, both in its fundamental nature and in its developments.
Quantity in all its forms is but a development of number. That which is
mathematical is not the less logical; if anything it is more logical,
in the sense that it presents logical results in a higher degree of
complexity and variety.

Before proceeding then from Perfect to Imperfect Induction I must
devote a portion of this work to treating the logical conditions
of number. I shall then employ number to estimate the variety of
combinations in which natural phenomena may present themselves, and
the probability or improbability of their occurrence under definite
circumstances. It is in later parts of the work that I must endeavour
to establish the notions which I have set forth upon the subject of
Imperfect Induction, as applied in the investigation of Nature, which
notions maybe thus briefly stated:--

  1. Imperfect Induction entirely rests upon Perfect Induction for its
  materials.

  2. The logical process by which we seem to pass directly from
  examined to unexamined cases consists in an inverse application of
  deductive inference, so that all reasoning may be said to be either
  directly or inversely deductive.

  3. The result is always of a hypothetical character, and is never
  more than probable.

  4. No net addition is ever made to our knowledge by reasoning; what
  we know of future events or unexamined objects is only the unfolded
  contents of our previous knowledge, and it becomes less probable as
  it is more boldly extended to remote cases.




BOOK II.

NUMBER, VARIETY, AND PROBABILITY.




CHAPTER VIII.

PRINCIPLES OF NUMBER.


Not without reason did Pythagoras represent the world as ruled by
number. Into almost all our acts of thought number enters, and in
proportion as we can define numerically we enjoy exact and useful
knowledge of the Universe. The science of numbers, too, has hitherto
presented the widest and most practicable training in logic. So free
and energetic has been the study of mathematical forms, compared
with the forms of logic, that mathematicians have passed far in
advance of pure logicians. Occasionally, in recent times, they have
condescended to apply their algebraic instrument to a reflex treatment
of the primary logical science. It is thus that we owe to profound
mathematicians, such as John Herschel, Whewell, De Morgan, or Boole,
the regeneration of logic in the present century. I entertain no
doubt that it is in maintaining a close alliance with quantitative
reasoning that we must look for further progress in our comprehension
of qualitative inference.

I cannot assent, indeed, to the common notion that certainty begins and
ends with numerical determination. Nothing is more certain than logical
truth. The laws of identity and difference are the tests of all that is
certain throughout the range of thought, and mathematical reasoning is
cogent only when it conforms to these conditions, of which logic is the
first development. And if it be erroneous to suppose that all certainty
is mathematical, it is equally an error to imagine that all which is
mathematical is certain. Many processes of mathematical reasoning are
of most doubtful validity. There are points of mathematical doctrine
which must long remain matter of opinion; for instance, the best form
of the definition and axiom concerning parallel lines, or the true
nature of a limit. In the use of symbolic reasoning questions occur on
which the best mathematicians may differ, as Bernoulli and Leibnitz
differed irreconcileably concerning the existence of the logarithms of
negative quantities.[87] In fact we no sooner leave the simple logical
conditions of number, than we find ourselves involved in a mazy and
mysterious science of symbols.

  [87] Montucla. *Histoire des Mathématiques*, vol. iii. p. 373.

Mathematical science enjoys no monopoly, and not even a supremacy,
in certainty of results. It is the boundless extent and variety of
quantitative questions that delights the mathematical student. When
simple logic can give but a bare answer Yes or No, the algebraist
raises a score of subtle questions, and brings out a crowd of curious
results. The flower and the fruit, all that is attractive and
delightful, fall to the share of the mathematician, who too often
despises the plain but necessary stem from which all has arisen. In
no region of thought can a reasoner cast himself free from the prior
conditions of logical correctness. The mathematician is only strong and
true as long as he is logical, and if number rules the world, it is
logic which rules number.

Nearly all writers have hitherto been strangely content to look upon
numerical reasoning as something apart from logical inference. A long
divorce has existed between quality and quantity, and it has not
been uncommon to treat them as contrasted in nature and restricted
to independent branches of thought. For my own part, I believe that
all the sciences meet somewhere. No part of knowledge can stand
wholly disconnected from other parts of the universe of thought; it
is incredible, above all, that the two great branches of abstract
science, interlacing and co-operating in every discourse, should
rest upon totally distinct foundations. I assume that a connection
exists, and care only to inquire, What is its nature? Does the science
of quantity rest upon that of quality; or, *vice versâ*, does the
science of quality rest upon that of quantity? There might conceivably
be a third view, that they both rest upon some still deeper set of
principles.

It is generally supposed that Boole adopted the second view, and
treated logic as an application of algebra, a special case of
analytical reasoning which admits only two quantities, unity and zero.
It is not easy to ascertain clearly which of these views really was
accepted by Boole. In his interesting biographical sketch of Boole,[88]
the Rev. R. Harley protests against the statement that Boole’s logical
calculus imported the conditions of number and quantity into logic.
He says: “Logic is never identified or confounded with mathematics;
the two systems of thought are kept perfectly distinct, each being
subject to its own laws and conditions. The symbols are the same for
both systems, but they have not the same interpretation.” The Rev. J.
Venn, again, in his review of Boole’s logical system,[89] holds that
Boole’s processes are at bottom logical, not mathematical, though
stated in a highly generalized form and with a mathematical dress. But
it is quite likely that readers of Boole should be misled. Not only
have his logical works an entirely mathematical appearance, but I find
on p. 12 of his *Laws of Thought* the following unequivocal statement:
“That logic, as a science, is susceptible of very wide applications
is admitted; but it is equally certain that its ultimate forms and
processes are mathematical.” A few lines below he adds, “It is not of
the essence of mathematics to be conversant with the ideas of number
and quantity.”

  [88] *British Quarterly Review*, No. lxxxvii, July 1866.

  [89] *Mind*, October 1876, vol. i. p. 484.

The solution of the difficulty is that Boole used the term mathematics
in a wider sense than that usually attributed to it. He probably
adopted the third view, so that his mathematical *Laws of Thought* are
the common basis both of logic and of quantitative mathematics. But
I do not care to pursue the subject because I think that, in either
case Boole was wrong. In my opinion logic is the superior science, the
general basis of mathematics as well as of all other sciences. Number
is but logical discrimination, and algebra a highly developed logic.
Thus it is easy to understand the deep analogy which Boole pointed out
between the forms of algebraic and logical deduction. Logic resembles
algebra as the mould resembles that which is cast in it. Boole mistook
the cast for the mould. Considering that logic imposes its own laws
upon every branch of mathematical science, it is no wonder that we
constantly meet with the traces of logical laws in mathematical
processes.


*The Nature of Number.*

Number is but another name for *diversity*. Exact identity is unity,
and with difference arises plurality. An abstract notion, as was
pointed out (p. 28), possesses a certain *oneness*. The quality of
*justice*, for instance, is one and the same in whatever just acts it
is manifested. In justice itself there are no marks of difference by
which to discriminate justice from justice. But one just act can be
discriminated from another just act by circumstances of time and place,
and we can count many acts thus discriminated each from each. In like
manner pure gold is simply pure gold, and is so far one and the same
throughout. But besides its intrinsic qualities, gold occupies space
and must have shape and size. Portions of gold are always mutually
exclusive and capable of discrimination, in respect that they must be
each without the other. Hence they may be numbered.

Plurality arises when and only when we detect difference. For instance,
in counting a number of gold coins I must count each coin once, and not
more than once. Let C denote a coin, and the mark above it the order of
counting. Then I must count the coins

  C′ + C″ + C‴ + C″″ + ....

If I were to count them as follows

  C′ + C″ + C‴ + C‴ + C″″ + ...,

I should make the third coin into two, and should imply the existence
of difference where there is no difference.[90] C‴ and C‴ are but
the names of one coin named twice over. But according to one of the
conditions of logical symbols, which I have called the Law of Unity
(p. 72), the same name repeated has no effect, and

  A ꖌ A = A.

  [90] *Pure Logic*, Appendix, p. 82, § 192.

We must apply the Law of Unity, and must reduce all identical
alternatives before we can count with certainty and use the processes
of numerical calculation. Identical alternatives are harmless in
logic, but are wholly inadmissible in number. Thus logical science
ascertains the nature of the mathematical unit, and the definition may
be given in these terms--*A unit is any object of thought which can be
discriminated from every other object treated as a unit in the same
problem.*

It has often been said that units are units in respect of being
perfectly similar to each other; but though they may be perfectly
similar in some respects, they must be different in at least one point,
otherwise they would be incapable of plurality. If three coins were
so similar that they occupied the same space at the same time, they
would not be three coins, but one coin. It is a property of space that
every point is discriminable from every other point, and in time every
moment is necessarily distinct from any other moment before or after.
Hence we frequently count in space or time, and Locke, with some other
philosophers, has held that number arises from repetition in time.
Beats of a pendulum may be so perfectly similar that we can discover no
difference except that one beat is before and another after. Time alone
is here the ground of difference and is a sufficient foundation for the
discrimination of plurality; but it is by no means the only foundation.
Three coins are three coins, whether we count them successively or
regard them all simultaneously. In many cases neither time nor space
is the ground of difference, but pure quality alone enters. We can
discriminate the weight, inertia, and hardness of gold as three
qualities, though none of these is before nor after the other, neither
in space nor time. Every means of discrimination may be a source of
plurality.

Our logical notation may be used to express the rise of number.
The symbol A stands for one thing or one class, and in itself must
be regarded as a unit, because no difference is specified. But the
combinations AB and A*b* are necessarily *two*, because they cannot
logically coalesce, and there is a mark B which distinguishes one
from the other. A logical definition of the number *four* is given in
the combinations ABC, AB*c*, A*b*C, A*bc*, where there is a double
difference. As Puck says--

  “Yet but three? Come one more;
  Two of both kinds makes up four.”

I conceive that all numbers might be represented as arising out of
the combinations of the Logical Alphabet, more or less of each series
being struck out by various logical conditions. The number three, for
instance, arises from the condition that A must be either B or C, so
that the combinations are ABC, AB*c*, A*b*C.


*Of Numerical Abstraction.*

There will now be little difficulty in forming a clear notion of
the nature of numerical abstraction. It consists in abstracting the
character of the difference from which plurality arises, retaining
merely the fact. When I speak of *three men* I need not at once specify
the marks by which each may be known from each. Those marks must exist
if they are really three men and not one and the same, and in speaking
of them as many I imply the existence of the requisite differences.
Abstract number, then, is *the empty form of difference*; the abstract
number *three* asserts the existence of marks without specifying their
kind.

Numerical abstraction is thus seen to be a different process from
logical abstraction (p. 27), for in the latter process we drop out
of notice the very existence of difference and plurality. In forming
the abstract notion *hardness*, we ignore entirely the diverse
circumstances in which the quality may appear. It is the concrete
notion *three hard objects*, which asserts the existence of hardness
along with sufficient other undefined qualities, to mark out *three*
such objects. Numerical thought is indeed closely interwoven with
logical thought. We cannot use a concrete term in the plural, as
*men*, without implying that there are marks of difference. But when we
use an abstract term, we deal with unity.

The origin of the great generality of number is now apparent. Three
sounds differ from three colours, or three riders from three horses;
but they agree in respect of the variety of marks by which they can be
discriminated. The symbols 1 + 1 + 1 are thus the empty marks asserting
the existence of discrimination. But in dropping out of sight the
character of the differences we give rise to new agreements on which
mathematical reasoning is founded. Numerical abstraction is so far from
being incompatible with logical abstraction that it is the origin of
our widest acts of generalization.


*Concrete and Abstract Number.*

The common distinction between concrete and abstract number can now be
easily stated. In proportion as we specify the logical characters of
the things numbered, we render them concrete. In the abstract number
three there is no statement of the points in which the *three* objects
agree; but in *three coins*, *three men*, or *three horses*, not only
are the objects numbered but their nature is restricted. Concrete
number thus implies the same consciousness of difference as abstract
number, but it is mingled with a groundwork of similarity expressed in
the logical terms. There is identity so far as logical terms enter;
difference so far as the terms are merely numerical.

The reason of the important Law of Homogeneity will now be apparent.
This law asserts that in every arithmetical calculation the logical
nature of the things numbered must remain unaltered. The specified
logical agreement of the things must not be affected by the unspecified
numerical differences. A calculation would be palpably absurd which,
after commencing with length, gave a result in hours. It is equally
absurd, in a purely arithmetical point of view, to deduce areas from
the calculation of lengths, masses from the combination of volume
and density, or momenta from mass and velocity. It must remain for
subsequent consideration to decide in what sense we may truly say that
two linear feet multiplied by two linear feet give four superficial
feet; arithmetically it is absurd, because there is a change of unit.

As a general rule we treat in each calculation only objects of one
nature. We do not, and cannot properly add, in the same sum yards of
cloth and pounds of sugar. We cannot even conceive the result of adding
area to velocity, or length to density, or weight to value. The units
added must have a basis of homogeneity, or must be reducible to some
common denominator. Nevertheless it is possible, and in fact common, to
treat in one complex calculation the most heterogeneous quantities, on
the condition that each kind of object is kept distinct, and treated
numerically only in conjunction with its own kind. Different units,
so far as their logical differences are specified, must never be
substituted one for the other. Chemists continually use equations which
assert the equivalence of groups of atoms. Ordinary fermentation is
represented by the formula

  C^{6} H^{12} O^{6} = 2C^{2} H^{6} O + 2CO^{2}.

Three kinds of units, the atoms respectively of carbon, hydrogen, and
oxygen, are here intermingled, but there is really a separate equation
in regard to each kind. Mathematicians also employ compound equations
of the same kind; for in, *a* + *b* √ - 1 = *c* + *d* √ - 1,
it is impossible by ordinary addition to add *a* to *b* √ - 1.
Hence we really have the separate equations *a* = *b*, and
*c* √ - 1 = *d* √ - 1. Similarly an equation between
two quaternions is equivalent to four equations between ordinary
quantities, whence indeed the name *quaternion*.


*Analogy of Logical and Numerical Terms.*

If my assertion is correct that number arises out of logical
conditions, we ought to find number obeying all the laws of logic.
It is almost superfluous to point out that this is the case with the
fundamental laws of identity and difference, and it only remains to
show that mathematical symbols do really obey the special conditions
of logical symbols which were formerly pointed out (p. 32). Thus the
Law of Commutativeness, is equally true of quality and quantity. As in
logic we have

  AB = BA,

so in mathematics it is familiarly known that

  2 × 3 = 3 × 2, or *x* × *y* = *y* × *x*.

The properties of space are as indifferent in multiplication as we
found them in pure logical thought.

Similarly, as in logic

  triangle or square = square or triangle,

  or generally       A ꖌ B  =  B ꖌ A,
  so in quantity     2  +  3  =  3  +  2,
  or generally      *x* + *y* = *y* + *x*.

The symbol ꖌ is not identical with +, but it is thus far analogous.

How far, now, is it true that mathematical symbols obey the Law of
Simplicity expressed in the form

  AA = A,

or the example

  Round round = round?

Apparently there are but two numbers which obey this law; for it is
certain that

  *x* × *x* = *x*

is true only in the two cases when *x* = 1, or *x* = 0.

In reality all numbers obey the law, for 2 × 2 = 2 is not really
analogous to AA = A. According to the definition of a unit already
given, each unit is discriminated from each other in the same problem,
so that in 2′ × 2″, the first *two* involves a different discrimination
from the second *two*. I get four kinds of things, for instance, if I
first discriminate “heavy and light” and then “cubical and spherical,”
for we now have the following classes--

  heavy, cubical.         light, cubical.
  heavy, spherical.       light, spherical.

But suppose that my two classes are in both cases discriminated by the
same difference of light and heavy, then we have

  heavy heavy = heavy,
  heavy light = 0,
  light heavy = 0,
  light light = light.

Thus, (heavy or light) × (heavy or light) = (heavy or light).

In short, *twice two is two* unless we take care that the second two
has a different meaning from the first. But under similar circumstances
logical terms give the like result, and it is not true that A′A″ = A′,
when A″ is different in meaning from A′.

In a similar manner it may be shown that the Law of Unity

  A ꖌ A = A.

holds true alike of logical and mathematical terms. It is absurd indeed
to say that

  *x* + *x* = *x*

except in the one case when *x* = absolute zero. But this contradiction
*x* + *x* = *x* arises from the fact that we have already defined
the units in one x as differing from those in the other. Under such
circumstances the Law of Unity does not apply. For if in

  A′ ꖌ A″ = A′

we mean that A″ is in any way different from A′ the assertion of
identity is evidently false.

The contrast then which seems to exist between logical and mathematical
symbols is only apparent. It is because the Laws of Simplicity and
Unity must always be observed in the operation of counting that those
laws seem no further to apply. This is the understood condition under
which we use all numerical symbols. Whenever I write the symbol 5 I
really mean

  1 + 1 + 1 + 1 + 1,

and it is perfectly understood that each of these units is distinct
from each other. If requisite I might mark them thus

  1′+ 1″ + 1‴ + 1″″ + 1″‴.


Were this not the case and were the units really

  1′ + 1″ + 1″ + 1‴ + 1″″,

the Law of Unity would, as before remarked, apply, and

  1″ + 1″ = 1″.

Mathematical symbols then obey all the laws of logical symbols, but
two of these laws seem to be inapplicable simply because they are
presupposed in the definition of the mathematical unit. Logic thus lays
down the conditions of number, and the science of arithmetic developed
as it is into all the wondrous branches of mathematical calculus is but
an outgrowth of logical discrimination.


*Principle of Mathematical Inference.*

The universal principle of all reasoning, as I have asserted, is that
which allows us to substitute like for like. I have now to point out
how in the mathematical sciences this principle is involved in each
step of reasoning. It is in these sciences indeed that we meet with the
clearest cases of substitution, and it is the simplicity with which the
principle can be applied which probably led to the comparatively early
perfection of the sciences of geometry and arithmetic. Euclid, and
the Greek mathematicians from the first, recognised *equality* as the
fundamental relation of quantitative thought, but Aristotle rejected
the exactly analogous, but far more general relation of identity, and
thus crippled the formal science of logic as it has descended to the
present day.

Geometrical reasoning starts from the axiom that “things equal to the
same thing are equal to each other.” Two equalities enable us to infer
a third equality; and this is true not only of lines and angles, but
of areas, volumes, numbers, intervals of time, forces, velocities,
degrees of intensity, or, in short, anything which is capable of being
equal or unequal. Two stars equally bright with the same star must be
equally bright with each other, and two forces equally intense with a
third force are equally intense with each other. It is remarkable that
Euclid has not explicitly stated two other axioms, the truth of which
is necessarily implied. The second axiom should be that “Two things of
which one is equal and the other unequal to a third common thing, are
unequal to each other.” An equality and inequality, in short, give an
inequality, and this is equally true with the first axiom of all kinds
of quantity. If Venus, for instance, agrees with Mars in density, but
Mars differs from Jupiter, then Venus differs from Jupiter. A third
axiom must exist to the effect that “Things unequal to the same thing
may or may not be equal to each other.” *Two inequalities give no
ground of inference whatever.* If we only know, for instance, that
Mercury and Jupiter differ in density from Mars, we cannot say whether
or not they agree between themselves. As a fact they do not agree;
but Venus and Mars on the other hand both differ from Jupiter and yet
closely agree with each other. The force of the axioms can be most
clearly illustrated by drawing equal and unequal lines.[91]

  [91] *Elementary Lessons in Logic* (Macmillan), p. 123. It is pointed
  out in the preface to this Second Edition, that the views here given
  were partially stated by Leibnitz.

The general conclusion then must be that where there is equality there
may be inference, but where there is not equality there cannot be
inference. A plain induction will lead us to believe that *equality is
the condition of inference concerning quantity*. All the three axioms
may in fact be summed up in one, to the effect, that “*in whatever
relation one quantity stands to another, it stands in the same relation
to the equal of that other*.”

The active power is always the substitution of equals, and it is an
accident that in a pair of equalities we can make the substitution
in two ways. From *a* = *b* = *c* we can infer *a* = *c*, either by
substituting in *a* = *b* the value of *b* as given in *b* = *c*,
or else by substituting in *b* = *c* the value of *b* as given in
*a* = *b*. In *a* = *b* ~ *d* we can make but the one substitution of
*a* for *b*. In *e* ~ *f* ~ *g* we can make no substitution and get no
inference.

In mathematics the relations in which terms may stand to each other are
far more varied than in pure logic, yet our principle of substitution
always holds true. We may say in the most general manner that *In
whatever relation one quantity stands to another, it stands in the same
relation to the equal of that other.* In this axiom we sum up a number
of axioms which have been stated in more or less detail by algebraists.
Thus, “If equal quantities be added to equal quantities, the sums will
be equal.” To explain this, let

  *a* = *b*,        *c* = *d*.

Now *a* + *c*, whatever it means, must be identical with itself, so that

  *a* + *c* = *a* + *c*.

In one side of this equation substitute for the quantities their
equivalents, and we have the axiom proved

  *a* + *c* = *b* + *d*.

The similar axiom concerning subtraction is equally evident, for
whatever *a* - *c* may mean it is equal to *a* - *c*, and therefore by
substitution to *b* - *d*. Again, “if equal quantities be multiplied by
the same or equal quantities, the products will be equal,” For evidently

  *ac* = *ac*,

and if for *c* in one side we substitute its equal *d*, we have

  *ac* = *ad*,

and a second similar substitution gives us

  *ac* = *bd*.

We might prove a like axiom concerning division in an exactly
similar manner. I might even extend the list of axioms and say that
“Equal powers of equal numbers are equal.” For certainly, whatever
*a* × *a* × *a* may mean, it is equal to *a* × *a* × *a*; hence by our
usual substitution it is equal to *b* × *b* × *b*. The same will be
true of roots of numbers and ^{c}√*a* = ^{d}√*b* provided that
the roots are so taken that the root of *a* shall really be related
to *a* as the root of *b* is to *b*. The ambiguity of meaning of an
operation thus fails in any way to shake the universality of the
principle. We may go further and assert that, not only the above common
relations, but all other known or conceivable mathematical relations
obey the same principle. Let Q*a* denote in the most general manner
that we do something with the quantity *a*; then if *a* = *b* it
follows that

  Q*a* = Q*b*.

The reader will also remember that one of the most frequent operations
in mathematical reasoning is to substitute for a quantity its equal,
as known either by assumed, natural, or self-evident conditions.
Whenever a quantity appears twice over in a problem, we may apply
what we learn of its relations in one place to its relations in the
other. All reasoning in mathematics, as in other branches of science,
thus involves the principle of treating equals equally, or similars
similarly. In whatever way we employ quantitative reasoning in the
remaining parts of this work, we never can desert the simple principle
on which we first set out.


*Reasoning by Inequalities.*

I have stated that all the processes of mathematical reasoning may
be deduced from the principle of substitution. Exceptions to this
assertion may seem to exist in the use of inequalities. The greater of
a greater is undoubtedly a greater, and what is less than a less is
certainly less. Snowdon is higher than the Wrekin, and Ben Nevis than
Snowdon; therefore Ben Nevis is higher than the Wrekin. But a little
consideration discloses sufficient reason for believing that even in
such cases, where equality does not apparently enter, the force of the
reasoning entirely depends upon underlying and implied equalities.

In the first place, two statements of mere difference do not give
any ground of inference. We learn nothing concerning the comparative
heights of St. Paul’s and Westminster Abbey from the assertions that
they both differ in height from St. Peter’s at Rome. We need something
more than inequality; we require one identity in addition, namely the
identity in direction of the two differences. Thus we cannot employ
inequalities in the simple way in which we do equalities, and, when we
try to express what other conditions are requisite, we find ourselves
lapsing into the use of equalities or identities.

In the second place, every argument by inequalities may be represented
in the form of equalities. We express that *a* is greater than *b* by
the equation

  *a* = *b* + *p*,        (1)

where *p* is an intrinsically positive quantity, denoting the
difference of *a* and *b*. Similarly we express that *b* is greater
than *c* by the equation

  *b* = *c* + *q*,        (2)

and substituting for *b* in (1) its value in (2) we have

  *a* = *c* + *q* + *p*.        (3)

Now as *p* and *q* are both positive, it follows that *a* is greater
than *c*, and we have the exact amount of excess specified. It will be
easily seen that the reasoning concerning that which is less than a
less will result in an equation of the form

  *c* = *a* - *r* - *s*.

Every argument by inequalities may then be thrown into the form of an
equality; but the converse is not true. We cannot possibly prove that
two quantities are equal by merely asserting that they are both greater
or both less than another quantity. From *e* > *f* and *g* > *f*, or
*e* < *f* and *g* < *f*, we can infer no relation between *e* and *g*.
And if the reader take the equations *x* = *y* = 3 and attempt to prove
that therefore *x* = 3, by throwing them into inequalities, he will
find it impossible to do so.

From these considerations I gather that reasoning in arithmetic or
algebra by so-called inequalities, is only an imperfectly expressed
reasoning by equalities, and when we want to exhibit exactly and
clearly the conditions of reasoning, we are obliged to use equalities
explicitly. Just as in pure logic a negative proposition, as expressing
mere difference, cannot be the means of inference, so inequality can
never really be the true ground of inference. I do not deny that
affirmation and negation, agreement and difference, equality and
inequality, are pairs of equally fundamental relations, but I assert
that inference is possible only where affirmation, agreement, or
equality, some species of identity in fact, is present, explicitly or
implicitly.


*Arithmetical Reasoning.*

It may seem somewhat inconsistent that I assert number to arise out of
difference or discrimination, and yet hold that no reasoning can be
grounded on difference. Number, of course, opens a most wide sphere
for inference, and a little consideration shows that this is due to
the unlimited series of identities which spring up out of numerical
abstraction. If six people are sitting on six chairs, there is no
resemblance between the chairs and the people in logical character.
But if we overlook all the qualities both of a chair and a person and
merely remember that there are marks by which each of six chairs may
be discriminated from the others, and similarly with the people, then
there arises a resemblance between the chairs and the people, and this
resemblance in number may be the ground of inference. If on another
occasion the chairs are filled by people again, we may infer that these
people resemble the others in number though they need not resemble them
in any other points.

Groups of units are what we really treat in arithmetic. The number
*five* is really 1 + 1 + 1 + 1 + 1, but for the sake of conciseness we
substitute the more compact sign 5, or the name *five*. These names
being arbitrarily imposed in any one manner, an infinite variety of
relations spring up between them which are not in the least arbitrary.
If we define *four* as 1 + 1 + 1 + 1, and *five* as 1 + 1 + 1 + 1 + 1,
then of course it follows that *five* = *four* + 1; but it would be
equally possible to take this latter equality as a definition, in
which case one of the former equalities would become an inference. It
is hardly requisite to decide how we define the names of numbers,
provided we remember that out of the infinitely numerous relations
of one number to others, some one relation expressed in an equality
must be a definition of the number in question and the other relations
immediately become necessary inferences.

In the science of number the variety of classes which can be formed is
altogether infinite, and statements of perfect generality may be made
subject only to difficulty or exception at the lower end of the scale.
Every existing number for instance belongs to the class *m* + 7; that
is, every number must be the sum of another number and seven, except of
course the first six or seven numbers, negative quantities not being
here taken into account. Every number is the half of some other, and so
on. The subject of generalization, as exhibited in mathematical truths,
is an infinitely wide one. In number we are only at the first step of
an extensive series of generalizations. As number is general compared
with the particular things numbered, so we have general symbols for
numbers, and general symbols for relations between undetermined
numbers. There is an unlimited hierarchy of successive generalizations.


*Numerically Definite Reasoning.*

It was first discovered by De Morgan that many arguments are valid
which combine logical and numerical reasoning, although they cannot be
included in the ancient logical formulas. He developed the doctrine of
the “Numerically Definite Syllogism,” fully explained in his *Formal
Logic* (pp. 141–170). Boole also devoted considerable attention to the
determination of what he called “Statistical Conditions,” meaning the
numerical conditions of logical classes. In a paper published among the
Memoirs of the Manchester Literary and Philosophical Society, Third
Series, vol. IV. p. 330 (Session 1869–70), I have pointed out that we
can apply arithmetical calculation to the Logical Alphabet. Having
given certain logical conditions and the numbers of objects in certain
classes, we can either determine the numbers of objects in other
classes governed by those conditions, or can show what further data
are required to determine them. As an example of the kind of questions
treated in numerical logic, and the mode of treatment, I give the
following problem suggested by De Morgan, with my mode of representing
its solution.

“For every man in the house there is a person who is aged; some of the
men are not aged. It follows that some persons in the house are not
men.”[92]

  [92] *Syllabus of a Proposed System of Logic*, p. 29.

  Now let    A = person in house,
             B = male,
             C = aged.

By enclosing a logical symbol in brackets, let us denote the number of
objects belonging to the class indicated by the symbol. Thus let

    (A) = number of persons in house,
   (AB) = number of male persons in house,
  (ABC) = number of aged male persons in house,

and so on. Now if we use *w* and *w*′ to denote unknown numbers,
the conditions of the problem may be thus stated according to my
interpretation of the words--

  (AB) = (AC) - *w*,        (1)

that is to say, the number of persons in the house who are aged is at
least equal to, and may exceed, the number of male persons in the house;

  (AB*c*) = *w*′,        (2)

that is to say, the number of male persons in the house who are not
aged is some unknown positive quantity.

If we develop the terms in (1) by the Law of Duality (pp. 74, 81, 89),
we obtain

  (ABC) + (AB*c*) = (ABC) + (A*b*C) - *w*.

Subtracting the common term (ABC) from each side and substituting for
(AB*c*) its value as given in (2), we get at once

  (A*b*C) = *w* + *w*′,

and adding (A*bc*) to each side, we have

  (A*b*) = (A*bc*) + *w* + *w*′.

The meaning of this result is that the number of persons in the house
who are not men is at least equal to *w* + *w*′, and exceeds it by the
number of persons in the house who are neither men nor aged (A*bc*).

It should be understood that this solution applies only to the terms of
the example quoted above, and not to the general problem for which De
Morgan intended it to serve as an illustration.

As a second instance, let us take the following question:--The
whole number of voters in a borough is *a*; the number against whom
objections have been lodged by liberals is *b*; and the number against
whom objections have been lodged by conservatives is *c*; required the
number, if any, who have been objected to on both sides. Taking

  A = voter,
  B = objected to by liberals,
  C = objected to by conservatives,

then we require the value of (ABC). Now the following equation is
identically true--

  (ABC) = (AB) + (AC) + (A*bc*) - (A).        (1)

For if we develop all the terms on the second side we obtain

  (ABC) = (ABC) + (AB*c*) + (ABC) + (A*b*C) + (A*bc*)
        - (ABC) - (AB*c*) - (A*b*C) - (A*bc*);

and striking out the corresponding positive and negative terms, we have
left only (ABC) = (ABC). Since then (1) is necessarily true, we have
only to insert the known values, and we have

  (ABC) = *b* + *c* - *a* + (A*bc*).

Hence the number who have received objections from both sides is equal
to the excess, if any, of the whole number of objections over the
number of voters together with the number of voters who have received
no objection (A*bc*).

The following problem illustrates the expression for the common part of
any three classes:--The number of paupers who are blind males, is equal
to the excess, if any, of the sum of the whole number of blind persons,
added to the whole number of male persons, added to the number of those
who being paupers are neither blind nor males, above the sum of the
whole number of paupers added to the number of those who, not being
paupers, are blind, and to the number of those who, not being paupers,
are male.

The reader is requested to prove the truth of the above statement, (1)
by his own unaided common sense; (2) by the Aristotelian Logic; (3) by
the method of numerical logic just expounded; and then to decide which
method is most satisfactory.


*Numerical meaning of Logical Conditions.*

In many cases classes of objects may exist under special logical
conditions, and we must consider how these conditions can be
interpreted numerically. Every logical proposition gives rise to a
corresponding numerical equation. Sameness of qualities occasions
sameness of numbers. Hence if

  A = B

denotes the identity of the qualities of A and B, we may conclude that

  (A) = (B).

It is evident that exactly those objects, and those objects only, which
are comprehended under A must be comprehended under B. It follows that
wherever we can draw an equation of qualities, we can draw a similar
equation of numbers. Thus, from

  A = B = C

we infer

  A = C;

and similarly from

  (A) = (B) = (C),

meaning that the numbers of A’s and C’s are equal to the number of B’s,
we can infer

  (A) = (C).

But, curiously enough, this does not apply to negative propositions and
inequalities. For if

  A = B ~ D

means that A is identical with B, which differs from D, it does not
follow that

  (A) = (B) ~ (D).

Two classes of objects may differ in qualities, and yet they may agree
in number. This point strongly confirms me in the opinion which I have
already expressed, that all inference really depends upon equations,
not differences.

The Logical Alphabet thus enables us to make a complete analysis of any
numerical problem, and though the symbolical statement may sometimes
seem prolix, I conceive that it really represents the course which the
mind must follow in solving the question. Although thought may outstrip
the rapidity with which the symbols can be written down, yet the mind
does not really follow a different course from that indicated by the
symbols. For a fuller explanation of this natural system of Numerically
Definite Reasoning, with more abundant illustrations and an analysis
of De Morgan’s Numerically Definite Syllogism, I must refer the
reader to the paper[93] in the Memoirs of the Manchester Literary and
Philosophical Society, already mentioned, portions of which, however,
have been embodied in the present section.

  [93] It has been pointed out to me by Mr. C. J. Monroe, that section
  14 (p. 339) of this paper is erroneous, and ought to be cancelled.
  The problem concerning the number of paupers illustrates the answer
  which should have been obtained. Mr. A. J. Ellis, F.R.S., had
  previously observed that my solution in the paper of De Morgan’s
  problem about “men in the house” did not answer the conditions
  intended by De Morgan, and I therefore give in the text a more
  satisfactory solution.

The reader may be referred, also, to Boole’s writings upon the
subject in the *Laws of Thought*, chap. xix. p. 295, and in a paper
on “Propositions Numerically Definite,” communicated by De Morgan, in
1868, to the Cambridge Philosophical Society, and printed in their
*Transactions*, vol. xi. part ii.




CHAPTER IX.

THE VARIETY OF NATURE, OR THE DOCTRINE OF COMBINATIONS AND PERMUTATIONS.


Nature may be said to be evolved from the monotony of non-existence
by the creation of diversity. It is plausibly asserted that we are
conscious only so far as we experience difference. Life is change, and
perfectly uniform existence would be no better than non-existence.
Certain it is that life demands incessant novelty, and that nature,
though it probably never fails to obey the same fixed laws, yet
presents to us an apparently unlimited series of varied combinations
of events. It is the work of science to observe and record the kinds
and comparative numbers of such combinations of phenomena, occurring
spontaneously or produced by our interference. Patient and skilful
examination of the records may then disclose the laws imposed on matter
at its creation, and enable us more or less successfully to predict, or
even to regulate, the future occurrence of any particular combination.

The Laws of Thought are the first and most important of all the laws
which govern the combinations of phenomena, and, though they be binding
on the mind, they may also be regarded as verified in the external
world. The Logical Alphabet develops the utmost variety of things and
events which may occur, and it is evident that as each new quality is
introduced, the number of combinations is doubled. Thus four qualities
may occur in 16 combinations; five qualities in 32; six qualities in
64; and so on. In general language, if n be the number of qualities,
2^{n} is the number of varieties of things which may be formed from
them, if there be no conditions but those of logic. This number,
it need hardly be said, increases after the first few terms, in an
extraordinary manner, so that it would require 302 figures to express
the number of combinations in which 1,000 qualities might conceivably
present themselves.

If all the combinations allowed by the Laws of Thought occurred
indifferently in nature, then science would begin and end with those
laws. To observe nature would give us no additional knowledge, because
no two qualities would in the long run be oftener associated than any
other two. We could never predict events with more certainty than we
now predict the throws of dice, and experience would be without use.
But the universe, as actually created, presents a far different and
much more interesting problem. The most superficial observation shows
that some things are constantly associated with other things. The more
mature our examination, the more we become convinced that each event
depends upon the prior occurrence of some other series of events.
Action and reaction are gradually discovered to underlie the whole
scene, and an independent or casual occurrence does not exist except
in appearance. Even dice as they fall are surely determined in their
course by prior conditions and fixed laws. Thus the combinations of
events which can really occur are found to be comparatively restricted,
and it is the work of science to detect these restricting conditions.

In the English alphabet, for instance, we have twenty-six letters. Were
the combinations of such letters perfectly free, so that any letter
could be indifferently sounded with any other, the number of words
which could be formed without any repetition would be 2^{26} - 1, or
67,108,863, equal in number to the combinations of the twenty-seventh
column of the Logical Alphabet, excluding one for the case in which
all the letters would be absent. But the formation of our vocal organs
prevents us from using the far greater part of these conjunctions of
letters. At least one vowel must be present in each word; more than two
consonants cannot usually be brought together; and to produce words
capable of smooth utterance a number of other rules must be observed.
To determine exactly how many words might exist in the English language
under these circumstances, would be an exceedingly complex problem,
the solution of which has never been attempted. The number of existing
English words may perhaps be said not to exceed one hundred thousand,
and it is only by investigating the combinations presented in the
dictionary, that we can learn the Laws of Euphony or calculate the
possible number of words. In this example we have an epitome of the
work and method of science. The combinations of natural phenomena are
limited by a great number of conditions which are in no way brought to
our knowledge except so far as they are disclosed in the examination of
nature.

It is often a very difficult matter to determine the numbers
of permutations or combinations which may exist under various
restrictions. Many learned men puzzled themselves in former centuries
over what were called Protean verses, or verses admitting many
variations in accordance with the Laws of Metre. The most celebrated of
these verses was that invented by Bernard Bauhusius, as follows:[94]--

  “Tot tibi sunt dotes, Virgo, quot sidera cœlo.”

  [94] Montucla, *Histoire*, &c., vol. iii. p. 388.

One author, Ericius Puteanus, filled forty-eight pages of a work in
reckoning up its possible transpositions, making them only 1022. Other
calculators gave 2196, 3276, 2580 as their results. Wallis assigned
3096, but without much confidence in the accuracy of his result.[95]
It required the skill of James Bernoulli to decide that the number of
transpositions was 3312, under the condition that the sense and metre
of the verse shall be perfectly preserved.

  [95] Wallis, *Of Combinations*, &c., p. 119.

In approaching the consideration of the great Inductive problem,
it is very necessary that we should acquire correct notions as
to the comparative numbers of combinations which may exist under
different circumstances. The doctrine of combinations is that part of
mathematical science which applies numerical calculation to determine
the numbers of combinations under various conditions. It is a part of
the science which really lies at the base not only of other sciences,
but of other branches of mathematics. The forms of algebraical
expressions are determined by the principles of combination, and
Hindenburg recognised this fact in his Combinatorial Analysis. The
greatest mathematicians have, during the last three centuries,
given their best powers to the treatment of this subject; it was
the favourite study of Pascal; it early attracted the attention of
Leibnitz, who wrote his curious essay, *De Arte Combinatoria*, at
twenty years of age; James Bernoulli, one of the very profoundest
mathematicians, devoted no small part of his life to the investigation
of the subject, as connected with that of Probability; and in his
celebrated work, *De Arte Conjectandi*, he has so finely described the
importance of the doctrine of combinations, that I need offer no excuse
for quoting his remarks at full length.

“It is easy to perceive that the prodigious variety which appears
both in the works of nature and in the actions of men, and which
constitutes the greatest part of the beauty of the universe, is owing
to the multitude of different ways in which its several parts are
mixed with, or placed near, each other. But, because the number of
causes that concur in producing a given event, or effect, is oftentimes
so immensely great, and the causes themselves are so different one
from another, that it is extremely difficult to reckon up all the
different ways in which they may be arranged or combined together, it
often happens that men, even of the best understandings and greatest
circumspection, are guilty of that fault in reasoning which the writers
on logic call *the insufficient or imperfect enumeration of parts or
cases*: insomuch that I will venture to assert, that this is the chief,
and almost the only, source of the vast number of erroneous opinions,
and those too very often in matters of great importance, which we are
apt to form on all the subjects we reflect upon, whether they relate to
the knowledge of nature, or the merits and motives of human actions.

“It must therefore be acknowledged, that that art which affords a cure
to this weakness, or defect, of our understandings, and teaches us so
to enumerate all the possible ways in which a given number of things
may be mixed and combined together, that we may be certain that we have
not omitted any one arrangement of them that can lead to the object
of our inquiry, deserves to be considered as most eminently useful and
worthy of our highest esteem and attention. And this is the business
of *the art or doctrine of combinations*. Nor is this art or doctrine
to be considered merely as a branch of the mathematical sciences. For
it has a relation to almost every species of useful knowledge that the
mind of man can be employed upon. It proceeds indeed upon mathematical
principles, in calculating the number of the combinations of the things
proposed: but by the conclusions that are obtained by it, the sagacity
of the natural philosopher, the exactness of the historian, the skill
and judgment of the physician, and the prudence and foresight of the
politician may be assisted; because the business of all these important
professions is but *to form reasonable conjectures* concerning the
several objects which engage their attention, and all wise conjectures
are the results of a just and careful examination of the several
different effects that may possibly arise from the causes that are
capable of producing them.”[96]

  [96] James Bernoulli, *De Arte Conjectandi*, translated by Baron
  Maseres. London, 1795, pp. 35, 36.


*Distinction of Combinations and Permutations.*

We must first consider the deep difference which exists between
Combinations and Permutations, a difference involving important logical
principles, and influencing the form of mathematical expressions.
In *permutation* we recognise varieties of order, treating AB as a
different group from BA. In *combination* we take notice only of the
presence or absence of a certain thing, and pay no regard to its place
in order of time or space. Thus the four letters *a*, *e*, *m*, *n*
can form but one combination, but they occur in language in several
permutations, as *name*, *amen*, *mean*, *mane*.

We have hitherto been dealing with purely logical questions, involving
only combination of qualities. I have fully pointed out in more than
one place that, though our symbols could not but be written in order
of place and read in order of time, the relations expressed had no
regard to place or time (pp. 33, 114). The Law of Commutativeness, in
fact, expresses the condition that in logic we deal with combinations,
and the same law is true of all the processes of algebra. In some
cases, order may be a matter of indifference; it makes no difference,
for instance, whether gunpowder is a mixture of sulphur, carbon, and
nitre, or carbon, nitre, and sulphur, or nitre, sulphur, and carbon,
provided that the substances are present in proper proportions and
well mixed. But this indifference of order does not usually extend to
the events of physical science or the operations of art. The change of
mechanical energy into heat is not exactly the same as the change from
heat into mechanical energy; thunder does not indifferently precede and
follow lightning; it is a matter of some importance that we load, cap,
present, and fire a rifle in this precise order. Time is the condition
of all our thoughts, space of all our actions, and therefore both in
art and science we are to a great extent concerned with permutations.
Language, for instance, treats different permutations of letters as
having different meanings.

Permutations of things are far more numerous than combinations of those
things, for the obvious reason that each distinct thing is regarded
differently according to its place. Thus the letters A, B, C, will
make different permutations according as A stands first, second, or
third; having decided the place of A, there are two places between
which we may choose for B; and then there remains but one place for
C. Accordingly the permutations of these letters will be altogether
3 × 2 × 1 or 6 in number. With four things or letters, A, B, C, D,
we shall have four choices of place for the first letter, three for
the second, two for the third, and one for the fourth, so that there
will be altogether, 4 × 3 × 2 × 1, or 24 permutations. The same simple
rule applies in all cases; beginning with the whole number of things
we multiply at each step by a number decreased by a unit. In general
language, if *n* be the number of things in a combination, the number
of permutations is

*n* (*n* - 1)(*n* - 2) .... 4 . 3 . 2 . 1.

If we were to re-arrange the names of the days of the week, the
possible arrangements out of which we should have to choose the new
order, would be no less than 7 . 6 . 5 . 4 . 3 . 2 . 1, or 5040, or,
excluding the existing order, 5039.

The reader will see that the numbers which we reach in questions
of permutation, increase in a more extraordinary manner even than
in combination. Each new object or term doubles the number of
combinations, but increases the permutations by a factor continually
growing. Instead of 2 × 2 × 2 × 2 × .... we have 2 × 3 × 4 × 5 × ....
and the products of the latter expression immensely exceed those of the
former. These products of increasing factors are frequently employed,
as we shall see, in questions both of permutation and combination. They
are technically called *factorials*, that is to say, the product of all
integer numbers, from unity up to any number *n* is the *factorial*
of *n*, and is often indicated symbolically by *n*!. I give below the
factorials up to that of twelve:--

           24 = 1 . 2 . 3 . 4
          120 = 1 . 2 ... 5
          720 = 1 . 2 ... 6
        5,040 = 7!
       40,320 = 8!
      362,880 = 9!
    3,628,800 = 10!
   39,916,800 = 11!
  479,001,600 = 12!

The factorials up to 36! are given in Rees’s ‘Cyclopædia,’ art.
*Cipher*, and the logarithms of factorials up to 265! are to be
found at the end of the table of logarithms published under the
superintendence of the Society for the Diffusion of Useful Knowledge
(p. 215). To express the factorial 265! would require 529 places of
figures.

Many writers have from time to time remarked upon the extraordinary
magnitude of the numbers with which we deal in this subject. Tacquet
calculated[97] that the twenty-four [sic] letters of the alphabet may
be arranged in more than 620 thousand trillions of orders; and Schott
estimated[98] that if a thousand millions of men were employed for the
same number of years in writing out these arrangements, and each man
filled each day forty pages with forty arrangements in each, they would
not have accomplished the task, as they would have written only 584
thousand trillions instead of 620 thousand trillions.

  [97] *Arithmeticæ Theoria.* Ed. Amsterd. 1704. p. 517.

  [98] Rees’s *Cyclopædia*, art. *Cipher*.

In some questions the number of permutations may be restricted
and reduced by various conditions. Some things in a group may
be undistinguishable from others, so that change of order will
produce no difference. Thus if we were to permutate the letters of
the name *Ann*, according to our previous rule, we should obtain
3 × 2 × 1, or 6 orders; but half of these arrangements would be
identical with the other half, because the interchange of the two
*n*’s has no effect. The really different orders will therefore be
(3 . 2 . 1)/(1 . 2) or 3, namely *Ann*, *Nan*, *Nna*. In the word
*utility* there are two *i*’s and two *t*’s, in respect of both of
which pairs the numbers of permutations must be halved. Thus we obtain
(7 . 6 . 5 . 4 . 3 . 2 . 1)/(1 . 2 . 1 . 2) or 1260, as the number of
permutations. The simple rule evidently is--when some things or letters
are undistinguished, proceed in the first place to calculate all the
possible permutations as if all were different, and then divide by
the numbers of possible permutations of those series of things which
are not distinguished, and of which the permutations have therefore
been counted in excess. Thus since the word *Utilitarianism* contains
fourteen letters, of which four are *i*’s, two *a*’s, and two *t*’s,
the number of distinct arrangements will be found by dividing the
factorial of 14, by the factorials of 4, 2, and 2, the result being
908,107,200. From the letters of the word *Mississippi* we can get in
like manner 11!/(4! × 4! × 2!) or 34,650 permutations, which is not
the one-thousandth part of what we should obtain were all the letters
different.


*Calculation of Number of Combinations.*

Although in many questions both of art and science we need to calculate
the number of permutations on account of their own interest, it far
more frequently happens in scientific subjects that they possess but
an indirect interest. As I have already pointed out, we almost always
deal in the logical and mathematical sciences with *combinations*, and
variety of order enters only through the inherent imperfections of our
symbols and modes of calculation. Signs must be used in some order,
and we must withdraw our attention from this order before the signs
correctly represent the relations of things which exist neither before
nor after each other. Now, it often happens that we cannot choose all
the combinations of things, without first choosing them subject to the
accidental variety of order, and we must then divide by the number of
possible variations of order, that we may get to the true number of
pure combinations.

Suppose that we wish to determine the number of ways in which we can
select a group of three letters out of the alphabet, without allowing
the same letter to be repeated. At the first choice we can take any
one of 26 letters; at the next step there remain 25 letters, any one
of which may be joined with that already taken; at the third step
there will be 24 choices, so that apparently the whole number of ways
of choosing is 26 × 25 × 24. But the fact that one choice succeeded
another has caused us to obtain the same combinations of letters in
different orders; we should get, for instance, *a*, *p*, *r* at one
time, and *p*, *r*, *a* at another, and every three distinct letters
will appear six times over, because three things can be arranged in
six permutations. To get the number of combinations, then, we must
divide the whole number of ways of choosing, by six, the number of
permutations of three things, obtaining (26 × 25 × 24)/(1 × 2 × 3) or
2,600.

It is apparent that we need the doctrine of combinations in order
that we may in many questions counteract the exaggerating effect of
successive selection. If out of a senate of 30 persons we have to
choose a committee of 5, we may choose any of 30 first, any of 29 next,
and so on, in fact there will be 30 × 29 × 28 × 27 × 26 selections;
but as the actual character of the members of the committee will not
be affected by the accidental order of their selection, we divide by
1 × 2 × 3 × 4 × 5, and the possible number of different committees will
be 142,506. Similarly if we want to calculate the number of ways in
which the eight major planets may come into conjunction, it is evident
that they may meet either two at a time or three at a time, or four or
more at a time, and as nothing is said as to the relative order or
place in the conjunction, we require the number of combinations. Now
a selection of 2 out of 8 is possible in (8 . 7)/(1 . 2) or 28 ways;
of 3 out of 8 in (8 . 7 . 6)/(1 . 2 . 3) or 56 ways; of 4 out of 8 in
(8 . 7 . 6 . 5)/(1 . 2 . 3 . 4) or 70 ways; and it may be similarly
shown that for 5, 6, 7, and 8 planets, meeting at one time, the numbers
of ways are 56, 28, 8, and 1. Thus we have solved the whole question
of the variety of conjunctions of eight planets; and adding all the
numbers together, we find that 247 is the utmost possible number of
modes of meeting.

In general algebraic language, we may say that a group of *m* things
may be chosen out of a total number of *n* things, in a number of
combinations denoted by the formula

  (*n* . (*n*-1)(*n*-2)(*n*-3) .... (*n* - *m* + 1))/(1 . 2 . 3 . 4 .... *m*)

The extreme importance and significance of this formula seems to have
been first adequately recognised by Pascal, although its discovery
is attributed by him to a friend, M. de Ganières.[99] We shall find
it perpetually recurring in questions both of combinations and
probability, and throughout the formulæ of mathematical analysis traces
of its influence may be noticed.

  [99] *Œuvres Complètes de Pascal* (1865), vol. iii. p. 302. Montucla
  states the name as De Gruières, *Histoire des Mathématiques*,
  vol. iii. p. 389.


*The Arithmetical Triangle.*

The Arithmetical Triangle is a name long since given to a series
of remarkable numbers connected with the subject we are treating.
According to Montucla[100] “this triangle is in the theory of
combinations and changes of order, almost what the table of Pythagoras
is in ordinary arithmetic, that is to say, it places at once under the
eyes the numbers required in a multitude of cases of this theory.” As
early as 1544 Stifels had noticed the remarkable properties of these
numbers and the mode of their evolution. Briggs, the inventor of the
common system of logarithms, was so struck with their importance that
he called them the Abacus Panchrestus. Pascal, however, was the first
who wrote a distinct treatise on these numbers, and gave them the name
by which they are still known. But Pascal did not by any means exhaust
the subject, and it remained for James Bernoulli to demonstrate fully
the importance of the *figurate numbers*, as they are also called. In
his treatise *De Arte Conjectandi*, he points out their application
in the theory of combinations and probabilities, and remarks of the
Arithmetical Triangle, “It not only contains the clue to the mysterious
doctrine of combinations, but it is also the ground or foundation of
most of the important and abstruse discoveries that have been made in
the other branches of the mathematics.”[101]

  [100] *Histoire des Mathématiques*, vol. iii. p. 378.

  [101] Bernoulli, *De Arte Conjectandi*, translated by Francis
  Maseres. London, 1795, p. 75.

The numbers of the triangle can be calculated in a very easy manner by
successive additions. We commence with unity at the apex; in the next
line we place a second unit to the right of this; to obtain the third
line of figures we move the previous line one place to the right, and
add them to the same figures as they were before removal; we can then
repeat the same process *ad infinitum*. The fourth line of figures,
for instance, contains 1, 3, 3, 1; moving them one place and adding as
directed we obtain:--

  Fourth line ...  1  3  3  1
                      1  3  3  1
                   --------------
  Fifth line ....  1  4  6  4  1
                      1  4  6  4  1
                   ----------------
  Sixth line ....  1  5 10 10  5  1

Carrying out this simple process through ten more steps we obtain the
first seventeen lines of the Arithmetical Triangle as printed on the
next page. Theoretically speaking the Triangle must be regarded as
infinite in extent, but the numbers increase so rapidly that it soon
becomes impracticable to continue the table. The longest table of the
numbers which I have found is in Fortia’s “Traité des Progressions”
(p. 80), where they are given up to the fortieth line and the ninth
column.

THE ARITHMETICAL TRIANGLE.

Line. First Column.
1 1 Second Column.
2 1 1 Third Column.
3 1 2 1 Fourth Column.
4 1 3 3 1 Fifth Column.
5 1 4 6 4 1 Sixth Column.
6 1 5 10 10 5 1 Seventh Column.
7 1 6 15 20 15 6 1 Eighth Column.
8 1 7 21 35 35 21 7 1 Ninth Column.
9 1 8 28 56 70 56 28 8 1 Tenth Column.
10 1 9 36 84 126 126 84 36 9 1 Eleventh Column.
11 1 10 45 120 210 252 210 120 45 10 1 Twelfth Column.
12 1 11 55 165 330 462 462 330 165 55 11 1 Thirteenth Column.
13 1 12 66 220 495 792 924 792 495 220 66 12 1 Fourteenth Column.
14 1 13 78 286 715 1287 1716 1716 1287 715 286 78 13 1 Fifteenth Column.
15 1 14 91 364 1001 2002 3003 3432 3003 2002 1001 364 91 14 1 Sixteenth Column.
16 1 15 105 455 1365 3003 5005 6435 6435 5005 3003 1365 455 105 15 1 Seventeenth Col.
17 1 16 120 560 1820 4368 8008 11440 12870 11440 8008 4368 1820 560 120 16 1

Examining these numbers, we find that they are connected by an
unlimited series of relations, a few of the more simple of which may be
noticed. Each vertical column of numbers exactly corresponds with an
oblique series descending from left to right, so that the triangle is
perfectly symmetrical in its contents. The first column contains only
*units*; the second column contains the *natural numbers*, 1, 2, 3,
&c.; the third column contains a remarkable series of numbers, 1, 3,
6, 10, 15, &c., which have long been called *the triangular numbers*,
because they correspond with the numbers of balls which may be arranged
in a triangular form, thus--

[Illustration]

The fourth column contains the *pyramidal numbers*, so called because
they correspond to the numbers of equal balls which can be piled in
regular triangular pyramids. Their differences are the triangular
numbers. The numbers of the fifth column have the pyramidal numbers
for their differences, but as there is no regular figure of which
they express the contents, they have been arbitrarily called the
*trianguli-triangular numbers*. The succeeding columns have, in a
similar manner, been said to contain the *trianguli-pyramidal*, the
*pyramidi-pyramidal* numbers, and so on.[102]

  [102] Wallis’s *Algebra*, Discourse of Combinations, &c., p. 109.

From the mode of formation of the table, it follows that the
differences of the numbers in each column will be found in the
preceding column to the left. Hence the *second differences*, or the
*differences of differences*, will be in the second column to the left
of any given column, the third differences in the third column, and so
on. Thus we may say that unity which appears in the first column is the
*first difference* of the numbers in the second column; the *second
difference* of those in the third column; the *third difference* of
those in the fourth, and so on. The triangle is seen to be a complete
classification of all numbers according as they have unity for any of
their differences.

Since each line is formed by adding the previous line to itself, it
is evident that the sum of the numbers in each horizontal line must be
double the sum of the numbers in the line next above. Hence we know,
without making the additions, that the successive sums must be 1, 2,
4, 8, 16, 32, 64, &c., the same as the numbers of combinations in the
Logical Alphabet. Speaking generally, the sum of the numbers in the
*n*th line will be 2^{*n* - 1}.

Again, if the whole of the numbers down to any line be added together,
we shall obtain a number less by unity than some power of 2; thus,
the first line gives 1 or 2^{1} - 1; the first two lines give 3 or
2^{2} - 1; the first three lines 7 or 2^{3} - 1; the first six lines
give 63 or 2^{6} - 1; or, speaking in general language, the sum of the
first *n* lines is 2^{*n*} - 1. It follows that the sum of the numbers
in any one line is equal to the sum of those in all the preceding
lines increased by a unit. For the sum of the *n*th line is, as
already shown, 2^{*n* - 1}, and the sum of the first *n* - 1 lines is
2^{*n* - 1} - 1, or less by a unit.

This account of the properties of the figurate numbers does not
approach completeness; a considerable, probably an unlimited, number of
less simple and obvious relations might be traced out. Pascal, after
giving many of the properties, exclaims[103]: “Mais j’en laisse bien
plus que je n’en donne; c’est une chose étrange combien il est fertile
en propriétés! Chacun peut s’y exercer.” The arithmetical triangle may
be considered a natural classification of numbers, exhibiting, in the
most complete manner, their evolution and relations in a certain point
of view. It is obvious that in an unlimited extension of the triangle,
each number, with the single exception of the number *two*, has at
least two places.

  [103] *Œuvres Complètes*, vol. iii. p. 251.

Though the properties above explained are highly curious, the greatest
value of the triangle arises from the fact that it contains a complete
statement of the values of the formula (p. 182), for the numbers of
combinations of *m* things out of *n*, for all possible values of *m*
and *n*. Out of seven things one may be chosen in seven ways, and
seven occurs in the eighth line of the second column. The combinations
of two things chosen out of seven are (7 × 6)/(1 × 2) or 21, which
is the third number in the eighth line. The combinations of three
things out of seven are (7 × 6 × 5)/(1 × 2 × 3) or 35, which appears
fourth in the eighth line. In a similar manner, in the fifth, sixth,
seventh, and eighth columns of the eighth line I find it stated in
how many ways I can select combinations of 4, 5, 6, and 7 things out
of 7. Proceeding to the ninth line, I find in succession the number
of ways in which I can select 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, and 8 things, out
of 8 things. In general language, if I wish to know in how many ways
*m* things can be selected in combinations out of *n* things, I must
look in the *n* + 1^{th} line, and take the *m* + 1^{th} number, as
the answer. In how many ways, for instance, can a subcommittee of
five be chosen out of a committee of nine. The answer is 126, and
is the sixth number in the tenth line; it will be found equal to
(9 . 8 . 7 . 6 . 5)/(1 . 2 . 3 . 4 . 5), which our formula (p. 182)
gives.

The full utility of the figurate numbers will be more apparent when
we reach the subject of probabilities, but I may give an illustration
or two in this place. In how many ways can we arrange four pennies as
regards head and tail? The question amounts to asking in how many ways
we can select 0, 1, 2, 3, or 4 heads, out of 4 heads, and the *fifth*
line of the triangle gives us the complete answer, thus--

  We can select No head and 4 tails in 1 way.
         "       1 head and 3 tails in 4 ways.
         "       2 heads and 2 tails in 6 ways.
         "       3 heads and 1 tail in 4 ways.
         "       4 heads and 0 tail in 1 way.

The total number of different cases is 16, or 2^{4}, and when we come
to the next chapter, it will be found that these numbers give us the
respective probabilities of all throws with four pennies.

I gave in p. 181 a calculation of the number of ways in which eight
planets can meet in conjunction; the reader will find all the numbers
detailed in the ninth line of the arithmetical triangle. The sum of the
whole line is 2^{8} or 256; but we must subtract a unit for the case
where no planet appears, and 8 for the 8 cases in which only one planet
appears; so that the total number of conjunctions is 2^{8} -1 - 8
or 247. If an organ has eleven stops we find in the twelfth line the
numbers of ways in which we can draw them, 1, 2, 3, or more at a time.
Thus there are 462 ways of drawing five stops at once, and as many of
drawing six stops. The total number of ways of varying the sound is
2048, including the single case in which no stop at all is drawn.

One of the most important scientific uses of the arithmetical triangle
consists in the information which it gives concerning the comparative
frequency of divergencies from an average. Suppose, for the sake of
argument, that all persons were naturally of the equal stature of five
feet, but enjoyed during youth seven independent chances of growing one
inch in addition. Of these seven chances, one, two, three, or more,
may happen favourably to any individual; but, as it does not matter
what the chances are, so that the inch is gained, the question really
turns upon the number of combinations of 0, 1, 2, 3, &c., things out of
seven. Hence the eighth line of the triangle gives us a complete answer
to the question, as follows:--

Out of every 128 people--

                                      Feet  Inches.
One person would have the stature of    5      0
 7 persons       "           "          5      1
21 persons       "           "          5      2
35 persons       "           "          5      3
35 persons       "           "          5      4
21 persons       "           "          5      5
 7 persons       "           "          5      6
 1 person        "           "          5      7

By taking a proper line of the triangle, an answer may be had under
any more natural supposition. This theory of comparative frequency of
divergence from an average, was first adequately noticed by Quetelet,
and has lately been employed in a very interesting and bold manner by
Mr. Francis Galton,[104] in his remarkable work on “Hereditary Genius.”
We shall afterwards find that the theory of error, to which is made the
ultimate appeal in cases of quantitative investigation, is founded upon
the comparative numbers of combinations as displayed in the triangle.

  [104] See also Galton’s Lecture at the Royal Institution, 27th
  February, 1874; Catalogue of the Special Loan Collection of
  Scientific Instruments, South Kensington, Nos. 48, 49; and Galton,
  *Philosophical Magazine*, January 1875.


*Connection between the Arithmetical Triangle and the Logical Alphabet.*

There exists a close connection between the arithmetical triangle
described in the last section, and the series of combinations of
letters called the Logical Alphabet. The one is to mathematical science
what the other is to logical science. In fact the figurate numbers, or
those exhibited in the triangle, are obtained by summing up the logical
combinations. Accordingly, just as the total of the numbers in each
line of the triangle is twice as great as that for the preceding line
(p. 186), so each column of the Alphabet (p. 94) contains twice as many
combinations as the preceding one. The like correspondence also exists
between the sums of all the lines of figures down to any particular
line, and of the combinations down to any particular column.

By examining any column of the Logical Alphabet we find that the
combinations naturally group themselves according to the figurate
numbers. Take the combinations of the letters A, B, C, D; they consist
of all the ways in which I can choose four, three, two, one, or none of
the four letters, filling up the vacant spaces with negative terms.

There is one combination, ABCD, in which all the positive letters are
present; there are four combinations in each of which three positive
letters are present; six in which two are present; four in which only
one is present; and, finally, there is the single case, *abcd*, in
which all positive letters are absent. These numbers, 1, 4, 6, 4, 1,
are those of the fifth line of the arithmetical triangle, and a like
correspondence will be found to exist in each column of the Logical
Alphabet.

Numerical abstraction, it has been asserted, consists in overlooking
the kind of difference, and retaining only a consciousness of its
existence (p. 158). While in logic, then, we have to deal with each
combination as a separate kind of thing, in arithmetic we distinguish
only the classes which depend upon more or less positive terms being
present, and the numbers of these classes immediately produce the
numbers of the arithmetical triangle.

It may here be pointed out that there are two modes in which we
can calculate the whole number of combinations of certain things.
Either we may take the whole number at once as shown in the Logical
Alphabet, in which case the number will be some power of two, or else
we may calculate successively, by aid of permutations, the number of
combinations of none, one, two, three things, and so on. Hence we
arrive at a necessary identity between two series of numbers. In the
case of four things we shall have

  2 = 1 + 4/1 + (4 . 3)/(1 . 2) + (4 . 3 . 2)/(1 . 2 . 3) +
  (4 . 3 . 2 . 1)/(1 . 2 . 3 . 4).

In a general form of expression we shall have

  2 = 1 + *n*/1 + (*n* . (*n* - 1))/(1 . 2) + (*n*
  (*n* - 1)(*n* - 2))/(1 . 2 . 3) + &c.,

the terms being continued until they cease to have any value. Thus we
arrive at a proof of simple cases of the Binomial Theorem, of which
each column of the Logical Alphabet is an exemplification. It may be
shown that all other mathematical expansions likewise arise out of
simple processes of combination, but the more complete consideration of
this subject must be deferred to another work.


*Possible Variety of Nature and Art.*

We cannot adequately understand the difficulties which beset us in
certain branches of science, unless we have some clear idea of the vast
numbers of combinations or permutations which may be possible under
certain conditions. Thus only can we learn how hopeless it would be
to attempt to treat nature in detail, and exhaust the whole number of
events which might arise. It is instructive to consider, in the first
place, how immensely great are the numbers of combinations with which
we deal in many arts and amusements.

In dealing a pack of cards, the number of hands, of thirteen cards
each, which can be produced is evidently 52 × 51 × 50 × ... × 40
divided by 1 × 2 × 3 ... × 13. or 635,013,559,600. But in whist
four hands are simultaneously held, and the number of distinct
deals becomes so vast that it would require twenty-eight figures to
express it. If the whole population of the world, say one thousand
millions of persons, were to deal cards day and night, for a hundred
million of years, they would not in that time have exhausted one
hundred-thousandth part of the possible deals. Even with the same hands
of cards the play may be almost infinitely varied, so that the complete
variety of games at whist which may exist is almost incalculably great.
It is in the highest degree improbable that any one game of whist was
ever exactly like another, except it were intentionally so.

The end of novelty in art might well be dreaded, did we not find that
nature at least has placed no attainable limit, and that the deficiency
will lie in our inventive faculties. It would be a cheerless time
indeed when all possible varieties of melody were exhausted, but it
is readily shown that if a peal of twenty-four bells had been rung
continuously from the so-called beginning of the world to the present
day, no approach could have been made to the completion of the possible
changes. Nay, had every single minute been prolonged to 10,000 years,
still the task would have been unaccomplished.[105] As regards ordinary
melodies, the eight notes of a single octave give more than 40,000
permutations, and two octaves more than a million millions. If we were
to take into account the semitones, it would become apparent that it
is impossible to exhaust the variety of music. When the late Mr. J. S.
Mill, in a depressed state of mind, feared the approaching exhaustion
of musical melodies, he had certainly not bestowed sufficient study on
the subject of permutations.

  [105] Wallis, *Of Combinations*, p. 116, quoting Vossius.

Similar considerations apply to the possible number of natural
substances, though we cannot always give precise numerical results. It
was recommended by Hatchett[106] that a systematic examination of all
alloys of metals should be carried out, proceeding from the binary ones
to more complicated ternary or quaternary ones. He can hardly have been
aware of the extent of his proposed inquiry. If we operate only upon
thirty of the known metals, the number of binary alloys would be 435,
of ternary alloys 4060, of quaternary 27,405, without paying regard
to the varying proportions of the metals, and only regarding the kind
of metal. If we varied all the ternary alloys by quantities not less
than one per cent., the number of these alloys would be 11,445,060.
An exhaustive investigation of the subject is therefore out of the
question, and unless some laws connecting the properties of the alloy
and its components can be discovered, it is not apparent how our
knowledge of them can ever be more than fragmentary.

  [106] *Philosophical Transactions* (1803), vol. xciii. p. 193.

The possible variety of definite chemical compounds, again, is
enormously great. Chemists have already examined many thousands
of inorganic substances, and a still greater number of organic
compounds;[107] they have nevertheless made no appreciable impression
on the number which may exist. Taking the number of elements at
sixty-one, the number of compounds containing different selections of
four elements each would be more than half a million (521,855). As the
same elements often combine in many different proportions, and some of
them, especially carbon, have the power of forming an almost endless
number of compounds, it would hardly be possible to assign any limit
to the number of chemical compounds which may be formed. There are
branches of physical science, therefore, of which it is unlikely that
scientific men, with all their industry, can ever obtain a knowledge in
any appreciable degree approaching to completeness.

  [107] Hofmann’s *Introduction to Chemistry*, p. 36.


*Higher Orders of Variety.*

The consideration of the facts already given in this chapter will
not produce an adequate notion of the possible variety of existence,
unless we consider the comparative numbers of combinations of different
orders. By a combination of a higher order, I mean a combination of
groups, which are themselves groups. The immense numbers of compounds
of carbon, hydrogen, and oxygen, described in organic chemistry, are
combinations of a second order, for the atoms are groups of groups.
The wave of sound produced by a musical instrument may be regarded as
a combination of motions; the body of sound proceeding from a large
orchestra is therefore a complex aggregate of sounds, each in itself
a complex combination of movements. All literature may be said to be
developed out of the difference of white paper and black ink. From the
unlimited number of marks which might be chosen we select twenty-six
conventional letters. The pronounceable combinations of letters are
probably some trillions in number. Now, as a sentence is a selection
of words, the possible sentences must be inconceivably more numerous
than the words of which it may be composed. A book is a combination
of sentences, and a library is a combination of books. A library,
therefore, may be regarded as a combination of the fifth order, and the
powers of numerical expression would be severely tasked in attempting
to express the number of distinct libraries which might be constructed.
The calculation, of course, would not be possible, because the union
of letters in words, of words in sentences, and of sentences in books,
is governed by conditions so complex as to defy analysis. I wish only
to point out that the infinite variety of literature, existing or
possible, is all developed out of one fundamental difference. Galileo
remarked that all truth is contained in the compass of the alphabet. He
ought to have said that it is all contained in the difference of ink
and paper.

One consequence of successive combination is that the simplest marks
will suffice to express any information. Francis Bacon proposed for
secret writing a biliteral cipher, which resolves all letters of the
alphabet into permutations of the two letters *a* and *b*. Thus A
was *aaaaa*, B *aaaab*, X *babab*, and so on.[108] In a similar way,
as Bacon clearly saw, any one difference can be made the ground of a
code of signals; we can express, as he says, *omnia per omnia*. The
Morse alphabet uses only a succession of long and short marks, and
other systems of telegraphic language employ right and left strokes.
A single lamp obscured at various intervals, long or short, may be
made to spell out any words, and with two lamps, distinguished by
colour, position, or any other circumstance, we could at once represent
Bacon’s biliteral alphabet. Babbage ingeniously suggested that every
lighthouse in the world should be made to spell out its own name or
number perpetually, by flashes or obscurations of various duration
and succession. A system like that of Babbage is now being applied
to lighthouses in the United Kingdom by Sir W. Thomson and Dr. John
Hopkinson.

  [108] *Works*, edited by Shaw, vol. i. pp. 141–145, quoted in Rees’s
  *Encyclopædia*, art. *Cipher*.

Let us calculate the numbers of combinations of different orders which
may arise out of the presence or absence of a single mark, say A. In
these figures

  +---+---+   +---+---+   +---+---+   +---+---+
  | A | A |   | A |   |   |   | A |   |   |   |
  +---+---+   +---+---+   +---+---+   +---+---+

we have four distinct varieties. Form them into a group of a higher
order, and consider in how many ways we may vary that group by omitting
one or more of the component parts. Now, as there are four parts,
and any one may be present or absent, the possible varieties will
be 2 × 2 × 2 × 2, or 16 in number. Form these into a new whole, and
proceed again to create variety by omitting any one or more of the
sixteen. The number of possible changes will now be 2 . 2 . 2 . 2 .
2 . 2 . 2 . 2 . 2 . 2 . 2 . 2 . 2 . 2 . 2 . 2, or 2^{16}, and we can
repeat the process again and again. We are imagining the creation of
objects, whose numbers are represented by the successive orders of the
powers of *two*.

At the first step we have 2; at the next 2^{2}, or 4; at the third
(2^{2})^{2}, or 16, numbers of very moderate amount. Let the reader
calculate the next term, ((2^{2})^{2})^{2}, and he will be surprised
to find it leap up to 65,536. But at the next step he has to calculate
the value of 65,536 *two*’s multiplied together, and it is so great
that we could not possibly compute it, the mere expression of the
result requiring 19,729 places of figures. But go one step more and we
pass the bounds of all reason. The sixth order of the powers of *two*
becomes so great, that we could not even express the number of figures
required in writing it down, without using about 19,729 figures for
the purpose. The successive orders of the powers of two have then the
following values so far as we can succeed in describing them:--

  First order                           2
  Second order                          4
  Third order                          16
  Fourth order                     65,536
  Fifth order, number expressed by 19,729 figures.
  Sixth order, number expressed by
    figures, to express the number
    of which figures would require
    about                          19,729 figures.

It may give us some notion of infinity to remember that at this sixth
step`, having long surpassed all bounds of intuitive conception, we
make no approach to a limit. Nay, were we to make a hundred such steps,
we should be as far away as ever from actual infinity.

It is well worth observing that our powers of expression rapidly
overcome the possible multitude of finite objects which may exist in
any assignable space. Archimedes showed long ago, in one of the most
remarkable writings of antiquity, the *Liber de Arcnæ Numero*, that
the grains of sand in the world could be numbered, or rather, that
if numbered, the result could readily be expressed in arithmetical
notation. Let us extend his problem, and ascertain whether we could
express the number of atoms which could exist in the visible universe.
The most distant stars which can now be seen by telescopes--those of
the sixteenth magnitude--are supposed to have a distance of about
33,900,000,000,000,000 miles. Sir W. Thomson has shown reasons for
supposing that there do not exist more than from 3 × 10^{24} to 10^{26}
molecules in a cubic centimetre of a solid or liquid substance.[109]
Assuming these data to be true, for the sake of argument, a simple
calculation enables us to show that the almost inconceivably vast
sphere of our stellar system if entirely filled with solid matter,
would not contain more than about 68 × 10^{90} atoms, that is to say,
a number requiring for its expression 92 places of figures. Now, this
number would be immensely less than the fifth order of the powers of
two.

  [109] *Nature*, vol. i. p. 553.

In the variety of logical relations, which may exist between a certain
number of logical terms, we also meet a case of higher combinations.
We have seen (p. 142) that with only six terms the number of possible
selections of combinations is 18,446,744,073,709,551,616. Considering
that it is the most common thing in the world to use an argument
involving six objects or terms, it may excite some surprise that the
complete investigation of the relations in which six such terms may
stand to each other, should involve an almost inconceivable number of
cases. Yet these numbers of possible logical relations belong only to
the second order of combinations.




CHAPTER X.

THE THEORY OF PROBABILITY.


The subject upon which we now enter must not be regarded as an isolated
and curious branch of speculation. It is the necessary basis of the
judgments we make in the prosecution of science, or the decisions we
come to in the conduct of ordinary affairs. As Butler truly said,
“Probability is the very guide of life.” Had the science of numbers
been studied for no other purpose, it must have been developed for
the calculation of probabilities. All our inferences concerning the
future are merely probable, and a due appreciation of the degree of
probability depends upon a comprehension of the principles of the
subject. I am convinced that it is impossible to expound the methods of
induction in a sound manner, without resting them upon the theory of
probability. Perfect knowledge alone can give certainty, and in nature
perfect knowledge would be infinite knowledge, which is clearly beyond
our capacities. We have, therefore, to content ourselves with partial
knowledge--knowledge mingled with ignorance, producing doubt.

A great difficulty in this subject consists in acquiring a precise
notion of the matter treated. What is it that we number, and measure,
and calculate in the theory of probabilities? Is it belief, or opinion,
or doubt, or knowledge, or chance, or necessity, or want of art? Does
probability exist in the things which are probable, or in the mind
which regards them as such? The etymology of the name lends us no
assistance: for, curiously enough, *probable* is ultimately the same
word as *provable*, a good instance of one word becoming differentiated
to two opposite meanings.

Chance cannot be the subject of the theory, because there is really
no such thing as chance, regarded as producing and governing events.
The word chance signifies *falling*, and the notion of falling is
continually used as a simile to express uncertainty, because we can
seldom predict how a die, a coin, or a leaf will fall, or when a bullet
will hit the mark. But everyone sees, after a little reflection, that
it is in our knowledge the deficiency lies, not in the certainty of
nature’s laws. There is no doubt in lightning as to the point it shall
strike; in the greatest storm there is nothing capricious; not a grain
of sand lies upon the beach, but infinite knowledge would account for
its lying there; and the course of every falling leaf is guided by the
principles of mechanics which rule the motions of the heavenly bodies.

Chance then exists not in nature, and cannot coexist with knowledge;
it is merely an expression, as Laplace remarked, for our ignorance
of the causes in action, and our consequent inability to predict the
result, or to bring it about infallibly. In nature the happening of
an event has been pre-determined from the first fashioning of the
universe. *Probability belongs wholly to the mind.* This is proved by
the fact that different minds may regard the very same event at the
same time with widely different degrees of probability. A steam-vessel,
for instance, is missing and some persons believe that she has sunk
in mid-ocean; others think differently. In the event itself there can
be no such uncertainty; the steam-vessel either has sunk or has not
sunk, and no subsequent discussion of the probable nature of the event
can alter the fact. Yet the probability of the event will really vary
from day to day, and from mind to mind, according as the slightest
information is gained regarding the vessels met at sea, the weather
prevailing there, the signs of wreck picked up, or the previous
condition of the vessel. Probability thus belongs to our mental
condition, to the light in which we regard events, the occurrence
or non-occurrence of which is certain in themselves. Many writers
accordingly have asserted that probability is concerned with degree or
quantity of belief. De Morgan says,[110] “By degree of probability
we really mean or ought to mean degree of belief.” The late Professor
Donkin expressed the meaning of probability as “quantity of belief;”
but I have never felt satisfied with such definitions of probability.
The nature of *belief* is not more clear to my mind than the notion
which it is used to define. But an all-sufficient objection is, that
*the theory does not measure what the belief is, but what it ought to
be*. Few minds think in close accordance with the theory, and there
are many cases of evidence in which the belief existing is habitually
different from what it ought to be. Even if the state of belief in any
mind could be measured and expressed in figures, the results would be
worthless. The value of the theory consists in correcting and guiding
our belief, and rendering our states of mind and consequent actions
harmonious with our knowledge of exterior conditions.

  [110] *Formal Logic*, p. 172.

This objection has been clearly perceived by some of those who still
used quantity of belief as a definition of probability. Thus De
Morgan adds--“Belief is but another name for imperfect knowledge.”
Donkin has well said that the quantity of belief is “always relative
to a particular state of knowledge or ignorance; but it must be
observed that it is absolute in the sense of not being relative to
any individual mind; since, the same information being presupposed,
all minds *ought* to distribute their belief in the same way.”[111]
Boole seemed to entertain a like view, when he described the theory as
engaged with “the equal distribution of ignorance;”[112] but we may
just as well say that it is engaged with the equal distribution of
knowledge.

  [111] *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. i. p. 355.

  [112] *Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh*, vol. xxi.
  part 4.

I prefer to dispense altogether with this obscure word belief, and to
say that the theory of probability deals with *quantity of knowledge*,
an expression of which a precise explanation and measure can presently
be given. An event is only probable when our knowledge of it is diluted
with ignorance, and exact calculation is needed to discriminate how
much we do and do not know. The theory has been described by some
writers as professing *to evolve knowledge out of ignorance*; but as
Donkin admirably remarked, it is really “a method of avoiding the
erection of belief upon ignorance.” It defines rational expectation
by measuring the comparative amounts of knowledge and ignorance, and
teaches us to regulate our actions with regard to future events in a
way which will, in the long run, lead to the least disappointment. It
is, as Laplace happily said, *good sense reduced to calculation*. This
theory appears to me the noblest creation of intellect, and it passes
my conception how two such men as Auguste Comte and J. S. Mill could be
found depreciating it and vainly questioning its validity. To eulogise
the theory ought to be as needless as to eulogise reason itself.


*Fundamental Principles of the Theory.*

The calculation of probabilities is really founded, as I conceive, upon
the principle of reasoning set forth in preceding chapters. We must
treat equals equally, and what we know of one case may be affirmed of
every case resembling it in the necessary circumstances. The theory
consists in putting similar cases on a par, and distributing equally
among them whatever knowledge we possess. Throw a penny into the air,
and consider what we know with regard to its way of falling. We know
that it will certainly fall upon a side, so that either head or tail
will be uppermost; but as to whether it will be head or tail, our
knowledge is equally divided. Whatever we know concerning head, we know
also concerning tail, so that we have no reason for expecting one more
than the other. The least predominance of belief to either side would
be irrational; it would consist in treating unequally things of which
our knowledge is equal.

The theory does not require, as some writers have erroneously supposed,
that we should first ascertain by experiment the equal facility of
the events we are considering. So far as we can examine and measure
the causes in operation, events are removed out of the sphere of
probability. The theory comes into play where ignorance begins, and the
knowledge we possess requires to be distributed over many cases. Nor
does the theory show that the coin will fall as often on the one side
as the other. It is almost impossible that this should happen, because
some inequality in the form of the coin, or some uniform manner in
throwing it up, is almost sure to occasion a slight preponderance
in one direction. But as we do not previously know in which way a
preponderance will exist, we have no reason for expecting head more
than tail. Our state of knowledge will be changed should we throw up
the coin many times and register the results. Every throw gives us some
slight information as to the probable tendency of the coin, and in
subsequent calculations we must take this into account. In other cases
experience might show that we had been entirely mistaken; we might
expect that a die would fall as often on each of the six sides as on
each other side in the long run; trial might show that the die was a
loaded one, and falls most often on a particular face. The theory would
not have misled us: it treated correctly the information we had, which
is all that any theory can do.

It may be asked, as Mill asks, Why spend so much trouble in calculating
from imperfect data, when a little trouble would enable us to render a
conclusion certain by actual trial? Why calculate the probability of a
measurement being correct, when we can try whether it is correct? But I
shall fully point out in later parts of this work that in measurement
we never can attain perfect coincidence. Two measurements of the
same base line in a survey may show a difference of some inches, and
there may be no means of knowing which is the better result. A third
measurement would probably agree with neither. To select any one of the
measurements, would imply that we knew it to be the most nearly correct
one, which we do not. In this state of ignorance, the only guide is
the theory of probability, which proves that in the long run the mean
of divergent results will come most nearly to the truth. In all other
scientific operations whatsoever, perfect knowledge is impossible, and
when we have exhausted all our instrumental means in the attainment of
truth, there is a margin of error which can only be safely treated by
the principles of probability.

The method which we employ in the theory consists in calculating the
number of all the cases or events concerning which our knowledge is
equal. If we have the slightest reason for suspecting that one event
is more likely to occur than another, we should take this knowledge
into account. This being done, we must determine the whole number of
events which are, so far as we know, equally likely. Thus, if we have
no reason for supposing that a penny will fall more often one way than
another, there are two cases, head and tail, equally likely. But if
from trial or otherwise we know, or think we know, that of 100 throws
55 will give tail, then the probability is measured by the ratio of 55
to 100.

The mathematical formulæ of the theory are exactly the same as those
of the theory of combinations. In this latter theory we determine in
how many ways events may be joined together, and we now proceed to use
this knowledge in calculating the number of ways in which a certain
event may come about. It is the comparative numbers of ways in which
events can happen which measure their comparative probabilities. If
we throw three pennies into the air, what is the probability that two
of them will fall tail uppermost? This amounts to asking in how many
possible ways can we select two tails out of three, compared with the
whole number of ways in which the coins can be placed. Now, the fourth
line of the Arithmetical Triangle (p. 184) gives us the answer. The
whole number of ways in which we can select or leave three things is
eight, and the possible combinations of two things at a time is three;
hence the probability of two tails is the ratio of three to eight. From
the numbers in the triangle we may similarly draw all the following
probabilities:--

  One combination gives 0 tail. Probability 1/8.
  Three combinations gives 1 tail. Probability 3/8.
  Three combinations give 2 tails. Probability 3/8.
  One combination gives 3 tails. Probability 1/8.

We can apply the same considerations to the imaginary causes of the
difference of stature, the combinations of which were shown in p. 188.
There are altogether 128 ways in which seven causes can be present or
absent. Now, twenty-one of these combinations give an addition of two
inches, so that the probability of a person under the circumstances
being five feet two inches is 21/128. The probability of five feet
three inches is 35/128; of five feet one inch 7/128; of five feet
1/128, and so on. Thus the eighth line of the Arithmetical Triangle
gives all the probabilities arising out of the combinations of seven
causes.


*Rules for the Calculation of Probabilities.*

I will now explain as simply as possible the rules for calculating
probabilities. The principal rule is as follows:--

Calculate the number of events which may happen independently of each
other, and which, as far as is known, are equally probable. Make this
number the denominator of a fraction, and take for the numerator the
number of such events as imply or constitute the happening of the
event, whose probability is required.

Thus, if the letters of the word *Roma* be thrown down casually in a
row, what is the probability that they will form a significant Latin
word? The possible arrangements of four letters are 4 × 3 × 2 × 1,
or 24 in number (p. 178), and if all the arrangements be examined,
seven of these will be found to have meaning, namely *Roma*, *ramo*,
*oram*, *mora*, *maro*, *armo*, and *amor*. Hence the probability of a
significant result is 7/24.

We must distinguish comparative from absolute probabilities. In drawing
a card casually from a pack, there is no reason to expect any one card
more than any other. Now, there are four kings and four queens in a
pack, so that there are just as many ways of drawing one as the other,
and the probabilities are equal. But there are thirteen diamonds, so
that the probability of a king is to that of a diamond as four to
thirteen. Thus the probabilities of each are proportional to their
respective numbers of ways of happening. Again, I can draw a king in
four ways, and not draw one in forty-eight, so that the probabilities
are in this proportion, or, as is commonly said, the *odds* against
drawing a king are forty-eight to four. The odds are seven to seventeen
in favour, or seventeen to seven against the letters R,o,m,a,
accidentally forming a significant word. The odds are five to three
against two tails appearing in three throws of a penny. Conversely,
when the odds of an event are given, and the probability is required,
*take the odds in favour of the event for numerator, and the sum of the
odds for denominator*.

It is obvious that an event is certain when all the combinations of
causes which can take place produce that event. If we represent the
probability of such event according to our rule, it gives the ratio
of some number to itself, or unity. An event is certain not to happen
when no possible combination of causes gives the event, and the ratio
by the same rule becomes that of 0 to some number. Hence it follows
that in the theory of probability certainty is expressed by 1, and
impossibility by 0; but no mystical meaning should be attached to these
symbols, as they merely express the fact that *all* or *no* possible
combinations give the event.

By a *compound event*, we mean an event which may be decomposed into
two or more simpler events. Thus the firing of a gun may be decomposed
into pulling the trigger, the fall of the hammer, the explosion of
the cap, &c. In this example the simple events are not *independent*,
because if the trigger is pulled, the other events will under proper
conditions necessarily follow, and their probabilities are therefore
the same as that of the first event. Events are *independent* when
the happening of one does not render the other either more or less
probable than before. Thus the death of a person is neither more nor
less probable because the planet Mars happens to be visible. When
the component events are independent, a simple rule can be given for
calculating the probability of the compound event, thus--*Multiply
together the fractions expressing the probabilities of the independent
component events.*

The probability of throwing tail twice with a penny is 1/2 × 1/2,
or 1/4; the probability of throwing it three times running is
1/2 × 1/2 × 1/2, or 1/8; a result agreeing with that obtained in
an apparently different manner (p. 202). In fact, when we multiply
together the denominators, we get the whole number of ways of happening
of the compound event, and when we multiply the numerators, we get the
number of ways favourable to the required event.

Probabilities may be added to or subtracted from each other under the
important condition that the events in question are exclusive of each
other, so that not more than one of them can happen. It might be argued
that, since the probability of throwing head at the first trial is
1/2, and at the second trial also 1/2, the probability of throwing it
in the first two throws is 1/2 + 1/2, or certainty. Not only is this
result evidently absurd, but a repetition of the process would lead
us to a probability of 1-1/2 or of any greater number, results which
could have no meaning whatever. The probability we wish to calculate is
that of one head in two throws, but in our addition we have included
the case in which two heads appear. The true result is 1/2 + 1/2 × 1/2
or 3/4, or the probability of head at the first throw, added to the
exclusive probability that if it does not come at the first, it will
come at the second. The greatest difficulties of the theory arise
from the confusion of exclusive and unexclusive alternatives. I may
remind the reader that the possibility of unexclusive alternatives was
a point previously discussed (p. 68), and to the reasons then given
for considering alternation as logically unexclusive, may be added
the existence of these difficulties in the theory of probability. The
erroneous result explained above really arose from overlooking the
fact that the expression “head first throw or head second throw” might
include the case of head at both throws.


*The Logical Alphabet in questions of Probability.*

When the probabilities of certain simple events are given, and it is
required to deduce the probabilities of compound events, the Logical
Alphabet may give assistance, provided that there are no special
logical conditions so that all the combinations are possible. Thus,
if there be three events, A, B, C, of which the probabilities are, α,
β, γ, then the negatives of those events, expressing the absence of
the events, will have the probabilities 1 - α, 1 - β, 1 - γ. We have
only to insert these values for the letters of the combinations and
multiply, and we obtain the probability of each combination. Thus the
probability of ABC is αβγ; of A*bc*, α(1 - β)(1 - γ).

We can now clearly distinguish between the probabilities of exclusive
and unexclusive events. Thus, if A and B are events which may happen
together like rain and high tide, or an earthquake and a storm, the
probability of A or B happening is not the sum of their separate
probabilities. For by the Laws of Thought we develop A ꖌ  B into
AB ꖌ A*b* ꖌ *a*B, and substituting α and β, the probabilities of A
and B respectively, we obtain α . β + α . (1 - β) + (1 - α) . β or
α + β - α . β. But if events are *incompossible* or incapable of
happening together, like a clear sky and rain, or a new moon and a full
moon, then the events are not really A or B, but A not-B, or B not-A,
or in symbols A*b* ꖌ *a*B. Now if we take μ = probability of A*b* and ν
= probability of *a*B, then we may add simply, and the probability of
A*b* ꖌ *a*B is μ + ν.

Let the reader carefully observe that if the combination AB cannot
exist, the probability of A*b* is not the product of the probabilities
of A and *b*. When certain combinations are logically impossible, it
is no longer allowable to substitute the probability of each term for
the term, because the multiplication of probabilities presupposes the
independence of the events. A large part of Boole’s Laws of Thought
is devoted to an attempt to overcome this difficulty and to produce
a General Method in Probabilities by which from certain logical
conditions and certain given probabilities it would be possible to
deduce the probability of any other combinations of events under those
conditions. Boole pursued his task with wonderful ingenuity and power,
but after spending much study on his work, I am compelled to adopt
the conclusion that his method is fundamentally erroneous. As pointed
out by Mr. Wilbraham,[113] Boole obtained his results by an arbitrary
assumption, which is only the most probable, and not the only possible
assumption. The answer obtained is therefore not the real probability,
which is usually indeterminate, but only, as it were, the most probable
probability. Certain problems solved by Boole are free from logical
conditions and therefore may admit of valid answers. These, as I have
shown,[114] may be solved by the combinations of the Logical Alphabet,
but the rest of the problems do not admit of a determinate answer, at
least by Boole’s method.

  [113] *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. vii. p. 465;
  vol. viii. p. 91.

  [114] *Memoirs of the Manchester Literary and Philosophical Society*,
  3rd Series, vol. iv. p. 347.


*Comparison of the Theory with Experience.*

The Laws of Probability rest upon the fundamental principles of
reasoning, and cannot be really negatived by any possible experience.
It might happen that a person should always throw a coin head
uppermost, and appear incapable of getting tail by chance. The theory
would not be falsified, because it contemplates the possibility of
the most extreme runs of luck. Our actual experience might be counter
to all that is probable; the whole course of events might seem to be
in complete contradiction to what we should expect, and yet a casual
conjunction of events might be the real explanation. It is just
possible that some regular coincidences, which we attribute to fixed
laws of nature, are due to the accidental conjunction of phenomena
in the cases to which our attention is directed. All that we can
learn from finite experience is capable, according to the theory of
probabilities, of misleading us, and it is only infinite experience
that could assure us of any inductive truths.

At the same time, the probability that any extreme runs of luck will
occur is so excessively slight, that it would be absurd seriously
to expect their occurrence. It is almost impossible, for instance,
that any whist player should have played in any two games where the
distribution of the cards was exactly the same, by pure accident
(p. 191). Such a thing as a person always losing at a game of
pure chance, is wholly unknown. Coincidences of this kind are not
impossible, as I have said, but they are so unlikely that the lifetime
of any person, or indeed the whole duration of history, does not give
any appreciable probability of their being encountered. Whenever we
make any extensive series of trials of chance results, as in throwing
a die or coin, the probability is great that the results will agree
nearly with the predictions yielded by theory. Precise agreement must
not be expected, for that, as the theory shows, is highly improbable.
Several attempts have been made to test, in this way, the accordance of
theory and experience. Buffon caused the first trial to be made by a
young child who threw a coin many times in succession, and he obtained
1992 tails to 2048 heads. A pupil of De Morgan repeated the trial for
his own satisfaction, and obtained 2044 tails to 2048 heads. In both
cases the coincidence with theory is as close as could be expected, and
the details may be found in De Morgan’s “Formal Logic,” p. 185.

Quetelet also tested the theory in a rather more complete manner, by
placing 20 black and 20 white balls in an urn and drawing a ball out
time after time in an indifferent manner, each ball being replaced
before a new drawing was made. He found, as might be expected, that the
greater the number of drawings made, the more nearly were the white
and black balls equal in number. At the termination of the experiment
he had registered 2066 white and 2030 black balls, the ratio being
1·02.[115]

  [115] *Letters on the Theory of Probabilities*, translated by Downes,
  1849, pp. 36, 37.

I have made a series of experiments in a third manner, which seemed to
me even more interesting, and capable of more extensive trial. Taking
a handful of ten coins, usually shillings, I threw them up time after
time, and registered the numbers of heads which appeared each time. Now
the probability of obtaining 10, 9, 8, 7, &c., heads is proportional
to the number of combinations of 10, 9, 8, 7, &c., things out of 10
things. Consequently the results ought to approximate to the numbers in
the eleventh line of the Arithmetical Triangle. I made altogether 2048
throws, in two sets of 1024 throws each, and the numbers obtained are
given in the following table:--

+-------------------+-----------+---------+---------+----------+-----------+
|Character of Throw.|Theoretical|  First  | Second  | Average. |Divergence.|
|                   | Numbers.  | Series. | Series. |          |           |
+-------------------+-----------+---------+---------+----------+-----------+
|  10 Heads 0 Tail  |      1    |     3   |     1   |    2     |  +  1     |
|   9   "   1   "   |     10    |    12   |    23   |   17-1/2 |  +  7-1/2 |
|   8   "   2   "   |     45    |    57   |    73   |   65     |  + 20     |
|   7   "   3   "   |    120    |   129   |   123   |  126     |  +  6     |
|   6   "   4   "   |    210    |   181   |   190   |  185-1/2 |  - 25     |
|   5   "   5   "   |    252    |   257   |   232   |  244-1/2 |  -  7-1/2 |
|   4   "   6   "   |    210    |   201   |   197   |  199     |  - 11     |
|   3   "   7   "   |    120    |   111   |   119   |  115     |  -  5     |
|   2   "   8   "   |     45    |    52   |    50   |   51     |  +  6     |
|   1   "   9   "   |     10    |    21   |    15   |   18     |  +  8     |
|   0   "  10   "   |      1    |     0   |     1   |      1/2 |  -    1/2 |
+-------------------+-----------+---------+---------+----------+-----------+
|      Totals       |   1024    |  1024   |  1024   | 1024     |  -  1     |
+-------------------+-----------+---------+---------+----------+-----------+

The whole number of single throws of coins amounted to 10 × 2048, or
20,480 in all, one half of which or 10,240 should theoretically give
head. The total number of heads obtained was actually 10,353, or 5222
in the first series, and 5131 in the second. The coincidence with
theory is pretty close, but considering the large number of throws
there is some reason to suspect a tendency in favour of heads.

The special interest of this trial consists in the exhibition, in a
practical form, of the results of Bernoulli’s theorem, and the law
of error or divergence from the mean to be afterwards more fully
considered. It illustrates the connection between combinations and
permutations, which is exhibited in the Arithmetical Triangle, and
which underlies many important theorems of science.


*Probable Deductive Arguments*.

With the aid of the theory of probabilities, we may extend the sphere
of deductive argument. Hitherto we have treated propositions as
certain, and on the hypothesis of certainty have deduced conclusions
equally certain. But the information on which we reason in ordinary
life is seldom or never certain, and almost all reasoning is really a
question of probability. We ought therefore to be fully aware of the
mode and degree in which deductive reasoning is affected by the theory
of probability, and many persons may be surprised at the results which
must be admitted. Some controversial writers appear to consider, as De
Morgan remarked,[116] that an inference from several equally probable
premises is itself as probable as any of them, but the true result is
very different. If an argument involves many propositions, and each of
them is uncertain, the conclusion will be of very little force.

  [116] *Encyclopædia Metropolitana*, art. *Probabilities*, p. 396.

The validity of a conclusion may be regarded as a compound event,
depending upon the premises happening to be true; thus, to obtain the
probability of the conclusion, we must multiply together the fractions
expressing the probabilities of the premises. If the probability is
1/2 that A is B, and also 1/2 that B is C, the conclusion that A is
C, on the ground of these premises, is 1/2 × 1/2 or 1/4. Similarly
if there be any number of premises requisite to the establishment
of a conclusion and their probabilities be *p*, *q*, *r*, &c., the
probability of the conclusion on the ground of these premises is
*p* × *q* × *r* × ... This product has but a small value, unless each
of the quantities *p*, *q*, &c., be nearly unity.

But it is particularly to be noticed that the probability thus
calculated is not the whole probability of the conclusion, but that
only which it derives from the premises in question. Whately’s[117]
remarks on this subject might mislead the reader into supposing that
the calculation is completed by multiplying together the probabilities
of the premises. But it has been fully explained by De Morgan[118] that
we must take into account the antecedent probability of the conclusion;
A may be C for other reasons besides its being B, and as he remarks,
“It is difficult, if not impossible, to produce a chain of argument of
which the reasoner can rest the result on those arguments only.” The
failure of one argument does not, except under special circumstances,
disprove the truth of the conclusion it is intended to uphold,
otherwise there are few truths which could survive the ill-considered
arguments adduced in their favour. As a rope does not necessarily break
because one or two strands in it fail, so a conclusion may depend upon
an endless number of considerations besides those immediately in view.
Even when we have no other information we must not consider a statement
as devoid of all probability. The true expression of complete doubt is
a ratio of equality between the chances in favour of and against it,
and this ratio is expressed in the probability 1/2.

  [117] *Elements of Logic*, Book III. sections 11 and 18.

  [118] *Encyclopædia Metropolitana*, art. *Probabilities*, p. 400.

Now if A and C are wholly unknown things, we have no reason to believe
that A is C rather than A is not C. The antecedent probability is then
1/2. If we also have the probabilities that A is B, 1/2 and that B is
C, 1/2 we have no right to suppose that the probability of A being C
is reduced by the argument in its favour. If the conclusion is true
on its own grounds, the failure of the argument does not affect it;
thus its total probability is its antecedent probability, added to the
probability that this failing, the new argument in question establishes
it. There is a probability 1/2 that we shall not require the special
argument; a probability 1/2 that we shall, and a probability 1/4
that the argument does in that case establish it. Thus the complete
result is 1/2 + 1/2 × 1/4, or 5/8. In general language, if *a* be the
probability founded on a particular argument, and *c* the antecedent
probability of the event, the general result is 1 - (1 - *a*)(1 - *c*),
or *a* + *c* - *ac*.

We may put it still more generally in this way:--Let *a*, *b*, *c*, &c.
be the probabilities of a conclusion grounded on various arguments. It
is only when all the arguments fail that our conclusion proves finally
untrue; the probabilities of each failing are respectively, 1 - *a*,
1 - *b*, 1 - *c*, &c.; the probability that they will all fail is
(1 - *a*)(1 - *b*)(1 - *c*) ...; therefore the probability that the
conclusion will not fail is 1 - (1 - *a*)(1 - *b*)(1 - *c*) ... &c. It
follows that every argument in favour of a conclusion, however flimsy
and slight, adds probability to it. When it is unknown whether an
overdue vessel has foundered or not, every slight indication of a lost
vessel will add some probability to the belief of its loss, and the
disproof of any particular evidence will not disprove the event.

We must apply these principles of evidence with great care, and
observe that in a great proportion of cases the adducing of a weak
argument does tend to the disproof of its conclusion. The assertion
may have in itself great inherent improbability as being opposed to
other evidence or to the supposed law of nature, and every reasoner
may be assumed to be dealing plainly, and putting forward the whole
force of evidence which he possesses in its favour. If he brings but
one argument, and its probability *a* is small, then in the formula
1 - (1 - *a*)(1 - *c*) both *a* and *c* are small, and the whole
expression has but little value. The whole effect of an argument thus
turns upon the question whether other arguments remain, so that we
can introduce other factors (1 - *b*), (1 - *d*), &c., into the above
expression. In a court of justice, in a publication having an express
purpose, and in many other cases, it is doubtless right to assume
that the whole evidence considered to have any value as regards the
conclusion asserted, is put forward.

To assign the antecedent probability of any proposition, may be a
matter of difficulty or impossibility, and one with which logic and
the theory of probability have little concern. From the general body of
science in our possession, we must in each case make the best judgment
we can. But in the absence of all knowledge the probability should
be considered = 1/2, for if we make it less than this we incline to
believe it false rather than true. Thus, before we possessed any means
of estimating the magnitudes of the fixed stars, the statement that
Sirius was greater than the sun had a probability of exactly 1/2; it
was as likely that it would be greater as that it would be smaller; and
so of any other star. This was the assumption which Michell made in
his admirable speculations.[119] It might seem, indeed, that as every
proposition expresses an agreement, and the agreements or resemblances
between phenomena are infinitely fewer than the differences (p. 44),
every proposition should in the absence of other information be
infinitely improbable. But in our logical system every term may be
indifferently positive or negative, so that we express under the same
form as many differences as agreements. It is impossible therefore
that we should have any reason to disbelieve rather than to believe a
statement about things of which we know nothing. We can hardly indeed
invent a proposition concerning the truth of which we are absolutely
ignorant, except when we are entirely ignorant of the terms used. If I
ask the reader to assign the odds that a “Platythliptic Coefficient is
positive” he will hardly see his way to doing so, unless he regard them
as even.

  [119] *Philosophical Transactions* (1767). Abridg. vol. xii. p. 435.

The assumption that complete doubt is properly expressed by 1/2 has
been called in question by Bishop Terrot,[120] who proposes instead
the indefinite symbol 0/0; and he considers that “the *à priori*
probability derived from absolute ignorance has no effect upon the
force of a subsequently admitted probability.” But if we grant that the
probability may have any value between 0 and 1, and that every separate
value is equally likely, then *n* and 1 - *n* are equally likely, and
the average is always 1/2. Or we may take *p* . *dp* to express the
probability that our estimate concerning any proposition should lie
between *p* and *p* + *dp*. The complete probability of the proposition
is then the integral taken between the limits 1 and 0, or again 1/2.

  [120] *Transactions of the Edinburgh Philosophical Society*,
  vol. xxi. p. 375.


*Difficulties of the Theory.*

The theory of probability, though undoubtedly true, requires very
careful application. Not only is it a branch of mathematics in which
oversights are frequently committed, but it is a matter of great
difficulty in many cases, to be sure that the formula correctly
represents the data of the problem. These difficulties often arise from
the logical complexity of the conditions, which might be, perhaps, to
some extent cleared up by constantly bearing in mind the system of
combinations as developed in the Indirect Logical Method. In the study
of probabilities, mathematicians had unconsciously employed logical
processes far in advance of those in possession of logicians, and the
Indirect Method is but the full statement of these processes.

It is very curious how often the most acute and powerful intellects
have gone astray in the calculation of probabilities. Seldom was Pascal
mistaken, yet he inaugurated the science with a mistaken solution.[121]
Leibnitz fell into the extraordinary blunder of thinking that the
number twelve was as probable a result in the throwing of two dice as
the number eleven.[122] In not a few cases the false solution first
obtained seems more plausible to the present day than the correct
one since demonstrated. James Bernoulli candidly records two false
solutions of a problem which he at first thought self-evident; and he
adds a warning against the risk of error, especially when we attempt
to reason on this subject without a rigid adherence to methodical
rules and symbols. Montmort was not free from similar mistakes.
D’Alembert constantly fell into blunders, and could not perceive,
for instance, that the probabilities would be the same when coins
are thrown successively as when thrown simultaneously. Some men of
great reputation, such as Ancillon, Moses Mendelssohn, Garve, Auguste
Comte,[123] Poinsot, and J. S. Mill,[124] have so far misapprehended
the theory, as to question its value or even to dispute its validity.
The erroneous statements about the theory given in the earlier editions
of Mill’s *System of Logic* were partially withdrawn in the later
editions.

  [121] Montucla, *Histoire des Mathématiques*, vol. iii. p. 386.

  [122] Leibnitz *Opera*, Dutens’ Edition, vol. vi. part i. p. 217.
  Todhunter’s *History of the Theory of Probability*, p. 48. To the
  latter work I am indebted for many of the statements in the text.

  [123] *Positive Philosophy*, translated by Martineau, vol. ii. p. 120.

  [124] *System of Logic*, bk. iii. chap. 18, 5th Ed. vol. ii. p. 61.

Many persons have a fallacious tendency to believe that when a chance
event has happened several times together in an unusual conjunction, it
is less likely to happen again. D’Alembert seriously held that if head
was thrown three times running with a coin, tail would more probably
appear at the next trial.[125] Bequelin adopted the same opinion, and
yet there is no reason for it whatever. If the event be really casual,
what has gone before cannot in the slightest degree influence it. As
a matter of fact, the more often a casual event takes place the more
likely it is to happen again; because there is some slight empirical
evidence of a tendency. The source of the fallacy is to be found
entirely in the feelings of surprise with which we witness an event
happening by chance, in a manner which seems to proceed from design.

  [125] Montucla, *Histoire*, vol. iii. p. 405; Todhunter, p. 263.

Misapprehension may also arise from overlooking the difference between
permutations and combinations. To throw ten heads in succession with a
coin is no more unlikely than to throw any other particular succession
of heads and tails, but it is much less likely than five heads and five
tails without regard to their order, because there are no less than
252 different particular throws which will give this result, when we
abstract the difference of order.

Difficulties arise in the application of the theory from our habitual
disregard of slight probabilities. We are obliged practically to accept
truths as certain which are nearly so, because it ceases to be worth
while to calculate the difference. No punishment could be inflicted
if absolutely certain evidence of guilt were required, and as Locke
remarks, “He that will not stir till he infallibly knows the business
he goes about will succeed, will have but little else to do but to
sit still and perish.”[126] There is not a moment of our lives when
we do not lie under a slight danger of death, or some most terrible
fate. There is not a single action of eating, drinking, sitting down,
or standing up, which has not proved fatal to some person. Several
philosophers have tried to assign the limit of the probabilities
which we regard as zero; Buffon named 1/10,000, because it is the
probability, practically disregarded, that a man of 56 years of age
will die the next day. Pascal remarked that a man would be esteemed a
fool for hesitating to accept death when three dice gave sixes twenty
times running, if his reward in case of a different result was to be a
crown; but as the chance of death in question is only 1 ÷ 6^{60}, or
unity divided by a number of 47 places of figures, we may be said to
incur greater risks every day for less motives. There is far greater
risk of death, for instance, in a game of cricket or a visit to the
rink.

  [126] *Essay concerning Human Understanding*, bk. iv. ch. 14. § 1.

Nothing is more requisite than to distinguish carefully between the
truth of a theory and the truthful application of the theory to actual
circumstances. As a general rule, events in nature and art will present
a complexity of relations exceeding our powers of treatment. The
intricate action of the mind often intervenes and renders complete
analysis hopeless. If, for instance, the probability that a marksman
shall hit the target in a single shot be 1 in 10, we might seem to
have no difficulty in calculating the probability of any succession of
hits; thus the probability of three successive hits would be one in a
thousand. But, in reality, the confidence and experience derived from
the first successful shot would render a second success more probable.
The events are not really independent, and there would generally be
a far greater preponderance of runs of apparent luck, than a simple
calculation of probabilities could account for. In some persons,
however, a remarkable series of successes will produce a degree of
excitement rendering continued success almost impossible.

Attempts to apply the theory of probability to the results of judicial
proceedings have proved of little value, simply because the conditions
are far too intricate. As Laplace said, “Tant de passions, d’intérêts
divers et de circonstances compliquent les questions relatives à ces
objets, qu’elles sont presque toujours insolubles.” Men acting on a
jury, or giving evidence before a court, are subject to so many complex
influences that no mathematical formulas can be framed to express the
real conditions. Jurymen or even judges on the bench cannot be regarded
as acting independently, with a definite probability in favour of each
delivering a correct judgment. Each man of the jury is more or less
influenced by the opinion of the others, and there are subtle effects
of character and manner and strength of mind which defy analysis. Even
in physical science we can in comparatively few cases apply the theory
in a definite manner, because the data required are too complicated and
difficult to obtain. But such failures in no way diminish the truth and
beauty of the theory itself; in reality there is no branch of science
in which our symbols can cope with the complexity of Nature. As Donkin
said,--

“I do not see on what ground it can be doubted that every definite
state of belief concerning a proposed hypothesis, is in itself capable
of being represented by a numerical expression, however difficult or
impracticable it may be to ascertain its actual value. It would be very
difficult to estimate in numbers the *vis viva* of all the particles of
a human body at any instant; but no one doubts that it is capable of
numerical expression.”[127]

  [127] *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. i. p. 354.

The difficulty, in short, is merely relative to our knowledge and
skill, and is not absolute or inherent in the subject. We must
distinguish between what is theoretically conceivable and what is
practicable with our present mental resources. Provided that our
aspirations are pointed in a right direction, we must not allow them
to be damped by the consideration that they pass beyond what can now
be turned to immediate use. In spite of its immense difficulties of
application, and the aspersions which have been mistakenly cast upon
it, the theory of probabilities, I repeat, is the noblest, as it
will in course of time prove, perhaps the most fruitful branch of
mathematical science. It is the very guide of life, and hardly can
we take a step or make a decision of any kind without correctly or
incorrectly making an estimation of probabilities. In the next chapter
we proceed to consider how the whole cogency of inductive reasoning
rests upon probabilities. The truth or untruth of a natural law, when
carefully investigated, resolves itself into a high or low degree of
probability, and this is the case whether or not we are capable of
producing precise numerical data.




CHAPTER XI.

PHILOSOPHY OF INDUCTIVE INFERENCE.


We have inquired into the nature of perfect induction, whereby we pass
backwards from certain observed combinations of events, to the logical
conditions governing such combinations. We have also investigated the
grounds of that theory of probability, which must be our guide when we
leave certainty behind, and dilute knowledge with ignorance. There is
now before us the difficult task of endeavouring to decide how, by the
aid of that theory, we can ascend from the facts to the laws of nature;
and may then with more or less success anticipate the future course
of events. All our knowledge of natural objects must be ultimately
derived from observation, and the difficult question arises--How can
we ever know anything which we have not directly observed through one
of our senses, the apertures of the mind? The utility of reasoning is
to assure ourselves that, at a determinate time and place, or under
specified conditions, a certain phenomenon will be observed. When
we can use our senses and perceive that the phenomenon does occur,
reasoning is superfluous. If the senses cannot be used, because the
event is in the future, or out of reach, how can reasoning take their
place? Apparently, at least, we must infer the unknown from the known,
and the mind must itself create an addition to the sum of knowledge.
But I hold that it is quite impossible to make any real additions to
the contents of our knowledge, except through new impressions upon
the senses, or upon some seat of feeling. I shall attempt to show
that inference, whether inductive or deductive, is never more than
an unfolding of the contents of our experience, and that it always
proceeds upon the assumption that the future and the unperceived will
be governed by the same conditions as the past and the perceived, an
assumption which will often prove to be mistaken.

In inductive as in deductive reasoning the conclusion never passes
beyond the premises. Reasoning adds no more to the implicit contents of
our knowledge, than the arrangement of the specimens in a museum adds
to the number of those specimens. Arrangement adds to our knowledge
in a certain sense: it allows us to perceive the similarities and
peculiarities of the specimens, and on the assumption that the museum
is an adequate representation of nature, it enables us to judge of
the prevailing forms of natural objects. Bacon’s first aphorism holds
perfectly true, that man knows nothing but what he has observed,
provided that we include his whole sources of experience, and the whole
implicit contents of his knowledge. Inference but unfolds the hidden
meaning of our observations, and *the theory of probability shows how
far we go beyond our data in assuming that new specimens will resemble
the old ones*, or that the future may be regarded as proceeding
uniformly with the past.


*Various Classes of Inductive Truths.*

It will be desirable, in the first place, to distinguish between the
several kinds of truths which we endeavour to establish by induction.
Although there is a certain common and universal element in all our
processes of reasoning, yet diversity arises in their application.
Similarity of condition between the events from which we argue, and
those to which we argue, must always be the ground of inference; but
this similarity may have regard either to time or place, or the simple
logical combination of events, or to any conceivable junction of
circumstances involving quality, time, and place. Having met with many
pieces of substance possessing ductility and a bright yellow colour,
and having discovered, by perfect induction, that they all possess a
high specific gravity, and a freedom from the corrosive action of
acids, we are led to expect that every piece of substance, possessing
like ductility and a similar yellow colour, will have an equally high
specific gravity, and a like freedom from corrosion by acids. This
is a case of the coexistence of qualities; for the character of the
specimens examined alters not with time nor place.

In a second class of cases, time will enter as a principal ground of
similarity. When we hear a clock pendulum beat time after time, at
equal intervals, and with a uniform sound, we confidently expect that
the stroke will continue to be repeated uniformly. A comet having
appeared several times at nearly equal intervals, we infer that it will
probably appear again at the end of another like interval. A man who
has returned home evening after evening for many years, and found his
house standing, may, on like grounds, expect that it will be standing
the next evening, and on many succeeding evenings. Even the continuous
existence of an object in an unaltered state, or the finding again of
that which we have hidden, is but a matter of inference depending on
experience.

A still larger and more complex class of cases involves the relations
of space, in addition to those of time and quality. Having observed
that every triangle drawn upon the diameter of a circle, with its
apex upon the circumference, apparently contains a right angle,
we may ascertain that all triangles in similar circumstances will
contain right angles. This is a case of pure space reasoning, apart
from circumstances of time or quality, and it seems to be governed by
different principles of reasoning. I shall endeavour to show, however,
that geometrical reasoning differs but in degree from that which
applies to other natural relations.


*The Relation of Cause and Effect.*

In a very large part of the scientific investigations which must be
considered, we deal with events which follow from previous events, or
with existences which succeed existences. Science, indeed, might arise
even were material nature a fixed and changeless whole. Endow mind
with the power to travel about, and compare part with part, and it
could certainly draw inferences concerning the similarity of forms, the
coexistence of qualities, or the preponderance of a particular kind of
matter in a changeless world. A solid universe, in at least approximate
equilibrium, is not inconceivable, and then the relation of cause and
effect would evidently be no more than the relation of before and
after. As nature exists, however, it is a progressive existence, ever
moving and changing as time, the great independent variable, proceeds.
Hence it arises that we must continually compare what is happening now
with what happened a moment before, and a moment before that moment,
and so on, until we reach indefinite periods of past time. A comet
is seen moving in the sky, or its constituent particles illumine
the heavens with their tails of fire. We cannot explain the present
movements of such a body without supposing its prior existence, with
a definite amount of energy and a definite direction of motion; nor
can we validly suppose that our task is concluded when we find that it
came wandering to our solar system through the unmeasured vastness of
surrounding space. Every event must have a cause, and that cause again
a cause, until we are lost in the obscurity of the past, and are driven
to the belief in one First Cause, by whom the course of nature was
determined.


*Fallacious Use of the Term Cause.*

The words Cause and Causation have given rise to infinite trouble
and obscurity, and have in no slight degree retarded the progress of
science. From the time of Aristotle, the work of philosophy has been
described as the discovery of the causes of things, and Francis Bacon
adopted the notion when he said “*vere scire esse per causas scire*.”
Even now it is not uncommonly supposed that the knowledge of causes is
something different from other knowledge, and consists, as it were, in
getting possession of the keys of nature. A single word may thus act
as a spell, and throw the clearest intellect into confusion, as I have
often thought that Locke was thrown into confusion when endeavouring to
find a meaning for the word *power*.[128] In Mill’s *System of Logic*
the term *cause* seems to have re-asserted its old noxious power. Not
only does Mill treat the Laws of Causation as almost coextensive with
science, but he so uses the expression as to imply that when once we
pass within the circle of causation we deal with certainties.

  [128] *Essay concerning Human Understanding*, bk. ii. chap. xxi.

The philosophical danger which attaches to the use of this word may
be thus described. A cause is defined as the necessary or invariable
antecedent of an event, so that when the cause exists the effect will
also exist or soon follow. If then we know the cause of an event, we
know what will certainly happen; and as it is implied that science,
by a proper experimental method, may attain to a knowledge of causes,
it follows that experience may give us a certain knowledge of future
events. But nothing is more unquestionable than that finite experience
can never give us certain knowledge of the future, so that either
a cause is not an invariable antecedent, or else we can never gain
certain knowledge of causes. The first horn of this dilemma is hardly
to be accepted. Doubtless there is in nature some invariably acting
mechanism, such that from certain fixed conditions an invariable result
always emerges. But we, with our finite minds and short experience, can
never penetrate the mystery of those existences which embody the Will
of the Creator, and evolve it throughout time. We are in the position
of spectators who witness the productions of a complicated machine, but
are not allowed to examine its intimate structure. We learn what does
happen and what does appear, but if we ask for the reason, the answer
would involve an infinite depth of mystery. The simplest bit of matter,
or the most trivial incident, such as the stroke of two billiard balls,
offers infinitely more to learn than ever the human intellect can
fathom. The word cause covers just as much untold meaning as any of the
words *substance*, *matter*, *thought*, *existence*.


*Confusion of Two Questions.*

The subject is much complicated, too, by the confusion of two distinct
questions. An event having happened, we may ask--

  (1) Is there any cause for the event?
  (2) Of what kind is that cause?

No one would assert that the mind possesses any faculty capable of
inferring, prior to experience, that the occurrence of a sudden noise
with flame and smoke indicates the combustion of a black powder, formed
by the mixture of black, white, and yellow powders. The greatest
upholder of *à priori* doctrines will allow that the particular aspect,
shape, size, colour, texture, and other qualities of a cause must be
gathered through the senses.

The question whether there is any cause at all for an event, is of
a totally different kind. If an explosion could happen without any
prior existing conditions, it must be a new creation--a distinct
addition to the universe. It may be plausibly held that we can imagine
neither the creation nor annihilation of anything. As regards matter,
this has long been held true; as regards force, it is now almost
universally assumed as an axiom that energy can neither come into
nor go out of existence without distinct acts of Creative Will. That
there exists any instinctive belief to this effect, indeed, seems
doubtful. We find Lucretius, a philosopher of the utmost intellectual
power and cultivation, gravely assuming that his raining atoms could
turn aside from their straight paths in a self-determining manner,
and by this spontaneous origination of energy determine the form of
the universe.[129] Sir George Airy, too, seriously discussed the
mathematical conditions under which a perpetual motion, that is, a
perpetual source of self-created energy, might exist.[130] The larger
part of the philosophic world has long held that in mental acts there
is free will--in short, self-causation. It is in vain to attempt to
reconcile this doctrine with that of an intuitive belief in causation,
as Sir W. Hamilton candidly allowed.

  [129] *De Rerum Natura*, bk. ii. ll. 216–293.

  [130] *Cambridge Philosophical Transactions* (1830), vol. iii. pp.
  369–372.

It is obvious, moreover, that to assert the existence of a cause for
every event cannot do more than remove into the indefinite past the
inconceivable fact and mystery of creation. At any given moment matter
and energy were equal to what they are at present, or they were not;
if equal, we may make the same inquiry concerning any other moment,
however long prior, and we are thus obliged to accept one horn of the
dilemma--existence from infinity, or creation at some moment. This is
but one of the many cases in which we are compelled to believe in one
or other of two alternatives, both inconceivable. My present purpose,
however, is to point out that we must not confuse this supremely
difficult question with that into which inductive science inquires on
the foundation of facts. By induction we gain no certain knowledge;
but by observation, and the inverse use of deductive reasoning, we
estimate the probability that an event which has occurred was preceded
by conditions of specified character, or that such conditions will be
followed by the event.


*Definition of the Term Cause.*

Clear definitions of the word cause have been given by several
philosophers. Hobbes has said, “A cause is the sum or aggregate of all
such accidents, both in the agents and the patients, as concur in the
producing of the effect propounded; all which existing together, it
cannot be understood but that the effect existeth with them; or that
it can possibly exist if any of them be absent.” Brown, in his *Essay
on Causation*, gave a nearly corresponding statement. “A cause,” he
says,[131] “may be defined to be the object or event which immediately
precedes any change, and which existing again in similar circumstances
will be always immediately followed by a similar change.” Of the
kindred word *power*, he likewise says:[132] “Power is nothing more
than that invariableness of antecedence which is implied in the belief
of causation.”

  [131] *Observations on the Nature and Tendency of the Doctrine of Mr.
  Hume, concerning the Relation of Cause and Effect.* Second ed. p. 44.

  [132] Ibid. p. 97.

These definitions may be accepted with the qualification that our
knowledge of causes in such a sense can be probable only. The work of
science consists in ascertaining the combinations in which phenomena
present themselves. Concerning every event we shall have to determine
its probable conditions, or the group of antecedents from which it
probably follows. An antecedent is anything which exists prior to
an event; a consequent is anything which exists subsequently to an
antecedent. It will not usually happen that there is any probable
connection between an antecedent and consequent. Thus nitrogen is an
antecedent to the lighting of a common fire; but it is so far from
being a cause of the lighting, that it renders the combustion less
active. Daylight is an antecedent to all fires lighted during the day,
but it probably has no appreciable effect upon their burning. But
in the case of any given event it is usually possible to discover a
certain number of antecedents which seem to be always present, and with
more or less probability we conclude that when they exist the event
will follow.

Let it be observed that the utmost latitude is at present enjoyed in
the use of the term *cause*. Not only may a cause be an existent thing
endowed with powers, as oxygen is the cause of combustion, gunpowder
the cause of explosion, but the very absence or removal of a thing may
also be a cause. It is quite correct to speak of the dryness of the
Egyptian atmosphere, or the absence of moisture, as being the cause of
the preservation of mummies, and other remains of antiquity. The cause
of a mountain elevation, Ingleborough for instance, is the excavation
of the surrounding valleys by denudation. It is not so usual to speak
of the existence of a thing at one moment as the cause of its existence
at the next, but to me it seems the commonest case of causation which
can occur. The cause of motion of a billiard ball may be the stroke of
another ball; and recent philosophy leads us to look upon all motions
and changes, as but so many manifestations of prior existing energy.
In all probability there is no creation of energy and no destruction,
so that as regards both mechanical and molecular changes, the cause is
really the manifestation of existing energy. In the same way I see not
why the prior existence of matter is not also a cause as regards its
subsequent existence. All science tends to show us that the existence
of the universe in a particular state at one moment, is the condition
of its existence at the next moment, in an apparently different
state. When we analyse the meaning which we can attribute to the word
*cause*, it amounts to the existence of suitable portions of matter
endowed with suitable quantities of energy. If we may accept Horne
Tooke’s assertion, *cause* has etymologically the meaning of *thing
before*. Though, indeed, the origin of the word is very obscure, its
derivatives, the Italian *cosa*, and the French *chose*, mean simply
*thing*. In the German equivalent *ursache*, we have plainly the
original meaning of *thing before*, the *sache* denoting “interesting
or important object,” the English *sake*, and *ur* being the equivalent
of the English *ere*, *before*. We abandon, then, both etymology and
philosophy, when we attribute to the *laws of causation* any meaning
beyond that of the *conditions* under which an event may be expected to
happen, according to our observation of the previous course of nature.

I have no objection to use the words cause and causation, provided they
are never allowed to lead us to imagine that our knowledge of nature
can attain to certainty. I repeat that if a cause is an invariable
and necessary condition of an event, we can never know certainly
whether the cause exists or not. To us, then, a cause is not to be
distinguished from the group of positive or negative conditions which,
with more or less probability, precede an event. In this sense, there
is no particular difference between knowledge of causes and our general
knowledge of the succession of combinations, in which the phenomena of
nature are presented to us, or found to occur in experimental inquiry.


*Distinction of Inductive and Deductive Results.*

We must carefully avoid confusing together inductive investigations
which terminate in the establishment of general laws, and those which
seem to lead directly to the knowledge of future particular events.
That process only can be called induction which gives general laws,
and it is by the subsequent employment of deduction that we anticipate
particular events. If the observation of a number of cases shows that
alloys of metals fuse at lower temperatures than their constituent
metals, I may with more or less probability draw a general inference
to that effect, and may thence deductively ascertain the probability
that the next alloy examined will fuse at a lower temperature than
its constituents. It has been asserted, indeed, by Mill,[133] and
partially admitted by Mr. Fowler,[134] that we can argue directly from
case to case, so that what is true of some alloys will be true of the
next. Professor Bain has adopted the same view of reasoning. He thinks
that Mill has extricated us from the dead lock of the syllogism and
effected a total revolution in logic. He holds that reasoning from
particulars to particulars is not only the usual, the most obvious and
the most ready method, but that it is the type of reasoning which best
discloses the real process.[135] Doubtless, this is the usual result of
our reasoning, regard being had to degrees of probability; but these
logicians fail entirely to give any explanation of the process by which
we get from case to case.

  [133] *System of Logic*, bk. II. chap, iii.

  [134] *Inductive Logic*, pp. 13, 14.

  [135] Bain, *Deductive Logic*, pp. 208, 209.

It may be allowed that the knowledge of future particular events is
the main purpose of our investigations, and if there were any process
of thought by which we could pass directly from event to event without
ascending into general truths, this method would be sufficient, and
certainly the briefest. It is true, also, that the laws of mental
association lead the mind always to expect the like again in apparently
like circumstances, and even animals of very low intelligence must
have some trace of such powers of association, serving to guide them
more or less correctly, in the absence of true reasoning faculties.
But it is the purpose of logic, according to Mill, to ascertain
whether inferences have been correctly drawn, rather than to discover
them.[136] Even if we can, then, by habit, association, or any rude
process of inference, infer the future directly from the past, it is
the work of logic to analyse the conditions on which the correctness
of this inference depends. Even Mill would admit that such analysis
involves the consideration of general truths,[137] and in this, as in
several other important points, we might controvert Mill’s own views
by his own statements. It seems to me undesirable in a systematic work
like this to enter into controversy at any length, or to attempt to
refute the views of other logicians. But I shall feel bound to state,
in a separate publication, my very deliberate opinion that many of
Mill’s innovations in logical science, and especially his doctrine of
reasoning from particulars to particulars, are entirely groundless and
false.

  [136] *System of Logic.* Introduction, § 4. Fifth ed. pp. 8, 9.

  [137] Ibid. bk. II. chap. iii. § 5, pp. 225, &c.


*The Grounds of Inductive Inference.*

I hold that in all cases of inductive inference we must invent
hypotheses, until we fall upon some hypothesis which yields deductive
results in accordance with experience. Such accordance renders the
chosen hypothesis more or less probable, and we may then deduce, with
some degree of likelihood, the nature of our future experience, on the
assumption that no arbitrary change takes place in the conditions of
nature. We can only argue from the past to the future, on the general
principle set forth in this work, that what is true of a thing will
be true of the like. So far then as one object or event differs from
another, all inference is impossible, particulars as particulars can
no more make an inference than grains of sand can make a rope. We
must always rise to something which is general or same in the cases,
and assuming that sameness to be extended to new cases we learn their
nature. Hearing a clock tick five thousand times without exception or
variation, we adopt the very probable hypothesis that there is some
invariably acting machine which produces those uniform sounds, and
which will, in the absence of change, go on producing them. Meeting
twenty times with a bright yellow ductile substance, and finding it
always to be very heavy and incorrodible, I infer that there was some
natural condition which tended in the creation of things to associate
these properties together, and I expect to find them associated in the
next instance. But there always is the possibility that some unknown
change may take place between past and future cases. The clock may run
down, or be subject to a hundred accidents altering its condition.
There is no reason in the nature of things, so far as known to us, why
yellow colour, ductility, high specific gravity, and incorrodibility,
should always be associated together, and in other cases, if not in
this, men’s expectations have been deceived. Our inferences, therefore,
always retain more or less of a hypothetical character, and are so far
open to doubt. Only in proportion as our induction approximates to the
character of perfect induction, does it approximate to certainty. The
amount of uncertainty corresponds to the probability that other objects
than those examined may exist and falsity our inferences; the amount
of probability corresponds to the amount of information yielded by our
examination; and the theory of probability will be needed to prevent us
from over-estimating or under-estimating the knowledge we possess.


*Illustrations of the Inductive Process.*

To illustrate the passage from the known to the apparently unknown, let
us suppose that the phenomena under investigation consist of numbers,
and that the following six numbers being exhibited to us, we are
required to infer the character of the next in the series:--

  5, 15, 35, 45, 65, 95.

The question first of all arises, How may we describe this series of
numbers? What is uniformly true of them? The reader cannot fail to
perceive at the first glance that they all end in five, and the problem
is, from the properties of these six numbers, to infer the properties
of the next number ending in five. If we test their properties by the
process of perfect induction, we soon perceive that they have another
common property, namely that of being *divisible by five without
remainder*. May we then assert that the next number ending in five is
also divisible by five, and, if so, upon what grounds? Or extending
the question, Is every number ending in five divisible by five? Does
it follow that because six numbers obey a supposed law, therefore
376,685,975 or any other number, however large, obeys the law? I answer
*certainly not*. The law in question is undoubtedly true; but its truth
is not proved by any finite number of examples. All that these six
numbers can do is to suggest to my mind the possible existence of such
a law; and I then ascertain its truth, by proving deductively from the
rules of decimal numeration, that any number ending in five must be
made up of multiples of five, and must therefore be itself a multiple.

To make this more plain, let the reader now examine the numbers--

  7, 17, 37, 47, 67, 97.

They all end in 7 instead of 5, and though not at equal intervals, the
intervals are the same as in the previous case. After consideration,
the reader will perceive that these numbers all agree in being *prime
numbers*, or multiples of unity only. May we then infer that the next,
or any other number ending in 7, is a prime number? Clearly not, for
on trial we find that 27, 57, 117 are not primes. Six instances,
then, treated empirically, lead us to a true and universal law in one
case, and mislead us in another case. We ought, in fact, to have no
confidence in any law until we have treated it deductively, and have
shown that from the conditions supposed the results expected must
ensue. No one can show from the principles of number, that numbers
ending in 7 should be primes.

From the history of the theory of numbers some good examples of false
induction can be adduced. Taking the following series of prime numbers,

  41, 43, 47, 53, 61, 71, 83, 97, 113, 131, 151, &c.,

it will be found that they all agree in being values of the general
expression *x*^{2} + *x* + 41, putting for *x* in succession the
values, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, &c. We seem always to obtain a prime number, and
the induction is apparently strong, to the effect that this expression
always will give primes. Yet a few more trials disprove this false
conclusion. Put *x* = 40, and we obtain 40 × 40 + 40 + 41, or 41 × 41.
Such a failure could never have happened, had we shown any deductive
reason why *x*^{2} + *x* + 41 should give primes.

There can be no doubt that what here happens with forty instances,
might happen with forty thousand or forty million instances. An
apparent law never once failing up to a certain point may then suddenly
break down, so that inductive reasoning, as it has been described by
some writers, can give no sure knowledge of what is to come. Babbage
pointed out, in his Ninth Bridgewater Treatise, that a machine could
be constructed to give a perfectly regular series of numbers through
a vast series of steps, and yet to break the law of progression
suddenly at any required point. No number of particular cases as
particulars enables us to pass by inference to any new case. It is
hardly needful to inquire here what can be inferred from an infinite
series of facts, because they are never practically within our power;
but we may unhesitatingly accept the conclusion, that no finite number
of instances can ever prove a general law, or can give us certain
knowledge of even one other instance.

General mathematical theorems have indeed been discovered by the
observation of particular cases, and may again be so discovered. We
have Newton’s own statement, to the effect that he was thus led to
the all-important Binomial Theorem, the basis of the whole structure
of mathematical analysis. Speaking of a certain series of terms,
expressing the area of a circle or hyperbola, he says: “I reflected
that the denominators were in arithmetical progression; so that
only the numerical co-efficients of the numerators remained to be
investigated. But these, in the alternate areas, were the figures of
the powers of the number eleven, namely 11^{0}, 11^{1}, 11^{2}, 11^{3},
11^{4}; that is, in the first 1; in the second 1, 1; in the third 1,
2, 1; in the fourth 1, 3, 3, 1; in the fifth 1, 4, 6, 4, 1.[138] I
inquired, therefore, in what manner all the remaining figures could
be found from the first two; and I found that if the first figure be
called *m*, all the rest could be found by the continual multiplication
of the terms of the formula

  ((*m* - 0)/1) × ((*m* - 1)/2) × ((*m* - 2)/3) ×
  ((*m* - 3)/4) × &c.”[139]

  [138] These are the figurate numbers considered in pages 183, 187, &c.

  [139] *Commercium Epistolicum.* *Epistola ad Oldenburgum*, Oct. 24,
  1676. Horsley’s *Works of Newton*, vol. iv. p. 541. See De Morgan in
  *Penny Cyclopædia*, art. “Binomial Theorem,” p. 412.

It is pretty evident, from this most interesting statement, that
Newton, having simply observed the succession of the numbers, tried
various formulæ until he found one which agreed with them all. He
was so little satisfied with this process, however, that he verified
particular results of his new theorem by comparison with the results
of common multiplication, and the rule for the extraction of the
square root. Newton, in fact, gave no demonstration of his theorem;
and the greatest mathematicians of the last century, James Bernoulli,
Maclaurin, Landen, Euler, Lagrange, &c., occupied themselves with
discovering a conclusive method of deductive proof.

There can be no doubt that in geometry also discoveries have been
suggested by direct observation. Many of the now trivial propositions
of Euclid’s Elements were probably thus discovered, by the ancient
Greek geometers; and we have pretty clear evidence of this in the
Commentaries of Proclus.[140] Galileo was the first to examine the
remarkable properties of the cycloid, the curve described by a point in
the circumference of a wheel rolling on a plane. By direct observation
he ascertained that the area of the curve is apparently three times
that of the generating circle or wheel, but he was unable to prove this
exactly, or to verify it by strict geometrical reasoning. Sir George
Airy has recorded a curious case, in which he fell accidentally by
trial on a new geometrical property of the sphere.[141] But discovery
in such cases means nothing more than suggestion, and it is always by
pure deduction that the general law is really established. As Proclus
puts it, *we must pass from sense to consideration*.

  [140] Bk. ii. chap. iv.

  [141] *Philosophical Transactions* (1866), vol. 146, p. 334.

[Illustration]

Given, for instance, the series of figures in the accompanying diagram,
measurement will show that the curved lines approximate to semicircles,
and the rectilinear figures to right-angled triangles. These figures
may seem to suggest to the mind the general law that angles inscribed
in semicircles are right angles; but no number of instances, and no
possible accuracy of measurement would really establish the truth of
that general law. Availing ourselves of the suggestion furnished by
the figures, we can only investigate deductively the consequences
which flow from the definition of a circle, until we discover among
them the property of containing right angles. Persons have thought
that they had discovered a method of trisecting angles by plane
geometrical construction, because a certain complex arrangement of
lines and circles had appeared to trisect an angle in every case tried
by them, and they inferred, by a supposed act of induction, that it
would succeed in all other cases. De Morgan has recorded a proposed
mode of trisecting the angle which could not be discriminated by the
senses from a true general solution, except when it was applied to
very obtuse angles.[142] In all such cases, it has always turned out
either that the angle was not trisected at all, or that only certain
particular angles could be thus trisected. The trisectors were misled
by some apparent or special coincidence, and only deductive proof could
establish the truth and generality of the result. In this particular
case, deductive proof shows that the problem attempted is impossible,
and that angles generally cannot be trisected by common geometrical
methods.

  [142] *Budget of Paradoxes*, p. 257.


*Geometrical Reasoning.*

This view of the matter is strongly supported by the further
consideration of geometrical reasoning. No skill and care could ever
enable us to verify absolutely any one geometrical proposition.
Rousseau, in his *Emile*, tells us that we should teach a child
geometry by causing him to measure and compare figures by
superposition. While a child was yet incapable of general reasoning,
this would doubtless be an instructive exercise; but it never could
teach geometry, nor prove the truth of any one proposition. All our
figures are rude approximations, and they may happen to seem unequal
when they should be equal, and equal when they should be unequal.
Moreover figures may from chance be equal in case after case, and yet
there may be no general reason why they should be so. The results of
deductive geometrical reasoning are absolutely certain, and are either
exactly true or capable of being carried to any required degree of
approximation. In a perfect triangle, the angles must be equal to one
half-revolution precisely; even an infinitesimal divergence would be
impossible; and I believe with equal confidence, that however many are
the angles of a figure, provided there are no re-entrant angles, the
sum of the angles will be precisely and absolutely equal to twice as
many right-angles as the figure has sides, less by four right-angles.
In such cases, the deductive proof is absolute and complete; empirical
verification can at the most guard against accidental oversights.

There is a second class of geometrical truths which can only be
proved by approximation; but, as the mind sees no reason why that
approximation should not always go on, we arrive at complete
conviction. We thus learn that the surface of a sphere is equal exactly
to two-thirds of the whole surface of the circumscribing cylinder, or
to four times the area of the generating circle. The area of a parabola
is exactly two-thirds of that of the circumscribing parallelogram.
The area of the cycloid is exactly three times that of the generating
circle. These are truths that we could never ascertain, nor even verify
by observation; for any finite amount of difference, less than what the
senses can discern, would falsify them.

There are geometrical relations again which we cannot assign
exactly, but can carry to any desirable degree of approximation. The
ratio of the circumference to the diameter of a circle is that of
3·14159265358979323846.... to 1, and the approximation may be carried
to any extent by the expenditure of sufficient labour. Mr. W. Shanks
has given the value of this natural constant, known as π, to the extent
of 707 places of decimals.[143] Some years since, I amused myself
by trying how near I could get to this ratio, by the careful use of
compasses, and I did not come nearer than 1 part in 540. We might
imagine measurements so accurately executed as to give us eight or ten
places correctly. But the power of the hands and senses must soon
stop, whereas the mental powers of deductive reasoning can proceed
to an unlimited degree of approximation. Geometrical truths, then,
are incapable of verification; and, if so, they cannot even be learnt
by observation. How can I have learnt by observation a proposition
of which I cannot even prove the truth by observation, when I am in
possession of it? All that observation or empirical trial can do is
to suggest propositions, of which the truth may afterwards be proved
deductively.

  [143] *Proceedings of the Royal Society* (1872–3), vol. xxi. p. 319.

If Viviani’s story is to be believed, Galileo endeavoured to satisfy
himself about the area of the cycloid by cutting out several large
cycloids in pasteboard, and then comparing the areas of the curve and
the generating circle by weighing them. In every trial the curve seemed
to be rather less than three times the circle, so that Galileo, we are
told, began to suspect that the ratio was not precisely 3 to 1. It is
quite clear, however, that no process of weighing or measuring could
ever prove truths like these, and it remained for Torricelli to show
what his master Galileo had only guessed at.[144]

  [144] *Life of Galileo*, Society for the Diffusion of Useful
  Knowledge, p. 102.

Much has been said about the peculiar certainty of mathematical
reasoning, but it is only certainty of deductive reasoning, and equal
certainty attaches to all correct logical deduction. If a triangle be
right-angled, the square on the hypothenuse will undoubtedly equal the
sum of the two squares on the other sides; but I can never be sure that
a triangle is right-angled: so I can be certain that nitric acid will
not dissolve gold, provided I know that the substances employed really
correspond to those on which I tried the experiment previously. Here is
like certainty of inference, and like doubt as to the facts.


*Discrimination of Certainty and Probability.*

We can never recur too often to the truth that our knowledge of the
laws and future events of the external world is only probable. The mind
itself is quite capable of possessing certain knowledge, and it is well
to discriminate carefully between what we can and cannot know with
certainty. In the first place, whatever feeling is actually present to
the mind is certainly known to that mind. If I see blue sky, I may be
quite sure that I do experience the sensation of blueness. Whatever
I do feel, I do feel beyond all doubt. We are indeed very likely to
confuse what we really feel with what we are inclined to associate with
it, or infer inductively from it; but the whole of our consciousness,
as far as it is the result of pure intuition and free from inference,
is certain knowledge beyond all doubt.

In the second place, we may have certainty of inference; the
fundamental laws of thought, and the rule of substitution (p. 9),
are certainly true; and if my senses could inform me that A was
indistinguishable in colour from B, and B from C, then I should be
equally certain that A was indistinguishable from C. In short, whatever
truth there is in the premises, I can certainly embody in their correct
logical result. But the certainty generally assumes a hypothetical
character. I never can be quite sure that two colours are exactly
alike, that two magnitudes are exactly equal, or that two bodies
whatsoever are identical even in their apparent qualities. Almost all
our judgments involve quantitative relations, and, as will be shown in
succeeding chapters, we can never attain exactness and certainty where
continuous quantity enters. Judgments concerning discontinuous quantity
or numbers, however, allow of certainty; I may establish beyond doubt,
for instance, that the difference of the squares of 17 and 13 is the
product of 17 + 13 and 17 - 13, and is therefore 30 × 4, or 120.

Inferences which we draw concerning natural objects are never certain
except in a hypothetical point of view. It might seem to be certain
that iron is magnetic, or that gold is incapable of solution in
nitric acid; but, if we carefully investigate the meanings of these
statements, they will be found to involve no certainty but that of
consciousness and that of hypothetical inference. For what do I mean
by iron or gold? If I choose a remarkable piece of yellow substance,
call it gold, and then immerse it in a liquid which I call nitric acid,
and find that there is no change called solution, then consciousness
has certainly informed me that, with my meaning of the terms, “Gold is
insoluble in nitric acid.” I may further be certain of something else;
for if this gold and nitric acid remain what they were, I may be sure
there will be no solution on again trying the experiment. If I take
other portions of gold and nitric acid, and am sure that they really
are identical in properties with the former portions, I can be certain
that there will be no solution. But at this point my knowledge becomes
purely hypothetical; for how can I be sure without trial that the gold
and acid are really identical in nature with what I formerly called
gold and nitric acid. How do I know gold when I see it? If I judge by
the apparent qualities--colour, ductility, specific gravity, &c., I
may be misled, because there may always exist a substance which to the
colour, ductility, specific gravity, and other specified qualities,
joins others which we do not expect. Similarly, if iron is magnetic,
as shown by an experiment with objects answering to those names, then
all iron is magnetic, meaning all pieces of matter identical with my
assumed piece. But in trying to identify iron, I am always open to
mistake. Nor is this liability to mistake a matter of speculation
only.[145]

  [145] Professor Bowen has excellently stated this view. *Treatise on
  Logic.* Cambridge, U.S.A., 1866, p. 354.

The history of chemistry shows that the most confident inferences may
have been falsified by the confusion of one substance with another.
Thus strontia was never discriminated from baryta until Klaproth
and Haüy detected differences between some of their properties.
Accordingly chemists must often have inferred concerning strontia what
was only true of baryta, and *vice versâ*. There is now no doubt that
the recently discovered substances, cæsium and rubidium, were long
mistaken for potassium.[146] Other elements have often been confused
together--for instance, tantalum and niobium; sulphur and selenium;
cerium, lanthanum, and didymium; yttrium and erbium.

  [146] Roscoe’s *Spectrum Analysis*, 1st edit., p. 98.

Even the best known laws of physical science do not exclude false
inference. No law of nature has been better established than that of
universal gravitation, and we believe with the utmost confidence that
any body capable of affecting the senses will attract other bodies,
and fall to the earth if not prevented. Euler remarks that, although
he had never made trial of the stones which compose the church of
Magdeburg, yet he had not the least doubt that all of them were heavy,
and would fall if unsupported. But he adds, that it would be extremely
difficult to give any satisfactory explanation of this confident
belief.[147] The fact is, that the belief ought not to amount to
certainty until the experiment has been tried, and in the meantime a
slight amount of uncertainty enters, because we cannot be sure that
the stones of the Magdeburg Church resemble other stones in all their
properties.

  [147] Euler’s *Letters to a German Princess*, translated by Hunter.
  2nd ed., vol. ii. pp. 17, 18.

In like manner, not one of the inductive truths which men have
established, or think they have established, is really safe from
exception or reversal. Lavoisier, when laying the foundations of
chemistry, met with so many instances tending to show the existence
of oxygen in all acids, that he adopted a general conclusion to that
effect, and devised the name oxygen accordingly. He entertained no
appreciable doubt that the acid existing in sea salt also contained
oxygen;[148] yet subsequent experience falsified his expectations. This
instance refers to a science in its infancy, speaking relatively to
the possible achievements of men. But all sciences are and ever will
remain in their infancy, relatively to the extent and complexity of
the universe which they undertake to investigate. Euler expresses no
more than the truth when he says that it would be impossible to fix
on any one thing really existing, of which we could have so perfect
a knowledge as to put us beyond the reach of mistake.[149] We may be
quite certain that a comet will go on moving in a similar path *if*
all circumstances remain the same as before; but if we leave out this
extensive qualification, our predictions will always be subject to the
chance of falsification by some unexpected event, such as the division
of Biela’s comet or the interference of an unknown gravitating body.

  [148] Lavoisier’s *Chemistry*, translated by Kerr. 3rd ed., pp. 114,
  121, 123.

  [149] Euler’s *Letters*, vol. ii. p. 21.

Inductive inference might attain to certainty if our knowledge of the
agents existing throughout the universe were complete, and if we were
at the same time certain that the same Power which created the universe
would allow it to proceed without arbitrary change. There is always
a possibility of causes being in existence without our knowledge,
and these may at any moment produce an unexpected effect. Even when
by the theory of probabilities we succeed in forming some notion of
the comparative confidence with which we should receive inductive
results, it yet appears to me that we must make an assumption. Events
come out like balls from the vast ballot-box of nature, and close
observation will enable us to form some notion, as we shall see in the
next chapter, of the contents of that ballot-box. But we must still
assume that, between the time of an observation and that to which our
inferences relate, no change in the ballot-box has been made.




CHAPTER XII.

THE INDUCTIVE OR INVERSE APPLICATION OF THE THEORY OF PROBABILITY.


We have hitherto considered the theory of probability only in its
simple deductive employment, in which it enables us to determine
from given conditions the probable character of events happening
under those conditions. But as deductive reasoning when inversely
applied constitutes the process of induction, so the calculation of
probabilities may be inversely applied; from the known character
of certain events we may argue backwards to the probability of a
certain law or condition governing those events. Having satisfactorily
accomplished this work, we may indeed calculate forwards to the
probable character of future events happening under the same
conditions; but this part of the process is a direct use of deductive
reasoning (p. 226).

Now it is highly instructive to find that whether the theory of
probability be deductively or inductively applied, the calculation is
always performed according to the principles and rules of deduction.
The probability that an event has a particular condition entirely
depends upon the probability that if the condition existed the event
would follow. If we take up a pack of common playing cards, and observe
that they are arranged in perfect numerical order, we conclude beyond
all reasonable doubt that they have been thus intentionally arranged
by some person acquainted with the usual order of sequence. This
conclusion is quite irresistible, and rightly so; for there are but
two suppositions which we can make as to the reason of the cards being
in that particular order:--

1. They may have been intentionally arranged by some one who would
probably prefer the numerical order.

2. They may have fallen into that order by chance, that is, by some
series of conditions which, being unknown to us, cannot be known to
lead by preference to the particular order in question.

The latter supposition is by no means absurd, for any one order is as
likely as any other when there is no preponderating tendency. But we
can readily calculate by the doctrine of permutations the probability
that fifty-two objects would fall by chance into any one particular
order. Fifty-two objects can be arranged in 52 × 51 × ... × 3 × 2 × 1
or about 8066 × (10)^{64} possible orders, the number obtained
requiring 68 places of figures for its full expression. Hence it is
excessively unlikely that anyone should ever meet with a pack of cards
arranged in perfect order by accident. If we do meet with a pack so
arranged, we inevitably adopt the other supposition, that some person,
having reasons for preferring that special order, has thus put them
together.

We know that of the immense number of possible orders the numerical
order is the most remarkable; it is useful as proving the perfect
constitution of the pack, and it is the intentional result of certain
games. At any rate, the probability that intention should produce that
order is incomparably greater than the probability that chance should
produce it; and as a certain pack exists in that order, we rightly
prefer the supposition which most probably leads to the observed result.

By a similar mode of reasoning we every day arrive, and validly arrive,
at conclusions approximating to certainty. Whenever we observe a
perfect resemblance between two objects, as, for instance, two printed
pages, two engravings, two coins, two foot-prints, we are warranted in
asserting that they proceed from the same type, the same plate, the
same pair of dies, or the same boot. And why? Because it is almost
impossible that with different types, plates, dies, or boots some
apparent distinction of form should not be produced. It is impossible
for the hand of the most skilful artist to make two objects alike, so
that mechanical repetition is the only probable explanation of exact
similarity.

We can often establish with extreme probability that one document
is copied from another. Suppose that each document contains 10,000
words, and that the same word is incorrectly spelt in each. There is
then a probability of less than 1 in 10,000 that the same mistake
should be made in each. If we meet with a second error occurring in
each document, the probability is less than 1 in 10,000 × 9999, that
two such coincidences should occur by chance, and the numbers grow
with extreme rapidity for more numerous coincidences. We cannot make
any precise calculations without taking into account the character of
the errors committed, concerning the conditions of which we have no
accurate means of estimating probabilities. Nevertheless, abundant
evidence may thus be obtained as to the derivation of documents from
each other. In the examination of many sets of logarithmic tables, six
remarkable errors were found to be present in all but two, and it was
proved that tables printed at Paris, Berlin, Florence, Avignon, and
even in China, besides thirteen sets printed in England between the
years 1633 and 1822, were derived directly or indirectly from some
common source.[150] With a certain amount of labour, it is possible
to establish beyond reasonable doubt the relationship or genealogy of
any number of copies of one document, proceeding possibly from parent
copies now lost. The relations between the manuscripts of the New
Testament have been elaborately investigated in this manner, and the
same work has been performed for many classical writings, especially by
German scholars.

  [150] Lardner, *Edinburgh Review*, July 1834, p. 277.


*Principle of the Inverse Method.*

The inverse application of the rules of probability entirely depends
upon a proposition which may be thus stated, nearly in the words of
Laplace.[151] *If an event can be produced by any one of a certain
number of different causes, all equally probable à priori, the
probabilities of the existence of these causes as inferred from the
event, are proportional to the probabilities of the event as derived
from these causes.* In other words, the most probable cause of an
event which has happened is that which would most probably lead to the
event supposing the cause to exist; but all other possible causes are
also to be taken into account with probabilities proportional to the
probability that the event would happen if the cause existed. Suppose,
to fix our ideas clearly, that E is the event, and C_{1} C_{2} C_{3}
are the three only conceivable causes. If C_{1} exist, the probability
is *p*_{1} that E would follow; if C_{2} or C_{3} exist, the like
probabilities are respectively *p*_{2} and *p*_{3}. Then as *p*_{1}
is to *p*_{2}, so is the probability of C_{1} being the actual cause
to the probability of C_{2} being it; and, similarly, as *p*_{2} is
to *p*_{3}, so is the probability of C_{2} being the actual cause to
the probability of C_{3} being it. By a simple mathematical process we
arrive at the conclusion that the actual probability of C_{1} being the
cause is

  *p*_{1}/(*p*_{1} + *p*_{2} + *p*_{3});

  [151] *Mémoires par divers Savans*, tom. vi.; quoted by Todhunter in
  his *History of the Theory of Probability*, p. 458.

and the similar probabilities of the existence of C_{2} and C_{3} are,

  *p*_{2}/(*p*_{1} + *p*_{2} + *p*_{3}) and
  *p*_{3}/(*p*_{1} + *p*_{2} + *p*_{3}).

The sum of these three fractions amounts to unity, which correctly
expresses the certainty that one cause or other must be in operation.

We may thus state the result in general language. *If it is certain
that one or other of the supposed causes exists, the probability that
any one does exist is the probability that if it exists the event
happens, divided by the sum of all the similar probabilities.* There
may seem to be an intricacy in this subject which may prove distasteful
to some readers; but this intricacy is essential to the subject in
hand. No one can possibly understand the principles of inductive
reasoning, unless he will take the trouble to master the meaning of
this rule, by which we recede from an event to the probability of each
of its possible causes.

This rule or principle of the indirect method is that which common
sense leads us to adopt almost instinctively, before we have any
comprehension of the principle in its general form. It is easy to see,
too, that it is the rule which will, out of a great multitude of cases,
lead us most often to the truth, since the most probable cause of an
event really means that cause which in the greatest number of cases
produces the event. Donkin and Boole have given demonstrations of this
principle, but the one most easy to comprehend is that of Poisson.
He imagines each possible cause of an event to be represented by a
distinct ballot-box, containing black and white balls, in such a ratio
that the probability of a white ball being drawn is equal to that of
the event happening. He further supposes that each box, as is possible,
contains the same total number of balls, black and white; then, mixing
all the contents of the boxes together, he shows that if a white ball
be drawn from the aggregate ballot-box thus formed, the probability
that it proceeded from any particular ballot-box is represented by the
number of white balls in that particular box, divided by the total
number of white balls in all the boxes. This result corresponds to that
given by the principle in question.[152]

  [152] Poisson, *Recherches sur la Probabilité des Jugements*, Paris,
  1837, pp. 82, 83.

Thus, if there be three boxes, each containing ten balls in all, and
respectively containing seven, four, and three white balls, then on
mixing all the balls together we have fourteen white ones; and if
we draw a white ball, that is if the event happens, the probability
that it came out of the first box is 7/14; which is exactly equal to
(7/10)/(7/10 + 4/10 + 3/10), the fraction given by the rule of the
Inverse Method.


*Simple Applications of the Inverse Method.*

In many cases of scientific induction we may apply the principle of the
inverse method in a simple manner. If only two, or at the most a few
hypotheses, may be made as to the origin of certain phenomena, we may
sometimes easily calculate the respective probabilities. It was thus
that Bunsen and Kirchhoff established, with a probability little short
of certainty, that iron exists in the sun. On comparing the spectra
of sunlight and of the light proceeding from the incandescent vapour
of iron, it became apparent that at least sixty bright lines in the
spectrum of iron coincided with dark lines in the sun’s spectrum. Such
coincidences could never be observed with certainty, because, even if
the lines only closely approached, the instrumental imperfections of
the spectroscope would make them apparently coincident, and if one line
came within half a millimetre of another, on the map of the spectra,
they could not be pronounced distinct. Now the average distance of the
solar lines on Kirchhoff’s map is 2 mm., and if we throw down a line,
as it were, by pure chance on such a map, the probability is about
one-half that the new line will fall within 1/2 mm. on one side or the
other of some one of the solar lines. To put it in another way, we may
suppose that each solar line, either on account of its real breadth, or
the defects of the instrument, possesses a breadth of 1/2 mm., and that
each line in the iron spectrum has a like breadth. The probability then
is just one-half that the centre of each iron line will come by chance
within 1 mm. of the centre of a solar line, so as to appear to coincide
with it. The probability of casual coincidence of each iron line with
a solar line is in like manner 1/2. Coincidence in the case of each of
the sixty iron lines is a very unlikely event if it arises casually,
for it would have a probability of only (1/2)^{60} or less than 1
in a trillion. The odds, in short, are more than a million million
millions to unity against such casual coincidence.[153] But on the
other hypothesis, that iron exists in the sun, it is highly probable
that such coincidences would be observed; it is immensely more probable
that sixty coincidences would be observed if iron existed in the sun,
than that they should arise from chance. Hence by our principle it is
immensely probable that iron does exist in the sun.

  [153] Kirchhoff’s *Researches on the Solar Spectrum*. First part,
  translated by Roscoe, pp. 18, 19.

All the other interesting results, given by the comparison of spectra,
rest upon the same principle of probability. The almost complete
coincidence between the spectra of solar, lunar, and planetary light
renders it practically certain that the light is all of solar origin,
and is reflected from the surfaces of the moon and planets, suffering
only slight alteration from the atmospheres of some of the planets.
A fresh confirmation of the truth of the Copernican theory is thus
furnished.

Herschel proved in this way the connection between the direction of the
oblique faces of quartz crystals, and the direction in which the same
crystals rotate the plane of polarisation of light. For if it is found
in a second crystal that the relation is the same as in the first, the
probability of this happening by chance is 1/2; the probability that
in another crystal also the direction will be the same is 1/4, and so
on. The probability that in *n* + 1 crystals there would be casual
agreement of direction is the nth power of 1/2. Thus, if in examining
fourteen crystals the same relation of the two phenomena is discovered
in each, the odds that it proceeds from uniform conditions are more
than 8000 to 1.[154] Since the first observations on this subject were
made in 1820, no exceptions have been observed, so that the probability
of invariable connection is incalculably great.

  [154] *Edinburgh Review*, No. 185, vol. xcii. July 1850, p. 32;
  Herschel’s *Essays*, p. 421; *Transactions of the Cambridge
  Philosophical Society*, vol. i. p. 43.

It is exceedingly probable that the ancient Egyptians had exactly
recorded the eclipses occurring during long periods of time, for
Diogenes Laertius mentions that 373 solar and 832 lunar eclipses had
been observed, and the ratio between these numbers exactly expresses
that which would hold true of the eclipses of any long period, of say
1200 or 1300 years, as estimated on astronomical grounds. It is evident
that an agreement between small numbers, or customary numbers, such
as seven, one hundred, a myriad, &c., is much more likely to happen
from chance, and therefore gives much less presumption of dependence.
If two ancient writers spoke of the sacrifice of oxen, they would in
all probability describe it as a hecatomb, and there would be nothing
remarkable in the coincidence. But it is impossible to point out any
special reason why an old writer should select such numbers as 373 and
832, unless they had been the results of observation.

On similar grounds, we must inevitably believe in the human origin
of the flint flakes so copiously discovered of late years. For
though the accidental stroke of one stone against another may often
produce flakes, such as are occasionally found on the sea-shore, yet
when several flakes are found in close company, and each one bears
evidence, not of a single blow only, but of several successive blows,
all conducing to form a symmetrical knife-like form, the probability
of a natural and accidental origin becomes incredibly small, and the
contrary supposition, that they are the work of intelligent beings,
approximately certain.[155]

  [155] Evans’ *Ancient Stone Implements of Great Britain*. London,
  1872 (Longmans).


*The Theory of Probability in Astronomy.*

The science of astronomy, occupied with the simple relations of
distance, magnitude, and motion of the heavenly bodies, admits more
easily than almost any other science of interesting conclusions founded
on the theory of probability. More than a century ago, in 1767, Michell
showed the extreme probability of bonds connecting together systems
of stars. He was struck by the unexpected number of fixed stars
which have companions close to them. Such a conjunction might happen
casually by one star, although possibly at a great distance from the
other, happening to lie on a straight line passing near the earth.
But the probabilities are so greatly against such an optical union
happening often in the expanse of the heavens, that Michell asserted
the existence of some connection between most of the double stars.
It has since been estimated by Struve, that the odds are 9570 to 1
against any two stars of not less than the seventh magnitude falling
within the apparent distance of four seconds of each other by chance,
and yet ninety-one such cases were known when the estimation was made,
and many more cases have since been discovered. There were also four
known triple stars, and yet the odds against the appearance of any one
such conjunction are 173,524 to 1.[156] The conclusions of Michell have
been entirely verified by the discovery that many double stars are
connected by gravitation.

  [156] Herschel, *Outlines of Astronomy*, 1849, p. 565; but Todhunter,
  in his *History of the Theory of Probability*, p. 335, states that
  the calculations do not agree with those published by Struve.

Michell also investigated the probability that the six brightest stars
in the Pleiades should have come by accidents into such striking
proximity. Estimating the number of stars of equal or greater
brightness at 1500, be found the odds to be nearly 500,000 to 1 against
casual conjunction. Extending the same kind of argument to other
clusters, such as that of Præsepe, the nebula in the hilt of Perseus’
sword, he says:[157] “We may with the highest probability conclude,
the odds against the contrary opinion being many million millions
to one, that the stars are really collected together in clusters
in some places, where they form a kind of system, while in others
there are either few or none of them, to whatever cause this may be
owing, whether to their mutual gravitation, or to some other law or
appointment of the Creator.”

  [157] *Philosophical Transactions*, 1767, vol. lvii. p. 431.

The calculations of Michell have been called in question by the late
James D. Forbes,[158] and Mr. Todhunter vaguely countenances his
objections,[159] otherwise I should not have thought them of much
weight. Certainly Laplace accepts Michell’s views,[160] and if Michell
be in error it is in the methods of calculation, not in the general
validity of his reasoning and conclusions.

  [158] *Philosophical Magazine*, 3rd Series, vol. xxxvii. p. 401,
  December 1850; also August 1849.

  [159] *History*, &c., p. 334.

  [160] *Essai Philosophique*, p. 57.

Similar calculations might no doubt be applied to the peculiar drifting
motions which have been detected by Mr. R A. Proctor in some of the
constellations.[161] The odds are very greatly against any numerous
group of stars moving together in any one direction by chance. On like
grounds, there can be no doubt that the sun has a considerable proper
motion because on the average the fixed stars show a tendency to move
apparently from one point of the heavens towards that diametrically
opposite. The sun’s motion in the contrary direction would explain
this tendency, otherwise we must believe that thousands of stars
accidentally agree in their direction of motion, or are urged by some
common force from which the sun is exempt. It may be said that the
rotation of the earth is proved in like manner, because it is immensely
more probable that one body would revolve than that the sun, moon,
planets, comets, and the whole of the stars of the heavens should be
whirled round the earth daily, with a uniform motion superadded to
their own peculiar motions. This appears to be mainly the reason which
led Gilbert, one of the earliest English Copernicans, and in every
way an admirable physicist, to admit the rotation of the earth, while
Francis Bacon denied it.

  [161] *Proceedings of the Royal Society*; 20 January, 1870;
  *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. xxxix. p. 381.

In contemplating the planetary system, we are struck with the
similarity in direction of nearly all its movements. Newton remarked
upon the regularity and uniformity of these motions, and contrasted
them with the eccentricity and irregularity of the cometary
orbits.[162] Could we, in fact, look down upon the system from the
northern side, we should see all the planets moving round from west
to east, the satellites moving round their primaries, and the sun,
planets, and satellites rotating in the same direction, with some
exceptions on the verge of the system. In the time of Laplace eleven
planets were known, and the directions of rotation were known for the
sun, six planets, the satellites of Jupiter, Saturn’s ring, and one of
his satellites. Thus there were altogether 43 motions all concurring,
namely:--

  Orbital motions of eleven planets       11
  Orbital motions of eighteen satellites  18
  Axial rotations                         14
                                          --
                                          43

  [162] *Principia*, bk. ii. General scholium.

The probability that 43 motions independent of each other would
coincide by chance is the 42nd power of 1/2, so that the odds are
about 4,400,000,000,000 to 1 in favour of some common cause for the
uniformity of direction. This probability, as Laplace observes,[163]
is higher than that of many historical events which we undoubtingly
believe. In the present day, the probability is much increased by the
discovery of additional planets, and the rotation of other satellites,
and it is only slightly weakened by the fact that some of the outlying
satellites are exceptional in direction, there being considerable
evidence of an accidental disturbance in the more distant parts of the
system.

  [163] *Essai Philosophique*, p. 55. Laplace appears to count the
  rings of Saturn as giving two independent movements.

Hardly less remarkable than the uniform direction of motion is the
near approximation of the orbits of the planets to a common plane.
Daniel Bernoulli roughly estimated the probability of such an agreement
arising from accident as 1 ÷ (12)^{6} the greatest inclination of any
orbit to the sun’s equator being 1-12th part of a quadrant. Laplace
devoted to this subject some of his most ingenious investigations. He
found the probability that the sum of the inclinations of the planetary
orbits would not exceed by accident the actual amount (·914187
of a right angle for the ten planets known in 1801) to be (1/10)!
(·914187)^{10} or about ·00000011235. This probability may be combined
with that derived from the direction of motion, and it then becomes
immensely probable that the constitution of the planetary system arose
out of uniform conditions, or, as we say, from some common cause.[164]

  [164] Lubbock, *Essay on Probability*, p. 14. De Morgan, *Encyc.
  Metrop.* art. *Probability*, p. 412. Todhunter’s *History of the
  Theory of Probability*, p. 543. Concerning the objections raised to
  these conclusions by Boole, see the *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th
  Series, vol. ii. p. 98. Boole’s *Laws of Thought*, pp. 364–375.

If the same kind of calculation be applied to the orbits of comets,
the result is very different.[165] Of the orbits which have been
determined 48·9 per cent. only are direct or in the same direction as
the planetary motions.[166] Hence it becomes apparent that comets do
not properly belong to the solar system, and it is probable that they
are stray portions of nebulous matter which have accidentally become
attached to the system by the attractive powers of the sun or Jupiter.

  [165] Laplace, *Essai Philosophique*, pp. 55, 56.

  [166] Chambers’ *Astronomy*, 2nd ed. pp. 346–49.


*The General Inverse Problem.*

In the instances described in the preceding sections, we have been
occupied in receding from the occurrence of certain similar events to
the probability that there must have been a condition or cause for
such events. We have found that the theory of probability, although
never yielding a certain result, often enables us to establish an
hypothesis beyond the reach of reasonable doubt. There is, however,
another method of applying the theory, which possesses for us even
greater interest, because it illustrates, in the most complete manner,
the theory of inference adopted in this work, which theory indeed it
suggested. The problem to be solved is as follows:--

*An event having happened a certain number of times, and failed a
certain number of times, required the probability that it will happen
any given number of times in the future under the same circumstances.*

All the *larger* planets hitherto discovered move in one direction
round the sun; what is the probability that, if a new planet exterior
to Neptune be discovered, it will move in the same direction? All
known permanent gases, except chlorine, are colourless; what is the
probability that, if some new permanent gas should be discovered, it
will be colourless? In the general solution of this problem, we wish to
infer the future happening of any event from the number of times that
it has already been observed to happen. Now, it is very instructive to
find that there is no known process by which we can pass directly from
the data to the conclusion. It is always requisite to recede from the
data to the probability of some hypothesis, and to make that hypothesis
the ground of our inference concerning future events. Mathematicians,
in fact, make every hypothesis which is applicable to the question in
hand; they then calculate, by the inverse method, the probability of
every such hypothesis according to the data, and the probability that
if each hypothesis be true, the required future event will happen. The
total probability that the event will happen is the sum of the separate
probabilities contributed by each distinct hypothesis.

To illustrate more precisely the method of solving the problem, it
is desirable to adopt some concrete mode of representation, and the
ballot-box, so often employed by mathematicians, will best serve
our purpose. Let the happening of any event be represented by the
drawing of a white ball from a ballot-box, while the failure of an
event is represented by the drawing of a black ball. Now, in the
inductive problem we are supposed to be ignorant of the contents of
the ballot-box, and are required to ground all our inferences on our
experience of those contents as shown in successive drawings. Rude
common sense would guide us nearly to a true conclusion. Thus, if we
had drawn twenty balls one after another, replacing the ball after each
drawing, and the ball had in each case proved to be white, we should
believe that there was a considerable preponderance of white balls in
the urn, and a probability in favour of drawing a white ball on the
next occasion. Though we had drawn white balls for thousands of times
without fail, it would still be possible that some black balls lurked
in the urn and would at last appear, so that our inferences could never
be certain. On the other hand, if black balls came at intervals, we
should expect that after a certain number of trials the black balls
would appear again from time to time with somewhat the same frequency.

The mathematical solution of the question consists in little more
than a close analysis of the mode in which our common sense proceeds.
If twenty white balls have been drawn and no black ball, my common
sense tells me that any hypothesis which makes the black balls in
the urn considerable compared with the white ones is improbable; a
preponderance of white balls is a more probable hypothesis, and as a
deduction from this more probable hypothesis, I expect a recurrence
of white balls. The mathematician merely reduces this process of
thought to exact numbers. Taking, for instance, the hypothesis that
there are 99 white and one black ball in the urn, he can calculate the
probability that 20 white balls would be drawn in succession in those
circumstances; he thus forms a definite estimate of the probability
of this hypothesis, and knowing at the same time the probability of a
white ball reappearing if such be the contents of the urn, he combines
these probabilities, and obtains an exact estimate that a white ball
will recur in consequence of this hypothesis. But as this hypothesis
is only one out of many possible ones, since the ratio of white and
black balls may be 98 to 2, or 97 to 3, or 96 to 4, and so on, he has
to repeat the estimate for every such possible hypothesis. To make the
method of solving the problem perfectly evident, I will describe in the
next section a very simple case of the problem, originally devised for
the purpose by Condorcet, which was also adopted by Lacroix,[167] and
has passed into the works of De Morgan, Lubbock, and others.

  [167] *Traité élémentaire du Calcul des Probabilités*, 3rd ed.
  (1833), p. 148.


*Simple Illustration of the Inverse Problem.*

Suppose it to be known that a ballot-box contains only four black or
white balls, the ratio of black and white balls being unknown. Four
drawings having been made with replacement, and a white ball having
appeared on each occasion but one, it is required to determine the
probability that a white ball will appear next time. Now the hypotheses
which can be made as to the contents of the urn are very limited in
number, and are at most the following five:--

  4 white and 0 black balls
  3   "    "  1   "     "
  2   "    "  2   "     "
  1   "    "  3   "     "
  0   "    "  4   "     "

The actual occurrence of black and white balls in the drawings puts the
first and last hypothesis out of the question, so that we have only
three left to consider.

If the box contains three white and one black, the probability of
drawing a white each time is 3/4, and a black 1/4; so that the compound
event observed, namely, three white and one black, has the probability
3/4 × 3/4 × 3/4 × 1/4, by the rule already given (p. 204). But as it is
indifferent in what order the balls are drawn, and the black ball might
come first, second, third, or fourth, we must multiply by four, to
obtain the probability of three white and one black in any order, thus
getting 27/64.

Taking the next hypothesis of two white and two black balls
in the urn, we obtain for the same probability the quantity
1/2 × 1/2 × 1/2 × 1/2 × 4, or 16/64, and from the third hypothesis of
one white and three black we deduce likewise 1/4 × 1/4 × 1/4 × 3/4 × 4,
or 3/64. According, then, as we adopt the first, second, or third
hypothesis, the probability that the result actually noticed would
follow is 27/64, 16/64, and 3/64. Now it is certain that one or
other of these hypotheses must be the true one, and their absolute
probabilities are proportional to the probabilities that the observed
events would follow from them (pp. 242, 243). All we have to do, then,
in order to obtain the absolute probability of each hypothesis, is to
alter these fractions in a uniform ratio, so that their sum shall be
unity, the expression of certainty. Now, since 27 + 16 + 3 = 46, this
will be effected by dividing each fraction by 46, and multiplying by
64. Thus the probabilities of the first, second, and third hypotheses
are respectively--

  27/46, 16/46, 3/46.

The inductive part of the problem is completed, since we have found
that the urn most likely contains three white and one black ball, and
have assigned the exact probability of each possible supposition. But
we are now in a position to resume deductive reasoning, and infer the
probability that the next drawing will yield, say a white ball. For if
the box contains three white and one black ball, the probability of
drawing a white one is certainly 3/4; and as the probability of the box
being so constituted is 27/46, the compound probability that the box
will be so filled and will give a white ball at the next trial, is

  27/46 × 3/4 or 81/184.

Again, the probability is 16/46 that the box contains two white and two
black, and under those conditions the probability is 1/2 that a white
ball will appear; hence the probability that a white ball will appear
in consequence of that condition, is

  16/46 × 1/2 or 32/184.

From the third supposition we get in like manner the probability

  3/46 × 1/4 or 3/184.

Since one and not more than one hypothesis can be true, we may add
together these separate probabilities, and we find that

  81/184 + 32/184 + 3/184 or 116/184

is the complete probability that a white ball will be next drawn under
the conditions and data supposed.


*General Solution of the Inverse Problem.*

In the instance of the inverse method described in the last section,
the balls supposed to be in the ballot-box were few, for the purpose of
simplifying the calculation. In order that our solution may apply to
natural phenomena, we must render our hypotheses as little arbitrary
as possible. Having no *à priori* knowledge of the conditions of the
phenomena in question, there is no limit to the variety of hypotheses
which might be suggested. Mathematicians have therefore had recourse
to the most extensive suppositions which can be made, namely, that the
ballot-box contains an infinite number of balls; they have then varied
the proportion of white to black balls continuously, from the smallest
to the greatest possible proportion, and estimated the aggregate
probability which results from this comprehensive supposition.

To explain their procedure, let us imagine that, instead of an infinite
number, the ballot-box contains a large finite number of balls, say
1000. Then the number of white balls might be 1 or 2 or 3 or 4, and so
on, up to 999. Supposing that three white and one black ball have been
drawn from the urn as before, there is a certain very small probability
that this would have occurred in the case of a box containing one white
and 999 black balls; there is also a small probability that from such
a box the next ball would be white. Compound these probabilities, and
we have the probability that the next ball really will be white, in
consequence of the existence of that proportion of balls. If there be
two white and 998 black balls in the box, the probability is greater
and will increase until the balls are supposed to be in the proportion
of those drawn. Now 999 different hypotheses are possible, and the
calculation is to be made for each of these, and their aggregate taken
as the final result. It is apparent that as the number of balls in
the box is increased, the absolute probability of any one hypothesis
concerning the exact proportion of balls is decreased, but the
aggregate results of all the hypotheses will assume the character of a
wider average.

When we take the step of supposing the balls within the urn to be
infinite in number, the possible proportions of white and black balls
also become infinite, and the probability of any one proportion
actually existing is infinitely small. Hence the final result that
the next ball drawn will be white is really the sum of an infinite
number of infinitely small quantities. It might seem impossible to
calculate out a problem having an infinite number of hypotheses,
but the wonderful resources of the integral calculus enable this
to be done with far greater facility than if we supposed any large
finite number of balls, and then actually computed the results. I
will not attempt to describe the processes by which Laplace finally
accomplished the complete solution of the problem. They are to be found
described in several English works, especially De Morgan’s *Treatise
on Probabilities*, in the *Encyclopædia Metropolitana*, and Mr.
Todhunter’s *History of the Theory of Probability*. The abbreviating
power of mathematical analysis was never more strikingly shown. But
I may add that though the integral calculus is employed as a means
of summing infinitely numerous results, we in no way abandon the
principles of combinations already treated. We calculate the values of
infinitely numerous factorials, not, however, obtaining their actual
products, which would lead to an infinite number of figures, but
obtaining the final answer to the problem by devices which can only be
comprehended after study of the integral calculus.

It must be allowed that the hypothesis adopted by Laplace is in some
degree arbitrary, so that there was some opening for the doubt which
Boole has cast upon it.[168] But it may be replied, (1) that the
supposition of an infinite number of balls treated in the manner of
Laplace is less arbitrary and more comprehensive than any other that
can be suggested. (2) The result does not differ much from that
which would be obtained on the hypothesis of any large finite number
of balls. (3) The supposition leads to a series of simple formulas
which can be applied with ease in many cases, and which bear all the
appearance of truth so far as it can be independently judged by a sound
and practiced understanding.

  [168] *Laws of Thought*, pp. 368–375.


*Rules of the Inverse Method.*

By the solution of the problem, as described in the last section, we
obtain the following series of simple rules.

1. *To find the probability that an event which has not hitherto been
observed to fail will happen once more, divide the number of times the
event has been observed increased by one, by the same number increased
by two.*

If there have been *m* occasions on which a certain event might have
been observed to happen, and it has happened on all those occasions,
then the probability that it will happen on the next occasion of the
same kind (*m* + 1)/(*m* + 2). For instance, we may say that there are
nine places in the planetary system where planets might exist obeying
Bode’s law of distance, and in every place there is a planet obeying
the law more or less exactly, although no reason is known for the
coincidence. Hence the probability that the next planet beyond Neptune
will conform to the law is 10/11.

2. *To find the, probability that an event which has not hitherto
failed will not fail for a certain number of new occasions, divide the
number of times the event has happened increased by one, by the same
number increased by one and the number of times it is to happen.*

An event having happened *m* times without fail, the probability that
it will happen *n* more times is (*m* + 1)/(*m* + *n* + 1). Thus the
probability that three new planets would obey Bode’s law is 10/13; but
it must be allowed that this, as well as the previous result, would be
much weakened by the fact that Neptune can barely be said to obey the
law.

*3. An event having happened and failed a certain number of times, to
find the probability that it will happen the next time, divide the
number of times the event has happened increased by one, by the whole
number of times the event has happened or failed increased by two.*

If an event has happened *m* times and failed *n* times,
the probability that it will happen on the next occasion is
(*m* + 1)/(*m* + *n* + 2). Thus, if we assume that of the elements
discovered up to the year 1873, 50 are metallic and 14 non-metallic,
then the probability that the next element discovered will be metallic
is 51/66. Again, since of 37 metals which have been sufficiently
examined only four, namely, sodium, potassium, lanthanum, and
lithium, are of less density than water, the probability that the
next metal examined or discovered will be less dense than water is
(4 + 1)/(37 + 2) or 5/39.

We may state the results of the method in a more general manner
thus,[169]--If under given circumstances certain events A, B, C, &c.,
have happened respectively *m*, *n*, *p*, &c., times, and one or other
of these events must happen, then the probabilities of these events are
proportional to *m* + 1, *n* + 1, *p* + 1, &c., so that the probability
of A will be (*m* + 1)/(*m* + 1 + *n* + 1 + *p* + 1 + &c.) But if new
events may happen in addition to those which have been observed, we
must assign unity for the probability of such new event. The odds then
become 1 for a new event, *m* + 1 for A, *n* + 1 for B, and so on, and
the absolute probability of A is (*m* + 1)/(1 + *m* + 1 + *n* + 1 + &c.)

  [169] De Morgan’s *Essay on Probabilities*, Cabinet Cyclopædia, p. 67.

It is interesting to trace out the variations of probability according
to these rules. The first time a casual event happens it is 2 to 1
that it will happen again; if it does happen it is 3 to 1 that it
will happen a third time; and on successive occasions of the like
kind the odds become 4, 5, 6, &c., to 1. The odds of course will be
discriminated from the probabilities which are successively 2/3, 3/4,
4/5, &c. Thus on the first occasion on which a person sees a shark,
and notices that it is accompanied by a little pilot fish, the odds
are 2 to 1, or the probability 2/3, that the next shark will be so
accompanied.

When an event has happened a very great number of times, its
happening once again approaches nearly to certainty. If we suppose
the sun to have risen one thousand million times, the probability
that it will rise again, on the ground of this knowledge merely, is
(1,000,000,000 + 1)/(1,000,000,000 + 1 + 1). But then the probability
that it will continue to rise for as long a period in the future is
only (1,000,000,000 + 1)/(2,000,000,000 + 1), or almost exactly 1/2.
The probability that it will continue so rising a thousand times
as long is only about 1/1001. The lesson which we may draw from
these figures is quite that which we should adopt on other grounds,
namely, that experience never affords certain knowledge, and that
it is exceedingly improbable that events will always happen as we
observe them. Inferences pushed far beyond their data soon lose
any considerable probability. De Morgan has said,[170] “No finite
experience whatsoever can justify us in saying that the future shall
coincide with the past in all time to come, or that there is any
probability for such a conclusion.” On the other hand, we gain the
assurance that experience sufficiently extended and prolonged will
give us the knowledge of future events with an unlimited degree of
probability, provided indeed that those events are not subject to
arbitrary interference.

  [170] *Essay on Probabilities*, p. 128.

It must be clearly understood that these probabilities are only such
as arise from the mere happening of the events, irrespective of any
knowledge derived from other sources concerning those events or the
general laws of nature. All our knowledge of nature is indeed founded
in like manner upon observation, and is therefore only probable. The
law of gravitation itself is only probably true. But when a number of
different facts, observed under the most diverse circumstances, are
found to be harmonized under a supposed law of nature, the probability
of the law approximates closely to certainty. Each science rests upon
so many observed facts, and derives so much support from analogies or
connections with other sciences, that there are comparatively few cases
where our judgment of the probability of an event depends entirely
upon a few antecedent events, disconnected from the general body of
physical science.

Events, again, may often exhibit a regularity of succession or
preponderance of character, which the simple formula will not take into
account. For instance, the majority of the elements recently discovered
are metals, so that the probability of the next discovery being that
of a metal, is doubtless greater than we calculated (p. 258). At
the more distant parts of the planetary system, there are symptoms
of disturbance which would prevent our placing much reliance on any
inference from the prevailing order of the known planets to those
undiscovered ones which may possibly exist at great distances. These
and all like complications in no way invalidate the theoretic truth of
the formulas, but render their sound application much more difficult.

Erroneous objections have been raised to the theory of probability, on
the ground that we ought not to trust to our *à priori* conceptions
of what is likely to happen, but should always endeavour to obtain
precise experimental data to guide us.[171] This course, however,
is perfectly in accordance with the theory, which is our best and
only guide, whatever data we possess. We ought to be always applying
the inverse method of probabilities so as to take into account all
additional information. When we throw up a coin for the first time, we
are probably quite ignorant whether it tends more to fall head or tail
upwards, and we must therefore assume the probability of each event as
1/2. But if it shows head in the first throw, we now have very slight
experimental evidence in favour of a tendency to show head. The chance
of two heads is now slightly greater than 1/4, which it appeared to
be at first,[172] and as we go on throwing the coin time after time,
the probability of head appearing next time constantly varies in a
slight degree according to the character of our previous experience. As
Laplace remarks, we ought always to have regard to such considerations
in common life. Events when closely scrutinized will hardly ever prove
to be quite independent, and the slightest preponderance one way or
the other is some evidence of connection, and in the absence of better
evidence should be taken into account.

  [171] J. S. Mill, *System of Logic*, 5th edition, bk. iii. chap.
  xviii. § 3.

  [172] Todhunter’s *History*, pp. 472, 598.

The grand object of seeking to estimate the probability of future
events from past experience, seems to have been entertained by James
Bernoulli and De Moivre, at least such was the opinion of Condorcet;
and Bernoulli may be said to have solved one case of the problem.[173]
The English writers Bayes and Price are, however, undoubtedly the first
who put forward any distinct rules on the subject.[174] Condorcet and
several other eminent mathematicians advanced the mathematical theory
of the subject; but it was reserved to the immortal Laplace to bring
to the subject the full power of his genius, and carry the solution of
the problem almost to perfection. It is instructive to observe that a
theory which arose from petty games of chance, the rules and the very
names of which are forgotten, gradually advanced, until it embraced the
most sublime problems of science, and finally undertook to measure the
value and certainty of all our inductions.

  [173] Todhunter’s *History*, pp. 378, 379.

  [174] *Philosophical Transactions*, [1763], vol. liii. p. 370, and
  [1764], vol. liv. p. 296. Todhunter, pp. 294–300.


*Fortuitous Coincidences.*

We should have studied the theory of probability to very little
purpose, if we thought that it would furnish us with an infallible
guide. The theory itself points out the approximate certainty, that we
shall sometimes be deceived by extraordinary fortuitous coincidences.
There is no run of luck so extreme that it may not happen, and it
may happen to us, or in our time, as well as to other persons or in
other times. We may be forced by correct calculation to refer such
coincidences to a necessary cause, and yet we may be deceived. All
that the calculus of probability pretends to give, is *the result in
the long run*, as it is called, and this really means in *an infinity
of cases*. During any finite experience, however long, chances may be
against us. Nevertheless the theory is the best guide we can have. If
we always think and act according to its well-interpreted indications,
we shall have the best chance of escaping error; and if all persons,
throughout all time to come, obey the theory in like manner, they will
undoubtedly thereby reap the greatest advantage.

No rule can be given for discriminating between coincidences which
are casual and those which are the effects of law. By a fortuitous
or casual coincidence, we mean an agreement between events, which
nevertheless arise from wholly independent and different causes or
conditions, and which will not always so agree. It is a fortuitous
coincidence, if a penny thrown up repeatedly in various ways always
falls on the same side; but it would not be fortuitous if there were
any similarity in the motions of the hand, and the height of the
throw, so as to cause or tend to cause a uniform result. Now among the
infinitely numerous events, objects, or relations in the universe, it
is quite likely that we shall occasionally notice casual coincidences.
There are seven intervals in the octave, and there is nothing very
improbable in the colours of the spectrum happening to be apparently
divisible into the same or similar series of seven intervals. It is
hardly yet decided whether this apparent coincidence, with which Newton
was much struck, is well founded or not,[175] but the question will
probably be decided in the negative.

  [175] Newton’s *Opticks*, Bk. I., Part ii. Prop. 3; *Nature*, vol. i.
  p. 286.

It is certainly a casual coincidence which the ancients noticed between
the seven vowels, the seven strings of the lyre, the seven Pleiades,
and the seven chiefs at Thebes.[176] The accidents connected with the
number seven have misled the human intellect throughout the historical
period. Pythagoras imagined a connection between the seven planets and
the seven intervals of the monochord. The alchemists were never tired
of drawing inferences from the coincidence in numbers of the seven
planets and the seven metals, not to speak of the seven days of the
week.

  [176] Aristotle’s *Metaphysics*, xiii. 6. 3.

A singular circumstance was pointed out concerning the dimensions
of the earth, sun, and moon; the sun’s diameter was almost exactly
110 times as great as the earth’s diameter, while in almost exactly
the same ratio the mean distance of the earth was greater than the
sun’s diameter, and the mean distance of the moon from the earth was
greater than the moon’s diameter. The agreement was so close that it
might have proved more than casual, but its fortuitous character is
now sufficiently shown by the fact, that the coincidence ceases to be
remarkable when we adopt the amended dimensions of the planetary system.

A considerable number of the elements have atomic weights, which are
apparently exact multiples of that of hydrogen. If this be not a law to
be ultimately extended to all the elements, as supposed by Prout, it
is a most remarkable coincidence. But, as I have observed, we have no
means of absolutely discriminating accidental coincidences from those
which imply a deep producing cause. A coincidence must either be very
strong in itself, or it must be corroborated by some explanation or
connection with other laws of nature. Little attention was ever given
to the coincidence concerning the dimensions of the sun, earth, and
moon, because it was not very strong in itself, and had no apparent
connection with the principles of physical astronomy. Prout’s Law
bears more probability because it would bring the constitution of
the elements themselves in close connection with the atomic theory,
representing them as built up out of a simpler substance.

In historical and social matters, coincidences are frequently pointed
out which are due to chance, although there is always a strong popular
tendency to regard them as the work of design, or as having some hidden
meaning. If to 1794, the number of the year in which Robespierre fell,
we add the sum of its digits, the result is 1815, the year in which
Napoleon fell; the repetition of the process gives 1830 the year
in which Charles the Tenth abdicated. Again, the French Chamber of
Deputies, in 1830, consisted of 402 members, of whom 221 formed the
party called “La queue de Robespierre,” while the remainder, 181 in
number, were named “Les honnêtes gens.” If we give to each letter a
numerical value corresponding to its place in the alphabet, it will be
found that the sum of the values of the letters in each name exactly
indicates the number of the party.

A number of such coincidences, often of a very curious character,
might be adduced, and the probability against the occurrence of each
is enormously great. They must be attributed to chance, because they
cannot be shown to have the slightest connection with the general
laws of nature; but persons are often found to be greatly influenced
by such coincidences, regarding them as evidence of fatality, that
is of a system of causation governing human affairs independently of
the ordinary laws of nature. Let it be remembered that there are an
infinite number of opportunities in life for some strange coincidence
to present itself, so that it is quite to be expected that remarkable
conjunctions will sometimes happen.

In all matters of judicial evidence, we must bear in mind the probable
occurrence from time to time of unaccountable coincidences. The Roman
jurists refused for this reason to invalidate a testamentary deed, the
witnesses of which had sealed it with the same seal. For witnesses
independently using their own seals might be found to possess identical
ones by accident.[177] It is well known that circumstantial evidence of
apparently overwhelming completeness will sometimes lead to a mistaken
judgment, and as absolute certainty is never really attainable, every
court must act upon probabilities of a high amount, and in a certain
small proportion of cases they must almost of necessity condemn the
innocent victims of a remarkable conjuncture of circumstances.[178]
Popular judgments usually turn upon probabilities of far less amount,
as when the palace of Nicomedia, and even the bedchamber of Diocletian,
having been on fire twice within fifteen days, the people entirely
refused to believe that it could be the result of accident. The Romans
believed that there was fatality connected with the name of Sextus.

  “Semper sub Sextis perdita Roma fuit.”

  [177] Possunt autem omnes testes et uno annulo signare testamentum
  Quid enim si septem annuli una sculptura fuerint, secundum quod
  Pomponio visum est?--*Justinian*, ii. tit. x. 5.

  [178] See Wills on *Circumstantial Evidence*, p. 148.

The utmost precautions will not provide against all contingencies.
To avoid errors in important calculations, it is usual to have them
repeated by different computers; but a case is on record in which three
computers made exactly the same calculations of the place of a star,
and yet all did it wrong in precisely the same manner, for no apparent
reason.[179]

  [179] *Memoirs of the Royal Astronomical Society*, vol. iv. p. 290,
  quoted by Lardner, *Edinburgh Review*, July 1834, p. 278.


*Summary of the Theory of Inductive Inference.*

The theory of inductive inference stated in this and the previous
chapters, was suggested by the study of the Inverse Method of
Probability, but it also bears much resemblance to the so-called
Deductive Method described by Mill, in his celebrated *System of
Logic*. Mill’s views concerning the Deductive Method, probably form
the most original and valuable part of his treatise, and I should
have ascribed the doctrine entirely to him, had I not found that
the opinions put forward in other parts of his work are entirely
inconsistent with the theory here upheld. As this subject is the most
important and difficult one with which we have to deal, I will try to
remedy the imperfect manner in which I have treated it, by giving a
recapitulation of the views adopted.

All inductive reasoning is but the inverse application of deductive
reasoning. Being in possession of certain particular facts or events
expressed in propositions, we imagine some more general proposition
expressing the existence of a law or cause; and, deducing the
particular results of that supposed general proposition, we observe
whether they agree with the facts in question. Hypothesis is thus
always employed, consciously or unconsciously. The sole conditions to
which we need conform in framing any hypothesis is, that we both have
and exercise the power of inferring deductively from the hypothesis to
the particular results, which are to be compared with the known facts.
Thus there are but three steps in the process of induction:--

(1) Framing some hypothesis as to the character of the general law.

(2) Deducing consequences from that law.

(3) Observing whether the consequences agree with the particular facts
under consideration.

In very simple cases of inverse reasoning, hypothesis may seem
altogether needless. To take numbers again as a convenient
illustration, I have only to look at the series,

  1, 2, 4, 8, 16, 32, &c.,

to know at once that the general law is that of geometrical
progression; I need no successive trial of various hypotheses, because
I am familiar with the series, and have long since learnt from what
general formula it proceeds. In the same way a mathematician becomes
acquainted with the integrals of a number of common formulas, so
that he need not go through any process of discovery. But it is none
the less true that whenever previous reasoning does not furnish the
knowledge, hypotheses must be framed and tried (p. 124).

There naturally arise two cases, according as the nature of the
subject admits of certain or only probable deductive reasoning.
Certainty, indeed, is but a singular case of probability, and the
general principles of procedure are always the same. Nevertheless,
when certainty of inference is possible, the process is simplified.
Of several mutually inconsistent hypotheses, the results of which can
be certainly compared with fact, but one hypothesis can ultimately
be entertained. Thus in the inverse logical problem, two logically
distinct conditions could not yield the same series of possible
combinations. Accordingly, in the case of two terms we had to choose
one of six different kinds of propositions (p. 136), and in the case
of three terms, our choice lay among 192 possible distinct hypotheses
(p. 140). Natural laws, however, are often quantitative in character,
and the possible hypotheses are then infinite in variety.

When deduction is certain, comparison with fact is needed only to
assure ourselves that we have rightly selected the hypothetical
conditions. The law establishes itself, and no number of particular
verifications can add to its probability. Having once deduced from
the principles of algebra that the difference of the squares of two
numbers is equal to the product of their sum and difference, no number
of particular trials of its truth will render it more certain. On the
other hand, no finite number of particular verifications of a supposed
law will render that law certain. In short, certainty belongs only to
the deductive process, and to the teachings of direct intuition; and
as the conditions of nature are not given by intuition, we can only be
certain that we have got a correct hypothesis when, out of a limited
number conceivably possible, we select that one which alone agrees with
the facts to be explained.

In geometry and kindred branches of mathematics, deductive reasoning
is conspicuously certain, and it would often seem as if the
consideration of a single diagram yields us certain knowledge of a
general proposition. But in reality all this certainty is of a purely
hypothetical character. Doubtless if we could ascertain that a supposed
circle was a true and perfect circle, we could be certain concerning a
multitude of its geometrical properties. But geometrical figures are
physical objects, and the senses can never assure us as to their exact
forms. The figures really treated in Euclid’s *Elements* are imaginary,
and we never can verify in practice the conclusions which we draw with
certainty in inference; questions of degree and probability enter.

Passing now to subjects in which deduction is only probable, it ceases
to be possible to adopt one hypothesis to the exclusion of the others.
We must entertain at the same time all conceivable hypotheses, and
regard each with the degree of esteem proportionate to its probability.
We go through the same steps as before.

(1) We frame an hypothesis.

(2) We deduce the probability of various series of possible
consequences.

(3) We compare the consequences with the particular facts, and observe
the probability that such facts would happen under the hypothesis.

The above processes must be performed for every conceivable hypothesis,
and then the absolute probability of each will be yielded by the
principle of the inverse method (p. 242). As in the case of certainty
we accept that hypothesis which certainly gives the required results,
so now we accept as most probable that hypothesis which most probably
gives the results; but we are obliged to entertain at the same time
all other hypotheses with degrees of probability proportionate to the
probabilities that they would give the same results.

So far we have treated only of the process by which we pass from
special facts to general laws, that inverse application of deduction
which constitutes induction. But the direct employment of deduction
is often combined with the inverse. No sooner have we established
a general law, than the mind rapidly draws particular consequences
from it. In geometry we may almost seem to infer that *because* one
equilateral triangle is equiangular, therefore another is so. In
reality it is not because one is that another is, but because all
are. The geometrical conditions are perfectly general, and by what
is sometimes called *parity of reasoning* whatever is true of one
equilateral triangle, so far as it is equilateral, is true of all
equilateral triangles.

Similarly, in all other cases of inductive inference, where we seem to
pass from some particular instances to a new instance, we go through
the same process. We form an hypothesis as to the logical conditions
under which the given instances might occur; we calculate inversely
the probability of that hypothesis, and compounding this with the
probability that a new instance would proceed from the same conditions,
we gain the absolute probability of occurrence of the new instance in
virtue of this hypothesis. But as several, or many, or even an infinite
number of mutually inconsistent hypotheses may be possible, we must
repeat the calculation for each such conceivable hypothesis, and then
the complete probability of the future instance will be the sum of the
separate probabilities. The complication of this process is often very
much reduced in practice, owing to the fact that one hypothesis may be
almost certainly true, and other hypotheses, though conceivable, may be
so improbable as to be neglected without appreciable error.

When we possess no knowledge whatever of the conditions from which
the events proceed, we may be unable to form any probable hypotheses
as to their mode of origin. We have now to fall back upon the general
solution of the problem effected by Laplace, which consists in
admitting on an equal footing every conceivable ratio of favourable
and unfavourable chances for the production of the event, and then
accepting the aggregate result as the best which can be obtained. This
solution is only to be accepted in the absence of all better means,
but like other results of the calculus of probability, it comes to our
aid where knowledge is at an end and ignorance begins, and it prevents
us from over-estimating the knowledge we possess. The general results
of the solution are in accordance with common sense, namely, that
the more often an event has happened the more probable, as a general
rule, is its subsequent recurrence. With the extension of experience
this probability increases, but at the same time the probability is
slight that events will long continue to happen as they have previously
happened.

We have now pursued the theory of inductive inference, as far as
can be done with regard to simple logical or numerical relations.
The laws of nature deal with time and space, which are infinitely
divisible. As we passed from pure logic to numerical logic, so we must
now pass from questions of discontinuous, to questions of continuous
quantity, encountering fresh considerations of much difficulty. Before,
therefore, we consider how the great inductions and generalisations
of physical science illustrate the views of inductive reasoning just
explained, we must break off for a time, and review the means which we
possess of measuring and comparing magnitudes of time, space, mass,
force, momentum, energy, and the various manifestations of energy in
motion, heat, electricity, chemical change, and the other phenomena of
nature.




BOOK III.

METHODS OF MEASUREMENT.




CHAPTER XIII.

THE EXACT MEASUREMENT OF PHENOMENA.


As physical science advances, it becomes more and more accurately
quantitative. Questions of simple logical fact after a time resolve
themselves into questions of degree, time, distance, or weight. Forces
hardly suspected to exist by one generation, are clearly recognised
by the next, and precisely measured by the third generation. But
one condition of this rapid advance is the invention of suitable
instruments of measurement. We need what Francis Bacon called
*Instantiæ citantes*, or *evocantes*, methods of rendering minute
phenomena perceptible to the senses; and we also require *Instantiæ
radii* or *curriculi*, that is measuring instruments. Accordingly,
the introduction of a new instrument often forms an epoch in the
history of science. As Davy said, “Nothing tends so much to the
advancement of knowledge as the application of a new instrument. The
native intellectual powers of men in different times are not so much
the causes of the different success of their labours, as the peculiar
nature of the means and artificial resources in their possession.”

In the absence indeed of advanced theory and analytical power, a
very precise instrument would be useless. Measuring apparatus and
mathematical theory should advance *pari passu*, and with just such
precision as the theorist can anticipate results, the experimentalist
should be able to compare them with experience. The scrupulously
accurate observations of Flamsteed were the proper complement to the
intense mathematical powers of Newton.

Every branch of knowledge commences with quantitative notions of a
very rude character. After we have far progressed, it is often amusing
to look back into the infancy of the science, and contrast present
with past methods. At Greenwich Observatory in the present day, the
hundredth part of a second is not thought an inconsiderable portion
of time. The ancient Chaldæans recorded an eclipse to the nearest
hour, and the early Alexandrian astronomers thought it superfluous to
distinguish between the edge and centre of the sun. By the introduction
of the astrolabe, Ptolemy and the later Alexandrian astronomers could
determine the places of the heavenly bodies within about ten minutes
of arc. Little progress then ensued for thirteen centuries, until
Tycho Brahe made the first great step towards accuracy, not only by
employing better instruments, but even more by ceasing to regard an
instrument as correct. Tycho, in fact, determined the errors of his
instruments, and corrected his observations. He also took notice of
the effects of atmospheric refraction, and succeeded in attaining an
accuracy often sixty times as great as that of Ptolemy. Yet Tycho and
Hevelius often erred several minutes in the determination of a star’s
place, and it was a great achievement of Rœmer and Flamsteed to reduce
this error to seconds. Bradley, the modern Hipparchus, carried on the
improvement, his errors in right ascension, according to Bessel, being
under one second of time, and those of declination under four seconds
of arc. In the present day the average error of a single observation
is probably reduced to the half or quarter of what it was in Bradley’s
time; and further extreme accuracy is attained by the multiplication
of observations, and their skilful combination according to the theory
of error. Some of the more important constants, for instance that of
nutation, have been determined within the tenth part of a second of
space.[180]

  [180] Baily, *British Association Catalogue of Stars*, pp. 7, 23.

It would be a matter of great interest to trace out the dependence of
this progress upon the introduction of new instruments. The astrolabe
of Ptolemy, the telescope of Galileo, the pendulum of Galileo and
Huyghens, the micrometer of Horrocks, and the telescopic sights and
micrometer of Gascoygne and Picard, Rœmer’s transit instrument,
Newton’s and Hadley’s quadrant, Dollond’s achromatic lenses, Harrison’s
chronometer, and Ramsden’s dividing engine--such were some of the
principal additions to astronomical apparatus. The result is, that we
now take note of quantities, 300,000 or 400,000 times as small as in
the time of the Chaldæans.

It would be interesting again to compare the scrupulous accuracy of a
modern trigonometrical survey with Eratosthenes’ rude but ingenious
guess at the difference of latitude between Alexandria and Syene--or
with Norwood’s measurement of a degree of latitude in 1635. “Sometimes
I measured, sometimes I paced,” said Norwood; “and I believe I am
within a scantling of the truth.” Such was the germ of those elaborate
geodesical measurements which have made the dimensions of the globe
known to us within a few hundred yards.

In other branches of science, the invention of an instrument has
usually marked, if it has not made, an epoch. The science of heat might
be said to commence with the construction of the thermometer, and it
has recently been advanced by the introduction of the thermo-electric
pile. Chemistry has been created chiefly by the careful use of the
balance, which forms a unique instance of an instrument remaining
substantially in the form in which it was first applied to scientific
purposes by Archimedes. The balance never has been and probably never
can be improved, except in details of construction. The torsion
balance, introduced by Coulomb towards the end of last century, has
rapidly become essential in many branches of investigation. In the
hands of Cavendish and Baily, it gave a determination of the earth’s
density; applied in the galvanometer, it gave a delicate measure of
electrical forces, and is indispensable in the thermo-electric pile.
This balance is made by simply suspending any light rod by a thin wire
or thread attached to the middle point. And we owe to it almost all the
more delicate investigations in the theories of heat, electricity, and
magnetism.

Though we can now take note of the millionth of an inch in space,
and the millionth of a second in time, we must not overlook the fact
that in other operations of science we are yet in the position of the
Chaldæans. Not many years have elapsed since the magnitudes of the
stars, meaning the amounts of light they send to the observer’s eye,
were guessed at in the rudest manner, and the astronomer adjudged a
star to this or that order of magnitude by a rough comparison with
other stars of the same order. To Sir John Herschel we owe an attempt
to introduce a uniform method of measurement and expression, bearing
some relation to the real photometric magnitudes of the stars.[181]
Previous to the researches of Bunsen and Roscoe on the chemical action
of light, we were devoid of any mode of measuring the energy of light;
even now the methods are tedious, and it is not clear that they give
the energy of light so much as one of its special effects. Many natural
phenomena have hardly yet been made the subject of measurement at all,
such as the intensity of sound, the phenomena of taste and smell, the
magnitude of atoms, the temperature of the electric spark or of the
sun’s photosphere.

  [181] *Outlines of Astronomy*, 4th ed. sect. 781, p. 522. *Results of
  Observations at the Cape of Good Hope*, &c., p. 37.

To suppose, then, that quantitative science treats only of exactly
measurable quantities, is a gross if it be a common mistake. Whenever
we are treating of an event which either happens altogether or does
not happen at all, we are engaged with a non-quantitative phenomenon,
a matter of fact, not of degree; but whenever a thing may be greater
or less, or twice or thrice as great as another, whenever, in short,
ratio enters even in the rudest manner, there science will have a
quantitative character. There can be little doubt, indeed, that
every science as it progresses will become gradually more and more
quantitative. Numerical precision is the soul of science, as Herschel
said, and as all natural objects exist in space, and involve molecular
movements, measurable in velocity and extent, there is no apparent
limit to the ultimate extension of quantitative science. But the reader
must not for a moment suppose that, because we depend more and more
upon mathematical methods, we leave logical methods behind us. Number,
as I have endeavoured to show, is logical in its origin, and quantity
is but a development of number, or analogous thereto.


*Division of the Subject.*

The general subject of quantitative investigation will have to be
divided into several parts. We shall firstly consider the means at
our disposal for measuring phenomena, and thus rendering them more or
less amenable to mathematical treatment. This task will involve an
analysis of the principles on which accurate methods of measurement are
founded, forming the subject of the remainder of the present chapter.
As measurement, however, only yields ratios, we have in the next
chapter to consider the establishment of unit magnitudes, in terms of
which our results may be expressed. As every phenomenon is usually the
sum of several distinct quantities depending upon different causes,
we have next to investigate in Chapter XV. the methods by which we
may disentangle complicated effects, and refer each part of the joint
effect to its separate cause.

It yet remains for us in subsequent chapters to treat of quantitative
induction, properly so called. We must follow out the inverse logical
method, as it presents itself in problems of a far higher degree of
difficulty than those which treat of objects related in a simple
logical manner, and incapable of merging into each other by addition
and subtraction.


*Continuous Quantity.*

The phenomena of nature are for the most part manifested in quantities
which increase or decrease continuously. When we inquire into the
precise meaning of continuous quantity, we find that it can only be
described as that which is divisible without limit. We can divide
a millimetre into ten, or a hundred, or a thousand, or ten thousand
parts, and mentally at any rate we can carry on the division *ad
infinitum*. Any finite space, then, must be conceived as made up of an
infinite number of parts each infinitely small. We cannot entertain the
simplest geometrical notions without allowing this. The conception of a
square involves the conception of a side and diagonal, which, as Euclid
beautifully proves in the 117th proposition of his tenth book, have no
common measure,[182] meaning no finite common measure. Incommensurable
quantities are, in fact, those which have for their only common measure
an infinitely small quantity. It is somewhat startling to find, too,
that in theory incommensurable quantities will be infinitely more
frequent than commensurable. Let any two lines be drawn haphazard;
it is infinitely unlikely that they will be commensurable, so that
the commensurable quantities, which we are supposed to deal with in
practice, are but singular cases among an infinitely greater number of
incommensurable cases.

  [182] See De Morgan, *Study of Mathematics*, in U.K.S. Library, p. 81.

Practically, however, we treat all quantities as made up of the
least quantities which our senses, assisted by the best measuring
instruments, can perceive. So long as microscopes were uninvented, it
was sufficient to regard an inch as made up of a thousand thousandths
of an inch; now we must treat it as composed of a million millionths.
We might apparently avoid all mention of infinitely small quantities,
by never carrying our approximations beyond quantities which the
senses can appreciate. In geometry, as thus treated, we should never
assert two quantities to be equal, but only to be *apparently* equal.
Legendre really adopts this mode of treatment in the twentieth
proposition of the first book of his Geometry; and it is practically
adopted throughout the physical sciences, as we shall afterwards
see. But though our fingers, and senses, and instruments must stop
somewhere, there is no reason why the mind should not go on. We can
see that a proof which is only carried through a few steps in fact,
might be carried on without limit, and it is this consciousness of no
stopping-place, which renders Euclid’s proof of his 117th proposition
so impressive. Try how we will to circumvent the matter, we cannot
really avoid the consideration of the infinitely small and the
infinitely great. The same methods of approximation which seem confined
to the finite, mentally extend themselves to the infinite.

One result of these considerations is, that we cannot possibly adjust
two quantities in absolute equality. The suspension of Mahomet’s coffin
between two precisely equal magnets is theoretically conceivable but
practically impossible. The story of the *Merchant of Venice* turns
upon the infinite improbability that an exact quantity of flesh could
be cut. Unstable equilibrium cannot exist in nature, for it is that
which is destroyed by an infinitely small displacement. It might be
possible to balance an egg on its end practically, because no egg has
a surface of perfect curvature. Suppose the egg shell to be perfectly
smooth, and the feat would become impossible.


*The Fallacious Indications of the Senses.*

I may briefly remind the reader how little we can trust to our
unassisted senses in estimating the degree or magnitude of any
phenomenon. The eye cannot correctly estimate the comparative
brightness of two luminous bodies which differ much in brilliancy;
for we know that the iris is constantly adjusting itself to the
intensity of the light received, and thus admits more or less light
according to circumstances. The moon which shines with almost dazzling
brightness by night, is pale and nearly imperceptible while the eye is
yet affected by the vastly more powerful light of day. Much has been
recorded concerning the comparative brightness of the zodiacal light at
different times, but it would be difficult to prove that these changes
are not due to the varying darkness at the time, or the different
acuteness of the observer’s eye. For a like reason it is exceedingly
difficult to establish the existence of any change in the form or
comparative brightness of nebulæ; the appearance of a nebula greatly
depends upon the keenness of sight of the observer, or the accidental
condition of freshness or fatigue of his eye. The same is true of
lunar observations; and even the use of the best telescope fails to
remove this difficulty. In judging of colours, again, we must remember
that light of any given colour tends to dull the sensibility of the eye
for light of the same colour.

Nor is the eye when unassisted by instruments a much better judge
of magnitude. Our estimates of the size of minute bright points,
such as the fixed stars, are completely falsified by the effects of
irradiation. Tycho calculated from the apparent size of the star-discs,
that no one of the principal fixed stars could be contained within the
area of the earth’s orbit. Apart, however, from irradiation or other
distinct causes of error our visual estimates of sizes and shapes are
often astonishingly incorrect. Artists almost invariably draw distant
mountains in ludicrous disproportion to nearer objects, as a comparison
of a sketch with a photograph at once shows. The extraordinary apparent
difference of size of the sun or moon, according as it is high in the
heavens or near the horizon, should be sufficient to make us cautious
in accepting the plainest indications of our senses, unassisted by
instrumental measurement. As to statements concerning the height of the
aurora and the distance of meteors, they are to be utterly distrusted.
When Captain Parry says that a ray of the aurora shot suddenly
downwards between him and the land which was only 3,000 yards distant,
we must consider him subject to an illusion of sense.[183]

  [183] Loomis, *On the Aurora Borealis*. Smithsonian Transactions,
  quoting Parry’s Third Voyage, p. 61.

It is true that errors of observation are more often errors of judgment
than of sense. That which is actually seen must be so far truly seen;
and if we correctly interpret the meaning of the phenomenon, there
would be no error at all. But the weakness of the bare senses as
measuring instruments, arises from the fact that they import varying
conditions of unknown amount, and we cannot make the requisite
corrections and allowances as in the case of a solid and invariable
instrument.

Bacon has excellently stated the insufficiency of the senses for
estimating the magnitudes of objects, or detecting the degrees in which
phenomena present themselves. “Things escape the senses,” he says,
“because the object is not sufficient in quantity to strike the sense:
as all minute bodies; because the percussion of the object is too
great to be endured by the senses: as the form of the sun when looking
directly at it in mid-day; because the time is not proportionate to
actuate the sense: as the motion of a bullet in the air, or the quick
circular motion of a firebrand, which are too fast, or the hour-hand of
a common clock, which is too slow; from the distance of the object as
to place: as the size of the celestial bodies, and the size and nature
of all distant bodies; from prepossession by another object: as one
powerful smell renders other smells in the same room imperceptible;
from the interruption of interposing bodies: as the internal parts of
animals; and because the object is unfit to make an impression upon
the sense: as the air or the invisible and untangible spirit which is
included in every living body.”


*Complexity of Quantitative Questions.*

One remark which we may well make in entering upon quantitative
questions, has regard to the great variety and extent of phenomena
presented to our notice. So long as we deal only with a simply logical
question, that question is merely, Does a certain event happen? or,
Does a certain object exist? No sooner do we regard the event or object
as capable of more and less, than the question branches out into many.
We must now ask, How much is it compared with its cause? Does it change
when the amount of the cause changes? If so, does it change in the same
or opposite direction? Is the change in simple proportion to that of
the cause? If not, what more complex law of connection holds true? This
law determined satisfactorily in one series of circumstances may be
varied under new conditions, and the most complex relations of several
quantities may ultimately be established.

In every question of physical science there is thus a series of steps
the first one or two of which are usually made with ease while the
succeeding ones demand more and more careful measurement. We cannot
lay down any invariable series of questions which must be asked from
nature. The exact character of the questions will vary according
to the nature of the case, but they will usually be of an evident
kind, and we may readily illustrate them by examples. Suppose that
we are investigating the solution of some salt in water. The first
is a purely logical question: Is there solution, or is there not?
Assuming the answer to be in the affirmative, we next inquire, Does
the solubility vary with the temperature, or not? In all probability
some variation will exist, and we must have an answer to the further
question, Does the quantity dissolved increase, or does it diminish
with the temperature? In by far the greatest number of cases salts and
substances of all kinds dissolve more freely the higher the temperature
of the water; but there are a few salts, such as calcium sulphate,
which follow the opposite rule. A considerable number of salts resemble
sodium sulphate in becoming more soluble up to a certain temperature,
and then varying in the opposite direction. We next require to assign
the amount of variation as compared with that of the temperature,
assuming at first that the increase of solubility is proportional to
the increase of temperature. Common salt is an instance of very slight
variation, and potassium nitrate of very considerable increase with
temperature. Accurate observations will probably show, however, that
the simple law of proportionate variation is only approximately true,
and some more complicated law involving the second, third, or higher
powers of the temperature may ultimately be established. All these
investigations have to be carried out for each salt separately, since
no distinct principles by which we may infer from one substance to
another have yet been detected. There is still an indefinite field
for further research open; for the solubility of salts will probably
vary with the pressure under which the medium is placed; the presence
of other salts already dissolved may have effects yet unknown. The
researches already effected as regards the solvent power of water must
be repeated with alcohol, ether, carbon bisulphide, and other media,
so that unless general laws can be detected, this one phenomenon of
solution can never be exhaustively treated. The same kind of questions
recur as regards the solution or absorption of gases in liquids, the
pressure as well as the temperature having then a most decided effect,
and Professor Roscoe’s researches on the subject present an excellent
example of the successive determination of various complicated
laws.[184]

  [184] Watts’ *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. ii. p. 790.

There is hardly a branch of physical science in which similar
complications are not ultimately encountered. In the case of gravity,
indeed, we arrive at the final law, that the force is the same for
all kinds of matter, and varies only with the distance of action.
But in other subjects the laws, if simple in their ultimate nature,
are disguised and complicated in their apparent results. Thus the
effect of heat in expanding solids, and the reverse effect of forcible
extension or compression upon the temperature of a body, will vary
from one substance to another, will vary as the temperature is already
higher or lower, and, will probably follow a highly complex law, which
in some cases gives negative or exceptional results. In crystalline
substances the same researches have to be repeated in each distinct
axial direction.

In the sciences of pure observation, such as those of astronomy,
meteorology, and terrestrial magnetism, we meet with many interesting
series of quantitative determinations. The so-called fixed stars, as
Giordano Bruno divined, are not really fixed, and may be more truly
described as vast wandering orbs, each pursuing its own path through
space. We must then determine separately for each star the following
questions:--

1. Does it move?

2. In what direction?

3. At what velocity?

4. Is this velocity variable or uniform?

5. If variable, according to what law?

6. Is the direction uniform?

7. If not, what is the form of the apparent path?

8. Does it approach or recede? 9. What is the form of the real path?

The successive answers to such questions in the case of certain binary
stars, have afforded a proof that the motions are due to a central
force coinciding in law with gravity, and doubtless identical with it.
In other cases the motions are usually so small that it is exceedingly
difficult to distinguish them with certainty. And the time is yet
far off when any general results as regards stellar motions can be
established.

The variation in the brightness of stars opens an unlimited field for
curious observation. There is not a star in the heavens concerning
which we might not have to determine:--

1. Does it vary in brightness?

2. Is the brightness increasing or decreasing?

3. Is the variation uniform?

4. If not, according to what law does it vary?

In a majority of cases the change will probably be found to have a
periodic character, in which case several other questions will arise,
such as--

5. What is the length of the period?

6. Are there minor periods?

7. What is the law of variation within the period?

8. Is there any change in the amount of variation?

9. If so, is it a secular, *i.e.* a continually growing change, or does
it give evidence of a greater period?

Already the periodic changes of a certain number of stars have been
determined with accuracy, and the lengths of the periods vary from less
than three days up to intervals of time at least 250 times as great.
Periods within periods have also been detected.

There is, perhaps, no subject in which more complicated quantitative
conditions have to be determined than terrestrial magnetism. Since
the time when the declination of the compass was first noticed, as
some suppose by Columbus, we have had successive discoveries from
time to time of the progressive change of declination from century to
century; of the periodic character of this change; of the difference
of the declination in various parts of the earth’s surface; of the
varying laws of the change of declination; of the dip or inclination
of the needle, and the corresponding laws of its periodic changes; the
horizontal and perpendicular intensities have also been the subject of
exact measurement, and have been found to vary with place and time,
like the directions of the needle; daily and yearly periodic changes
have also been detected, and all the elements are found to be subject
to occasional storms or abnormal perturbations, in which the eleven
year period, now known to be common to many planetary relations,
is apparent. The complete solution of these motions of the compass
needle involves nothing less than a determination of its position
and oscillations in every part of the world at any epoch, the like
determination for another epoch, and so on, time after time, until the
periods of all changes are ascertained. This one subject offers to men
of science an almost inexhaustible field for interesting quantitative
research, in which we shall doubtless at some future time discover the
operation of causes now most mysterious and unaccountable.


*The Methods of Accurate Measurement.*

In studying the modes by which physicists have accomplished very exact
measurements, we find that they are very various, but that they may
perhaps be reduced under the following three classes:--

1. The increase or decrease, in some determinate ratio, of the quantity
to be measured, so as to bring it within the scope of our senses, and
to equate it with the standard unit, or some determinate multiple or
sub-multiple of this unit.

2. The discovery of some natural conjunction of events which will
enable us to compare directly the multiples of the quantity with those
of the unit, or a quantity related in a definite ratio to that unit.

3. Indirect measurement, which gives us not the quantity itself, but
some other quantity connected with it by known mathematical relations.


*Conditions of Accurate Measurement.*

Several conditions are requisite in order that a measurement may be
made with great accuracy, and that the results may be closely accordant
when several independent measurements are made.

In the first place the magnitude must be exactly defined by sharp
terminations, or precise marks of inconsiderable thickness. When a
boundary is vague and graduated, like the penumbra in a lunar eclipse,
it is impossible to say where the end really is, and different people
will come to different results. We may sometimes overcome this
difficulty to a certain extent, by observations repeated in a special
manner, as we shall afterwards see; but when possible, we should choose
opportunities for measurement when precise definition is easy. The
moment of occultation of a star by the moon can be observed with great
accuracy, because the star disappears with perfect suddenness; but
there are other astronomical conjunctions, eclipses, transits, &c.,
which occupy a certain length of time in happening, and thus open the
way to differences of opinion. It would be impossible to observe with
precision the movements of a body possessing no definite points of
reference. The colours of the complete spectrum shade into each other
so continuously that exact determinations of refractive indices would
have been impossible, had we not the dark lines of the solar spectrum
as precise points for measurement, or various kinds of homogeneous
light, such as that of sodium, possessing a nearly uniform length of
vibration.

In the second place, we cannot measure accurately unless we have the
means of multiplying or dividing a quantity without considerable error,
so that we may correctly equate one magnitude with the multiple or
submultiple of the other. In some cases we operate upon the quantity
to be measured, and bring it into accurate coincidence with the actual
standard, as when in photometry we vary the distance of our luminous
body, until its illuminating power at a certain point is equal to
that of a standard lamp. In other cases we repeat the unit until it
equals the object, as in surveying land, or determining a weight by
the balance. The requisites of accuracy now are:--(1) That we can
repeat unit after unit of exactly equal magnitude; (2) That these
can be joined together so that the aggregate shall really be the sum
of the parts. The same conditions apply to subdivision, which may be
regarded as a multiplication of subordinate units. In order to measure
to the thousandth of an inch, we must be able to add thousandth after
thousandth without error in the magnitude of these spaces, or in their
conjunction.


*Measuring Instruments.*

To consider the mechanical construction of scientific instruments, is
no part of my purpose in this book. I wish to point out merely the
general purpose of such instruments, and the methods adopted to carry
out that purpose with great precision. In the first place we must
distinguish between the instrument which effects a comparison between
two quantities, and the standard magnitude which often forms one of
the quantities compared. The astronomer’s clock, for instance, is
no standard of the efflux of time; it serves but to subdivide, with
approximate accuracy, the interval of successive passages of a star
across the meridian, which it may effect perhaps to the tenth part of
a second, or 1/864000 part of the whole. The moving globe itself is
the real standard clock, and the transit instrument the finger of the
clock, while the stars are the hour, minute, and second marks, none
the less accurate because they are disposed at unequal intervals. The
photometer is a simple instrument, by which we compare the relative
intensity of rays of light falling upon a given spot. The galvanometer
shows the comparative intensity of electric currents passing through a
wire. The calorimeter gauges the quantity of heat passing from a given
object. But no such instruments furnish the standard unit in terms of
which our results are to be expressed. In one peculiar case alone does
the same instrument combine the unit of measurement and the means of
comparison. A theodolite, mural circle, sextant, or other instrument
for the measurement of angular magnitudes has no need of an additional
physical unit; for the circle itself, or complete revolution, is
the natural unit to which all greater or lesser amounts of angular
magnitude are referred.

The result of every measurement is to make known the purely numerical
ratio existing between the magnitude to be measured, and a certain
other magnitude, which should, when possible, be a fixed unit or
standard magnitude, or at least an intermediate unit of which the
value can be ascertained in terms of the ultimate standard. But though
a ratio is the required result, an equation is the mode in which the
ratio is determined and expressed. In every measurement we equate
some multiple or submultiple of one quantity, with some multiple or
submultiple of another, and equality is always the fact which we
ascertain by the senses. By the eye, the ear, or the touch, we judge
whether there is a discrepancy or not between two lights, two sounds,
two intervals of time, two bars of metal. Often indeed we substitute
one sense for the other, as when the efflux of time is judged by
the marks upon a moving slip of paper, so that equal intervals of
time are represented by equal lengths. There is a tendency to reduce
all comparisons to the comparison of space magnitudes, but in every
case one of the senses must be the ultimate judge of coincidence or
non-coincidence.

Since the equation to be established may exist between any multiples or
submultiples of the quantities compared, there naturally arise several
different modes of comparison adapted to different cases. Let *p* be
the magnitude to be measured, and *q* that in terms of which it is to
be expressed. Then we wish to find such numbers *x* and *y*, that the
equation *p = (x/y)q* may be true. This equation may be presented in
four forms, namely:--

   First Form.    Second Form.    Third Form.    Fourth Form.
  *p = (x/y)q*    *p(y/x) = q*     *py = qx*     *p/x = q/y*

Each of these modes of expressing the same equation corresponds to one
mode of effecting a measurement.

When the standard quantity is greater than that to be measured, we
often adopt the first mode, and subdivide the unit until we get a
magnitude equal to that measured. The angles observed in surveying,
in astronomy, or in goniometry are usually smaller than a whole
revolution, and the measuring circle is divided by the use of the
screw and microscope, until we obtain an angle undistinguishable from
that observed. The dimensions of minute objects are determined by
subdividing the inch or centimetre, the screw micrometer being the most
accurate means of subdivision. Ordinary temperatures are estimated by
division of the standard interval between the freezing and boiling
points of water, as marked on a thermometer tube.

In a still greater number of cases, perhaps, we multiply the standard
unit until we get a magnitude equal to that to be measured. Ordinary
measurement by a foot rule, a surveyor’s chain, or the excessively
careful measurements of the base line of a trigonometrical survey by
standard bars, are sufficient instances of this procedure.

In the second case, where *p(y/x) = q*, we multiply or divide a
magnitude until we get what is equal to the unit, or to some magnitude
easily comparable with it. As a general rule the quantities which we
desire to measure in physical science are too small rather than too
great for easy determination, and the problem consists in multiplying
them without introducing error. Thus the expansion of a metallic bar
when heated from 0°C to 100° may be multiplied by a train of levers or
cog wheels. In the common thermometer the expansion of the mercury,
though slight, is rendered very apparent, and easily measurable by the
fineness of the tube, and many other cases might be quoted. There are
some phenomena, on the contrary, which are too great or rapid to come
within the easy range of our senses, and our task is then the opposite
one of diminution. Galileo found it difficult to measure the velocity
of a falling body, owing to the considerable velocity acquired in a
single second. He adopted the elegant device, therefore, of lessening
the rapidity by letting the body roll down an inclined plane, which
enables us to reduce the accelerating force in any required ratio.
The same purpose is effected in the well-known experiments performed
on Attwood’s machine, and the measurement of gravity by the pendulum
really depends on the same principle applied in a far more advantageous
manner. Wheatstone invented a beautiful method of galvanometry for
strong currents, which consists in drawing off from the main current a
certain determinate portion, which is equated by the galvanometer to a
standard current. In short, he measures not the current itself but a
known fraction of it.

In many electrical and other experiments, we wish to measure the
movements of a needle or other body, which are not only very slight
in themselves, but the manifestations of exceedingly small forces. We
cannot even approach a delicately balanced needle without disturbing
it. Under these circumstances the only mode of proceeding with
accuracy, is to attach a very small mirror to the moving body, and
employ a ray of light reflected from the mirror as an index of its
movements. The ray may be considered quite incapable of affecting the
body, and yet by allowing the ray to pass to a sufficient distance, the
motions of the mirror may be increased to almost any extent. A ray of
light is in fact a perfectly weightless finger or index of indefinite
length, with the additional advantage that the angular deviation is
by the law of reflection double that of the mirror. This method was
introduced by Gauss, and is now of great importance; but in Wollaston’s
reflecting goniometer a ray of light had previously been employed as an
index. Lavoisier and Laplace had also used a telescope in connection
with the pyrometer.

It is a great advantage in some instruments that they can be readily
made to manifest a phenomenon in a greater or less degree, by a very
slight change in the construction. Thus either by enlarging the bulb
or contracting the tube of the thermometer, we can make it give
more conspicuous indications of change of temperature. The ordinary
barometer, on the other hand, always gives the variations of pressure
on one scale. The torsion balance is remarkable for the extreme
delicacy which may be attained by increasing the length and lightness
of the rod, and the length and thinness of the supporting thread.
Forces so minute as the attraction of gravitation between two balls, or
the magnetic and diamagnetic attraction of common liquids and gases,
may thus be made apparent, and even measured. The common chemical
balance, too, is capable theoretically of unlimited sensibility.

The third mode of measurement, which may be called the Method of
Repetition, is of such great importance and interest that we must
consider it in a separate section. It consists in multiplying both
magnitudes to be compared until some multiple of the first is found
to coincide very nearly with some multiple of the second. If the
multiplication can be effected to an unlimited extent, without the
introduction of countervailing errors, the accuracy with which the
required ratio can be determined is unlimited, and we thus account for
the extraordinary precision with which intervals of time in astronomy
are compared together.

The fourth mode of measurement, in which we equate submultiples of
two magnitudes, is comparatively seldom employed, because it does not
conduce to accuracy. In the photometer, perhaps, we may be said to use
it; we compare the intensity of two sources of light, by placing them
both at such distances from a given surface, that the light falling
on the surface is tolerable to the eye, and equally intense from each
source. Since the intensity of light varies inversely as the square
of the distance, the relative intensities of the luminous bodies are
proportional to the squares of their distances. The equal intensity of
two rays of similarly coloured light may be most accurately ascertained
in the mode suggested by Arago, namely, by causing the rays to pass in
opposite directions through two nearly flat lenses pressed together.
There is an exact equation between the intensities of the beams when
Newton’s rings disappear, the ring created by one ray being exactly the
complement of that created by the other.


*The Method of Repetition.*

The ratio of two quantities can be determined with unlimited accuracy,
if we can multiply both the object of measurement and the standard unit
without error, and then observe what multiple of the one coincides or
nearly coincides with some multiple of the other. Although perfect
coincidence can never be really attained, the error thus arising
may be indefinitely reduced. For if the equation *py* = *qx* be
uncertain to the amount *e*, so that *py* = *qx* ± *e*, then we have
*p* = *q(x/y)* ± *e/y* , and as we are supposed to be able to make *y*
as great as we like without increasing the error *e*, it follows that
we can make *e* ÷ *y* as small as we like, and thus approximate within
an inconsiderable quantity to the required ratio *x* ÷ *y*.

This method of repetition is naturally employed whenever quantities
can be repeated, or repeat themselves without error of juxtaposition,
which is especially the case with the motions of the earth and heavenly
bodies. In determining the length of the sidereal day, we determine the
ratio between the earth’s revolution round the sun, and its rotation on
its own axis. We might ascertain the ratio by observing the successive
passages of a star across the zenith, and comparing the interval by a
good clock with that between two passages of the sun, the difference
being due to the angular movement of the earth round the sun. In such
observations we should have an error of a considerable part of a second
at each observation, in addition to the irregularities of the clock.
But the revolutions of the earth repeat themselves day after day, and
year after year, without the slightest interval between the end of one
period and the beginning of another. The operation of multiplication
is perfectly performed for us by nature. If, then, we can find an
observation of the passage of a star across the meridian a hundred
years ago, that is of the interval of time between the passage of the
sun and the star, the instrumental errors in measuring this interval by
a clock and telescope may be greater than in the present day, but will
be divided by about 36,524 days, and rendered excessively small. It is
thus that astronomers have been able to ascertain the ratio of the mean
solar to the sidereal day to the 8th place of decimals (1·00273791 to
1), or to the hundred millionth part, probably the most accurate result
of measurement in the whole range of science.

The antiquity of this mode of comparison is almost as great as that of
astronomy itself. Hipparchus made the first clear application of it,
when he compared his own observations with those of Aristarchus, made
145 years previously, and thus ascertained the length of the year.
This calculation may in fact be regarded as the earliest attempt at
an exact determination of the constants of nature. The method is the
main resource of astronomers; Tycho, for instance, detected the slow
diminution of the obliquity of the earth’s axis, by the comparison of
observations at long intervals. Living astronomers use the method as
much as earlier ones; but so superior in accuracy are all observations
taken during the last hundred years to all previous ones, that it is
often found preferable to take a shorter interval, rather than incur
the risk of greater instrumental errors in the earlier observations.

It is obvious that many of the slower changes of the heavenly bodies
must require the lapse of large intervals of time to render their
amount perceptible. Hipparchus could not possibly have discovered the
smaller inequalities of the heavenly motions, because there were no
previous observations of sufficient age or exactness to exhibit them.
And just as the observations of Hipparchus formed the starting-point
for subsequent comparisons, so a large part of the labour of present
astronomers is directed to recording the present state of the heavens
so exactly, that future generations of astronomers may detect changes,
which cannot possibly become known in the present age.

The principle of repetition was very ingeniously employed in an
instrument first proposed by Mayer in 1767, and carried into practice
in the Repeating Circle of Borda. The exact measurement of angles
is indispensable, not only in astronomy but also in trigonometrical
surveys, and the highest skill in the mechanical execution of the
graduated circle and telescope will not prevent terminal errors of
considerable amount. If instead of one telescope, the circle be
provided with two similar telescopes, these may be alternately directed
to two distant points, say the marks in a trigonometrical survey, so
that the circle shall be turned through any multiple of the angle
subtended by those marks, before the amount of the angular revolution
is read off upon the graduated circle. Theoretically speaking, all
error arising from imperfect graduation might thus be indefinitely
reduced, being divided by the number of repetitions. In practice, the
advantage of the invention is not found to be very great, probably
because a certain error is introduced at each observation in the
changing and fixing of the telescopes. It is moreover inapplicable to
moving objects like the heavenly bodies, so that its use is confined to
important trigonometrical surveys.

The pendulum is the most perfect of all instruments, chiefly because
it admits of almost endless repetition. Since the force of gravity
never ceases, one swing of the pendulum is no sooner ended than the
other is begun, so that the juxtaposition of successive units is
absolutely perfect. Provided that the oscillations be equal, one
thousand oscillations will occupy exactly one thousand times as great
an interval of time as one oscillation. Not only is the subdivision of
time entirely dependent on this fact, but in the accurate measurement
of gravity, and many other important determinations, it is of the
greatest service. In the deepest mine, we could not observe the
rapidity of fall of a body for more than a quarter of a minute, and
the measurement of its velocity would be difficult, and subject to
uncertain errors from resistance of air, &c. In the pendulum, we have a
body which can be kept rising and falling for many hours, in a medium
entirely under our command or if desirable in a vacuum. Moreover, the
comparative force of gravity at different points, at the top and bottom
of a mine for instance, can be determined with wonderful precision, by
comparing the oscillations of two exactly similar pendulums, with the
aid of electric clock signals.

To ascertain the comparative times of vibration of two pendulums, it
is only requisite to swing them one in front of the other, to record
by a clock the moment when they coincide in swing, so that one hides
the other, and then count the number of vibrations until they again
come to coincidence. If one pendulum makes *m* vibrations and the other
*n*, we at once have our equation *pn* = *qm*; which gives the length
of vibration of either pendulum in terms of the other. This method of
coincidence, embodying the principle of repetition in perfection, was
employed with wonderful skill by Sir George Airy, in his experiments on
the Density of the Earth at the Harton Colliery, the pendulums above
and below being compared with clocks, which again were compared with
each other by electric signals. So exceedingly accurate was this method
of observation, as carried out by Sir George Airy, that he was able to
measure a total difference in the vibrations at the top and bottom of
the shaft, amounting to only 2·24 seconds in the twenty-four hours,
with an error of less than one hundredth part of a second, or one part
in 8,640,000 of the whole day.[185]

  [185] *Philosophical Transactions*, (1856) vol. 146, Part i. p. 297.

The principle of repetition has been elegantly applied in observing
the motion of waves in water. If the canal in which the experiments are
made be short, say twenty feet long, the waves will pass through it
so rapidly that an observation of one length, as practised by Walker,
will be subject to much terminal error, even when the observer is very
skilful. But it is a result of the undulatory theory that a wave is
unaltered, and loses no time by complete reflection, so that it may be
allowed to travel backwards and forwards in the same canal, and its
motion, say through sixty lengths, or 1200 feet, may be observed with
the same accuracy as in a canal 1200 feet long, with the advantage of
greater uniformity in the condition of the canal and water.[186] It
is always desirable, if possible, to bring an experiment into a small
compass, so that it may be well under command, and yet we may often by
repetition enjoy at the same time the advantage of extensive trial.

  [186] Airy, *On Tides and Waves*, Encyclopædia Metropolitana, p. 345.
  Scott Russell, *British Association Report*, 1837, p. 432.

One reason of the great accuracy of weighing with a good balance is
the fact, that weights placed in the same scale are naturally added
together without the slightest error. There is no difficulty in the
precise juxtaposition of two grams, but the juxtaposition of two metre
measures can only be effected with tolerable accuracy, by the use of
microscopes and many precautions. Hence, the extreme trouble and cost
attaching to the exact measurement of a base line for a survey, the
risk of error entering at every juxtaposition of the measuring bars,
and indefatigable attention to all the requisite precautions being
necessary throughout the operation.


*Measurements by Natural Coincidence.*

In certain cases a peculiar conjunction of circumstances enables us to
dispense more or less with instrumental aids, and to obtain very exact
numerical results in the simplest manner. The mere fact, for instance,
that no human being has ever seen a different face of the moon from
that familiar to us, conclusively proves that the period of rotation
of the moon on its own axis is equal to that of its revolution round
the earth. Not only have we the repetition of these movements during
1000 or 2000 years at least, but we have observations made for us
at very remote periods, free from instrumental error, no instrument
being needed. We learn that the seventh satellite of Saturn is subject
to a similar law, because its light undergoes a variation in each
revolution, owing to the existence of some dark tract of land; now
this failure of light always occurs while it is in the same position
relative to Saturn, clearly proving the equality of the axial and
revolutional periods, as Huygens perceived.[187] A like peculiarity in
the motions of Jupiter’s fourth satellite was similarly detected by
Maraldi in 1713.

  [187] *Hugenii Cosmotheoros*, pp. 117, 118. Laplace’s *Système*,
  translated, vol. i. p. 67.

Remarkable conjunctions of the planets may sometimes allow us to
compare their periods of revolution, through great intervals of time,
with much accuracy. Laplace in explaining the long inequality in the
motions of Jupiter and Saturn, was assisted by a conjunction of these
planets, observed at Cairo, towards the close of the eleventh century.
Laplace calculated that such a conjunction must have happened on the
31st of October, A.D. 1087; and the discordance between the distances
of the planets as recorded, and as assigned by theory, was less than
one-fifth part of the apparent diameter of the sun. This difference
being less than the probable error of the early record, the theory was
confirmed as far as facts were available.[188]

  [188] Grant’s *History of Physical Astronomy*, p. 129.

Ancient astronomers often showed the highest ingenuity in turning
any opportunities of measurement which occurred to good account.
Eratosthenes, as early as 250 B.C., happening to hear that the sun at
Syene, in Upper Egypt, was visible at the summer solstice at the bottom
of a well, proving that it was in the zenith, proposed to determine
the dimensions of the earth, by measuring the length of the shadow of
a rod at Alexandria on the same day of the year. He thus learnt in a
rude manner the difference of latitude between Alexandria and Syene and
finding it to be about one fiftieth part of the whole circumference, he
ascertained the dimensions of the earth within about one sixth part
of the truth. The use of wells in astronomical observation appears to
have been occasionally practised in comparatively recent times as by
Flamsteed in 1679.[189] The Alexandrian astronomers employed the moon
as an instrument of measurement in several sagacious modes. When the
moon is exactly half full, the moon, sun, and earth, are at the angles
of a right-angled triangle. Aristarchus measured at such a time the
moon’s elongation from the sun, which gave him the two other angles of
the triangle, and enabled him to judge of the comparative distances
of the moon and sun from the earth. His result, though very rude, was
far more accurate than any notions previously entertained, and enabled
him to form some estimate of the comparative magnitudes of the bodies.
Eclipses of the moon were very useful to Hipparchus in ascertaining
the longitude of the stars, which are invisible when the sun is above
the horizon. For the moon when eclipsed must be 180° distant from the
sun; hence it is only requisite to measure the distance of a fixed star
in longitude from the eclipsed moon to obtain with ease its angular
distance from the sun.

  [189] Baily’s *Account of Flamsteed*, p. lix.

In later times the eclipses of Jupiter have served to measure an angle;
for at the middle moment of the eclipse the satellite must be in the
same straight line with the planet and sun, so that we can learn from
the known laws of movement of the satellite the longitude of Jupiter
as seen from the sun. If at the same time we measure the elongation or
apparent angular distance of Jupiter from the sun, as seen from the
earth, we have all the angles of the triangle between Jupiter, the sun,
and the earth, and can calculate the comparative magnitudes of the
sides of the triangle by trigonometry.

The transits of Venus over the sun’s face are other natural events
which give most accurate measurements of the sun’s parallax, or
apparent difference of position as seen from distant points of the
earth’s surface. The sun forms a kind of background on which the place
of the planet is marked, and serves as a measuring instrument free
from all the errors of construction which affect human instruments.
The rotation of the earth, too, by variously affecting the apparent
velocity of ingress or egress of Venus, as seen from different places,
discloses the amount of the parallax. It has been sufficiently shown
that by rightly choosing the moments of observation, the planetary
bodies may often be made to reveal their relative distance, to measure
their own position, to record their own movements with a high degree
of accuracy. With the improvement of astronomical instruments, such
conjunctions become less necessary to the progress of the science,
but it will always remain advantageous to choose those moments for
observation when instrumental errors enter with the least effect.

In other sciences, exact quantitative laws can occasionally be obtained
without instrumental measurement, as when we learn the exactly equal
velocity of sounds of different pitch, by observing that a peal of
bells or a musical performance is heard harmoniously at any distance
to which the sound penetrates; this could not be the case, as Newton
remarked, if one sound overtook the other. One of the most important
principles of the atomic theory, was proved by implication before the
use of the balance was introduced into chemistry. Wenzel observed,
before 1777, that when two neutral substances decompose each other,
the resulting salts are also neutral. In mixing sodium sulphate and
barium nitrate, we obtain insoluble barium sulphate and neutral sodium
nitrate. This result could not follow unless the nitric acid, requisite
to saturate one atom of sodium, were exactly equal to that required
by one atom of barium, so that an exchange could take place without
leaving either acid or base in excess.

An important principle of mechanics may also be established by a simple
acoustical observation. When a rod or tongue of metal fixed at one
end is set in vibration, the pitch of the sound may be observed to
be exactly the same, whether the vibrations be small or great; hence
the oscillations are isochronous, or equally rapid, independently of
their magnitude. On the ground of theory, it can be shown that such a
result only happens when the flexure is proportional to the deflecting
force. Thus the simple observation that the pitch of the sound of a
harmonium, for instance, does not change with its loudness establishes
an exact law of nature.[190]

  [190] Jamin, *Cours de Physique*, vol. i. p. 152.

A closely similar instance is found in the proof that the intensity
of light or heat rays varies inversely as the square of the distance
increases. For the apparent magnitude certainly varies according to
this law; hence, if the intensity of light varied according to any
other law, the brightness of an object would be different at different
distances, which is not observed to be the case. Melloni applied the
same kind of reasoning, in a somewhat different form, to the radiation
of heat-rays.


*Modes of Indirect Measurement.*

Some of the most conspicuously beautiful experiments in the whole range
of science, have been devised for the purpose of indirectly measuring
quantities, which in their extreme greatness or smallness surpass the
powers of sense. All that we need to do, is to discover some other
conveniently measurable phenomenon, which is related in a known ratio
or according to a known law, however complicated, with that to be
measured. Having once obtained experimental data, there is no further
difficulty beyond that of arithmetic or algebraic calculation.

Gold is reduced by the gold-beater to leaves so thin, that the most
powerful microscope would not detect any measurable thickness. If we
laid several hundred leaves upon each other to multiply the thickness,
we should still have no more than 1/100th of an inch at the most to
measure, and the errors arising in the superposition and measurement
would be considerable. But we can readily obtain an exact result
through the connected amount of weight. Faraday weighed 2000 leaves of
gold, each 3-3/8 inch square, and found them equal to 384 grains. From
the known specific gravity of gold it was easy to calculate that the
average thickness of the leaves was 1/282,000 of an inch.[191]

  [191] Faraday, *Chemical Researches*, p. 393.

We must ascribe to Newton the honour of leading the way in methods of
minute measurement. He did not call waves of light by their right name,
and did not understand their nature; yet he measured their length,
though it did not exceed the 2,000,000th part of a metre or the one
fifty-thousandth part of an inch. He pressed together two lenses of
large but known radii. It was easy to calculate the interval between
the lenses at any point, by measuring the distance from the central
point of contact. Now, with homogeneous rays the successive rings of
light and darkness mark the points at which the interval between the
lenses is equal to one half, or any multiple of half a vibration of
the light, so that the length of the vibration became known. In a
similar manner many phenomena of interference of rays of light admit
of the measurement of the wave lengths. Fringes of interference arise
from rays of light which cross each other at a small angle, and an
excessively minute difference in the lengths of the waves makes a very
perceptible difference in the position of the point at which two rays
will interfere and produce darkness.

Fizeau has recently employed Newton’s rings to measure small amounts of
motion. By merely counting the number of rings of sodium monochromatic
light passing a certain point where two glass plates are in close
proximity, he is able to ascertain with the greatest accuracy and ease
the change of distance between these glasses, produced, for instance,
by the expansion of a metallic bar, connected with one of the glass
plates.[192]

  [192] *Proceedings of the Royal Society*, 30th November, 1866.

Nothing excites more admiration than the mode in which scientific
observers can occasionally measure quantities, which seem beyond
the bounds of human observation. We know the *average* depth of the
Pacific Ocean to be 14,190 feet, not by actual sounding, which would
be impracticable in sufficient detail, but by noticing the rate of
transmission of earthquake waves from the South American to the
opposite coasts, the rate of movement being connected by theory with
the depth of the water.[193] In the same way the average depth of
the Atlantic Ocean is inferred to be no less than 22,157 feet, from
the velocity of the ordinary tidal waves. A tidal wave again gives
beautiful evidence of an effect of the law of gravity, which we could
never in any other way detect. Newton estimated that the moon’s force
in moving the ocean is only one part in 2,871,400 of the whole force of
gravity, so that even the pendulum, used with the utmost skill, would
fail to render it apparent. Yet, the immense extent of the ocean allows
the accumulation of the effect into a very palpable amount; and from
the comparative heights of the lunar and solar tides, Newton roughly
estimated the comparative forces of the moon’s and sun’s gravity at the
earth.[194]

  [193] Herschel, *Physical Geography*, § 40.

  [194] *Principia*, bk. iii. Prop. 37, *Corollaries*, 2 and 3. Motte’s
  translation, vol. ii. p. 310.

A few years ago it might have seemed impossible that we should ever
measure the velocity with which a star approaches or recedes from the
earth, since the apparent position of the star is thereby unaltered.
But the spectroscope now enables us to detect and even measure such
motions with considerable accuracy, by the alteration which it
causes in the apparent rapidity of vibration, and consequently in
the refrangibility of rays of light of definite colour. And while
our estimates of the lateral movements of stars depend upon our very
uncertain knowledge of their distances, the spectroscope gives the
motions of approach and recess irrespective of other motions excepting
that of the earth. It gives in short the motions of approach and recess
of the stars relatively to the earth.[195]

  [195] Roscoe’s *Spectrum Analysis*, 1st ed. p. 296.

The rapidity of vibration for each musical tone, having been accurately
determined by comparison with the Syren (p. 10), we can use sounds as
indirect indications of rapid vibrations. It is now known that the
contraction of a muscle arises from the periodical contractions of each
separate fibre, and from a faint sound or susurrus which accompanies
the action of a muscle, it is inferred that each contraction lasts for
about one 300th part of a second. Minute quantities of radiant heat are
now always measured indirectly by the electricity which they produce
when falling upon a thermopile. The extreme delicacy of the method
seems to be due to the power of multiplication at several points in the
apparatus. The number of elements or junctions of different metals in
the thermopile can be increased so that the tension of the electric
current derived from the same intensity of radiation is multiplied;
the effect of the current upon the magnetic needle can be multiplied
within certain bounds, by passing the current many times round it in
a coil; the excursions of the needle can be increased by rendering it
astatic and increasing the delicacy of its suspension; lastly, the
angular divergence can be observed, with any required accuracy, by the
use of an attached mirror and distant scale viewed through a telescope
(p. 287). Such is the delicacy of this method of measuring heat, that
Dr. Joule succeeded in making a thermopile which would indicate a
difference of 0°·000114 Cent.[196]

  [196] *Philosophical Transactions* (1859), vol. cxlix. p. 94.

A striking case of indirect measurement is furnished by the revolving
mirror of Wheatstone and Foucault, whereby a minute interval of time
is estimated in the form of an angular deviation. Wheatstone viewed an
electric spark in a mirror rotating so rapidly, that if the duration
of the spark had been more than one 72,000th part of a second, the
point of light would have appeared elongated to an angular extent
of one-half degree. In the spark, as drawn directly from a Leyden
jar, no elongation was apparent, so that the duration of the spark
was immeasurably small; but when the discharge took place through
a bad conductor, the elongation of the spark denoted a sensible
duration.[197] In the hands of Foucault the rotating mirror gave a
measure of the time occupied by light in passing through a few metres
of space.

  [197] Watts’ *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. ii. p. 393.


*Comparative Use of Measuring Instruments.*

In almost every case a measuring instrument serves, and should serve
only as a means of comparison between two or more magnitudes. As a
general rule, we should not attempt to make the divisions of the
measuring scale exact multiples or submultiples of the unit, but,
regarding them as arbitrary marks, should determine their values by
comparison with the standard itself. The perpendicular wires in the
field of a transit telescope, are fixed at nearly equal but arbitrary
distances, and those distances are afterwards determined, as first
suggested by Malvasia, by watching the passage of star after star
across them, and noting the intervals of time by the clock. Owing
to the perfectly regular motion of the earth, these time intervals
give exact determinations of the angular intervals. In the same way,
the angular value of each turn of the screw micrometer attached to a
telescope, can be easily and accurately ascertained.

When a thermopile is used to observe radiant heat, it would be almost
impossible to calculate on *à priori* grounds what is the value of
each division of the galvanometer circle, and still more difficult
to construct a galvanometer, so that each division should have a
given value. But this is quite unnecessary, because by placing the
thermopile before a body of known dimensions, at a known distance, with
a known temperature and radiating power, we measure a known amount
of radiant heat, and inversely measure the value of the indications
of the thermopile. In a similar way Dr. Joule ascertained the actual
temperature produced by the compression of bars of metal. For having
inserted a small thermopile composed of a single junction of copper and
iron wire, and noted the deflections of the galvanometer, he had only
to dip the bars into water of different temperatures, until he produced
a like deflection, in order to ascertain the temperature developed by
pressure.[198]

  [198] *Philosophical Transactions* (1859), vol. cxlix. p. 119, &c.

In some cases we are obliged to accept a very carefully constructed
instrument as a standard, as in the case of a standard barometer or
thermometer. But it is then best to treat all inferior instruments
comparatively only, and determine the values of their scales by
comparison with the assumed standard.


*Systematic Performance of Measurements.*

When a large number of accurate measurements have to be effected, it
is usually desirable to make a certain number of determinations with
scrupulous care, and afterwards use them as points of reference for the
remaining determinations. In the trigonometrical survey of a country,
the principal triangulation fixes the relative positions and distances
of a few points with rigid accuracy. A minor triangulation refers every
prominent hill or village to one of the principal points, and then the
details are filled in by reference to the secondary points. The survey
of the heavens is effected in a like manner. The ancient astronomers
compared the right ascensions of a few principal stars with the moon,
and thus ascertained their positions with regard to the sun; the minor
stars were afterwards referred to the principal stars. Tycho followed
the same method, except that he used the more slowly moving planet
Venus instead of the moon. Flamsteed was in the habit of using about
seven stars, favourably situated at points all round the heavens. In
his early observations the distances of the other stars from these
standard points were determined by the use of the quadrant.[199] Even
since the introduction of the transit telescope and the mural circle,
tables of standard stars are formed at Greenwich, the positions being
determined with all possible accuracy, so that they can be employed for
purposes of reference by astronomers.

  [199] Baily’s *Account of Flamsteed*, pp. 378–380.

In ascertaining the specific gravities of substances, all gases are
referred to atmospheric air at a given temperature and pressure;
all liquids and solids are referred to water. We require to compare
the densities of water and air with great care, and the comparative
densities of any two substances whatever can then be ascertained.

In comparing a very great with a very small magnitude, it is
usually desirable to break up the process into several steps, using
intermediate terms of comparison. We should never think of measuring
the distance from London to Edinburgh by laying down measuring rods,
throughout the whole length. A base of several miles is selected on
level ground, and compared on the one hand with the standard yard,
and on the other with the distance of London and Edinburgh, or any
other two points, by trigonometrical survey. Again, it would be
exceedingly difficult to compare the light of a star with that of the
sun, which would be about thirty thousand million times greater; but
Herschel[200] effected the comparison by using the full moon as an
intermediate unit. Wollaston ascertained that the sun gave 801,072
times as much light as the full moon, and Herschel determined that the
light of the latter exceeded that of α Centauri 27,408 times, so that
we find the ratio between the light of the sun and star to be that of
about 22,000,000,000 to 1.

  [200] Herschel’s *Astronomy*, § 817, 4th. ed. p. 553.


*The Pendulum.*

By far the most perfect and beautiful of all instruments of measurement
is the pendulum. Consisting merely of a heavy body suspended freely
at an invariable distance from a fixed point, it is most simple in
construction; yet all the highest problems of physical measurement
depend upon its careful use. Its excessive value arises from two
circumstances.

(1) The method of repetition is eminently applicable to it, as already
described (p. 290).

(2) Unlike other instruments, it connects together three different
quantities, those of space, time, and force.

In most works on natural philosophy it is shown, that when the
oscillations of the pendulum are infinitely small, the square of the
time occupied by an oscillation is directly proportional to the length
of the pendulum, and indirectly proportional to the force affecting it,
of whatever kind. The whole theory of the pendulum is contained in the
formula, first given by Huygens in his *Horologium Oscillatorium*.

  Time of oscillation = 3·14159 × √(length of pendulum/force).

The quantity 3·14159 is the constant ratio of the circumference and
radius of a circle, and is of course known with accuracy. Hence, any
two of the three quantities concerned being given, the third may be
found; or any two being maintained invariable, the third will be
invariable. Thus a pendulum of invariable length suspended at the
same place, where the force of gravity may be considered constant,
furnishes a measure of time. The same invariable pendulum being made
to vibrate at different points of the earth’s surface, and the times
of vibration being astronomically determined, the force of gravity
becomes accurately known. Finally, with a known force of gravity, and
time of vibration ascertained by reference to the stars, the length is
determinate.

All astronomical observations depend upon the first manner of using the
pendulum, namely, in the astronomical clock. In the second employment
it has been almost equally indispensable. The primary principle that
gravity is equal in all matter was proved by Newton’s and Gauss’
pendulum experiments. The torsion pendulum of Michell, Cavendish, and
Baily, depending upon exactly the same principles as the ordinary
pendulum, gave the density of the earth, one of the foremost natural
constants. Kater and Sabine, by pendulum observations in different
parts of the earth, ascertained the variation of gravity, whence comes
a determination of the earth’s ellipticity. The laws of electric
and magnetic attraction have also been determined by the method
of vibrations, which is in constant use in the measurement of the
horizontal force of terrestrial magnetism.

We must not confuse with the ordinary use of the pendulum its
application by Newton, to show the absence of internal friction against
space,[201] or to ascertain the laws of motion and elasticity.[202] In
these cases the extent of vibration is the quantity measured, and the
principles of the instrument are different.

  [201] *Principia*, bk. ii. Sect. 6. Prop. 31. Motte’s Translation,
  vol. ii. p. 107.

  [202] Ibid. bk. i. Law iii. Corollary 6. Motte’s Translation, vol. i.
  p. 33.


*Attainable Accuracy of Measurement.*

It is a matter of some interest to compare the degrees of accuracy
which can be attained in the measurement of different kinds of
magnitude. Few measurements of any kind are exact to more than six
significant figures,[203] but it is seldom that such accuracy can be
hoped for. Time is the magnitude which seems to be capable of the most
exact estimation, owing to the properties of the pendulum, and the
principle of repetition described in previous sections. As regards
short intervals of time, it has already been stated that Sir George
Airy was able to estimate one part in 8,640,000, an exactness, as he
truly remarks, “almost beyond conception.”[204] The ratio between the
mean solar and the sidereal day is known to be about one part in one
hundred millions, or to the eighth place of decimals, (p. 289).

  [203] Thomson and Tait’s *Natural Philosophy*, vol. i. p. 333.

  [204] *Philosophical Transactions*, (1856), vol. cxlvi. pp. 330, 331.

Determinations of weight seem to come next in exactness, owing to the
fact that repetition without error is applicable to them. An ordinary
good balance should show about one part in 500,000 of the load. The
finest balance employed by M. Stas, turned with one part in 825,000 of
the load.[205] But balances have certainly been constructed to show
one part in a million,[206] and Ramsden is said to have constructed a
balance for the Royal Society, to indicate one part in seven millions,
though this is hardly credible. Professor Clerk Maxwell takes it for
granted that one part in five millions can be detected, but we ought to
discriminate between what a balance can do when first constructed, and
when in continuous use.

  [205] *First Annual Report of the Mint*, p. 106.

  [206] Jevons, in Watts’ *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. i. p. 483.

Determinations of length, unless performed with extraordinary care,
are open to much error in the junction of the measuring bars. Even
in measuring the base line of a trigonometrical survey, the accuracy
generally attained is only that of about one part in 60,000, or an
inch in the mile; but it is said that in four measurements of a base
line carried out very recently at Cape Comorin, the greatest error was
0·077 inch in 1·68 mile, or one part in 1,382,400, an almost incredible
degree of accuracy. Sir J. Whitworth has shown that touch is even a
more delicate mode of measuring lengths than sight, and by means of
a splendidly executed screw, and a small cube of iron placed between
two flat-ended iron bars, so as to be suspended when touching them, he
can detect a change of dimension in a bar, amounting to no more than
one-millionth of an inch.[207]

  [207] British Association, Glasgow, 1856. *Address of the President
  of the Mechanical Section*.




CHAPTER XIV.

UNITS AND STANDARDS OF MEASUREMENT.


As we have seen, instruments of measurement are only means of
comparison between one magnitude and another, and as a general rule we
must assume some one arbitrary magnitude, in terms of which all results
of measurement are to be expressed. Mere ratios between any series of
objects will never tell us their absolute magnitudes; we must have at
least one ratio for each, and we must have one absolute magnitude.
The number of ratios *n* are expressible in *n* equations, which will
contain at least *n* + 1 quantities, so that if we employ them to make
known *n* magnitudes, we must have one magnitude known. Hence, whether
we are measuring time, space, density, mass, weight, energy, or any
other physical quantity, we must refer to some concrete standard, some
actual object, which if once lost and irrecoverable, all our measures
lose their absolute meaning. This concrete standard is in all cases
arbitrary in point of theory, and its selection a question of practical
convenience.

There are two kinds of magnitude, indeed, which do not need to be
expressed in terms of arbitrary concrete units, since they pre-suppose
the existence of natural standard units. One case is that of abstract
number itself, which needs no special unit, because any object which
exists or is thought of as separate from other objects (p. 157)
furnishes us with a unit, and is the only standard required.

Angular magnitude is the second case in which we have a natural unit
of reference, namely the whole revolution or *perigon*, as it has
been called by Mr. Sandeman.[208] It is a necessary result of the
uniform properties of space, that all complete revolutions are equal
to each other, so that we need not select any one revolution, but can
always refer anew to space itself. Whether we take the whole perigon,
its half, or its quarter, is really immaterial; Euclid took the right
angle, because the Greek geometers had never generalised their notions
of angular magnitude sufficiently to treat angles of all magnitudes,
or of unlimited *quantity of revolution*. Euclid defines a right angle
as half that made by a line with its own continuation, which is of
course equal to half a revolution, but which was not treated as an
angle by him. In mathematical analysis a different fraction of the
perigon is taken, namely, such a fraction that the arc or portion of
the circumference included within it is equal to the radius of the
circle. In this point of view angular magnitude is an abstract ratio,
namely, the ratio between the length of arc subtended and the length
of the radius. The geometrical unit is then necessarily the angle
corresponding to the ratio unity. This angle is equal to about 57°,
17′, 44″·8, or decimally 57°·295779513... .[209] It was called by De
Morgan the *arcual unit*, but a more convenient name for common use
would be *radian*, as suggested by Professor Everett. Though this
standard angle is naturally employed in mathematical analysis, and any
other unit would introduce great complexity, we must not look upon it
as a distinct unit, since its amount is connected with that of the half
perigon, by the natural constant 3·14159... usually denoted by the
letter π.

  [208] *Pelicotetics, or the Science of Quantity; an Elementary
  Treatise on Algebra, and its groundwork Arithmetic.* By Archibald
  Sandeman, M. A. Cambridge (Deighton, Bell, and Co.), 1868, p. 304.

  [209] De Morgan’s *Trigonometry and Double Algebra*, p. 5.

When we pass to other species of quantity, the choice of unit is found
to be entirely arbitrary. There is absolutely no mode of defining a
length, but by selecting some physical object exhibiting that length
between certain obvious points--as, for instance, the extremities of a
bar, or marks made upon its surface.


*Standard Unit of Time.*

Time is the great independent variable of all change--that which itself
flows on uninterruptedly, and brings the variety which we call motion
and life. When we reflect upon its intimate nature, Time, like every
other element of existence, proves to be an inscrutable mystery. We
can only say with St. Augustin, to one who asks us what is time, “I
know when you do not ask me.” The mind of man will ask what can never
be answered, but one result of a true and rigorous logical philosophy
must be to convince us that scientific explanation can only take place
between phenomena which have something in common, and that when we get
down to primary notions, like those of time and space, the mind must
meet a point of mystery beyond which it cannot penetrate. A definition
of time must not be looked for; if we say with Hobbes,[210] that it is
“the phantasm of before and after in motion,” or with Aristotle that it
is “the number of motion according to former and latter,” we obviously
gain nothing, because the notion of time is involved in the expressions
*before and after*, *former and latter*. Time is undoubtedly one of
those primary notions which can only be defined physically, or by
observation of phenomena which proceed in time.

  [210] *English Works of Thos. Hobbes*, Edit. by Molesworth, vol. i.
  p. 95.

If we have not advanced a step beyond Augustin’s acute reflections on
this subject,[211] it is curious to observe the wonderful advances
which have been made in the practical measurement of its efflux. In
earlier centuries the rude sun-dial or the rising of a conspicuous star
gave points of reference, while the flow of water from the clepsydra,
the burning of a candle, or, in the monastic ages, even the continuous
chanting of psalms, were the means of roughly subdividing periods, and
marking the hours of the day and night.[212] The sun and stars still
furnish the standard of time, but means of accurate subdivision have
become requisite, and this has been furnished by the pendulum and the
chronograph. By the pendulum we can accurately divide the day into
seconds of time. By the chronograph we can subdivide the second into
a hundred, a thousand, or even a million parts. Wheatstone measured
the duration of an electric spark, and found it to be no more than one
115,200th part of a second, while more recently Captain Noble has been
able to appreciate intervals of time not exceeding the millionth part
of a second.

  [211] *Confessions*, bk. xi. chapters 20–28.

  [212] Sir G. C. Lewis gives many curious particulars concerning the
  measurement of time in his *Astronomy of the Ancients*, pp. 241, &c.

When we come to inquire precisely what phenomenon it is that we thus
so minutely measure, we meet insurmountable difficulties. Newton
distinguished time according as it was *absolute* or *apparent* time,
in the following words:--“Absolute, true, and mathematical time,
of itself and from its own nature, flows equably without regard to
anything external, and by another name is called *duration*; relative,
apparent and common time, is some sensible and external measure of
duration by the means of motion.”[213] Though we are perhaps obliged to
assume the existence of a uniformly increasing quantity which we call
time, yet we cannot feel or know abstract and absolute time. Duration
must be made manifest to us by the recurrence of some phenomenon. The
succession of our own thoughts is no doubt the first and simplest
measure of time, but a very rude one, because in some persons and
circumstances the thoughts evidently flow with much greater rapidity
than in other persons and circumstances. In the absence of all
other phenomena, the interval between one thought and another would
necessarily become the unit of time, but the most cursory observations
show that there are changes in the outward world much better fitted by
their constancy to measure time than the change of thoughts within us.

  [213] *Principia*, bk. i. *Scholium to Definitions*. Translated by
  Motte, vol. i. p. 9. See also p. 11.

The earth, as I have already said, is the real clock of the astronomer,
and is practically assumed as invariable in its movements. But on
what ground is it so assumed? According to the first law of motion,
every body perseveres in its state of rest or of uniform motion in
a right line, unless it is compelled to change that state by forces
impressed thereon. Rotatory motion is subject to a like condition,
namely, that it perseveres uniformly unless disturbed by extrinsic
forces. Now uniform motion means motion through equal spaces in equal
times, so that if we have a body entirely free from all resistance
or perturbation, and can measure equal spaces of its path, we have a
perfect measure of time. But let it be remembered that this law has
never been absolutely proved by experience; for we cannot point to any
body, and say that it is wholly unresisted or undisturbed; and even if
we had such a body, we should need some independent standard of time
to ascertain whether its motion was really uniform. As it is in moving
bodies that we find the best standard of time, we cannot use them to
prove the uniformity of their own movements, which would amount to a
*petitio principii*. Our experience comes to this, that when we examine
and compare the movements of bodies which seem to us nearly free from
disturbance, we find them giving nearly harmonious measures of time.
If any one body which seems to us to move uniformly is not doing so,
but is subject to fits and starts unknown to us, because we have no
absolute standard of time, then all other bodies must be subject to the
same arbitrary fits and starts, otherwise there would be discrepancy
disclosing the irregularities. Just as in comparing together a number
of chronometers, we should soon detect bad ones by their going
irregularly, as compared with the others, so in nature we detect
disturbed movement by its discrepancy from that of other bodies which
we believe to be undisturbed, and which agree nearly among themselves.
But inasmuch as the measure of motion involves time, and the measure
of time involves motion, there must be ultimately an assumption. We
may define equal times, as times during which a moving body under the
influence of no force describes equal spaces;[214] but all we can
say in support of this definition is, that it leads us into no known
difficulties, and that to the best of our experience one freely moving
body gives the same results as any other.

  [214] Rankine, *Philosophical Magazine*, Feb. 1867, vol. xxxiii.
  p. 91.

When we inquire where the freely moving body is, no perfectly
satisfactory answer can be given. Practically the rotating globe is
sufficiently accurate, and Thomson and Tait say: “Equal times are
times during which the earth turns through equal angles.”[215] No long
time has passed since astronomers thought it impossible to detect any
inequality in its movement. Poisson was supposed to have proved that a
change in the length of the sidereal day amounting to one ten-millionth
part in 2,500 years was incompatible with an ancient eclipse recorded
by the Chaldæans, and similar calculations were made by Laplace. But
it is now known that these calculations were somewhat in error, and
that the dissipation of energy arising out of the friction of tidal
waves, and the radiation of the heat into space, has slightly decreased
the rapidity of the earth’s rotatory motion. The sidereal day is now
longer by one part in 2,700,000, than it was in 720 B.C. Even before
this discovery, it was known that invariability of rotation depended
upon the perfect maintenance of the earth’s internal heat, which is
requisite in order that the earth’s dimensions shall be unaltered. Now
the earth being superior in temperature to empty space, must cool more
or less rapidly, so that it cannot furnish an absolute measure of time.
Similar objections could be raised to all other rotating bodies within
our cognisance.

  [215] *Treatise on Natural Philosophy*, vol. i. p. 179.

The moon’s motion round the earth, and the earth’s motion round the
sun, form the next best measure of time. They are subject, indeed,
to disturbance from other planets, but it is believed that these
perturbations must in the course of time run through their rhythmical
courses, leaving the mean distances unaffected, and consequently, by
the third Law of Kepler, the periodic times unchanged. But there is
more reason than not to believe that the earth encounters a slight
resistance in passing through space, like that which is so apparent
in Encke’s comet. There may also be dissipation of energy in the
electrical relations of the earth to the sun, possibly identical with
that which is manifested in the retardation of comets.[216] It is
probably an untrue assumption then, that the earth’s orbit remains
quite invariable. It is just possible that some other body may be found
in the course of time to furnish a better standard of time than the
earth in its annual motion. The greatly superior mass of Jupiter and
its satellites, and their greater distance from the sun, may render the
electrical dissipation of energy less considerable than in the case of
the earth. But the choice of the best measure will always be an open
one, and whatever moving body we choose may ultimately be shown to be
subject to disturbing forces.

  [216] *Proceedings of the Manchester Philosophical Society*, 28th
  Nov. 1871, vol. xi. p. 33.

The pendulum, although so admirable an instrument for subdivision of
time, fails as a standard; for though the same pendulum affected by the
same force of gravity performs equal vibrations in equal times, yet
the slightest change in the form or weight of the pendulum, the least
corrosion of any part, or the most minute displacement of the point of
suspension, falsifies the results, and there enter many other difficult
questions of temperature, friction, resistance, length of vibration, &c.

Thomson and Tait are of opinion[217] that the ultimate standard of
chronometry must be founded on the physical properties of some body
of more constant character than the earth; for instance, a carefully
arranged metallic spring, hermetically sealed in an exhausted glass
vessel. But it is hard to see how we can be sure that the dimensions
and elasticity of a piece of wrought metal will remain perfectly
unchanged for the few millions of years contemplated by them. A nearly
perfect gas, like hydrogen, is perhaps the only kind of substance in
the unchanged elasticity of which we could have confidence. Moreover,
it is difficult to perceive how the undulations of such a spring could
be observed with the requisite accuracy. More recently Professor Clerk
Maxwell has made the novel suggestion, discussed in a subsequent
section, that undulations of light *in vacuo* would form the most
universal standard of reference, both as regards time and space.
According to this system the unit of time would be the time occupied
by one vibration of the particular kind of light whose wave length is
taken as the unit of length.

  [217] *The Elements of Natural Philosophy*, part i. p. 119.


*The Unit of Space and the Bar Standard.*

Next in importance after the measurement of time is that of space.
Time comes first in theory, because phenomena, our internal thoughts
for instance, may change in time without regard to space. As to the
phenomena of outward nature, they tend more and more to resolve
themselves into motions of molecules, and motion cannot be conceived or
measured without reference both to time and space.

Turning now to space measurement, we find it almost equally difficult
to fix and define once and for ever, a unit magnitude. There are
three different modes in which it has been proposed to attempt the
perpetuation of a standard length.

(1) By constructing an actual specimen of the standard yard or metre,
in the form of a bar.

(2) By assuming the globe itself to be the ultimate standard of
magnitude, the practical unit being a submultiple of some dimension of
the globe.

(3) By adopting the length of the simple seconds pendulum, as a
standard of reference.

At first sight it might seem that there was no great difficulty in this
matter, and that any one of these methods might serve well enough;
but the more minutely we inquire into the details, the more hopeless
appears to be the attempt to establish an invariable standard. We must
in the first place point out a principle not of an obvious character,
namely, that *the standard length must be defined by one single
object*.[218] To make two bars of exactly the same length, or even two
bars bearing a perfectly defined ratio to each other, is beyond the
power of human art. If two copies of the standard metre be made and
declared equally correct, future investigators will certainly discover
some discrepancy between them, proving of course that they cannot both
be the standard, and giving cause for dispute as to what magnitude
should then be taken as correct.

  [218] See Harris’ *Essay upon Money and Coins*, part. ii. [1758]
  p. 127.

If one invariable bar could be constructed and maintained as the
absolute standard, no such inconvenience could arise. Each successive
generation as it acquired higher powers of measurement, would detect
errors in the copies of the standard, but the standard itself would be
unimpeached, and would, as it were, become by degrees more and more
accurately known. Unfortunately to construct and preserve a metre or
yard is also a task which is either impossible, or what comes nearly
to the same thing, cannot be shown to be possible. Passing over the
practical difficulty of defining the ends of the standard length
with complete accuracy, whether by dots or lines on the surface, or
by the terminal points of the bar, we have no means of proving that
substances remain of invariable dimensions. Just as we cannot tell
whether the rotation of the earth is uniform, except by comparing it
with other moving bodies, believed to be more uniform in motion, so
we cannot detect the change of length in a bar, except by comparing
it with some other bar supposed to be invariable. But how are we to
know which is the invariable bar? It is certain that many rigid and
apparently invariable substances do change in dimensions. The bulb of
a thermometer certainly contracts by age, besides undergoing rapid
changes of dimensions when warmed or cooled through 100° Cent. Can
we be sure that even the most solid metallic bars do not slightly
contract by age, or undergo variations in their structure by change
of temperature. Fizeau was induced to try whether a quartz crystal,
subjected to several hundred alternations of temperature, would be
modified in its physical properties, and he was unable to detect any
change in the coefficient of expansion.[219] It does not follow,
however, that, because no apparent change was discovered in a quartz
crystal, newly-constructed bars of metal would undergo no change.

  [219] *Philosophical Magazine*, (1868), 4th Series, vol. xxxvi. p. 32.

The best principle, as it seems to me, upon which the perpetuation of
a standard of length can be rested, is that, if a variation of length
occurs, it will in all probability be of different amount in different
substances. If then a great number of standard metres were constructed
of all kinds of different metals and alloys; hard rocks, such as
granite, serpentine, slate, quartz, limestone; artificial substances,
such as porcelain, glass, &c., &c., careful comparison would show from
time to time the comparative variations of length of these different
substances. The most variable substances would be the most divergent,
and the standard would be furnished by the mean length of those which
agreed most closely with each other just as uniform motion is that of
those bodies which agree most closely in indicating the efflux of time.


*The Terrestrial Standard.*

The second method assumes that the globe itself is a body of invariable
dimensions and the founders of the metrical system selected the
ten-millionth part of the distance from the equator to the pole as
the definition of the metre. The first imperfection in such a method
is that the earth is certainly not invariable in size; for we know
that it is superior in temperature to surrounding space, and must be
slowly cooling and contracting. There is much reason to believe that
all earthquakes, volcanoes, mountain elevations, and changes of sea
level are evidences of this contraction as asserted by Mr. Mallet.[220]
But such is the vast bulk of the earth and the duration of its past
existence, that this contraction is perhaps less rapid in proportion
than that of any bar or other material standard which we can construct.

  [220] *Proceedings of the Royal Society*, 20th June, 1872, vol. xx.
  p. 438.

The second and chief difficulty of this method arises from the vast
size of the earth, which prevents us from making any comparison with
the ultimate standard, except by a trigonometrical survey of a most
elaborate and costly kind. The French physicists, who first proposed
the method, attempted to obviate this inconvenience by carrying out
the survey once for all, and then constructing a standard metre, which
should be exactly the one ten millionth part of the distance from the
pole to the equator. But since all measuring operations are merely
approximate, it was impossible that this operation could be perfectly
achieved. Accordingly, it was shown in 1838 that the supposed French
metre was erroneous to the considerable extent of one part in 5527. It
then became necessary either to alter the length of the assumed metre,
or to abandon its supposed relation to the earth’s dimensions. The
French Government and the International Metrical Commission have for
obvious reasons decided in favour of the latter course, and have thus
reverted to the first method of defining the metre by a given bar. As
from time to time the ratio between this assumed standard metre and the
quadrant of the earth becomes more accurately known, we have better
means of restoring that metre by reference to the globe if required.
But until lost, destroyed, or for some clear reason discredited,
the bar metre and not the globe is the standard. Thomson and Tait
remark that any of the more accurate measurements of the English
trigonometrical survey might in like manner be employed to restore our
standard yard, in terms of which the results are recorded.


*The Pendulum Standard.*

The third method of defining a standard length, by reference to the
seconds pendulum, was first proposed by Huyghens, and was at one time
adopted by the English Government. From the principle of the pendulum
(p. 302) it clearly appears that if the time of oscillation and the
force actuating the pendulum be the same, the length of the pendulum
must be the same. We do not get rid of theoretical difficulties, for
we must assume the attraction of gravity at some point of the earth’s
surface, say London, to be unchanged from time to time, and the
sidereal day to be invariable, neither assumption being absolutely
correct so far as we can judge. The pendulum, in short, is only an
indirect means of making one physical quantity of space depend upon two
other physical quantities of time and force.

The practical difficulties are, however, of a far more serious
character than the theoretical ones. The length of a pendulum is not
the ordinary length of the instrument, which might be greatly varied
without affecting the duration of a vibration, but the distance from
the centre of suspension to the centre of oscillation. There are no
direct means of determining this latter centre, which depends upon
the average momentum of all the particles of the pendulum as regards
the centre of suspension. Huyghens discovered that the centres of
suspension and oscillation are interchangeable, and Kater pointed
out that if a pendulum vibrates with exactly the same rapidity when
suspended from two different points, the distance between these points
is the true length of the equivalent simple pendulum.[221] But the
practical difficulties in employing Kater’s reversible pendulum are
considerable, and questions regarding the disturbance of the air, the
force of gravity, or even the interference of electrical attractions
have to be entertained. It has been shown that all the experiments made
under the authority of Government for determining the ratio between
the standard yard and the seconds pendulum, were vitiated by an error
in the corrections for the resisting, adherent, or buoyant power of
the air in which the pendulums were swung. Even if such corrections
were rendered unnecessary by operating in a vacuum, other difficult
questions remain.[222] Gauss’ mode of comparing the vibrations of a
wire pendulum when suspended at two different lengths is open to equal
or greater practical difficulties. Thus it is found that the pendulum
standard cannot compete in accuracy and certainty with the simple bar
standard, and the method would only be useful as an accessory mode of
restoring the bar standard if at any time again destroyed.

  [221] Kater’s *Treatise on Mechanics*, Cabinet Cyclopædia, p. 154.

  [222] Grant’s *History of Physical Astronomy*, p. 156.


*Unit of Density.*

Before we can measure the phenomena of nature, we require a third
independent unit, which shall enable us to define the quantity of
matter occupying any given space. All the changes of nature, as we
shall see, are probably so many manifestations of energy; but energy
requires some substratum or material machinery of molecules, in and by
which it may be manifested. Observation shows that, as regards force,
there may be two modes of variation of matter. As Newton says in the
first definition of the Principia, “the quantity of matter is the
measure of the same, arising from its density and bulk conjunctly.”
Thus the force required to set a body in motion varies both according
to the bulk of the matter, and also according to its quality. Two cubic
inches of iron of uniform quality, will require twice as much force
as one cubic inch to produce a certain velocity in a given time; but
one cubic inch of gold will require more force than one cubic inch of
iron. There is then some new measurable quality in matter apart from
its bulk, which we may call *density*, and which is, strictly speaking,
indicated by its capacity to resist and absorb the action of force.
For the unit of density we may assume that of any substance which is
uniform in quality, and can readily be referred to from time to time.
Pure water at any definite temperature, for instance that of snow
melting under inappreciable pressure, furnishes an invariable standard
of density, and by comparing equal bulks of various substances with
a like bulk of ice-cold water, as regards the velocity produced in a
unit of time by the same force, we should ascertain the densities of
those substances as expressed in that of water. Practically the force
of gravity is used to measure density; for a beautiful experiment with
the pendulum, performed by Newton and repeated by Gauss, shows that all
kinds of matter gravitate equally. Two portions of matter then which
are in equilibrium in the balance, may be assumed to possess equal
inertia, and their densities will therefore be inversely as their cubic
dimensions.


*Unit of Mass.*

Multiplying the number of units of density of a portion of matter,
by the number of units of space occupied by it, we arrive at the
quantity of matter, or, as it is usually called, the *unit of mass*, as
indicated by the inertia and gravity it possesses. To proceed in the
most simple manner, the unit of mass ought to be that of a cubic unit
of matter of the standard density; but the founders of the metrical
system took as their unit of mass, the cubic centimetre of water, at
the temperature of maximum density (about 4° Cent.). They called this
unit of mass the *gramme*, and constructed standard specimens of the
kilogram, which might be readily referred to by all who required to
employ accurate weights. Unfortunately the determination of the bulk
of a given weight of water at a certain temperature is an operation
involving many difficulties, and it cannot be performed in the present
day with a greater exactness than that of about one part in 5000, the
results of careful observers being sometimes found to differ as much as
one part in 1000.[223]

  [223] Clerk Maxwell’s *Theory of Heat*, p. 79.

Weights, on the other hand, can be compared with each other to at least
one part in a million. Hence if different specimens of the kilogram be
prepared by direct weighing against water, they will not agree closely
with each other; the two principal standard kilograms agree neither
with each other, nor with their definition. According to Professor
Miller the so-called Kilogramme des Archives weighs 15432·34874 grains,
while the kilogram deposited at the Ministry of the Interior in Paris,
as the standard for commercial purposes, weighs 15432·344 grains. Since
a standard weight constructed of platinum, or platinum and iridium, can
be preserved free from any appreciable alteration, and since it can be
very accurately compared with other weights, we shall ultimately attain
the greatest exactness in our measurements of mass, by assuming some
single kilogram as a *provisional standard*, leaving the determination
of its actual mass in units of space and density for future
investigation. This is what is practically done at the present day,
and thus a unit of mass takes the place of the unit of density, both
in the French and English systems. The English pound is defined by a
certain lump of platinum, preserved at Westminster, and is an arbitrary
mass, chosen merely that it may agree as nearly as possible with old
English pounds. The gallon, the old English unit of cubic measurement,
is defined by the condition that it shall contain exactly ten pounds
weight of water at 62° Fahr.; and although it is stated that it has the
capacity of about 277·274 cubic inches, this ratio between the cubic
and linear systems of measurement is not legally enacted, but left open
to investigation. While the French metric system as originally designed
was theoretically perfect, it does not differ practically in this point
from the English system.


*Natural System of Standards.*

Quite recently Professor Clerk Maxwell has suggested that the
vibrations of light and the atoms of matter might conceivably be
employed as the ultimate standards of length, time, and mass. We
should thus arrive at a *natural system of standards*, which,
though possessing no present practical importance, has considerable
theoretical interest. “In the present state of science,” he says, “the
most universal standard of length which we could assume would be the
wave-length in vacuum of a particular kind of light, emitted by some
widely diffused substance such as sodium, which has well-defined lines
in its spectrum. Such a standard would be independent of any changes in
the dimensions of the earth, and should be adopted by those who expect
their writings to be more permanent than that body.”[224] In the same
way we should get a universal standard unit of time, independent of
all questions about the motion of material bodies, by taking as the
unit the periodic time of vibration of that particular kind of light
whose wave-length is the unit of length. It would follow that with
these units of length and time the unit of velocity would coincide with
the velocity of light in empty space. As regards the unit of mass,
Professor Maxwell, humorously as I should think, remarks that if we
expect soon to be able to determine the mass of a single molecule of
some standard substance, we may wait for this determination before
fixing a universal standard of mass.

  [224] *Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism*, vol. i. p. 3.

In a theoretical point of view there can be no reasonable doubt that
vibrations of light are, as far as we can tell, the most fixed in
magnitude of all phenomena. There is as usual no certainty in the
matter, for the properties of the basis of light may vary to some
extent in different parts of space. But no differences could ever
be established in the velocity of light in different parts of the
solar system, and the spectra of the stars show that the times of
vibration there do not differ perceptibly from those in this part
of the universe. Thus all presumption is in favour of the absolute
constancy of the vibrations of light--absolute, that is, so far as
regards any means of investigation we are likely to possess. Nearly
the same considerations apply to the atomic weight as the standard of
mass. It is impossible to prove that all atoms of the same substance
are of equal mass, and some physicists think that they differ, so that
the fixity of combining proportions may be due only to the approximate
constancy of the mean of countless millions of discrepant weights. But
in any case the detection of difference is probably beyond our powers.
In a theoretical point of view, then, the magnitudes suggested by
Professor Maxwell seem to be the most fixed ones of which we have any
knowledge, so that they necessarily become the natural units.

In a practical point of view, as Professor Maxwell would be the first
to point out, they are of little or no value, because in the present
state of science we cannot measure a vibration or weigh an atom with
any approach to the accuracy which is attainable in the comparison
of standard metres and kilograms. The velocity of light is not known
probably within a thousandth part, and as we progress in the knowledge
of light, so we shall progress in the accurate fixation of other
standards. All that can be said then, is that it is very desirable
to determine the wave-lengths and periods of the principal lines of
the solar spectrum, and the absolute atomic weights of the elements,
with all attainable accuracy, in terms of our existing standards. The
numbers thus obtained would admit of the reproduction of our standards
in some future age of the world to a corresponding degree of accuracy,
were there need of such reference; but so far as we can see at present,
there is no considerable probability that this mode of reproduction
would ever be the best mode.


*Subsidiary Units.*

Having once established the standard units of time, space, and density
or mass, we might employ them for the expression of all quantities
of such nature. But it is often convenient in particular branches of
science to use multiples or submultiples of the original units, for the
expression of quantities in a simple manner. We use the mile rather
than the yard when treating of the magnitude of the globe, and the
mean distance of the earth and sun is not too large a unit when we
have to describe the distances of the stars. On the other hand, when
we are occupied with microscopic objects, the inch, the line or the
millimetre, become the most convenient terms of expression.

It is allowable for a scientific man to introduce a new unit in any
branch of knowledge, provided that it assists precise expression,
and is carefully brought into relation with the primary units. Thus
Professor A. W. Williamson has proposed as a convenient unit of
volume in chemical science, an absolute volume equal to about 11·2
litres representing the bulk of one gram of hydrogen gas at standard
temperature and pressure, or the *equivalent* weight of any other
gas, such as 16 grams of oxygen, 14 grams of nitrogen, &c.; in short,
the bulk of that quantity of any one of those gases which weighs as
many grams as there are units in the number expressing its atomic
weight.[225] Hofmann has proposed a new unit of weight for chemists,
called a *crith*, to be defined by the weight of one litre of hydrogen
gas at 0° C. and 0°·76 mm., weighing about 0·0896 gram.[226] Both of
these units must be regarded as purely subordinate units, ultimately
defined by reference to the primary units, and not involving any new
assumption.

  [225] *Chemistry for Students*, by A. W. Williamson. Clarendon Press
  Series, 2nd ed. Preface p. vi.

  [226] *Introduction to Chemistry*, p. 131.


*Derived Units.*

The standard units of time, space, and mass having been once fixed,
many kinds of magnitude are naturally measured by units derived from
them. From the metre, the unit of linear magnitude follows in the most
obvious manner the centiare or square metre, the unit of superficial
magnitude, and the litre that is the cube of the tenth part of a metre,
the unit of capacity or volume. Velocity of motion is expressed by the
ratio of the space passed over, when the motion is uniform, to the time
occupied; hence the unit of velocity is that of a body which passes
over a unit of space in a unit of time. In physical science the unit of
velocity might be taken as one metre per second. Momentum is measured
by the mass moving, regard being paid both to the amount of matter and
the velocity at which it is moving. Hence the unit of momentum will be
that of a unit volume of matter of the unit density moving with the
unit velocity, or in the French system, a cubic centimetre of water of
the maximum density moving one metre per second.

An accelerating force is measured by the ratio of the momentum
generated to the time occupied, the force being supposed to act
uniformly. The unit of force will therefore be that which generates
a unit of momentum in a unit of time, or which causes, in the French
system, one cubic centimetre of water at maximum density to acquire in
one second a velocity of one metre per second. The force of gravity is
the most familiar kind of force, and as, when acting unimpeded upon any
substance, it produces in a second a velocity of 9·80868 . . metres per
second in Paris, it follows that the absolute unit of force is about
the tenth part of the force of gravity. If we employ British weights
and measures, the absolute unit of force is represented by the gravity
of about half an ounce, since the force of gravity of any portion of
matter acting upon that matter during one second, produces a final
velocity of 32·1889 feet per second or about 32 units of velocity.
Although from its perpetual action and approximate uniformity we find
in gravity the most convenient force for reference, and thus habitually
employ it to estimate quantities of matter, we must remember that it
is only one of many instances of force. Strictly speaking, we should
express weight in terms of force, but practically we express other
forces in terms of weight.

We still require the unit of energy, a more complex notion. The
momentum of a body expresses the quantity of motion which belongs or
would belong to the aggregate of the particles; but when we consider
how this motion is related to the action of a force producing or
removing it, we find that the effect of a force is proportional to the
mass multiplied by the square of the velocity and it is convenient to
take half this product as the expression required. But it is shown in
books upon dynamics that it will be exactly the same thing if we define
energy by a force acting through a space. The natural unit of energy
will then be that which overcomes a unit of force acting through a unit
of space; when we lift one kilogram through one metre, against gravity,
we therefore accomplish 9·80868 . . units of work, that is, we turn so
many units of potential energy existing in the muscles, into potential
energy of gravitation. In lifting one pound through one foot there is
in like manner a conversion of 32·1889 units of energy. Accordingly the
unit of energy will be in the English system, that required to lift
one pound through about the thirty-second part of a foot; in terms of
metric units, it will be that required to lift a kilogram through about
one tenth part of a metre.

Every person is at liberty to measure and record quantities in terms of
any unit which he likes. He may use the yard for linear measurement and
the litre for cubic measurement, only there will then be a complicated
relation between his different results. The system of derived units
which we have been briefly considering, is that which gives the most
simple and natural relations between quantitative expressions of
different kinds, and therefore conduces to ease of comprehension and
saving of laborious calculation.

It would evidently be a source of great convenience if scientific men
could agree upon some single system of units, original and derived, in
terms of which all quantities could be expressed. Statements would thus
be rendered easily comparable, a large part of scientific literature
would be made intelligible to all, and the saving of mental labour
would be immense. It seems to be generally allowed, too, that the
metric system of weights and measures presents the best basis for the
ultimate system; it is thoroughly established in Western Europe; it is
legalised in England; it is already commonly employed by scientific
men; it is in itself the most simple and scientific of systems. There
is every reason then why the metric system should be accepted at least
in its main features.


*Provisional Units.*

Ultimately, as we can hardly doubt, all phenomena will be recognised
as so many manifestations of energy; and, being expressed in terms of
the unit of energy, will be referable to the primary units of space,
time, and density. To effect this reduction, however, in any particular
case, we must not only be able to compare different quantities of
the phenomenon, but to trace the whole series of steps by which it
is connected with the primary notions. We can readily observe that
the intensity of one source of light is greater than that of another;
and, knowing that the intensity of light decreases as the square of
the distance increases, we can easily determine their comparative
brilliance. Hence we can express the intensity of light falling upon
any surface, if we have a unit in which to make the expression. Light
is undoubtedly one form of energy, and the unit ought therefore to be
the unit of energy. But at present it is quite impossible to say how
much energy there is in any particular amount of light. The question
then arises,--Are we to defer the measurement of light until we can
assign its relation to other forms of energy? If we answer Yes, it
is equivalent to saying that the science of light must stand still
perhaps for a generation; and not only this science but many others.
The true course evidently is to select, as the provisional unit of
light, some light of convenient intensity, which can be reproduced from
time to time in the same intensity, and which is defined by physical
circumstances. All the phenomena of light may be experimentally
investigated relatively to this unit, for instance that obtained after
much labour by Bunsen and Roscoe.[227] In after years it will become a
matter of inquiry what is the energy exerted in such unit of light; but
it may be long before the relation is exactly determined.

  [227] *Philosophical Transactions* (1859), vol. cxlix. p. 884, &c.

A provisional unit, then, means one which is assumed and physically
defined in a safe and reproducible manner, in order that particular
quantities may be compared *inter se* more accurately than they can
yet be referred to the primary units. In reality the great majority
of our measurements are expressed in terms of such provisionally
independent units, and even the unit of mass, as we have seen, ought to
be considered as provisional.

The unit of heat ought to be simply the unit of energy, already
described. But a weight can be measured to the one-millionth part, and
temperature to less than the thousandth part of a degree Fahrenheit,
and to less therefore than the five-hundred thousandth part of the
absolute temperature, whereas the mechanical equivalent of heat
is probably not known to the thousandth part. Hence the need of a
provisional unit of heat, which is often taken as that requisite to
raise one gram of water through one degree Centigrade, that is from
0° to 1°. This quantity of heat is capable of approximate expression
in terms of time, space, and mass; for by the natural constant,
determined by Dr. Joule, and called the mechanical equivalent of heat,
we know that the assumed unit of heat is equal to the energy of 423·55
gram-metres, or that energy which will raise the mass of 423·55 grams
through one metre against 9·8... absolute units of force. Heat may also
be expressed in terms of the quantity of ice at 0° Cent., which it is
capable of converting into water under inappreciable pressure.


*Theory of Dimensions.*

In order to understand the relations between the quantities dealt with
in physical science, it is necessary to pay attention to the Theory of
Dimensions, first clearly stated by Joseph Fourier,[228] but in later
years developed by several physicists. This theory investigates the
manner in which each derived unit depends upon or involves one or more
of the fundamental units. The number of units in a rectangular area
is found by multiplying together the numbers of units in the sides;
thus the unit of length enters twice into the unit of area, which is
therefore said to have two dimensions with respect to length. Denoting
length by *L*, we may say that the dimensions of area are *L* × *L* or
*L*^{2}. It is obvious in the same way that the dimensions of volume or
bulk will be *L*^{3}.

  [228] *Théorie Analytique de la Chaleur*, Paris; 1822, §§ 157–162.

The number of units of mass in a body is found by multiplying the
number of units of volume, by those of density. Hence mass is of
three dimensions as regards length, and one as regards density.
Calling density *D*, the dimensions of mass are *L*^{3}*D*. As already
explained, however, it is usual to substitute an arbitrary provisional
unit of mass, symbolised by *M*; according to the view here taken we
may say that the dimensions of *M* are *L*^{3}*D*.

Introducing time, denoted by *T*, it is easy to see that the dimensions
of velocity will be *L/T* or *LT*^{-1}, because the number of units
in the velocity of a body is found by *dividing* the units of length
passed over by the units of time occupied in passing. The acceleration
of a body is measured by the increase of velocity in relation to the
time, that is, we must divide the units of velocity gained by the units
of time occupied in gaining it; hence its dimensions will be *LT*^{-2}.
Momentum is the product of mass and velocity, so that its dimensions
are *MLT*^{-1}. The effect of a force is measured by the acceleration
produced in a unit of mass in a unit of time; hence the dimensions of
force are *MLT*^{-2}. Work done is proportional to the force acting and
to the space through which it acts; so that it has the dimensions of
force with that of length added, giving *ML*^{2}*T*^{-2}.

It should be particularly noticed that angular magnitude has no
dimensions at all, being measured by the ratio of the arc to the radius
(p. 305). Thus we have the dimensions *LL*^{-1} or *L*^{0}. This
agrees with the statement previously made, that no arbitrary unit of
angular magnitude is needed. Similarly, all pure numbers expressing
ratios only, such as sines and other trigonometrical functions,
logarithms, exponents, &c., are devoid of dimensions. They are absolute
numbers necessarily expressed in terms of unity itself, and are quite
unaffected by the selection of the arbitrary physical units. Angular
magnitude, however, enters into other quantities, such as angular
velocity, which has the dimensions 1/*T* or *T*^{-1}, the units of
angle being divided by the units of time occupied. The dimensions of
angular acceleration are denoted by *T*^{-2}.

The quantities treated in the theories of heat and electricity
are numerous and complicated as regards their dimensions. Thermal
capacity has the dimensions *ML*^{-3}, thermal conductivity,
*ML*^{-1}*T*^{-1}. In Magnetism the dimensions of the strength
of pole are *M*^{1/2}*L*^{3/2}*T*^{-1}, the dimensions of
field-intensity are *M*^{1/2}*L*^{-1/2}*T*^{-1}, and the intensity
of magnetisation has the same dimensions. In the science of
electricity physicists have to deal with numerous kinds of quantity,
and their dimensions are different too in the electro-static
and the electro-magnetic systems. Thus electro-motive force has
the dimensions *M*^{1/2}*L*^{1/2}*T*^{-1}, in the former, and
*M*^{1/2}*L*^{3/2}*T*^{-2} in the latter system. Capacity simply
depends upon length in electro-statics, but upon *L*^{-1}*T*^{2} in
electro-magnetics. It is worthy of particular notice that electrical
quantities have simple dimensions when expressed in terms of density
instead of mass. The instances now given are sufficient to show the
difficulty of conceiving and following out the relations of the
quantities treated in physical science without a systematic method of
calculating and exhibiting their dimensions. It is only in quite recent
years that clear ideas about these quantities have been attained. Half
a century ago probably no one but Fourier could have explained what
he meant by temperature or capacity for heat. The notion of measuring
electricity had hardly been entertained.

Besides affording us a clear view of the complex relations of physical
quantities, this theory is specially useful in two ways. Firstly, it
affords a test of the correctness of mathematical reasoning. According
to the *Principle of Homogeneity*, all the quantities *added* together,
and equated in any equation, must have the same dimensions. Hence if,
on estimating the dimensions of the terms in any equation, they be not
homogeneous, some blunder must have been committed. It is impossible
to add a force to a velocity, or a mass to a momentum. Even if the
numerical values of the two members of a non-homogeneous equation were
equal, this would be accidental, and any alteration in the physical
units would produce inequality and disclose the falsity of the law
expressed in the equation.

Secondly, the theory of units enables us readily and infallibly to
deduce the change in the numerical expression of any physical quantity,
produced by a change in the fundamental units. It is of course obvious
that in order to represent the same absolute quantity, a number must
vary inversely as the magnitude of the units which are numbered. The
yard expressed in feet is 3; taking the inch as the unit instead of
the foot it becomes 36. Every quantity into which the dimension length
enters positively must be altered in like manner. Changing the unit
from the foot to the inch, numerical expressions of volume must be
multiplied by 12 × 12 × 12. When a dimension enters negatively the
opposite rule will hold. If for the minute we substitute the second
as unit of time, then we must divide all numbers expressing angular
velocities by 60, and numbers expressing angular acceleration by
60 × 60. The rule is that a numerical expression varies inversely as
the magnitude of the unit as regards each whole dimension entering
positively, and it varies directly as the magnitude of the unit for
each whole dimension entering negatively. In the case of fractional
exponents, the proper root of the ratio of change has to be taken.

The study of this subject may be continued in Professor J. D. Everett’s
“Illustrations of the Centimetre-gramme-second System of Units,”
published by Taylor and Francis, 1875; in Professor Maxwell’s “Theory
of Heat;” or Professor Fleeming Jenkin’s “Text Book of Electricity.”


*Natural Constants.*

Having acquired accurate measuring instruments, and decided upon the
units in which the results shall be expressed, there remains the
question, What use shall be made of our powers of measurement? Our
principal object must be to discover general quantitative laws of
nature; but a very large amount of preliminary labour is employed in
the accurate determination of the dimensions of existing objects, and
the numerical relations between diverse forces and phenomena. Step
by step every part of the material universe is surveyed and brought
into known relations with other parts. Each manifestation of energy is
correlated with each other kind of manifestation. Professor Tyndall has
described the care with which such operations are conducted.[229]

  [229] Tyndall’s *Sound*, 1st ed. p. 26.

“Those who are unacquainted with the details of scientific
investigation, have no idea of the amount of labour expended on
the determination of those numbers on which important calculations
or inferences depend. They have no idea of the patience shown by a
Berzelius in determining atomic weights; by a Regnault in determining
coefficients of expansion; or by a Joule in determining the mechanical
equivalent of heat. There is a morality brought to bear upon such
matters which, in point of severity, is probably without a parallel in
any other domain of intellectual action.”

Every new natural constant which is recorded brings many fresh
inferences within our power. For if *n* be the number of such constants
known, then 1/2 (*n*^{2}--*n*) is the number of ratios which are within
our powers of calculation, and this increases with the square of *n*.
We thus gradually piece together a map of nature, in which the lines of
inference from one phenomenon to another rapidly grow in complexity,
and the powers of scientific prediction are correspondingly augmented.

Babbage[230] proposed the formation of a collection of the constant
numbers of nature, a work which has at last been taken in hand by the
Smithsonian Institution.[231] It is true that a complete collection of
such numbers would be almost co-extensive with scientific literature,
since almost all the numbers occurring in works on chemistry,
mineralogy, physics, astronomy, &c., would have to be included.
Still a handy volume giving all the more important numbers and their
logarithms, referred when requisite to the different units in common
use, would be very useful. A small collection of constant numbers will
be found at the end of Babbage’s, Hutton’s, and many other tables of
logarithms, and a somewhat larger collection is given in Templeton’s
*Millwright and Engineer’s Pocket Companion*.

  [230] British Association, Cambridge, 1833. Report, pp. 484–490.

  [231] *Smithsonian Miscellaneous Collections*, vol. xii., the
  Constants of Nature, part. i. Specific gravities compiled by F. W.
  Clarke, 8vo. Washington, 1873.

Our present object will be to classify these constant numbers roughly,
according to their comparative generality and importance, under the
following heads:--

  (1) Mathematical constants.
  (2) Physical constants.
  (3) Astronomical constants.
  (4) Terrestrial numbers.
  (5) Organic numbers.
  (6) Social numbers.


*Mathematical Constants.*

At the head of the list of natural constants must come those which
express the necessary relations of numbers to each other. The ordinary
Multiplication Table is the most familiar and the most important of
such series of constants, and is, theoretically speaking, infinite in
extent. Next we must place the Arithmetical Triangle, the significance
of which has already been pointed out (p. 182). Tables of logarithms
also contain vast series of natural constants, arising out of the
relations of pure numbers. At the base of all logarithmic theory is
the mysterious natural constant commonly denoted by *e*, or ε, being
equal to the infinite series 1 + 1/1 + 1/1.2 + 1/1.2.3 + 1/1.2.3.4
+...., and thus consisting of the sum of the ratios between the numbers
of permutations and combinations of 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, &c. things. Tables
of prime numbers and of the factors of composite numbers must not be
forgotten.

Another vast and in fact infinite series of numerical constants
contains those connected with the measurement of angles, and embodied
in trigonometrical tables, whether as natural or logarithmic sines,
cosines, and tangents. It should never be forgotten that though these
numbers find their chief employment in connection with trigonometry,
or the measurement of the sides of a right-angled triangle, yet the
numbers themselves arise out of numerical relations bearing no special
relation to space. Foremost among trigonometrical constants is the
well known number π, usually employed as expressing the ratio of the
circumference and the diameter of a circle; from π follows the value of
the arcual or natural unit of angular value as expressed in ordinary
degrees (p. 306).

Among other mathematical constants not uncommonly used may be mentioned
tables of factorials (p. 179), tables of Bernoulli’s numbers, tables of
the error function,[232] which latter are indispensable not only in the
theory of probability but also in several other branches of science.

  [232] J. W. L. Glaisher, *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series,
  vol. xlii. p. 421.

It should be clearly understood that the mathematical constants and
tables of reference already in our possession, although very extensive,
are only an infinitely small part of what might be formed. With the
progress of science the tabulation of new functions will be continually
demanded, and it is worthy of consideration whether public money
should not be available to reward the severe, long continued, and
generally thankless labour which must be gone through in calculating
tables. Such labours are a benefit to the whole human race as long as
it shall exist, though there are few who can appreciate the extent
of this benefit. A most interesting and excellent description of
many mathematical tables will be found in De Morgan’s article on
*Tables*, in the *English Cyclopædia*, Division of Arts and Sciences,
vol. vii. p. 976. An almost exhaustive critical catalogue of extant
tables is being published by a Committee of the British Association,
two portions, drawn up chiefly by Mr. J. W. L. Glaisher and Professor
Cayley, having appeared in the Reports of the Association for 1873 and
1875.


*Physical Constants.*

The second class of constants contains those which refer to the
actual constitution of matter. For the most part they depend upon
the peculiarities of the chemical substance in question, but we may
begin with those which are of the most general character. In a first
sub-class we may place the velocity of light or heat undulations, the
numbers expressing the relation between the lengths of the undulations,
and the rapidity of the undulations, these numbers depending only on
the properties of the ethereal medium, and being probably the same in
all parts of the universe. The theory of heat gives rise to several
numbers of the highest importance, especially Joule’s mechanical
equivalent of heat, the absolute zero of temperature, the mean
temperature of empty space, &c.

Taking into account the diverse properties of the elements we must
have tables of the atomic weights, the specific heats, the specific
gravities, the refractive powers, not only of the elements, but their
almost infinitely numerous compounds. The properties of hardness,
elasticity, viscosity, expansion by heat, conducting powers for heat
and electricity, must also be determined in immense detail. There are,
however, certain of these numbers which stand out prominently because
they serve as intermediate units or terms of comparison. Such are, for
instance, the absolute coefficients of expansion of air, water and
mercury, the temperature of the maximum density of water, the latent
heats of water and steam, the boiling-point of water under standard
pressure, the melting and boiling-points of mercury, and so forth.


*Astronomical Constants.*

The third great class consists of numbers possessing far less
generality because they refer not to the properties of matter, but to
the special forms and distances in which matter has been disposed in
the part of the universe open to our examination. We have, first of
all, to define the magnitude and form of the earth, its mean density,
the constant of aberration of light expressing the relation between
the earth’s mean velocity in space and the velocity of light. From
the earth, as our observatory, we then proceed to lay down the mean
distances of the sun, and of the planets from the same centre; all the
elements of the planetary orbits, the magnitudes, densities, masses,
periods of axial rotation of the several planets are by degrees
determined with growing accuracy. The same labours must be gone through
for the satellites. Catalogues of comets with the elements of their
orbits, as far as ascertainable, must not be omitted.

From the earth’s orbit as a new base of observations, we next proceed
to survey the heavens and lay down the apparent positions, magnitudes,
motions, distances, periods of variation, &c. of the stars. All
catalogues of stars from those of Hipparchus and Tycho, are full of
numbers expressing rudely the conformation of the visible universe.
But there is obviously no limit to the labours of astronomers; not
only are millions of distant stars awaiting their first measurements,
but those already registered require endless scrutiny as regards
their movements in the three dimensions of space, their periods of
revolution, their changes of brilliance and colour. It is obvious that
though astronomical numbers are conventionally called *constant*, they
are probably in all cases subject to more or less rapid variation.


*Terrestrial Numbers.*

Our knowledge of the globe we inhabit involves many numerical
determinations, which have little or no connection with astronomical
theory. The extreme heights of the principal mountains, the mean
elevations of continents, the mean or extreme depths of the oceans,
the specific gravities of rocks, the temperature of mines, the host of
numbers expressing the meteorological or magnetic conditions of every
part of the surface, must fall into this class. Many such numbers
are not to be called constant, being subject to periodic or secular
changes, but they are hardly more variable in fact than some which in
astronomical science are set down as constant. In many cases quantities
which seem most variable may go through rhythmical changes resulting
in a nearly uniform average, and it is only in the long progress of
physical investigation that we can hope to discriminate successfully
between those elemental numbers which are fixed and those which vary.
In the latter case the law of variation becomes the constant relation
which is the object of our search.

*Organic Numbers.*

The forms and properties of brute nature having been sufficiently
defined by the previous classes of numbers, the organic world, both
vegetable and animal, remains outstanding, and offers a higher series
of phenomena for our investigation. All exact knowledge relating to
the forms and sizes of living things, their numbers, the quantities
of various compounds which they consume, contain, or excrete, their
muscular or nervous energy, &c. must be placed apart in a class by
themselves. All such numbers are doubtless more or less subject to
variation, and but in a minor degree capable of exact determination.
Man, so far as he is an animal, and as regards his physical form, must
also be treated in this class.


*Social Numbers.*

Little allusion need be made in this work to the fact that man in
his economic, sanitary, intellectual, æsthetic, or moral relations
may become the subject of sciences, the highest and most useful of
all sciences. Every one who is engaged in statistical inquiry must
acknowledge the possibility of natural laws governing such statistical
facts. Hence we must allot a distinct place to numerical information
relating to the numbers, ages, physical and sanitary condition,
mortality, &c., of different peoples, in short, to vital statistics.
Economic statistics, comprehending the quantities of commodities
produced, existing, exchanged and consumed, constitute another
extensive body of science. In the progress of time exact investigation
may possibly subdue regions of phenomena which at present defy all
scientific treatment. That scientific method can ever exhaust the
phenomena of the human mind is incredible.




CHAPTER XV.

ANALYSIS OF QUANTITATIVE PHENOMENA.


In the two preceding chapters we have been engaged in considering how
a phenomenon may be accurately measured and expressed. So delicate
and complex an operation is a measurement which pretends to any
considerable degree of exactness, that no small part of the skill
and patience of physicists is usually spent upon this work. Much
of this difficulty arises from the fact that it is scarcely ever
possible to measure a single effect at a time. The ultimate object
must be to discover the mathematical equation or law connecting a
quantitative cause with its quantitative effect; this purpose usually
involves, as we shall see, the varying of one condition at a time,
the other conditions being maintained constant. The labours of the
experimentalist would be comparatively light if he could carry out
this rule of varying one circumstance at a time. He would then obtain
a series of corresponding values of the variable quantities concerned,
from which he might by proper hypothetical treatment obtain the
required law of connection. But in reality it is seldom possible to
carry out this direction except in an approximate manner. Before then
we proceed to the consideration of the actual process of quantitative
induction, it is necessary to review the several devices by which a
complicated series of effects can be disentangled. Every phenomenon
measured will usually be the sum, difference, or it may be the product
or quotient, of two or more different effects, and these must be in
some way analysed and separately measured before we possess the
materials for inductive treatment.


*Illustrations of the Complication of Effects.*

It is easy to bring forward a multitude of instances to show that a
phenomenon is seldom to be observed simple and alone. A more or less
elaborate process of analysis is almost always necessary. Thus if an
experimentalist wishes to observe and measure the expansion of a liquid
by heat, he places it in a thermometer tube and registers the rise of
the column of liquid in the narrow tube. But he cannot heat the liquid
without also heating the glass, so that the change observed is really
the difference between the expansions of the liquid and the glass. More
minute investigation will show the necessity perhaps of allowing for
further minute effects, namely the compression of the liquid and the
expansion of the bulb due to the increased pressure of the column as it
becomes lengthened.

In a great many cases an observed effect will be apparently at least
the simple sum of two separate and independent effects. The heat
evolved in the combustion of oil is partly due to the carbon and partly
to the hydrogen. A measurement of the heat yielded by the two jointly,
cannot inform us how much proceeds from the one and how much from the
other. If by some separate determination we can ascertain how much the
hydrogen yields, then by mere subtraction we learn what is due to the
carbon; and *vice versâ*. The heat conveyed by a liquid, may be partly
conveyed by true conduction, partly by convection. The light dispersed
in the interior of a liquid consists both of what is reflected by
floating particles and what is due to true fluorescence;[233] and we
must find some mode of determining one portion before we can learn the
other. The apparent motion of the spots on the sun, is the algebraic
sum of the sun’s axial rotation, and of the proper motion of the spots
upon the sun’s surface; hence the difficulty of ascertaining by direct
observations the period of the sun’s rotation.

  [233] Stokes, *Philosophical Transactions* (1852), vol. cxlii. p. 529.

We cannot obtain the weight of a portion of liquid in a chemical
balance without weighing it with the containing vessel. Hence to have
the real weight of the liquid operated upon in an experiment, we must
make a separate weighing of the vessel, with or without the adhering
film of liquid according to circumstances. This is likewise the mode
in which a cart and its load are weighed together, the *tare* of the
cart previously ascertained being deducted. The variation in the height
of the barometer is a joint effect, partly due to the real variation
of the atmospheric pressure, partly to the expansion of the mercurial
column by heat. The effects may be discriminated, if, instead of one
barometer tube we have two tubes containing mercury placed closely side
by side, so as to have the same temperature. If one of them be closed
at the bottom so as to be unaffected by the atmospheric pressure, it
will show the changes due to temperature only, and, by subtracting
these changes from those shown in the other tube, employed as a
barometer, we get the real oscillations of atmospheric pressure. But
this correction, as it is called, of the barometric reading, is better
effected by calculation from the readings of an ordinary thermometer.

In other cases a quantitative effect will be the difference of
two causes acting in opposite directions. Sir John Herschel
invented an instrument like a large thermometer, which he called
the Actinometer,[234] and Pouillet constructed a somewhat similar
instrument called the Pyrheliometer, for ascertaining the heating power
of the sun’s rays. In both instruments the heat of the sun was absorbed
by a reservoir containing water, and the rise of temperature of the
water was exactly observed, either by its own expansion, or by the
readings of a delicate thermometer immersed in it. But in exposing the
actinometer to the sun, we do not obtain the full effect of the heat
absorbed, because the receiving surface is at the same time radiating
heat into empty space. The observed increment of temperature is in
short the difference between what is received from the sun and lost
by radiation. The latter quantity is capable of ready determination;
we have only to shade the instrument from the direct rays of the sun,
leaving it exposed to the sky, and we can observe how much it cools
in a certain time. The total effect of the sun’s rays will obviously
be the apparent effect *plus* the cooling effect in an equal time. By
alternate exposure in sun and shade during equal intervals the desired
result may be obtained with considerable accuracy.[235]

  [234] *Admiralty Manual of Scientific Enquiry*, 2nd ed. p. 299.

  [235] Pouillet, *Taylor’s Scientific Memoirs*, vol. iv. p. 45.

Two quantitative effects were beautifully distinguished in an
experiment of John Canton, devised in 1761 for the purpose of
demonstrating the compressibility of water. He constructed a
thermometer with a large bulb full of water and a short capillary
tube, the part of which above the water was freed from air. Under
these circumstances the water was relieved from the pressure of the
atmosphere, but the glass bulb in bearing that pressure was somewhat
contracted. He next placed the instrument under the receiver of an
air-pump, and on exhausting the air, the water sank in the tube. Having
thus obtained a measure of the effect of atmospheric pressure on the
bulb, he opened the top of the thermometer tube and admitted the air.
The level of the water now sank still more, partly from the pressure
on the bulb being now compensated, and partly from the compression of
the water by the atmospheric pressure. It is obvious that the amount of
the latter effect was approximately the difference of the two observed
depressions.

Not uncommonly the actual phenomenon which we wish to measure is
considerably less than various disturbing effects which enter into
the question. Thus the compressibility of mercury is considerably
less than the expansion of the vessels in which it is measured under
pressure, so that the attention of the experimentalist has chiefly
to be concentrated on the change of magnitude of the vessels. Many
astronomical phenomena, such as the parallax or the proper motions of
the fixed stars, are far less than the errors caused by instrumental
imperfections, or motions arising from precession, nutation, and
aberration. We need not be surprised that astronomers have from time to
time mistaken one phenomenon for another, as when Flamsteed imagined
that he had discovered the parallax of the Pole star.[236]

  [236] Baily’s *Account of the Rev. John Flamsteed*, p. 58.


*Methods of Eliminating Error.*

In any particular experiment it is the object of the experimentalist to
measure a single effect only, and he endeavours to obtain that effect
free from interfering effects. If this cannot be, as it seldom or
never can really be, he makes the effect as considerable as possible
compared with the other effects, which he reduces to a minimum, and
treats as noxious errors. Those quantities, which are called *errors*
in one case, may really be most important and interesting phenomena in
another investigation. When we speak of eliminating error we really
mean disentangling the complicated phenomena of nature. The physicist
rightly wishes to treat one thing at a time, but as this object can
seldom be rigorously carried into practice, he has to seek some mode of
counteracting the irrelevant and interfering causes.

The general principle is that a single observation can render known
only a single quantity. Hence, if several different quantitative
effects are known to enter into any investigation, we must have at
least as many distinct observations as there are quantities to be
determined. Every complete experiment will therefore consist in general
of several operations. Guided if possible by previous knowledge of the
causes in action, we must arrange the determinations, so that by a
simple mathematical process we may distinguish the separate quantities.
There appear to be five principal methods by which we may accomplish
this object; these methods are specified below and illustrated in the
succeeding sections.

(1) *The Method of Avoidance.* The physicist may seek for some special
mode of experiment or opportunity of observation, in which the error is
non-existent or inappreciable.

(2) *The Differential Method.* He may find opportunities of observation
when all interfering phenomena remain constant, and only the subject
of observation is at one time present and another time absent; the
difference between two observations then gives its amount.

(3) *The Method of Correction.* He may endeavour to estimate the amount
of the interfering effect by the best available mode, and then make a
corresponding correction in the results of observation.

(4) *The Method of Compensation.* He may invent some mode of
neutralising the interfering cause by balancing against it an exactly
equal and opposite cause of unknown amount.

(5) *The Method of Reversal.* He may so conduct the experiment that
the interfering cause may act in opposite directions, in alternate
observations, the mean result being free from interference.


I. *Method of Avoidance of Error.*

Astronomers seek opportunities of observation when errors will
be as small as possible. In spite of elaborate observations and
long-continued theoretical investigation, it is not practicable to
assign any satisfactory law to the refractive power of the atmosphere.
Although the apparent change of place of a heavenly body produced by
refraction may be more or less accurately calculated yet the error
depends upon the temperature and pressure of the atmosphere, and, when
a ray is highly inclined to the perpendicular, the uncertainty in the
refraction becomes very considerable. Hence astronomers always make
their observations, if possible, when the object is at the highest
point of its daily course, *i.e.* on the meridian. In some kinds of
investigation, as, for instance, in the determination of the latitude
of an observatory, the astronomer is at liberty to select one or
more stars out of the countless number visible. There is an evident
advantage in such a case, in selecting a star which passes close to
the zenith, so that it may be observed almost entirely free from
atmospheric refraction, as was done by Hooke.

Astronomers endeavour to render their clocks as accurate as
possible, by removing the source of variation. The pendulum is
perfectly isochronous so long as its length remains invariable, and
the vibrations are exactly of equal length. They render it nearly
invariable in length, that is in the distance between the centres of
suspension and oscillation, by a compensatory arrangement for the
change of temperature. But as this compensation may not be perfectly
accomplished, some astronomers place their chief controlling clock in
a cellar, or other apartment, where the changes of temperature may
be as slight as possible. At the Paris Observatory a clock has been
placed in the caves beneath the building, where there is no appreciable
difference between the summer and winter temperature.

To avoid the effect of unequal oscillations Huyghens made his beautiful
investigations, which resulted in the discovery that a pendulum, of
which the centre of oscillation moved upon a cycloidal path, would
be perfectly isochronous, whatever the variation in the length of
oscillations. But though a pendulum may be easily rendered in some
degree cycloidal by the use of a steel suspension spring, it is found
that the mechanical arrangements requisite to produce a truly cycloidal
motion introduce more error than they remove. Hence astronomers seek
to reduce the error to the smallest amount by maintaining their clock
pendulums in uniform movement; in fact, while a clock is in good order
and has the same weights, there need be little change in the length
of oscillation. When a pendulum cannot be made to swing uniformly,
as in experiments upon the force of gravity, it becomes requisite to
resort to the third method, and a correction is introduced, calculated
on theoretical grounds from the amount of the observed change in the
length of vibration.

It has been mentioned that the apparent expansion of a liquid by heat,
when contained in a thermometer tube or other vessel, is the difference
between the real expansion of the liquid and that of the containing
vessel. The effects can be accurately distinguished provided that we
can learn the real expansion by heat of any one convenient liquid;
for by observing the apparent expansion of the same liquid in any
required vessel we can by difference learn the amount of expansion of
the vessel due to any given change of temperature. When we once know
the change of dimensions of the vessel, we can of course determine the
absolute expansion of any other liquid tested in it. Thus it became an
all-important object in scientific research to measure with accuracy
the absolute dilatation by heat of some one liquid, and mercury owing
to several circumstances was by far the most suitable. Dulong and
Petit devised a beautiful mode of effecting this by simply avoiding
altogether the effect of the change of size of the vessel. Two upright
tubes full of mercury were connected by a fine tube at the bottom, and
were maintained at two different temperatures. As mercury was free to
flow from one tube to the other by the connecting tube, the two columns
necessarily exerted equal pressures by the principles of hydrostatics.
Hence it was only necessary to measure very accurately by a
cathetometer the difference of level of the surfaces of the two columns
of mercury, to learn the difference of length of columns of equal
hydrostatic pressure, which at once gives the difference of density of
the mercury, and the dilatation by heat. The changes of dimension in
the containing tubes became a matter of entire indifference, and the
length of a column of mercury at different temperatures was measured
as easily as if it had formed a solid bar. The experiment was carried
out by Regnault with many improvements of detail, and the absolute
dilatation of mercury, at temperatures between 0° Cent. and 350°, was
determined almost as accurately as was needful.[237]

  [237] Jamin, *Cours de Physique*, vol. ii. pp. 15–28.

The presence of a large and uncertain amount of error may render a
method of experiment valueless. Foucault devised a beautiful experiment
with the pendulum for demonstrating popularly the rotation of the
earth, but it could be of no use for measuring the rotation exactly. It
is impossible to make the pendulum swing in a perfect plane, and the
slightest lateral motion gives it an elliptic path with a progressive
motion of the axis of the ellipse, which disguises and often entirely
overpowers that due to the rotation of the earth.[238]

  [238] *Philosophical Magazine*, 1851, 4th Series, vol. ii. *passim*.

Faraday’s laborious experiments on the relation of gravity and
electricity were much obstructed by the fact that it is impossible
to move a large weight of metal without generating currents of
electricity, either by friction or induction. To distinguish the
electricity, if any, directly due to the action of gravity from the
greater quantities indirectly produced was a problem of excessive
difficulty. Baily in his experiments on the density of the earth was
aware of the existence of inexplicable disturbances which have since
been referred with much probability to the action of electricity.[239]
The skill and ingenuity of the experimentalist are often exhausted
in trying to devise a form of apparatus in which such causes of error
shall be reduced to a minimum.

  [239] Hearn, *Philosophical Transactions*, 1847, vol. cxxxvii.
  pp. 217–221.

In some rudimentary experiments we wish merely to establish the
existence of a quantitative effect without precisely measuring its
amount; if there exist causes of error of which we can neither
render the amount known or inappreciable, the best way is to make
them all negative so that the quantitative effects will be less than
the truth rather than greater. Grove, for instance, in proving that
the magnetisation or demagnetisation of a piece of iron raises its
temperature, took care to maintain the electro-magnet by which the iron
was magnetised at a lower temperature than the iron, so that it would
cool rather than warm the iron by radiation or conduction.[240]

  [240] *The Correlation of Physical Forces*, 3rd ed. p. 159.

Rumford’s celebrated experiment to prove that heat was generated out
of mechanical force in the boring of a cannon was subject to the
difficulty that heat might be brought to the cannon by conduction
from neighbouring bodies. It was an ingenious device of Davy to
produce friction by a piece of clock-work resting upon a block of
ice in an exhausted receiver; as the machine rose in temperature
above 32°, it was certain that no heat was received by conduction
from the support.[241] In many other experiments ice may be employed
to prevent the access of heat by conduction, and this device, first
put in practice by Murray,[242] is beautifully employed in Bunsen’s
calorimeter.

  [241] *Collected Works of Sir H. Davy*, vol. ii. pp. 12–14. *Elements
  of Chemical Philosophy*, p. 94.

  [242] *Nicholson’s Journal*, vol. i. p. 241; quoted in *Treatise on
  Heat*, Useful Knowledge Society, p. 24.

To observe the true temperature of the air, though apparently so easy,
is really a very difficult matter, because the thermometer is sure to
be affected either by the sun’s rays, the radiation from neighbouring
objects, or the escape of heat into space. These sources of error are
too fluctuating to allow of correction, so that the only accurate
mode of procedure is that devised by Dr. Joule, of surrounding the
thermometer with a copper cylinder ingeniously adjusted to the
temperature of the air, as described by him, so that the effect of
radiation shall be nullified.[243]

  [243] Clerk Maxwell, *Theory of Heat*, p. 228. *Proceedings of the
  Manchester Philosophical Society*, Nov. 26, 1867, vol. vii. p. 35.

When the avoidance of error is not practicable, it will yet be
desirable to reduce the absolute amount of the interfering error as
much as possible before employing the succeeding methods to correct
the result. As a general rule we can determine a quantity with less
inaccuracy as it is smaller, so that if the error itself be small
the error in determining that error will be of a still lower order
of magnitude. But in some cases the absolute amount of an error is
of no consequence, as in the index error of a divided circle, or the
difference between a chronometer and astronomical time. Even the rate
at which a clock gains or loses is a matter of little importance
provided it remain constant, so that a sure calculation of its amount
can be made.


2. *Differential Method.*

When we cannot avoid the existence of error, we can often resort
with success to the second mode by measuring phenomena under such
circumstances that the error shall remain very nearly the same in all
the observations, and neutralise itself as regards the purposes in
view. This mode is available whenever we want a difference between
quantities and not the absolute quantity of either. The determination
of the parallax of the fixed stars is exceedingly difficult, because
the amount of parallax is far less than most of the corrections for
atmospheric refraction, nutation, aberration, precession, instrumental
irregularities, &c., and can with difficulty be detected among these
phenomena of various magnitude. But, as Galileo long ago suggested,
all such difficulties would be avoided by the differential observation
of stars, which, though apparently close together, are really far
separated on the line of sight. Two such stars in close apparent
proximity will be subject to almost exactly equal errors, so that all
we need do is to observe the apparent change of place of the nearer
star as referred to the more distant one. A good telescope furnished
with an accurate micrometer is alone needed for the application of
the method. Huyghens appears to have been the first observer who
actually tried to employ the method practically, but it was not until
1835 that the improvement of telescopes and micrometers enabled
Struve to detect in this way the parallax of the star α Lyræ. It is
one of the many advantages of the observation of transits of Venus
for the determination of the solar parallax that the refraction of
the atmosphere affects in an exactly equal degree the planet and
the portion of the sun’s face over which it is passing. Thus the
observations are strictly of a differential nature.

By the process of substitutive weighing it is possible to ascertain
the equality or inequality of two weights with almost perfect freedom
from error. If two weights A and B be placed in the scales of the
best balance we cannot be sure that the equilibrium of the beam
indicates exact equality, because the arms of the beam may be unequal
or unbalanced. But if we take B out and put another weight C in, and
equilibrium still exists, it is apparent that the same causes of
erroneous weighing exist in both cases, supposing that the balance has
not been disarranged; B then must be exactly equal to C, since it has
exactly the same effect under the same circumstances. In like manner it
is a general rule that, if by any uniform mechanical process we get a
copy of an object, it is unlikely that this copy will be precisely the
same as the original in magnitude and form, but two copies will equally
diverge from the original, and will therefore almost exactly resemble
each other.

Leslie’s Differential Thermometer[244] was well adapted to the
experiments for which it was invented. Having two equal bulbs any
alteration in the temperature of the air will act equally by conduction
on each and produce no change in the indications of the instrument.
Only that radiant heat which is purposely thrown upon one of the bulbs
will produce any effect. This thermometer in short carries out the
principle of the differential method in a mechanical manner.

  [244] Leslie, *Inquiry into the Nature of Heat*, p. 10.


3. *Method of Correction.*

Whenever the result of an experiment is affected by an interfering
cause to a calculable amount, it is sufficient to add or subtract this
amount. We are said to correct observations when we thus eliminate
what is due to extraneous causes, although of course we are only
separating the correct effects of several agents. The variation in the
height of the barometer is partly due to the change of temperature,
but since the coefficient of absolute dilatation of mercury has been
exactly determined, as already described (p. 341), we have only to make
calculations of a simple character, or, what is better still, tabulate
a series of such calculations for general use, and the correction for
temperature can be made with all desired accuracy. The height of the
mercury in the barometer is also affected by capillary attraction,
which depresses it by a constant amount depending mainly on the
diameter of the tube. The requisite corrections can be estimated with
accuracy sufficient for most purposes, more especially as we can check
the correctness of the reading of a barometer by comparison with a
standard barometer, and introduce if need be an index error including
both the error in the affixing of the scale and the effect due to
capillarity. But in constructing the standard barometer itself we must
take greater precautions; the capillary depression depends somewhat
upon the quality of the glass, the absence of air, and the perfect
cleanliness of the mercury, so that we cannot assign the exact amount
of the effect. Hence a standard barometer is constructed with a wide
tube, sometimes even an inch in diameter, so that the capillary effect
may be rendered almost zero.[245] Gay-Lussac made barometers in the
form of a uniform siphon tube, so that the capillary forces acting at
the upper and lower surfaces should balance and destroy each other;
but the method fails in practice because the lower surface, being
open to the air, becomes sullied and subject to a different force of
capillarity.

  [245] Jevons, Watts’ *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. i. pp. 513–515.

In mechanical experiments friction is an interfering condition, and
drains away a portion of the energy intended to be operated upon in a
definite manner. We should of course reduce the friction in the first
place to the lowest possible amount, but as it cannot be altogether
prevented, and is not calculable with certainty from any general
laws, we must determine it separately for each apparatus by suitable
experiments. Thus Smeaton, in his admirable but almost forgotten
researches concerning water-wheels, eliminated friction in the most
simple manner by determining by trial what weight, acting by a cord
and roller upon his model water-wheel, would make it turn without
water as rapidly as the water made it turn. In short, he ascertained
what weight concurring with the water would exactly compensate for the
friction.[246] In Dr. Joule’s experiments to determine the mechanical
equivalent of heat by the condensation of air, a considerable amount
of heat was produced by friction of the condensing pump, and a small
portion by stirring the water employed to absorb the heat. This heat of
friction was measured by simply repeating the experiment in an exactly
similar manner except that no condensation was effected, and observing
the change of temperature then produced.[247]

  [246] *Philosophical Transactions*, vol. li. p. 100.

  [247] *Philosophical Magazine*, 3rd Series, vol. xxvi. p. 372.

We may describe as *test experiments* any in which we perform
operations not intended to give the quantity of the principal
phenomenon, but some quantity which would otherwise remain as an
error in the result. Thus in astronomical observations almost every
instrumental error may be avoided by increasing the number of
observations and distributing them in such a manner as to produce in
the final mean as much error in one way as in the other. But there
is one source of error, first discovered by Maskelyne, which cannot
be thus avoided, because it affects all observations in the same
direction and to the same average amount, namely the Personal Error of
the observer or the inclination to record the passage of a star across
the wires of the telescope a little too soon or a little too late.
This personal error was first carefully described in the *Edinburgh
Journal of Science*, vol. i. p. 178. The difference between the
judgment of observers at the Greenwich Observatory usually varies from
1/100 to 1/3 of a second, and remains pretty constant for the same
observers.[248] One practised observer in Sir George Airy’s pendulum
experiments recorded all his time observations half a second too early
on the average as compared with the chief observer.[249] In some
observers it has amounted to seven or eight-tenths of a second.[250]
De Morgan appears to have entertained the opinion that this source of
error was essentially incapable of elimination or correction.[251]
But it seems clear, as I suggested without knowing what had been
done,[252] that this personal error might be determined absolutely with
any desirable degree of accuracy by test experiments, consisting in
making an artificial star move at a considerable distance and recording
by electricity the exact moment of its passage over the wire. This
method has in fact been successfully employed in Leyden, Paris, and
Neuchatel.[253] More recently, observers were trained for the Transit
of Venus Expeditions by means of a mechanical model representing the
motion of Venus over the sun, this model being placed at a little
distance and viewed through a telescope, so that differences in the
judgments of different observers would become apparent. It seems likely
that tests of this nature might be employed with advantage in other
cases.

  [248] *Greenwich Observations for* 1866, p. xlix.

  [249] *Philosophical Transactions*, 1856, p. 309.

  [250] Penny *Cyclopædia*, art. *Transit*, vol. xxv. pp. 129, 130.

  [251] Ibid. art. *Observation*, p. 390.

  [252] *Nature*, vol. i. p. 85.

  [253] *Nature*, vol. i. p 337. See references to the Memoirs
  describing the method.

Newton employed the pendulum for making experiments on the impact of
balls. Two balls were hung in contact, and one of them, being drawn
aside through a measured arc, was then allowed to strike the other,
the arcs of vibration giving sufficient data for calculating the
distribution of energy at the moment of impact. The resistance of the
air was an interfering cause which he estimated very simply by causing
one of the balls to make several complete vibrations without impact
and then marking the reduction in the lengths of the arcs, a proper
fraction of which reduction was added to each of the other arcs of
vibration when impact took place.[254]

  [254] *Principia*, Book I. Law III. Corollary VI. Scholium. Motte’s
  translation, vol. i. p. 33.

The exact definition of the standard of length is one of the most
important, as it is one of the most difficult questions in physical
science, and the different practice of different nations introduces
needless confusion. Were all standards constructed so as to give
the true length at a fixed uniform temperature, for instance the
freezing-point, then any two standards could be compared without the
interference of temperature by bringing them both to exactly the same
fixed temperature. Unfortunately the French metre was defined by a
bar of platinum at 0°C, while our yard was defined by a bronze bar at
62°F. It is quite impossible, then, to make a comparison of the yard
and metre without the introduction of a correction, either for the
expansion of platinum or bronze, or both. Bars of metal differ too so
much in their rates of expansion according to their molecular condition
that it is dangerous to infer from one bar to another.

When we come to use instruments with great accuracy there are many
minute sources of error which must be guarded against. If a thermometer
has been graduated when perpendicular, it will read somewhat
differently when laid flat, as the pressure of a column of mercury is
removed from the bulb. The reading may also be somewhat altered if it
has recently been raised to a higher temperature than usual, if it be
placed under a vacuous receiver, or if the tube be unequally heated
as compared with the bulb. For these minute causes of error we may
have to introduce troublesome corrections, unless we adopt the simple
precaution of using the thermometer in circumstances of position, &c.,
exactly similar to those in which it was graduated. There is no end to
the number of minute corrections which may ultimately be required. A
large number of experiments on gases, standard weights and measures,
&c., depend upon the height of the barometer; but when experiments
in different parts of the world are compared together we ought as a
further refinement to take into account the varying force of gravity,
which even between London and Paris makes a difference of ·008 inch of
mercury.

The measurement of quantities of heat is a matter of great difficulty,
because there is no known substance impervious to heat, and the problem
is therefore as difficult as to measure liquids in porous vessels.
To determine the latent heat of steam we must condense a certain
amount of the steam in a known weight of water, and then observe the
rise of temperature of the water. But while we are carrying out the
experiment, part of the heat will escape by radiation and conduction
from the condensing vessel or calorimeter. We may indeed reduce the
loss of heat by using vessels with double sides and bright surfaces,
surrounded with swans-down wool or other non-conducting materials; and
we may also avoid raising the temperature of the water much above that
of the surrounding air. Yet we cannot by any such means render the
loss of heat inconsiderable. Rumford ingeniously proposed to reduce
the loss to zero by commencing the experiment when the temperature
of the calorimeter is as much below that of the air as it is at the
end of the experiment above it. Thus the vessel will first gain and
then lose by radiation and conduction, and these opposite errors will
approximately balance each other. But Regnault has shown that the loss
and gain do not proceed by exactly the same laws, so that in very
accurate investigations Rumford’s method is not sufficient. There
remains the method of correction which was beautifully carried out by
Regnault in his determination of the latent heat of steam. He employed
two calorimeters, made in exactly the same way and alternately used to
condense a certain amount of steam, so that while one was measuring
the latent heat, the other calorimeter was engaged in determining
the corrections to be applied, whether on account of radiation and
conduction from the vessel or on account of heat reaching the vessel by
means of the connecting pipes.[255]

  [255] Graham’s *Chemical Reports and Memoirs*, Cavendish Society, pp.
  247, 268, &c.


4. *Method of Compensation.*

There are many cases in which a cause of error cannot conveniently be
rendered null, and is yet beyond the reach of the third method, that
of calculating the requisite correction from independent observations.
The magnitude of an error may be subject to continual variations, on
account of change of weather, or other fickle circumstances beyond
our control. It may either be impracticable to observe the variation
of those circumstances in sufficient detail, or, if observed, the
calculation of the amount of error may be subject to doubt. In these
cases, and only in these cases, it will be desirable to invent some
artificial mode of counterpoising the variable error against an equal
error subject to exactly the same variation.

We cannot weigh an object with great accuracy unless we make a
correction for the weight of the air displaced by the object, and add
this to the apparent weight. In very accurate investigations relating
to standard weights, it is usual to note the barometer and thermometer
at the time of making a weighing, and, from the measured bulks of
the objects compared, to calculate the weight of air displaced; the
third method in fact is adopted. To make these calculations in the
frequent weighings requisite in chemical analysis would be exceedingly
laborious, hence the correction is usually neglected. But when the
chemist wishes to weigh gas contained in a large glass globe for the
purpose of determining its specific gravity, the correction becomes of
much importance. Hence chemists avoid at once the error, and the labour
of correcting it, by attaching to the opposite scale of the balance a
dummy sealed glass globe of equal capacity to that containing the gas
to be weighed, noting only the difference of weight when the operating
globe is full and empty. The correction, being the same for both
globes, may be entirely neglected.[256]

  [256] Regnault’s *Cours Elémentaire de Chimie*, 1851, vol i. p. 141.

A device of nearly the same kind is employed in the construction of
galvanometers which measure the force of an electric current by the
deflection of a suspended magnetic needle. The resistance of the needle
is partly due to the directive influence of the earth’s magnetism, and
partly to the torsion of the thread. But the former force may often be
inconveniently great as well as troublesome to determine for different
inclinations. Hence it is customary to connect together two equally
magnetised needles, with their poles pointing in opposite directions,
one needle being within and another without the coil of wire. As
regards the earth’s magnetism, the needles are now *astatic* or
indifferent, the tendency of one needle towards the pole being balanced
by that of the other.

An elegant instance of the elimination of a disturbing force by
compensation is found in Faraday’s researches upon the magnetism of
gases. To observe the magnetic attraction or repulsion of a gas seems
impossible unless we enclose the gas in an envelope, probably best made
of glass. But any such envelope is sure to be more or less affected
by the magnet, so that it becomes difficult to distinguish between
three forces which enter into the problem, namely, the magnetism of
the gas in question, that of the envelope, and that of the surrounding
atmospheric air. Faraday avoided all difficulties by employing two
equal and similar glass tubes connected together, and so suspended from
the arm of a torsion balance that the tubes were in similar parts of
the magnetic field. One tube being filled with nitrogen and the other
with oxygen, it was found that the oxygen seemed to be attracted and
the nitrogen repelled. The suspending thread of the balance was then
turned until the force of torsion restored the tubes to their original
places, where the magnetism of the tubes as well as that of the
surrounding air, being the same and in the opposite directions upon the
two tubes, could not produce any interference. The force required to
restore the tubes was measured by the amount of torsion of the thread,
and it indicated correctly the difference between the attractive powers
of oxygen and nitrogen. The oxygen was then withdrawn from one of the
tubes, and a second experiment made, so as to compare a vacuum with
nitrogen. No force was now required to maintain the tubes in their
places, so that nitrogen was found to be, approximately speaking,
indifferent to the magnet, that is, neither magnetic nor diamagnetic,
while oxygen was proved to be positively magnetic.[257] It required
the highest experimental skill on the part of Faraday and Tyndall, to
distinguish between what is apparent and real in magnetic attraction
and repulsion.

  [257] Tyndall’s *Faraday*, pp. 114, 115.

Experience alone can finally decide when a compensating arrangement
is conducive to accuracy. As a general rule mechanical compensation
is the last resource, and in the more accurate observations it is
likely to introduce more uncertainty than it removes. A multitude
of instruments involving mechanical compensation have been devised,
but they are usually of an unscientific character,[258] because the
errors compensated can be more accurately determined and allowed for.
But there are exceptions to this rule, and it seems to be proved that
in the delicate and tiresome operation of measuring a base line,
invariable bars, compensated for expansion by heat, give the most
accurate results. This arises from the fact that it is very difficult
to determine accurately the temperature of the measuring bars under
varying conditions of weather and manipulation.[259] Again, the last
refinement in the measurement of time at Greenwich Observatory depends
upon mechanical compensation. Sir George Airy, observing that the
standard clock increased its losing rate 0·30 second for an increase of
one inch in atmospheric pressure, placed a magnet moved by a barometer
in such a position below the pendulum, as almost entirely to neutralise
this cause of irregularity. The thorough remedy, however, would be to
remove the cause of error altogether by placing the clock in a vacuous
case.

  [258] See, for instance, the Compensated Sympiesometer,
  *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. xxxix. p. 371.

  [259] Grant, *History of Physical Astronomy*, pp. 146, 147.

We thus see that the choice of one or other mode of eliminating an
error depends entirely upon circumstances and the object in view; but
we may safely lay down the following conclusions. First of all, seek
to avoid the source of error altogether if it can be conveniently
done; if not, make the experiment so that the error may be as small,
but more especially as constant, as possible. If the means are at hand
for determining its amount by calculation from other experiments and
principles of science, allow the error to exist and make a correction
in the result. If this cannot be accurately done or involves too
much labour for the purposes in view, then throw in a counteracting
error which shall as nearly as possible be of equal amount in all
circumstances with that to be eliminated. There yet remains, however,
one important method, that of Reversal, which will form an appropriate
transition to the succeeding chapters on the Method of Mean Results and
the Law of Error.


5. *Method of Reversal.*

The fifth method of eliminating error is most potent and satisfactory
when it can be applied, but it requires that we shall be able to
reverse the apparatus and mode of procedure, so as to make the
interfering cause act alternately in opposite directions. If we can
get two experimental results, one of which is as much too great as
the other is too small, the error is equal to half the difference,
and the true result is the mean of the two apparent results. It is an
unavoidable defect of the chemical balance, for instance, that the
points of suspension of the pans cannot be fixed at exactly equal
distances from the centre of suspension of the beam. Hence two weights
which seem to balance each other will never be quite equal in reality.
The difference is detected by reversing the weights, and it may be
estimated by adding small weights to the deficient side to restore
equilibrium, and then taking as the true weight the geometric mean
of the two apparent weights of the same object. If the difference is
small, the arithmetic mean, that is half the sum, may be substituted
for the geometric mean, from which it will not appreciably differ.

This method of reversal is most extensively employed in practical
astronomy. The apparent elevation of a heavenly body is observed by a
telescope moving upon a divided circle, upon which the inclination of
the telescope is read off. Now this reading will be erroneous if the
circle and the telescope have not accurately the same centre. But if we
read off at the same time both ends of the telescope, the one reading
will be about as much too small as the other is too great, and the
mean will be nearly free from error. In practice the observation is
differently conducted, but the principle is the same; the telescope is
fixed to the circle, which moves with it, and the angle through which
it moves is read off at three, six, or more points, disposed at equal
intervals round the circle. The older astronomers, down even to the
time of Flamsteed, were accustomed to use portions only of a divided
circle, generally quadrants, and Römer made a vast improvement when he
introduced the complete circle.

The transit circle, employed to determine the meridian passage of
heavenly bodies, is so constructed that the telescope and the axis
bearing it, in fact the whole moving part of the instrument, can be
taken out of the bearing sockets and turned over, so that what was
formerly the western pivot becomes the eastern one, and *vice versâ*.
It is impossible that the instrument could have been so perfectly
constructed, mounted, and adjusted that the telescope should point
exactly to the meridian, but the effect of the reversal is that it will
point as much to the west in one position as it does to the east in the
other, and the mean result of observations in the two positions must be
free from such cause of error.

The accuracy with which the inclination of the compass needle can be
determined depends almost entirely on the method of reversal. The
dip needle consists of a bar of magnetised steel, suspended somewhat
like the beam of a delicate balance on a slender axis passing through
the centre of gravity of the bar, so that it is at liberty to rest
in that exact degree of inclination in the magnetic meridian which
the magnetism of the earth induces. The inclination is read off
upon a vertical divided circle, but to avoid error arising from the
centring of the needle and circle, both ends are read, and the mean
of the results is taken. The whole instrument is now turned carefully
round through 180°, which causes the needle to assume a new position
relatively to the circle and gives two new readings, in which any error
due to the wrong position of the zero of the division will be reversed.
As the axis of the needle may not be exactly horizontal, it is now
reversed in the same manner as the transit instrument, the end of the
axis which formerly pointed east being made to point west, and a new
set of four readings is taken.

Finally, error may arise from the axis not passing accurately through
the centre of gravity of the bar, and this error can only be detected
and eliminated on changing the magnetic poles of the bar by the
application of a strong magnet. The error is thus made to act in
opposite directions. To ensure all possible accuracy each reversal
ought to be combined with each other reversal, so that the needle will
be observed in eight different positions by sixteen readings, the mean
of the whole of which will give the required inclination free from all
eliminable errors.[260]

  [260] Quetelet, *Sur la Physique du Globe*, p. 174. Jamin, *Cours de
  Physique*, vol. i. p. 504.

There are certain cases in which a disturbing cause can with ease
be made to act in opposite directions, in alternate observations,
so that the mean of the results will be free from disturbance. Thus
in direct experiments upon the velocity of sound in passing through
the air between stations two or three miles apart, the wind is a
cause of error. It will be well, in the first place, to choose a
time for the experiment when the air is very nearly at rest, and the
disturbance slight, but if at the same moment signal sounds be made
at each station and observed at the other, two sounds will be passing
in opposite directions through the same body of air and the wind will
accelerate one sound almost exactly as it retards the other. Again, in
trigonometrical surveys the apparent height of a point will be affected
by atmospheric refraction and the curvature of the earth. But if in
the case of two points the apparent elevation of each as seen from
the other be observed, the corrections will be the same in amount,
but reversed in direction, and the mean between the two apparent
differences of altitude will give the true difference of level.

In the next two chapters we really pursue the Method of Reversal into
more complicated applications.




CHAPTER XVI.

THE METHOD OF MEANS.


All results of the measurement of continuous quantity can be only
approximately true. Were this assertion doubted, it could readily be
proved by direct experience. If any person, using an instrument of
the greatest precision, makes and registers successive observations
in an unbiassed manner, it will almost invariably be found that the
results differ from each other. When we operate with sufficient care
we cannot perform so simple an experiment as weighing an object in a
good balance without getting discrepant numbers. Only the rough and
careless experimenter will think that his observations agree, but
in reality he will be found to overlook the differences. The most
elaborate researches, such as those undertaken in connection with
standard weights and measures, always render it apparent that complete
coincidence is out of the question, and that the more accurate our
modes of observation are rendered, the more numerous are the sources
of minute error which become apparent. We may look upon the existence
of error in all measurements as the normal state of things. It is
absolutely impossible to eliminate separately the multitude of small
disturbing influences, except by balancing them off against each other.
Even in drawing a mean it is to be expected that we shall come near
the truth rather than exactly to it. In the measurement of continuous
quantity, absolute coincidence, if it seems to occur, must be only
apparent, and is no indication of precision. It is one of the most
embarrassing things we can meet when experimental results agree
too closely. Such coincidences should raise our suspicion that the
apparatus in use is in some way restricted in its operation, so as
not really to give the true result at all, or that the actual results
have not been faithfully recorded by the assistant in charge of the
apparatus.

If then we cannot get twice over exactly the same result, the question
arises, How can we ever attain the truth or select the result which may
be supposed to approach most nearly to it? The quantity of a certain
phenomenon is expressed in several numbers which differ from each
other; no more than one of them at the most can be true, and it is more
probable that they are all false. It may be suggested, perhaps, that
the observer should select the one observation which he judged to be
the best made, and there will often doubtless be a feeling that one
or more results were satisfactory, and the others less trustworthy.
This seems to have been the course adopted by the early astronomers.
Flamsteed, when he had made several observations of a star, probably
chose in an arbitrary manner that which seemed to him nearest to the
truth.[261]

  [261] Baily’s *Account of Flamsteed*, p. 376.

When Horrocks selected for his estimate of the sun’s semi-diameter a
mean between the results of Kepler and Tycho, he professed not to do
it from any regard to the idle adage, “Medio tutissimus ibis,” but
because he thought it from his own observations to be correct.[262] But
this method will not apply at all when the observer has made a number
of measurements which are equally good in his opinion, and it is quite
apparent that in using an instrument or apparatus of considerable
complication the observer will not necessarily be able to judge whether
slight causes have affected its operation or not.

  [262] *The Transit of Venus across the Sun*, by Horrocks, London,
  1859, p. 146.

In this question, as indeed throughout inductive logic, we deal only
with probabilities. There is no infallible mode of arriving at the
absolute truth, which lies beyond the reach of human intellect, and
can only be the distant object of our long-continued and painful
approximations. Nevertheless there is a mode pointed out alike by
common sense and the highest mathematical reasoning, which is more
likely than any other, as a general rule, to bring us near the truth.
The ἄριστον μέτρον, or the *aurea mediocritas*, was highly esteemed
in the ancient philosophy of Greece and Rome; but it is not probable
that any of the ancients should have been able clearly to analyse and
express the reasons why they advocated the *mean* as the safest course.
But in the last two centuries this apparently simple question of the
mean has been found to afford a field for the exercise of the utmost
mathematical skill. Roger Cotes, the editor of the *Principia*, appears
to have had some insight into the value of the mean; but profound
mathematicians such as De Moivre, Daniel Bernoulli, Laplace, Lagrange,
Gauss, Quetelet, De Morgan, Airy, Leslie Ellis, Boole, Glaisher, and
others, have hardly exhausted the subject.


*Several uses of the Mean Result.*

The elimination of errors of unknown sources, is almost always
accomplished by the simple arithmetical process of taking the *mean*,
or, as it is often called, the *average* of several discrepant numbers.
To take an average is to add the several quantities together, and
divide by the number of quantities thus added, which gives a quotient
lying among, or in the *middle* of, the several quantities. Before
however inquiring fully into the grounds of this procedure, it is
essential to observe that this one arithmetical process is really
applied in at least three different cases, for different purposes, and
upon different principles, and we must take great care not to confuse
one application of the process with another. A *mean result*, then, may
have any one of the following significations.

(1) It may give a merely representative number, expressing the general
magnitude of a series of quantities, and serving as a convenient mode
of comparing them with other series of quantities. Such a number is
properly called *The fictitious mean* or *The average result*.

(2) It may give a result approximately free from disturbing quantities,
which are known to affect some results in one direction, and other
results equally in the opposite direction. We may say that in this case
we get a *Precise mean result*.

(3) It may give a result more or less free from unknown and uncertain
errors; this we may call the *Probable mean result*.

Of these three uses of the mean the first is entirely different in
nature from the two last, since it does not yield an approximation
to any natural quantity, but furnishes us with an arithmetic result
comparing the aggregate of certain quantities with their number. The
third use of the mean rests entirely upon the theory of probability,
and will be more fully considered in a later part of this chapter. The
second use is closely connected, or even identical with, the Method of
Reversal already described, but it will be desirable to enter somewhat
fully into all the three employments of the same arithmetical process.


*The Mean and the Average.*

Much confusion exists in the popular, or even the scientific employment
of the terms *mean* and *average*, and they are commonly taken as
synonymous. It is necessary to ascertain carefully what significations
we ought to attach to them. The English word *mean* is equivalent to
*medium*, being derived, perhaps through the French *moyen*, from the
Latin *medius*, which again is undoubtedly kindred with the Greek
μεσος. Etymologists believe, too, that this Greek word is connected
with the preposition μετα, the German *mitte*, and the true English
*mid* or *middle*; so that after all the *mean* is a technical term
identical in its root with the more popular equivalent *middle*.

If we inquire what is the mean in a mathematical point of view, the
true answer is that there are several or many kinds of means. The old
arithmeticians recognised ten kinds, which are stated by Boethius, and
an eleventh was added by Jordanus.[263]

  [263] De Morgan, Supplement to the *Penny Cyclopædia*, art. *Old
  Appellations of Numbers*.

The *arithmetic mean* is the one by far the most commonly denoted by
the term, and that which we may understand it to signify in the absence
of any qualification. It is the sum of a series of quantities divided
by their number, and may be represented by the formula 1/2(*a* + *b*).
But there is also the *geometric mean*, which is the square root of the
product, √(*a* × *b*), or that quantity the logarithm of which
is the arithmetic mean of the logarithms of the quantities. There is
also the *harmonic mean*, which is the reciprocal of the arithmetic
mean of the reciprocals of the quantities. Thus if *a* and *b* be the
quantities, as before, their reciprocals are 1/*a* and 1/*b*, the
mean of which is 1/2 (1/*a* + 1/*b*), and the reciprocal again is
(2*ab*)/(*a* + *b*), which is the harmonic mean. Other kinds of means
might no doubt be invented for particular purposes, and we might apply
the term, as De Morgan pointed out,[264] to any quantity a function of
which is equal to a function of two or more other quantities, and is
such that the interchange of these latter quantities among themselves
will make no alteration in the value of the function. Symbolically, if
Φ(*y*, *y*, *y* ....) = Φ(*x*_{1}, *x*_{2}, *x*_{3} ....), then *y* is
a kind of mean of the quantities, *x*_{1}, *x*_{2}, &c.

  [264] *Penny Cyclopædia*, art. *Mean*.

The geometric mean is necessarily adopted in certain cases. When we
estimate the work done against a force which varies inversely as
the square of the distance from a fixed point, the mean force is
the geometric mean between the forces at the beginning and end of
the path. When in an imperfect balance, we reverse the weights to
eliminate error, the true weight will be the geometric mean of the two
apparent weights. In almost all the calculations of statistics and
commerce the geometric mean ought, strictly speaking, to be used. If a
commodity rises in price 100 per cent. and another remains unaltered,
the mean rise of a price is not 50 per cent. because the ratio
150 : 200 is not the same as 100 : 150. The mean ratio is as unity to
√(1·00 × 2·00) or 1 to 1·41. The difference between the three
kinds of means in such a case[265] is very considerable; while the
rise of price estimated by the Arithmetic mean would be 50 per cent.
it would be only 41 and 33 per cent. respectively according to the
Geometric and Harmonic means.

  [265] Jevons, *Journal of the Statistical Society*, June 1865,
  vol. xxviii, p. 296.

In all calculations concerning the average rate of progress of a
community, or any of its operations, the geometric mean should be
employed. For if a quantity increases 100 per cent. in 100 years, it
would not on the average increase 10 per cent. in each ten years, as
the 10 per cent. would at the end of each decade be calculated upon
larger and larger quantities, and give at the end of 100 years much
more than 100 per cent., in fact as much as 159 per cent. The true mean
rate in each decade would be ^{10}√2 or about 1·07, that is, the
increase would be about 7 per cent. in each ten years. But when the
quantities differ very little, the arithmetic and geometric means are
approximately the same. Thus the arithmetic mean of 1·000 and 1·001
is 1·0005, and the geometric mean is about 1·0004998, the difference
being of an order inappreciable in almost all scientific and practical
matters. Even in the comparison of standard weights by Gauss’ method
of reversal, the arithmetic mean may usually be substituted for the
geometric mean which is the true result.

Regarding the mean in the absence of express qualification to the
contrary as the common arithmetic mean, we must still distinguish
between its two uses where it gives with more or less accuracy and
probability a really existing quantity, and where it acts as a mere
representative of other quantities. If I make many experiments to
determine the atomic weight of an element, there is a certain number
which I wish to approximate to, and the mean of my separate results
will, in the absence of any reasons to the contrary, be the most
probable approximate result. When we determine the mean density of
the earth, it is not because any part of the earth is of that exact
density; there may be no part exactly corresponding to the mean
density, and as the crust of the earth has only about half the mean
density, the internal matter of the globe must of course be above the
mean. Even the density of a homogeneous substance like carbon or gold
must be regarded as a mean between the real density of its atoms, and
the zero density of the intervening vacuous space.

The very different signification of the word “mean” in these two uses
was fully explained by Quetelet,[266] and the importance of the
distinction was pointed out by Sir John Herschel in reviewing his
work.[267] It is much to be desired that scientific men would mark the
difference by using the word *mean* only in the former sense when it
denotes approximation to a definite existing quantity; and *average*,
when the mean is only a fictitious quantity, used for convenience
of thought and expression. The etymology of this word “average” is
somewhat obscure; but according to De Morgan[268] it comes from
*averia*, “havings or possessions,” especially applied to farm stock.
By the accidents of language *averagium* came to mean the labour of
farm horses to which the lord was entitled, and it probably acquired in
this manner the notion of distributing a whole into parts, a sense in
which it was early applied to maritime averages or contributions of the
other owners of cargo to those whose goods have been thrown overboard
or used for the safety of the vessel.

  [266] *Letters on the Theory of Probabilities*, transl. by Downes,
  Part ii.

  [267] Herschel’s *Essays*, &c. pp. 404, 405.

  [268] *On the Theory of Errors of Observations, Cambridge
  Philosophical Transactions*, vol. x. Part ii. 416.


*On the Average or Fictitious Mean.*

Although the average when employed in its proper sense of a fictitious
mean, represents no really existing quantity, it is yet of the
highest scientific importance, as enabling us to conceive in a single
result a multitude of details. It enables us to make a hypothetical
simplification of a problem, and avoid complexity without committing
error. The weight of a body is the sum of the weights of infinitely
small particles, each acting at a different place, so that a mechanical
problem resolves itself, strictly speaking, into an infinite number
of distinct problems. We owe to Archimedes the first introduction of
the beautiful idea that one point may be discovered in a gravitating
body such that the weight of all the particles may be regarded as
concentrated in that point, and yet the behaviour of the whole body
will be exactly represented by the behaviour of this heavy point. This
Centre of Gravity may be within the body, as in the case of a sphere,
or it may be in empty space, as in the case of a ring. Any two bodies,
whether connected or separate, may be conceived as having a centre of
gravity, that of the sun and earth lying within the sun and only 267
miles from its centre.

Although we most commonly use the notion of a centre or average point
with regard to gravity, the same notion is applicable to other cases.
Terrestrial gravity is a case of approximately parallel forces, and
the centre of gravity is but a special case of the more general Centre
of Parallel Forces. Wherever a number of forces of whatever amount
act in parallel lines, it is possible to discover a point at which
the algebraic sum of the forces may be imagined to act with exactly
the same effect. Water in a cistern presses against the side with a
pressure varying according to the depth, but always in a direction
perpendicular to the side. We may then conceive the whole pressure
as exerted on one point, which will be one-third from the bottom of
the cistern, and may be called the Centre of Pressure. The Centre
of Oscillation of a pendulum, discovered by Huyghens, is that point
at which the whole weight of the pendulum may be considered as
concentrated, without altering the time of oscillation (p. 315). When
one body strikes another the Centre of Percussion is that point in
the striking body at which all its mass might be concentrated without
altering the effect of the stroke. In position the Centre of Percussion
does not differ from the Centre of Oscillation. Mathematicians have
also described the Centre of Gyration, the Centre of Conversion, the
Centre of Friction, &c.

We ought carefully to distinguish between those cases in which an
*invariable* centre can be assigned, and those in which it cannot.
In perfect strictness, there is no such thing as a true invariable
centre of gravity. As a general rule a body is capable of possessing an
invariable centre only for perfectly parallel forces, and gravity never
does act in absolutely parallel lines. Thus, as usual, we find that our
conceptions are only hypothetically correct, and only approximately
applicable to real circumstances. There are indeed certain geometrical
forms called *Centrobaric*,[269] such that a body of that shape would
attract another exactly as if the mass were concentrated at the centre
of gravity, whether the forces act in a parallel manner or not.
Newton showed that uniform spheres of matter have this property,
and this truth proved of the greatest importance in simplifying his
calculations. But it is after all a purely hypothetical truth, because
we can nowhere meet with, nor can we construct, a perfectly spherical
and homogeneous body. The slightest irregularity or protrusion from
the surface will destroy the rigorous correctness of the assumption.
The spheroid, on the other hand, has no invariable centre at which its
mass may always be regarded as concentrated. The point from which its
resultant attraction acts will move about according to the distance
and position of the other attracting body, and it will only coincide
with the centre as regards an infinitely distant body whose attractive
forces may be considered as acting in parallel lines.

  [269] Thomson and Tait, *Treatise on Natural Philosophy*, vol. i.
  p. 394.

Physicists speak familiarly of the poles of a magnet, and the term
may be used with convenience. But, if we attach any definite meaning
to the word, the poles are not the ends of the magnet, nor any fixed
points within, but the variable points from which the resultants of
all the forces exerted by the particles in the bar upon exterior
magnetic particles may be considered as acting. The poles are, in
short, Centres of Magnetic Forces; but as those forces are never
really parallel, these centres will vary in position according to
the relative place of the object attracted. Only when we regard the
magnet as attracting a very distant, or, strictly speaking, infinitely
distant particle, do its centres become fixed points, situated in short
magnets approximately at one-sixth of the whole length from each end of
the bar. We have in the above instances of centres or poles of force
sufficient examples of the mode in which the Fictitious Mean or Average
is employed in physical science.


*The Precise Mean Result.*

We now turn to that mode of employing the mean result which is
analogous to the method of reversal, but which is brought into practice
in a most extensive manner throughout many branches of physical
science. We find the simplest possible case in the determination of
the latitude of a place by observations of the Pole-star. Tycho Brahe
suggested that if the elevation of any circumpolar star were observed
at its higher and lower passages across the meridian, half the sum of
the elevations would be the latitude of the place, which is equal to
the height of the pole. Such a star is as much above the pole at its
highest passage, as it is below at its lowest, so that the mean must
necessarily give the height of the pole itself free from doubt, except
as regards incidental errors. The Pole-star is usually selected for the
purpose of such observations because it describes the smallest circle,
and is thus on the whole least affected by atmospheric refraction.

Whenever several causes are in action, each of which at one time
increases and at another time decreases the joint effect by equal
quantities, we may apply this method and disentangle the effects. Thus
the solar and lunar tides roll on in almost complete independence of
each other. When the moon is new or full the solar tide coincides, or
nearly so, with that caused by the moon, and the joint effect is the
sum of the separate effects. When the moon is in quadrature, or half
full, the two tides are acting in opposition, one raising and the other
depressing the water, so that we observe only the difference of the
effects. We have in fact--

  Spring tide = lunar tide + solar tide;
  Neap tide   = lunar tide - solar tide.

We have only then to add together the heights of the maximum spring
tide and the minimum neap tide, and half the sum is the true height of
the lunar tide. Half the difference of the spring and neap tides on the
other hand gives the solar tide.

Effects of very small amount may be detected with great approach to
certainty among much greater fluctuations, provided that we have
a series of observations sufficiently numerous and long continued
to enable us to balance all the larger effects against each other.
For this purpose the observations should be continued over at least
one complete cycle, in which the effects run through all their
variations, and return exactly to the same relative positions as at the
commencement. If casual or irregular disturbing causes exist, we should
probably require many such cycles of results to render their effect
inappreciable. We obtain the desired result by taking the mean of all
the observations in which a cause acts positively, and the mean of all
in which it acts negatively. Half the difference of these means will
give the effect of the cause in question, provided that no other effect
happens to vary in the same period or nearly so.

Since the moon causes a movement of the ocean, it is evident that
its attraction must have some effect upon the atmosphere. The laws
of atmospheric tides were investigated by Laplace, but as it would
be impracticable by theory to calculate their amounts we can only
determine them by observation, as Laplace predicted that they would
one day be determined.[270] But the oscillations of the barometer thus
caused are far smaller than the oscillations due to several other
causes. Storms, hurricanes, or changes of weather produce movements
of the barometer sometimes as much as a thousand times as great as
the tides in question. There are also regular daily, yearly, or other
fluctuations, all greater than the desired quantity. To detect and
measure the atmospheric tide it was desirable that observations should
be made in a place as free as possible from irregular disturbances.
On this account several long series of observations were made at St.
Helena, where the barometer is far more regular in its movements than
in a continental climate. The effect of the moon’s attraction was
then detected by taking the mean of all the readings when the moon
was on the meridian and the similar mean when she was on the horizon.
The difference of these means was found to be only ·00365, yet it was
possible to discover even the variation of this tide according as the
moon was nearer to or further from the earth, though this difference
was only ·00056 inch.[271] It is quite evident that such minute effects
could never be discovered in a purely empirical manner. Having no
information but the series of observations before us, we could have
no clue as to the mode of grouping them which would give so small a
difference. In applying this method of means in an extensive manner
we must generally then have *à priori* knowledge as to the periods at
which a cause will act in one direction or the other.

  [270] *Essai Philosophique sur les Probabilités*, pp. 49, 50.

  [271] Grant, *History of Physical Astronomy*, p. 163.

We are sometimes able to eliminate fluctuations and take a mean result
by purely mechanical arrangements. The daily variations of temperature,
for instance, become imperceptible one or two feet below the surface
of the earth, so that a thermometer placed with its bulb at that
depth gives very nearly the true daily mean temperature. At a depth
of twenty feet even the yearly fluctuations are nearly effaced, and
the thermometer stands a little above the true mean temperature of the
locality. In registering the rise and fall of the tide by a tide-gauge,
it is desirable to avoid the oscillations arising from surface waves,
which is very readily accomplished by placing the float in a cistern
communicating by a small hole with the sea. Only a general rise or
fall of the level is then perceptible, just as in the marine barometer
the narrow tube prevents any casual fluctuations and allows only a
continued change of pressure to manifest itself.


*Determination of the Zero point.*

In many important observations the chief difficulty consists in
defining exactly the zero point from which we are to measure. We can
point a telescope with great precision to a star and can measure to
a second of arc the angle through which the telescope is raised or
lowered; but all this precision will be useless unless we know exactly
the centre point of the heavens from which we measure, or, what comes
to the same thing, the horizontal line 90° distant from it. Since the
true horizon has reference to the figure of the earth at the place of
observation, we can only determine it by the direction of gravity,
as marked either by the plumb-line or the surface of a liquid. The
question resolves itself then into the most accurate mode of observing
the direction of gravity, and as the plumb-line has long been found
hopelessly inaccurate, astronomers generally employ the surface of
mercury in repose as the criterion of horizontality. They ingeniously
observe the direction of the surface by making a star the index. From
the laws of reflection it follows that the angle between the direct
ray from a star and that reflected from a surface of mercury will
be exactly double the angle between the surface and the direct ray
from the star. Hence the horizontal or zero point is the mean between
the apparent place of any star or other very distant object and its
reflection in mercury.

A plumb-line is perpendicular, or a liquid surface is horizontal only
in an approximate sense; for any irregularity of the surface of the
earth, a mountain, or even a house must cause some deviation by its
attracting power. To detect such deviation might seem very difficult,
because every other plumb-line or liquid surface would be equally
affected by gravity. Nevertheless it can be detected; for if we place
one plumb-line to the north of a mountain, and another to the south,
they will be about equally deflected in opposite directions, and if
by observations of the same star we can measure the angle between the
plumb-lines, half the inclination will be the deviation of either,
after allowance has been made for the inclination due to the difference
of latitude of the two places of observation. By this mode of
observation applied to the mountain Schiehallion the deviation of the
plumb-line was accurately measured by Maskelyne, and thus a comparison
instituted between the attractive forces of the mountain and the whole
globe, which led to a probable estimate of the earth’s density.

In some cases it is actually better to determine the zero point by the
average of equally diverging quantities than by direct observation. In
delicate weighings by a chemical balance it is requisite to ascertain
exactly the point at which the beam comes to rest, and when standard
weights are being compared the position of the beam is ascertained
by a carefully divided scale viewed through a microscope. But when
the beam is just coming to rest, friction, small impediments or other
accidental causes may readily obstruct it, because it is near the
point at which the force of stability becomes infinitely small. Hence
it is found better to let the beam vibrate and observe the terminal
points of the vibrations. The mean between two extreme points will
nearly indicate the position of rest. Friction and the resistance of
air tend to reduce the vibrations, so that this mean will be erroneous
by half the amount of this effect during a half vibration. But by
taking several observations we may determine this retardation and
allow for it. Thus if *a*, *b*, *c* be the readings of the terminal
points of three excursions of the beam from the zero of the scale,
then 1/2(*a* + *b*) will be about as much erroneous in one direction
as 1/2(*b* + *c*) in the other, so that the mean of these two means,
or 1/4(*a* + 2*b* + *c*), will be exceedingly near to the point of
rest.[272] A still closer approximation may be made by taking four
readings and reducing them by the formula 1/6(*a* + 2*b* + 2*c* + *d*).

  [272] Gauss, Taylor’s *Scientific Memoirs*, vol. ii. p. 43, &c.

The accuracy of Baily’s experiments, directed to determine the
density of the earth, entirely depended upon this mode of observing
oscillations. The balls whose gravitation was measured were so
delicately suspended by a torsion balance that they never came to
rest. The extreme points of the oscillations were observed both when
the heavy leaden attracting ball was on one side and on the other. The
difference of the mean points when the leaden ball was on the right
hand and that when it was on the left hand gave double the amount of
the deflection.

A beautiful instance of avoiding the use of a zero point is found in
Mr. E. J. Stone’s observations on the radiant heat of the fixed stars.
The difficulty of these observations arose from the comparatively great
amounts of heat which were sent into the telescope from the atmosphere,
and which were sufficient to disguise almost entirely the feeble heat
rays of a star. But Mr. Stone fixed at the focus of his telescope a
double thermo-electric pile of which the two parts were reversed in
order. Now any disturbance of temperature which acted uniformly upon
both piles produced no effect upon the galvanometer needle, and when
the rays of the star were made to fall alternately upon one pile and
the other, the total amount of the deflection represented double the
heating power of the star. Thus Mr. Stone was able to detect with
much certainty a heating effect of the star Arcturus, which even when
concentrated by the telescope amounted only to 0°·02 Fahr., and which
represents a heating effect of the direct ray of only about 0°·00000137
Fahr., equivalent to the heat which would be received from a three-inch
cubic vessel full of boiling water at the distance of 400 yards.[273]
It is probable that Mr. Stone’s arrangement of the pile might be
usefully employed in other delicate thermometric experiments subject to
considerable disturbing influences.

  [273] *Proceedings of the Royal Society*, vol. xviii. p. 159 (Jan.
  13, 1870). *Philosophical Magazine* (4th Series), vol. xxxix. p. 376.


*Determination of Maximum Points.*

We employ the method of means in a certain number of observations
directed to determine the moment at which a phenomenon reaches its
highest point in quantity. In noting the place of a fixed star at a
given time there is no difficulty in ascertaining the point to be
observed, for a star in a good telescope presents an exceedingly small
disc. In observing a nebulous body which from a bright centre fades
gradually away on all sides, it will not be possible to select with
certainty the middle point. In many such cases the best method is not
to select arbitrarily the supposed middle point, but points of equal
brightness on either side, and then take the mean of the observations
of these two points for the centre. As a general rule, a variable
quantity in reaching its maximum increases at a less and less rate,
and after passing the highest point begins to decrease by insensible
degrees. The maximum may indeed be defined as that point at which
the increase or decrease is null. Hence it will usually be the most
indefinite point, and if we can accurately measure the phenomenon we
shall best determine the place of the maximum by determining points on
either side at which the ordinates are equal. There is moreover this
advantage in the method that several points may be determined with the
corresponding ones on the other side, and the mean of the whole taken
as the true place of the maximum. But this method entirely depends upon
the existence of symmetry in the curve, so that of two equal ordinates
one shall be as far on one side of the maximum as the other is on the
other side. The method fails when other laws of variation prevail.

In tidal observations great difficulty is encountered in fixing
the moment of high water, because the rate at which the water is
then rising or falling, is almost imperceptible. Whewell proposed,
therefore, to note the time at which the water passes a fixed point
somewhat below the maximum both in rising and falling, and take
the mean time as that of high water. But this mode of proceeding
unfortunately does not give a correct result, because the tide follows
different laws in rising and in falling. There is a difficulty again in
selecting the highest spring tide, another object of much importance in
tidology. Laplace discovered that the tide of the second day preceding
the conjunction of the sun and moon is nearly equal to that of the
fifth day following; and, believing that the increase and decrease of
the tides proceeded in a nearly symmetrical manner, he decided that the
highest tide would occur about thirty-six hours after the conjunction,
that is half-way between the second day before and the fifth day
after.[274]

  [274] Airy *On Tides and Waves*, Encycl. Metrop. pp. 364*-366*.

This method is also employed in determining the time of passage of the
middle or densest point of a stream of meteors. The earth takes two
or three days in passing completely through the November stream; but
astronomers need for their calculations to have some definite point
fixed within a few minutes if possible. When near to the middle they
observe the numbers of meteors which come within the sphere of vision
in each half hour, or quarter hour, and then, assuming that the law of
variation is symmetrical, they select a moment for the passage of the
centre equidistant between times of equal frequency.

The eclipses of Jupiter’s satellites are not only of great interest as
regards the motions of the satellites themselves, but were, and perhaps
still are, of use in determining longitudes, because they are events
occurring at fixed moments of absolute time, and visible in all parts
of the planetary system at the same time, allowance being made for the
interval occupied by the light in travelling. But, as is explained by
Herschel,[275] the moment of the event is wanting in definiteness,
partly because the long cone of Jupiter’s shadow is surrounded by
a penumbra, and partly because the satellite has itself a sensible
disc, and takes time in entering the shadow. Different observers using
different telescopes would usually select different moments for that
of the eclipse. But the increase of light in the emersion will proceed
according to a law the reverse of that observed in the immersion,
so that if an observer notes the time of both events with the same
telescope, he will be as much too soon in one observation as he is too
late in the other, and the mean moment of the two observations will
represent with considerable accuracy the time when the satellite is in
the middle of the shadow. Error of judgment of the observer is thus
eliminated, provided that he takes care to act at the emersion as he
did at the immersion.

  [275] *Outlines of Astronomy*, 4th edition, § 538.




CHAPTER XVII.

THE LAW OF ERROR.


To bring error itself under law might seem beyond human power. He who
errs surely diverges from law, and it might be deemed hopeless out of
error to draw truth. One of the most remarkable achievements of the
human intellect is the establishment of a general theory which not
only enables us among discrepant results to approximate to the truth,
but to assign the degree of probability which fairly attaches to this
conclusion. It would be a mistake indeed to suppose that this law is
necessarily the best guide under all circumstances. Every measuring
instrument and every form of experiment may have its own special law
of error; there may in one instrument be a tendency in one direction
and in another in the opposite direction. Every process has its
peculiar liabilities to disturbance, and we are never relieved from the
necessity of providing against special difficulties. The general Law of
Error is the best guide only when we have exhausted all other means of
approximation, and still find discrepancies, which are due to unknown
causes. We must treat such residual differences in some way or other,
since they will occur in all accurate experiments, and as their origin
is assumed to be unknown, there is no reason why we should treat them
differently in different cases. Accordingly the ultimate Law of Error
must be a uniform and general one.

It is perfectly recognised by mathematicians that in each case a
special Law of Error may exist, and should be discovered if possible.
“Nothing can be more unlikely than that the errors committed in all
classes of observations should follow the same law,”[276] and the
special Laws of Error which will apply to certain instruments, as for
instance the repeating circle, have been investigated by Bravais.[277]
He concludes that every distinct cause of error gives rise to a curve
of possibility of errors, which may have any form,--a curve which
we may either be able or unable to discover, and which in the first
case may be determined by *à priori* considerations on the peculiar
nature of this cause, or which may be determined *à posteriori* by
observation. Whenever it is practicable and worth the labour, we ought
to investigate these special conditions of error; nevertheless, when
there are a great number of different sources of minute error, the
general resultant will always tend to obey that general law which we
are about to consider.

  [276] *Philosophical Magazine*, 3rd Series, vol. xxxvii. p. 324.

  [277] *Letters on the Theory of Probabilities*, by Quetelet,
  translated by O. G. Downes, Notes to Letter XXVI. pp. 286–295.


*Establishment of the Law of Error.*

Mathematicians agree far better as to the form of the Law of Error
than they do as to the manner in which it can be deduced and proved.
They agree that among a number of discrepant results of observation,
that mean quantity is probably the best approximation to the truth
which makes the sum of the squares of the errors as small as possible.
But there are three principal ways in which this law has been arrived
at respectively by Gauss, by Laplace and Quetelet, and by Sir John
Herschel. Gauss proceeds much upon assumption; Herschel rests upon
geometrical considerations; while Laplace and Quetelet regard the Law
of Error as a development of the doctrine of combinations. A number
of other mathematicians, such as Adrain of New Brunswick, Bessel,
Ivory, Donkin, Leslie Ellis, Tait, and Crofton have either attempted
independent proofs or have modified or commented on those here to be
described. For full accounts of the literature of the subject the
reader should refer either to Mr. Todhunter’s *History of the Theory of
Probability* or to the able memoir of Mr. J. W. L. Glaisher.[278]

  [278] *On the Law of Facility of Errors of Observations, and on the
  Method of Least Squares*, Memoirs of the Royal Astronomical Society,
  vol. xxxix. p. 75.

According to Gauss the Law of Error expresses the comparative
probability of errors of various magnitude, and partly from experience,
partly from *à priori* considerations, we may readily lay down certain
conditions to which the law will certainly conform. It may fairly
be assumed as a first principle to guide us in the selection of the
law, that large errors will be far less frequent and probable than
small ones. We know that very large errors are almost impossible, so
that the probability must rapidly decrease as the amount of the error
increases. A second principle is that positive and negative errors
shall be equally probable, which may certainly be assumed, because we
are supposed to be devoid of any knowledge as to the causes of the
residual errors. It follows that the probability of the error must be a
function of an even power of the magnitude, that is of the square, or
the fourth power, or the sixth power, otherwise the probability of the
same amount of error would vary according as the error was positive or
negative. The even powers *x*^{2}, *x*^{4}, *x*^{6}, &c., are always
intrinsically positive, whether *x* be positive or negative. There is
no *à priori* reason why one rather than another of these even powers
should be selected. Gauss himself allows that the fourth or sixth power
would fulfil the conditions as well as the second;[279] but in the
absence of any theoretical reasons we should prefer the second power,
because it leads to formulæ of great comparative simplicity. Did the
Law of Error necessitate the use of the higher powers of the error, the
complexity of the necessary calculations would much reduce the utility
of the theory.

  [279] *Méthode des Moindres Carrés. Mémoires sur la Combinaison
  des Observations, par Ch. Fr. Gauss. Traduit en Français par J.
  Bertrand*, Paris, 1855, pp. 6, 133, &c.

By mathematical reasoning which it would be undesirable to attempt
to follow in this book, it is shown that under these conditions, the
facility of occurrence, or in other, words, the probability of error
is expressed by a function of the general form ε^{–*h*^{2} *x*^{2}}, in
which *x* represents the variable amount of errors. From this law, to
be more fully described in the following sections, it at once follows
that the most probable result of any observations is that which makes
the sum of the squares of the consequent errors the least possible.
Let *a*, *b*, *c*, &c., be the results of observation, and *x* the
quantity selected as the most probable, that is the most free from
unknown errors: then we must determine *x* so that (*a* - *x*)^{2} +
(*b* - *x*)^{2} + (*c* - *x*)^{2} + ... shall be the least possible
quantity. Thus we arrive at the celebrated *Method of Least Squares*,
as it is usually called, which appears to have been first distinctly
put in practice by Gauss in 1795, while Legendre first published in
1806 an account of the process in his work, entitled, *Nouvelles
Méthodes pour la Détermination des Orbites des Comètes*. It is worthy
of notice, however, that Roger Cotes had long previously recommended a
method of equivalent nature in his tract, “Estimatio Erroris in Mixta
Mathesi.”[280]

  [280] De Morgan, *Penny Cyclopædia*, art. *Least Squares*.


*Herschel’s Geometrical Proof.*

A second way of arriving at the Law of Error was proposed by Herschel,
and although only applicable to geometrical cases, it is remarkable as
showing that from whatever point of view we regard the subject, the
same principle will be detected. After assuming that some general law
must exist, and that it is subject to the principles of probability,
he supposes that a ball is dropped from a high point with the
intention that it shall strike a given mark on a horizontal plane. In
the absence of any known causes of deviation it will either strike
that mark, or, as is infinitely more probable, diverge from it by an
amount which we must regard as error of unknown origin. Now, to quote
the words of Herschel,[281] “the probability of that error is the
unknown function of its square, *i.e.* of the sum of the squares of
its deviations in any two rectangular directions. Now, the probability
of any deviation depending solely on its magnitude, and not on its
direction, it follows that the probability of each of these rectangular
deviations must be the same function of *its* square. And since the
observed oblique deviation is equivalent to the two rectangular ones,
supposed concurrent, and which are essentially independent of one
another, and is, therefore, a compound event of which they are the
simple independent constituents, therefore its probability will be the
product of their separate probabilities. Thus the form of our unknown
function comes to be determined from this condition, viz., that the
product of such functions of two independent elements is equal to the
same function of their sum. But it is shown in every work on algebra
that this property is the peculiar characteristic of, and belongs only
to, the exponential or antilogarithmic function. This, then, is the
function of the square of the error, which expresses the probability
of committing that error. That probability decreases, therefore, in
geometrical progression, as the square of the error increases in
arithmetical.”

  [281] *Edinburgh Review*, July 1850, vol. xcii. p. 17. Reprinted
  *Essays*, p. 399. This method of demonstration is discussed by Boole,
  *Transactions of Royal Society of Edinburgh*, vol. xxi. pp. 627–630.


*Laplace’s and Quetelet’s Proof of the Law.*

However much presumption the modes of determining the Law of Error,
already described, may give in favour of the law usually adopted, it is
difficult to feel that the arguments are satisfactory. The law adopted
is chosen rather on the grounds of convenience and plausibility, than
because it can be seen to be the necessary law. We can however approach
the subject from an entirely different point of view, and yet get to
the same result.

Let us assume that a particular observation is subject to four chances
of error, each of which will increase the result one inch if it occurs.
Each of these errors is to be regarded as an event independent of the
rest and we can therefore assign, by the theory of probability, the
comparative probability and frequency of each conjunction of errors.
From the Arithmetical Triangle (pp. 182–188) we learn that no error
at all can happen only in one way; an error of one inch can happen
in 4 ways; and the ways of happening of errors of 2, 3 and 4 inches
respectively, will be 6, 4 and 1 in number.

We may infer that the error of two inches is the most likely to occur,
and will occur in the long run in six cases out of sixteen. Errors
of one and three inches will be equally likely, but will occur less
frequently; while no error at all, or one of four inches will be a
comparatively rare occurrence. If we now suppose the errors to act
as often in one direction as the other, the effect will be to alter
the average error by the amount of two inches, and we shall have the
following results:--

  Negative error of 2 inches     1 way.
  Negative error of 1 inch       4 ways.
  No error at all                6 ways.
  Positive error of 1 inch       4 ways.
  Positive error of 2 inches     1 way.

We may now imagine the number of causes of error increased and the
amount of each error decreased, and the arithmetical triangle will
give us the frequency of the resulting errors. Thus if there be five
positive causes of error and five negative causes, the following
table shows the numbers of errors of various amount which will be the
result:--

  +----------------------+-------------------+---+-------------------+
  | Direction of Error.  |  Positive Error.  |   |  Negative Error.  |
  +----------------------+-------------------+---+-------------------+
  |   Amount of Error.   |5,  4,  3,   2,   1| 0 | 1,   2,  3,  4,  5|
  +----------------------+-------------------+---+-------------------+
  |Number of such Errors.|1, 10, 45, 120, 210|252|210, 120, 45, 10, 1|
  +----------------------+-------------------+---+-------------------+

It is plain that from such numbers I can ascertain the probability
of any particular amount of error under the conditions supposed. The
probability of a positive error of exactly one inch is 210/1024, in
which fraction the numerator is the number of combinations giving
one inch positive error, and the denominator the whole number of
possible errors of all magnitudes. I can also, by adding together the
appropriate numbers get the probability of an error not exceeding a
certain amount. Thus the probability of an error of three inches or
less, positive or negative, is a fraction whose numerator is the sum of
45 + 120 + 210 + 252 + 210 + 120 + 45, and the denominator, as before,
giving the result 1002/1024. We may see at once that, according to
these principles, the probability of small errors is far greater than
of large ones: the odds are 1002 to 22, or more than 45 to 1, that the
error will not exceed three inches; and the odds are 1022 to 2 against
the occurrence of the greatest possible error of five inches.

If any case should arise in which the observer knows the number and
magnitude of the chief errors which may occur, he ought certainly to
calculate from the Arithmetical Triangle the special Law of Error
which would apply. But the general law, of which we are in search,
is to be used in the dark, when we have no knowledge whatever of the
sources of error. To assume any special number of causes of error
is then an arbitrary proceeding, and mathematicians have chosen the
least arbitrary course of imagining the existence of an infinite
number of infinitely small errors, just as, in the inverse method of
probabilities, an infinite number of infinitely improbable hypotheses
were submitted to calculation (p. 255).

The reasons in favour of this choice are of several different kinds.

1. It cannot be denied that there may exist infinitely numerous causes
of error in any act of observation.

2. The law resulting from the hypothesis of a moderate number of causes
of error, does not appreciably differ from that given by the hypothesis
of an infinite number of causes of error.

3. We gain by the hypothesis of infinity a general law capable of ready
calculation, and applicable by uniform rules to all problems.

4. This law, when tested by comparison with extensive series of
observations, is strikingly verified, as will be shown in a later
section.

When we imagine the existence of any large number of causes of
error, for instance one hundred, the numbers of combinations become
impracticably large, as may be seen to be the case from a glance at
the Arithmetical Triangle, which proceeds only up to the seventeenth
line. Quetelet, by suitable abbreviating processes, calculated out
a table of probability of errors on the hypothesis of one thousand
distinct causes;[282] but mathematicians have generally proceeded on
the hypothesis of infinity, and then, by the devices of analysis,
have substituted a general law of easy treatment. In mathematical
works upon the subject, it is shown that the standard Law of Error is
expressed in the formula

  *y* = *Y*ε^{-*cx*^{2}},

  [282] *Letters on the Theory of Probabilities*, Letter XV. and
  Appendix, note pp. 256–266.

in which *x* is the amount of the error, *Y* the maximum ordinate
of the curve of error, and *c* a number constant for each series of
observations, and expressing the amount of the tendency to error,
varying between one series of observations and another. The letter ε
is the mathematical constant, the sum of ratios between the numbers of
permutations and combinations, previously referred to (p. 330).

[Illustration]

To show the close correspondence of this general law with the special
law which might be derived from the supposition of a moderate number
of causes of error, I have in the accompanying figure drawn a curved
line representing accurately the variation of *y* when *x* in the above
formula is taken equal 0, 1/2, 1, 3/2, 2, &c., positive or negative,
the arbitrary quantities *Y* and *c* being each assumed equal to unity,
in order to simplify the calculations. In the same figure are inserted
eleven dots, whose heights above the base line are proportional to
the numbers in the eleventh line of the Arithmetical Triangle, thus
representing the comparative probabilities of errors of various amounts
arising from ten equal causes of error. The correspondence of the
general and the special Law of Error is almost as close as can be
exhibited in the figure, and the assumption of a greater number of
equal causes of error would render the correspondence far more close.

It may be explained that the ordinates NM, *nm*, *n′m′*, represent
values of *y* in the equation expressing the Law of Error. The
occurrence of any one definite amount of error is infinitely
improbable, because an infinite number of such ordinates might be
drawn. But the probability of an error occurring between certain limits
is finite, and is represented by a portion of the *area* of the curve.
Thus the probability that an error, positive or negative, not exceeding
unity will occur, is represented by the area M*mnn′m′*, in short, by
the area standing upon the line *nn′*. Since every observation must
either have some definite error or none at all, it follows that the
whole area of the curve should be considered as the unit expressing
certainty, and the probability of an error falling between particular
limits will then be expressed by the ratio which the area of the curve
between those limits bears to the whole area of the curve.

The mere fact that the Law of Error allows of the possible existence of
errors of every assignable amount shows that it is only approximately
true. We may fairly say that in measuring a mile it would be impossible
to commit an error of a hundred miles, and the length of life
would never allow of our committing an error of one million miles.
Nevertheless the general Law of Error would assign a probability for
an error of that amount or more, but so small a probability as to be
utterly inconsiderable and almost inconceivable. All that can, or in
fact need, be said in defence of the law is, that it may be made to
represent the errors in any special case to a very close approximation,
and that the probability of large and practically impossible errors, as
given by the law, will be so small as to be entirely inconsiderable.
And as we are dealing with error itself, and our results pretend to
nothing more than approximation and probability, an indefinitely small
error in our process of approximation is of no importance whatever.


*Logical Origin of the Law of Error.*

It is worthy of notice that this Law of Error, abstruse though the
subject may seem, is really founded upon the simplest principles.
It arises entirely out of the difference between permutations and
combinations, a subject upon which I may seem to have dwelt with
unnecessary prolixity in previous pages (pp. 170, 189). The order in
which we add quantities together does not affect the amount of the sum,
so that if there be three positive and five negative causes of error
in operation, it does not matter in which order they are considered as
acting. They may be intermixed in any arrangement, and yet the result
will be the same. The reader should not fail to notice how laws or
principles which appeared to be absurdly simple and evident when first
noticed, reappear in the most complicated and mysterious processes of
scientific method. The fundamental Laws of Identity and Difference gave
rise to the Logical Alphabet which, after abstracting the character of
the differences, led to the Arithmetical Triangle. The Law of Error is
defined by an infinitely high line of that triangle, and the law proves
that the mean is the most probable result, and that divergencies from
the mean become much less probable as they increase in amount. Now
the comparative greatness of the numbers towards the middle of each
line of the Arithmetical Triangle is entirely due to the indifference
of order in space or time, which was first prominently pointed out
as a condition of logical relations, and the symbols indicating them
(pp. 32–35), and which was afterwards shown to attach equally to
numerical symbols, the derivatives of logical terms (p. 160).


*Verification of the Law of Error.*

The theory of error which we have been considering rests entirely
upon an assumption, namely that when known sources of disturbances
are allowed for, there yet remain an indefinite, possibly an infinite
number of other minute sources of error, which will as often produce
excess as deficiency. Granting this assumption, the Law of Error must
be as it is usually taken to be, and there is no more need to verify
it empirically than to test the truth of one of Euclid’s propositions
mechanically. Nevertheless, it is an interesting occupation to verify
even the propositions of geometry, and it is still more instructive to
try whether a large number of observations will justify our assumption
of the Law of Error.

Encke has given an excellent instance of the correspondence of theory
with experience, in the case of observations of the differences of
Right Ascension of the sun and two stars, namely α Aquilæ and α Canis
minoris. The observations were 470 in number, and were made by Bradley
and reduced by Bessel, who found the probable error of the final result
to be only about one-fourth part of a second (0·2637). He then compared
the numbers of errors of each magnitude from 0·1 second upwards, as
actually given by the observations, with what should occur according to
the Law of Error.

The results were as follow:--[283]

  +-------------------------+--------------------------+
  |                         | Number of errors of each |
  | Magnitude of the errors |  magnitude according to  |
  |  in parts of a second.  +-------------+------------+
  |                         | Observation.|   Theory.  |
  +-------------------------+-------------+------------+
  |       0·0  to 0·1       |      94     |     95     |
  |        ·1  "   ·2       |      88     |     89     |
  |        ·2  "   ·3       |      78     |     78     |
  |        ·3  "   ·4       |      58     |     64     |
  |        ·4  "   ·5       |      51     |     50     |
  |        ·5  "   ·6       |      36     |     36     |
  |        ·6  "   ·7       |      26     |     24     |
  |        ·7  "   ·8       |      14     |     15     |
  |        ·8  "   ·9       |      10     |      9     |
  |        ·9  "  1·0       |       7     |      5     |
  |        above  1·0       |       8     |      5     |
  +-------------------------+-------------+------------+

  [283] Encke, *On the Method of Least Squares*, Taylor’s *Scientific
  Memoirs*, vol. ii. pp. 338, 339.

The reader will remark that the correspondence is very close, except
as regards larger errors, which are excessive in practice. It is one
objection, indeed, to the theory of error, that, being expressed in
a continuous mathematical function, it contemplates the existence of
errors of every magnitude, such as could not practically occur; yet
in this case the theory seems to under-estimate the number of large
errors.

Another comparison of the law with observation was made by Quetelet,
who investigated the errors of 487 determinations in time of the Right
Ascension of the Pole-Star made at Greenwich during the four years
1836–39. These observations, although carefully corrected for all known
causes of error, as well as for nutation, precession, &c., are yet of
course found to differ, and being classified as regards intervals of
one-half second of time, and then proportionately increased in number,
so that their sum may be one thousand, give the following results as
compared with what Quetelet’s theory would lead us to expect:--[284]

  +------------+--------------------+------------+--------------------+
  |Magnitude of|  Number of Errors  |Magnitude of|  Number of Errors  |
  |   error    +------------+-------+   error    +------------+-------+
  | in tenths  |    by      |  by   | in tenths  |    by      |  by   |
  |of a second.|Observation.|Theory.|of a second.|Observation.|Theory.|
  +------------+------------+-------+------------+------------+-------+
  |     0·0    |    168     |  163  |     --     |      --    |   --  |
  |    +0·5    |    148     |  147  |    -0·5    |     150    |  152  |
  |    +1·0    |    129     |  112  |    -1·0    |     126    |  121  |
  |    +1·5    |     78     |   72  |    -1·5    |      74    |   82  |
  |    +2·0    |     33     |   40  |    -2·0    |      43    |   46  |
  |    +2·5    |     10     |   19  |    -2·5    |      25    |   22  |
  |    +3·0    |      2     |   10  |    -3·0    |      12    |   10  |
  |     --     |     --     |   --  |    -3·5    |       2    |    4  |
  +------------+------------+-------+------------+------------+-------+

  [284] Quetelet, *Letters on the Theory of Probabilities*, translated
  by Downes, Letter XIX. p. 88. See also Galton’s *Hereditary Genius*,
  p. 379.

In this instance also the correspondence is satisfactory, but the
divergence between theory and fact is in the opposite direction to
that discovered in the former comparison, the larger errors being less
frequent than theory would indicate. It will be noticed that Quetelet’s
theoretical results are not symmetrical.


*The Probable Mean Result.*

One immediate result of the Law of Error, as thus stated, is that the
mean result is the most probable one; and when there is only a single
variable this mean is found by the familiar arithmetical process. An
unfortunate error has crept into several works which allude to this
subject. Mill, in treating of the “Elimination of Chance,” remarks in
a note[285] that “the mean is spoken of as if it were exactly the
same thing as the average. But the mean, for purposes of inductive
inquiry, is not the average, or arithmetical mean, though in a familiar
illustration of the theory the difference may be disregarded.” He goes
on to say that, according to mathematical principles, the most probable
result is that for which the sums of the squares of the deviations is
the least possible. It seems probable that Mill and other writers were
misled by Whewell, who says[286] that “The method of least squares is
in fact a method of means, but with some peculiar characters.... The
method proceeds upon this supposition: that all errors are not equally
probable, but that small errors are more probable than large ones.” He
adds that this method “removes much that is arbitrary in the method
of means.” It is strange to find a mathematician like Whewell making
such remarks, when there is no doubt whatever that the Method of Means
is only an application of the Method of Least Squares. They are, in
fact, the same method, except that the latter method may be applied to
cases where two or more quantities have to be determined at the same
time. Lubbock and Drinkwater say,[287] “If only one quantity has to
be determined, this method evidently resolves itself into taking the
mean of all the values given by observation.” Encke says,[288] that the
expression for the probability of an error “not only contains in itself
the principle of the arithmetical mean, but depends so immediately upon
it, that for all those magnitudes for which the arithmetical mean holds
good in the simple cases in which it is principally applied, no other
law of probability can be assumed than that which is expressed by this
formula.”

  [285] *System of Logic*, bk. iii. chap. 17, § 3. 5th ed. vol. ii.
  p. 56.

  [286] *Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences*, 2nd ed. vol. ii.
  pp. 408, 409.

  [287] *Essay on Probability*, Useful Knowledge Society, 1833, p. 41.

  [288] Taylor’s *Scientific Memoirs*, vol. ii. p. 333.


*The Probable Error of Results.*

When we draw a conclusion from the numerical results of observations we
ought not to consider it sufficient, in cases of importance, to content
ourselves with finding the simple mean and treating it as true. We
ought also to ascertain what is the degree of confidence we may place
in this mean, and our confidence should be measured by the degree of
concurrence of the observations from which it is derived. In some cases
the mean may be approximately certain and accurate. In other cases it
may really be worth little or nothing. The Law of Error enables us to
give exact expression to the degree of confidence proper in any case;
for it shows how to calculate the probability of a divergence of any
amount from the mean, and we can thence ascertain the probability that
the mean in question is within a certain distance from the true number.
The *probable error* is taken by mathematicians to mean the limits
within which it is as likely as not that the truth will fall. Thus
if 5·45 be the mean of all the determinations of the density of the
earth, and ·20 be approximately the probable error, the meaning is that
the probability of the real density of the earth falling between 5·25
and 5·65 is 1/2. Any other limits might have been selected at will.
We might calculate the limits within which it was one hundred or one
thousand to one that the truth would fall; but there is a convention to
take the even odds one to one, as the quantity of probability of which
the limits are to be estimated.

Many books on probability give rules for making the calculations,
but as, in the progress of science, persons ought to become more
familiar with these processes, I propose to repeat the rules here and
illustrate their use. The calculations, when made in accordance with
the directions, involve none but arithmetic or logarithmic operations.

The following are the rules for treating a mean result, so as
thoroughly to ascertain its trustworthiness.

1. Draw the mean of all the observed results.

2. Find the excess or defect, that is, the error of each result from
the mean.

3. Square each of these reputed errors.

4. Add together all these squares of the errors, which are of course
all positive.

5. Divide by one less than the number of observations. This gives the
*square of the mean error*.

6. Take the square root of the last result; it is the *mean error of a
single observation*.

7. Divide now by the square root of the number of observations, and we
get the *mean error of the mean result*.

8. Lastly, multiply by the natural constant O·6745 (or approximately
by 0·674, or even by 2/3), and we arrive at the *probable error of the
mean result*.

Suppose, for instance, that five measurements of the height of a
hill, by the barometer or otherwise, have given the numbers of feet
as 293, 301, 306, 307, 313; we want to know the probable error of the
mean, namely 304. Now the differences between this mean and the above
numbers, *paying no regard to direction*, are 11, 3, 2, 3, 9; their
squares are 121, 9, 4, 9, 81, and the sum of the squares of the errors
consequently 224. The number of observations being 5, we divide by
1 less, or 4, getting 56. This is the square of the mean error, and
taking its square root we have 7·48 (say 7-1/2), the mean error of
a single observation. Dividing by 2·236, the square root of 5, the
number of observations, we find the mean error of the *mean* result to
be 3·35, or say 3-1/3, and lastly, multiplying by ·6745, we arrive at
the *probable error of the mean result*, which is found to be 2·259,
or say 2-1/4. The meaning of this is that the probability is one half,
or the odds are even that the true height of the mountain lies between
301-3/4 and 306-1/4 feet. We have thus an exact measure of the degree
of credibility of our mean result, which mean indicates the most likely
point for the truth to fall upon.

The reader should observe that as the object in these calculations
is only to gain a notion of the degree of confidence with which we
view the mean, there is no real use in carrying the calculations to
any great degree of precision; and whenever the neglect of decimal
fractions, or even the slight alteration of a number, will much
abbreviate the computations, it may be fearlessly done, except in
cases of high importance and precision. Brodie has shown how the law
of error may be usefully applied in chemical investigations, and some
illustrations of its employment may be found in his paper.[289]

  [289] *Philosophical Transactions*, 1873, p. 83.

The experiments of Benzenberg to detect the revolution of the earth, by
the deviation of a ball from the perpendicular line in falling down a
deep pit, have been cited by Encke[290] as an interesting illustration
of the Law of Error. The mean deviation was 5·086 lines, and its
probable error was calculated by Encke to be not more than ·950 line,
that is, the odds were even that the true result lay between 4·136 and
6·036. As the deviation, according to astronomical theory, should be
4·6 lines, which lies well within the limits, we may consider that the
experiments are consistent with the Copernican system of the universe.

  [290] Taylor’s *Scientific Memoirs*, vol. ii. pp. 330, 347, &c.

It will of course be understood that the probable error has regard only
to those causes of errors which in the long run act as much in one
direction as another; it takes no account of constant errors. The true
result accordingly will often fall far beyond the limits of probable
error, owing to some considerable constant error or errors, of the
existence of which we are unaware.


*Rejection of the Mean Result.*

We ought always to bear in mind that the mean of any series of
observations is the best, that is, the most probable approximation
to the truth, only in the absence of knowledge to the contrary. The
selection of the mean rests entirely upon the probability that unknown
causes of error will in the long run fall as often in one direction as
the opposite, so that in drawing the mean they will balance each other.
If we have any reason to suppose that there exists a tendency to error
in one direction rather than the other, then to choose the mean would
be to ignore that tendency. We may certainly approximate to the length
of the circumference of a circle, by taking the mean of the perimeters
of inscribed and circumscribed polygons of an equal and large number
of sides. The length of the circular line undoubtedly lies between the
lengths of the two perimeters, but it does not follow that the mean is
the best approximation. It may in fact be shown that the circumference
of the circle is *very nearly* equal to the perimeter of the inscribed
polygon, together with one-third part of the difference between the
inscribed and circumscribed polygons of the same number of sides.
Having this knowledge, we ought of course to act upon it, instead of
trusting to probability.

We may often perceive that a series of measurements tends towards an
extreme limit rather than towards a mean. In endeavouring to obtain
a correct estimate of the apparent diameter of the brightest fixed
stars, we find a continuous diminution in estimates as the powers of
observation increased. Kepler assigned to Sirius an apparent diameter
of 240 seconds; Tycho Brahe made it 126; Gassendi 10 seconds; Galileo,
Hevelius, and J. Cassini, 5 or 6 seconds. Halley, Michell, and
subsequently Sir W. Herschel came to the conclusion that the brightest
stars in the heavens could not have real discs of a second, and were
probably much less in diameter. It would of course be absurd to take
the mean of quantities which differ more than 240 times; and as the
tendency has always been to smaller estimates, there is a considerable
presumption in favour of the smallest.[291]

  [291] Quetelet, *Letters*, &c. p. 116.

In many experiments and measurements we know that there is a
preponderating tendency to error in one direction. The readings of a
thermometer tend to rise as the age of the instrument increases, and
no drawing of means will correct this result. Barometers, on the other
hand, are likely to read too low instead of too high, owing to the
imperfection of the vacuum and the action of capillary attraction. If
the mercury be perfectly pure and no appreciable error be due to the
measuring apparatus, the best barometer will be that which gives the
highest result. In determining the specific gravity of a solid body the
chief danger of error arises from bubbles of air adhering to the body,
which would tend to make the specific gravity too small. Much attention
must always be given to one-sided errors of this kind, since the
multiplication of experiments does not remove the error. In such cases
one very careful experiment is better than any number of careless ones.

When we have reasonable grounds for supposing that certain experimental
results are liable to grave errors, we should exclude them in drawing
a mean. If we want to find the most probable approximation to the
velocity of sound in air, it would be absurd to go back to the old
experiments which made the velocity from 1200 to 1474 feet per second;
for we know that the old observers did not guard against errors arising
from wind and other causes. Old chemical experiments are valueless as
regards quantitative results. The old chemists found the atmosphere
in different places to differ in composition nearly ten per cent.,
whereas modern accurate experimenters find very slight variations.
Any method of measurement which we know to avoid a source of error is
far to be preferred to others which trust to probabilities for the
elimination of the error. As Flamsteed says,[292] “One good instrument
is of as much worth as a hundred indifferent ones.” But an instrument
is good or bad only in a comparative sense, and no instrument gives
invariable and truthful results. Hence we must always ultimately fall
back upon probabilities for the selection of the final mean, when other
precautions are exhausted.

  [292] Baily, *Account of Flamsteed*, p. 56.

Legendre, the discoverer of the method of Least Squares,
recommended that observations differing very much from the results
of his method should be rejected. The subject has been carefully
investigated by Professor Pierce, who has proposed a criterion
for the rejection of doubtful observations based on the following
principle:[293]′“--observations should be rejected when the probability
of the system of errors obtained by retaining them is less than that
of the system of errors obtained by their rejection multiplied by the
probability of making so many and no more abnormal observations.”
Professor Pierce’s investigation is given nearly in his own words in
Professor W. Chauvenet’s “Manual of Spherical and Practical Astronomy,”
which contains a full and excellent discussion of the methods of
treating numerical observations.[294]

  [293] Gould’s *Astronomical Journal*, Cambridge, Mass., vol. ii.
  p. 161.

  [294] Philadelphia (London, Trübner) 1863. Appendix, vol. ii. p. 558.

Very difficult questions sometimes arise when one or more results of
a method of experiment diverge widely from the mean of the rest. Are
we or are we not to exclude them in adopting the supposed true mean
result of the method? The drawing of a mean result rests, as I have
frequently explained, upon the assumption that every error acting in
one direction will probably be balanced by other errors acting in an
opposite direction. If then we know or can possibly discover any causes
of error not agreeing with this assumption, we shall be justified in
excluding results which seem to be affected by this cause.

In reducing large series of astronomical observations, it is not
uncommon to meet with numbers differing from others by a whole degree
or half a degree, or some considerable integral quantity. These are
errors which could hardly arise in the act of observation or in
instrumental irregularity; but they might readily be accounted for
by misreading of figures or mistaking of division marks. It would be
absurd to trust to chance that such mistakes would balance each other
in the long run, and it is therefore better to correct arbitrarily
the supposed mistake, or better still, if new observations can be
made, to strike out the divergent numbers altogether. When results
come sometimes too great or too small in a regular manner, we should
suspect that some part of the instrument slips through a definite
space, or that a definite cause of error enters at times, and not at
others. We should then make it a point of prime importance to discover
the exact nature and amount of such an error, and either prevent its
occurrence for the future or else introduce a corresponding correction.
In many researches the whole difficulty will consist in this detection
and avoidance of sources of error. Professor Roscoe found that the
presence of phosphorus caused serious and almost unavoidable errors in
the determination of the atomic weight of vanadium.[295] Herschel, in
reducing his observations of double stars at the Cape of Good Hope,
was perplexed by an unaccountable difference of the angles of position
as measured by the seven-feet equatorial and the twenty-feet reflector
telescopes, and after a careful investigation was obliged to be
contented with introducing a correction experimentally determined.[296]

  [295] Bakerian Lecture, *Philosophical Transactions* (1868),
  vol. clviii. p. 6.

  [296] *Results of Observations at the Cape of Good Hope*, p. 283.

When observations are sufficiently numerous it seems desirable to
project the apparent errors into a curve, and then to observe whether
this curve exhibits the symmetrical and characteristic form of the
curve of error. If so, it may be inferred that the errors arise from
many minute independent sources, and probably compensate each other
in the mean result. Any considerable irregularity will indicate the
existence of one-sided or large causes of error, which should be made
the subject of investigation.

Even the most patient and exhaustive investigations will sometimes
fail to disclose any reason why some results diverge from others.
The question again recurs--Are we arbitrarily to exclude them? The
answer should be in the negative as a general rule. The mere fact
of divergence ought not to be taken as conclusive against a result,
and the exertion of arbitrary choice would open the way to the fatal
influence of bias, and what is commonly known as the “cooking” of
figures. It would amount to judging fact by theory instead of theory
by fact. The apparently divergent number may prove in time to be the
true one. It may be an exception of that valuable kind which upsets our
false theories, a real exception, exploding apparent coincidences, and
opening a way to a new view of the subject. To establish this position
for the divergent fact will require additional research; but in the
meantime we should give it some weight in our mean conclusions, and
should bear in mind the discrepancy as one demanding attention. To
neglect a divergent result is to neglect the possible clue to a great
discovery.


*Method of Least Squares.*

When two or more unknown quantities are so involved that they cannot
be separately determined by the Simple Method of Means, we can yet
obtain their most probable values by the Method of Least Squares,
without more difficulty than arises from the length of the arithmetical
computations. If the result of each observation gives an equation
between two unknown quantities of the form

  *ax* + *by* = *c*

then, if the observations were free from error, we should need only two
observations giving two equations; but for the attainment of greater
accuracy, we may take many observations, and reduce the equations
so as to give only a pair with mean coefficients. This reduction is
effected by (1.), multiplying the coefficients of each equation by the
first coefficient, and adding together all the similar coefficients
thus resulting for the coefficients of a new equation; and (2.), by
repeating this process, and multiplying the coefficients of each
equation by the coefficient of the second term. Meaning by (sum of
*a*^{2}) the sum of all quantities of the same kind, and having the
same place in the equations as *a*^{2}, we may briefly describe the two
resulting mean equations as follows:--

  (sum of *a*^{2}) . *x* + (sum of *ab*) . *y* = (sum of *ac*),
  (sum of *ab*) . *x* + (sum of *b*^{2}) . *y* = (sum of *bc*).

When there are three or more unknown quantities the process is exactly
the same in nature, and we get additional mean equations by multiplying
by the third, fourth, &c., coefficients. As the numbers are in any
case approximate, it is usually unnecessary to make the computations
with accuracy, and places of decimals may be freely cut off to save
arithmetical work. The mean equations having been computed, their
solution by the ordinary methods of algebra gives the most probable
values of the unknown quantities.


*Works upon the Theory of Probability.*

Regarding the Theory of Probability and the Law of Error as most
important subjects of study for any one who desires to obtain a
complete comprehension of scientific method as actually applied in
physical investigations, I will briefly indicate the works in one or
other of which the reader will best pursue the study.

The best popular, and at the same time profound English work on the
subject is De Morgan’s “Essay on Probabilities and on their Application
to Life Contingencies and Insurance Offices,” published in the *Cabinet
Cyclopædia*, and to be obtained (in print) from Messrs. Longman. Mr.
Venn’s work on *The Logic of Chance* can now be procured in a greatly
enlarged second edition;[297] it contains a most interesting and able
discussion of the metaphysical basis of probability and of related
questions concerning causation, belief, design, testimony, &c.; but I
cannot always agree with Mr. Venn’s opinions. No mathematical knowledge
beyond that of common arithmetic is required in reading these works.
Quetelet’s *Letters* form a good introduction to the subject, and the
mathematical notes are of value. Sir George Airy’s brief treatise *On
the Algebraical and Numerical Theory of Errors of Observations and
the Combination of Observations*, contains a complete explanation of
the Law of Error and its practical applications. De Morgan’s treatise
“On the Theory of Probabilities” in the *Encyclopædia Metropolitana*,
presents an abstract of the more abstruse investigations of
Laplace, together with a multitude of profound and original remarks
concerning the theory generally. In Lubbock and Drinkwater’s work on
*Probability*, in the Library of Useful Knowledge, we have a concise
but good statement of a number of important problems. The Rev.
W. A. Whitworth has given, in a work entitled *Choice and Chance*,
a number of good illustrations of calculations both in combinations
and probabilities. In Mr. Todhunter’s admirable History we have an
exhaustive critical account of almost all writings upon the subject
of probability down to the culmination of the theory in Laplace’s
works. The Memoir of Mr. J. W. L. Glaisher has already been mentioned
(p. 375). In spite of the existence of these and some other good
English works, there seems to be a want of an easy and yet pretty
complete mathematical introduction to the study of the theory.

  [297] *The Logic of Chance*, an Essay on the Foundations and Province
  of the Theory of Probability, with especial reference to its
  Logical Bearings and its Application to Moral and Social Science.
  (Macmillan), 1876.

Among French works the Traité *Élémentaire du Calcul des Probabilités*,
by S. E. Lacroix, of which several editions have been published, and
which is not difficult to obtain, forms probably the best elementary
treatise. Poisson’s *Recherches sur la Probabilité des Jugements*
(Paris 1837), commence with an admirable investigation of the grounds
and methods of the theory. While Laplace’s great *Théorie Analytique
des Probabilités* is of course the “Principia” of the subject; his
*Essai Philosophique sur les Probabilités* is a popular discourse, and
is one of the most profound and interesting essays ever published. It
should be familiar to every student of logical method, and has lost
little or none of its importance by lapse of time.


*Detection of Constant Errors.*

The Method of Means is absolutely incapable of eliminating any error
which is always the same, or which always lies in one direction. We
sometimes require to be roused from a false feeling of security, and
to be urged to take suitable precautions against such occult errors.
“It is to the observer,” says Gauss,[298] “that belongs the task of
carefully removing the causes of constant errors,” and this is quite
true when the error is absolutely constant. When we have made a number
of determinations with a certain apparatus or method of measurement,
there is a great advantage in altering the arrangement, or even
devising some entirely different method of getting estimates of the
same quantity. The reason obviously consists in the improbability that
the same error will affect two or more different methods of experiment.
If a discrepancy is found to exist, we shall at least be aware of the
existence of error, and can take measures for finding in which way it
lies. If we can try a considerable number of methods, the probability
becomes great that errors constant in one method will be balanced or
nearly so by errors of an opposite effect in the others. Suppose that
there be three different methods each affected by an error of equal
amount. The probability that this error will in all fall in the same
direction is only 1/4; and with four methods similarly 1/8. If each
method be affected, as is always the case, by several independent
sources of error, the probability becomes much greater that in the mean
result of all the methods some of the errors will partially compensate
the others. In this case as in all others, when human vigilance has
exhausted itself, we must trust the theory of probability.

  [298] Gauss, translated by Bertrand, p. 25.

In the determination of a zero point, of the magnitude of the
fundamental standards of time and space, in the personal equation of
an astronomical observer, we have instances of fixed errors; but as a
general rule a change of procedure is likely to reverse the character
of the error, and many instances may be given of the value of this
precaution. If we measure over and over again the same angular
magnitude by the same divided circle, maintained in exactly the same
position, it is evident that the same mark in the circle will be the
criterion in each case, and any error in the position of that mark will
equally affect all our results. But if in each measurement we use a
different part of the circle, a new mark will come into use, and as the
error of each mark cannot be in the same direction, the average result
will be nearly free from errors of division. It will be better still to
use more than one divided circle.

Even when we have no perception of the points at which error is
likely to enter, we may with advantage vary the construction of our
apparatus in the hope that we shall accidentally detect some latent
cause of error. Baily’s purpose in repeating the experiments of
Michell and Cavendish on the density of the earth was not merely to
follow the same course and verify the previous numbers, but to try
whether variations in the size and substance of the attracting balls,
the mode of suspension, the temperature of the surrounding air, &c.,
would yield different results. He performed no less than 62 distinct
series, comprising 2153 experiments, and he carefully classified and
discussed the results so as to disclose the utmost differences. Again,
in experimenting upon the resistance of the air to the motion of a
pendulum, Baily employed no less than 80 pendulums of various forms
and materials, in order to ascertain exactly upon what conditions
the resistance depends. Regnault, in his exact researches upon the
dilatation of gases, made arbitrary changes in the magnitude of parts
of his apparatus. He thinks that if, in spite of such modification,
the results are unchanged, the errors are probably of inconsiderable
amount;[299] but in reality it is always possible, and usually likely,
that we overlook sources of error which a future generation will
detect. Thus the pendulum experiments of Baily and Sabine were directed
to ascertain the nature and amount of a correction for air resistance,
which had been entirely misunderstood in the experiments by means of
the seconds pendulum, upon which was founded the definition of the
standard yard, in the Act of 5th George IV. c. 74. It has already been
mentioned that a considerable error was discovered in the determination
of the standard metre as the ten-millionth part of the distance from
the pole to the equator (p. 314).

  [299] Jamin, *Cours de Physique*, vol. ii. p. 60.

We shall return in Chapter XXV. to the further consideration of the
methods by which we may as far as possible secure ourselves against
permanent and undetected sources of error. In the meantime, having
completed the consideration of the special methods requisite for
treating quantitative phenomena, we must pursue our principal subject,
and endeavour to trace out the course by which the physicist, from
observation and experiment, collects the materials of knowledge, and
then proceeds by hypothesis and inverse calculation to induce from them
the laws of nature.




Book IV.

INDUCTIVE INVESTIGATION.




CHAPTER XVIII.

OBSERVATION.


ALL knowledge proceeds originally from experience. Using the name in a
wide sense, we may say that experience comprehends all that we *feel*,
externally or internally--the aggregate of the impressions which we
receive through the various apertures of perception--the aggregate
consequently of what is in the mind, except so far as some portions
of knowledge may be the reasoned equivalents of other portions. As
the word experience expresses, we *go through* much in life, and the
impressions gathered intentionally or unintentionally afford the
materials from which the active powers of the mind evolve science.

No small part of the experience actually employed in science is
acquired without any distinct purpose. We cannot use the eyes without
gathering some facts which may prove useful. A great science has in
many cases risen from an accidental observation. Erasmus Bartholinus
thus first discovered double refraction in Iceland spar; Galvani
noticed the twitching of a frog’s leg; Oken was struck by the form of
a vertebra; Malus accidentally examined light reflected from distant
windows with a double refracting substance; and Sir John Herschel’s
attention was drawn to the peculiar appearance of a solution of quinine
sulphate. In earlier times there must have been some one who first
noticed the strange behaviour of a loadstone, or the unaccountable
motions produced by amber. As a general rule we shall not know in what
direction to look for a great body of phenomena widely different from
those familiar to us. Chance then must give us the starting point; but
one accidental observation well used may lead us to make thousands of
observations in an intentional and organised manner, and thus a science
may be gradually worked out from the smallest opening.


*Distinction of Observation and Experiment.*

It is usual to say that the two sources of experience are Observation
and Experiment. When we merely note and record the phenomena which
occur around us in the ordinary course of nature we are said *to
observe*. When we change the course of nature by the intervention
of our muscular powers, and thus produce unusual combinations and
conditions of phenomena, we are said *to experiment*. Herschel justly
remarked[300] that we might properly call these two modes of experience
*passive and active observation*. In both cases we must certainly
employ our senses to observe, and an experiment differs from a mere
observation in the fact that we more or less influence the character
of the events which we observe. Experiment is thus observation *plus*
alteration of conditions.

  [300] *Preliminary Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy*,
  p. 77.

It may readily be seen that we pass upwards by insensible gradations
from pure observation to determinate experiment. When the earliest
astronomers simply noticed the ordinary motions of the sun, moon, and
planets upon the face of the starry heavens, they were pure observers.
But astronomers now select precise times and places for important
observations of stellar parallax, or the transits of planets. They make
the earth’s orbit the basis of a well arranged *natural experiment*,
as it were, and take well considered advantage of motions which they
cannot control. Meteorology might seem to be a science of pure
observation, because we cannot possibly govern the changes of weather
which we record. Nevertheless we may ascend mountains or rise in
balloons, like Gay-Lussac and Glaisher, and may thus so vary the points
of observation as to render our procedure experimental. We are wholly
unable either to produce or prevent earth-currents of electricity,
but when we construct long lines of telegraph, we gather such strong
currents during periods of disturbance as to render them capable of
easy observation.

The best arranged systems of observation, however, would fail to give
us a large part of the facts which we now possess. Many processes
continually going on in nature are so slow and gentle as to escape
our powers of observation. Lavoisier remarked that the decomposition
of water must have been constantly proceeding in nature, although its
possibility was unknown till his time.[301] No substance is wholly
destitute of magnetic or diamagnetic powers; but it required all the
experimental skill of Faraday to prove that iron and a few other
metals had no monopoly of these powers. Accidental observation long
ago impressed upon men’s minds the phenomena of lightning, and the
attractive properties of amber. Experiment only could have shown that
phenomena so diverse in magnitude and character were manifestations of
the same agent. To observe with accuracy and convenience we must have
agents under our control, so as to raise or lower their intensity,
to stop or set them in action at will. Just as Smeaton found it
requisite to create an artificial and governable supply of wind for
his investigation of windmills, so we must have governable supplies of
light, heat, electricity, muscular force, or whatever other agents we
are examining.

  [301] Lavoisier’s *Elements of Chemistry*, translated by Kerr, 3rd
  ed. p. 148.

It is hardly needful to point out too that on the earth’s surface we
live under nearly constant conditions of gravity, temperature, and
atmospheric pressure, so that if we are to extend our inferences to
other parts of the universe where conditions are widely different, we
must be prepared to imitate those conditions on a small scale here.
We must have intensely high and low temperatures; we must vary the
density of gases from approximate vacuum upwards; we must subject
liquids and solids to pressures or strains of almost unlimited amount.


*Mental Conditions of Correct Observation.*

Every observation must in a certain sense be true, for the observing
and recording of an event is in itself an event. But before we proceed
to deal with the supposed meaning of the record, and draw inferences
concerning the course of nature, we must take care to ascertain that
the character and feelings of the observer are not to a great extent
the phenomena recorded. The mind of man, as Francis Bacon said, is
like an uneven mirror, and does not reflect the events of nature
without distortion. We need hardly take notice of intentionally false
observations, nor of mistakes arising from defective memory, deficient
light, and so forth. Even where the utmost fidelity and care are used
in observing and recording, tendencies to error exist, and fallacious
opinions arise in consequence.

It is difficult to find persons who can with perfect fairness register
facts for and against their own peculiar views. Among uncultivated
observers the tendency to remark favourable and forget unfavourable
events is so great, that no reliance can be placed upon their supposed
observations. Thus arises the enduring fallacy that the changes of the
weather coincide in some way with the changes of the moon, although
exact and impartial registers give no countenance to the fact. The
whole race of prophets and quacks live on the overwhelming effect of
one success, compared with hundreds of failures which are unmentioned
and forgotten. As Bacon says, “Men mark when they hit, and never mark
when they miss.” And we should do well to bear in mind the ancient
story, quoted by Bacon, of one who in Pagan times was shown a temple
with a picture of all the persons who had been saved from shipwreck,
after paying their vows. When asked whether he did not now acknowledge
the power of the gods, “Ay,” he answered; “but where are they painted
that were drowned after their vows?”

If indeed we could estimate the amount of *bias* existing in any
particular observations, it might be treated like one of the forces
of the problem, and the true course of external nature might still be
rendered apparent. But the feelings of an observer are usually too
indeterminate, so that when there is reason to suspect considerable
bias, rejection is the only safe course. As regards facts casually
registered in past times, the capacity and impartiality of the observer
are so little known that we should spare no pains to replace these
statements by a new appeal to nature. An indiscriminate medley of
truth and absurdity, such as Francis Bacon collected in his *Natural
History*, is wholly unsuited to the purposes of science. But of course
when records relate to past events like eclipses, conjunctions,
meteoric phenomena, earthquakes, volcanic eruptions, changes of sea
margins, the existence of now extinct animals, the migrations of
tribes, remarkable customs, &c., we must make use of statements however
unsatisfactory, and must endeavour to verify them by the comparison of
independent records or traditions.

When extensive series of observations have to be made, as in
astronomical, meteorological, or magnetical observatories,
trigonometrical surveys, and extensive chemical or physical researches,
it is an advantage that the numerical work should be executed by
assistants who are not interested in, and are perhaps unaware of, the
expected results. The record is thus rendered perfectly impartial.
It may even be desirable that those who perform the purely routine
work of measurement and computation should be unacquainted with the
principles of the subject. The great table of logarithms of the
French Revolutionary Government was worked out by a staff of sixty or
eighty computers, most of whom were acquainted only with the rules of
arithmetic, and worked under the direction of skilled mathematicians;
yet their calculations were usually found more correct than those of
persons more deeply versed in mathematics.[302] In the Indian Ordnance
Survey the actual measurers were selected so that they should not have
sufficient skill to falsify their results without detection.

  [302] Babbage, *Economy of Manufactures*, p. 194.

Both passive observation and experimentation must, however, be
generally conducted by persons who know for what they are to look. It
is only when excited and guided by the hope of verifying a theory that
the observer will notice many of the most important points; and, where
the work is not of a routine character, no assistant can supersede the
mind-directed observations of the philosopher. Thus the successful
investigator must combine diverse qualities; he must have clear notions
of the result he expects and confidence in the truth of his theories,
and yet he must have that candour and flexibility of mind which enable
him to accept unfavourable results and abandon mistaken views.


*Instrumental and Sensual Conditions of Observation.*

In every observation one or more of the senses must be employed, and
we should ever bear in mind that the extent of our knowledge may be
limited by the power of the sense concerned. What we learn of the world
only forms the lower limit of what is to be learned, and, for all that
we can tell, the processes of nature may infinitely surpass in variety
and complexity those which are capable of coming within our means of
observation. In some cases inference from observed phenomena may make
us indirectly aware of what cannot be directly felt, but we can never
be sure that we thus acquire any appreciable fraction of the knowledge
that might be acquired.

It is a strange reflection that space may be filled with dark wandering
stars, whose existence could not have yet become in any way known to
us. The planets have already cooled so far as to be no longer luminous,
and it may well be that other stellar bodies of various size have
fallen into the same condition. From the consideration, indeed, of
variable and extinguished stars, Laplace inferred that there probably
exist opaque bodies as great and perhaps as numerous as those we
see.[303] Some of these dark stars might ultimately become known to
us, either by reflecting light, or more probably by their gravitating
effects upon luminous stars. Thus if one member of a double star
were dark, we could readily detect its existence, and even estimate
its size, position, and motions, by observing those of its visible
companion. It was a favourite notion of Huyghens that there may exist
stars and vast universes so distant that their light has never yet
had time to reach our eyes; and we must also bear in mind that light
may possibly suffer slow extinction in space, so that there is more
than one way in which an absolute limit to the powers of telescopic
discovery may exist.

  [303] *System of the World*, translated by Harte, vol. ii. p. 335.

There are natural limits again to the power of our senses in detecting
undulations of various kinds. It is commonly said that vibrations of
more than 38,000 strokes per second are not audible as sound; and
as some ears actually do hear sounds of much higher pitch, even two
octaves higher than what other ears can detect, it is exceedingly
probable that there are incessant vibrations which we cannot call sound
because they are never heard. Insects may communicate by such acute
sounds, constituting a language inaudible to us; and the remarkable
agreement apparent among bodies of ants or bees might thus perhaps be
explained. Nay, as Fontenelle long ago suggested in his scientific
romance, there may exist unlimited numbers of senses or modes of
perception which we can never feel, though Darwin’s theory would render
it probable that any useful means of knowledge in an ancestor would
be developed and improved in the descendants. We might doubtless have
been endowed with a sense capable of feeling electric phenomena with
acuteness, so that the positive or negative state of charge of a body
could be at once estimated. The absence of such a sense is probably due
to its comparative uselessness.

Heat undulations are subject to the same considerations. It is now
apparent that what we call light is the affection of the eye by certain
vibrations, the less rapid of which are invisible and constitute the
dark rays of radiant heat, in detecting which we must substitute
the thermometer or the thermopile for the eye. At the other end of
the spectrum, again, the ultra-violet rays are invisible, and only
indirectly brought to our knowledge in the phenomena of fluorescence or
photo-chemical action. There is no reason to believe that at either end
of the spectrum an absolute limit has yet been reached.

Just as our knowledge of the stellar universe is limited by the
power of the telescope and other conditions, so our knowledge of the
minute world has its limit in the powers and optical conditions of
the microscope. There was a time when it would have been a reasonable
induction that vegetables are motionless, and animals alone endowed
with power of locomotion. We are astonished to discover by the
microscope that minute plants are if anything more active than
minute animals. We even find that mineral substances seem to lose
their inactive character and dance about with incessant motion when
reduced to sufficiently minute particles, at least when suspended
in a non-conducting medium.[304] Microscopists will meet a natural
limit to observation when the minuteness of the objects examined
becomes comparable to the length of light undulations, and the extreme
difficulty already encountered in determining the forms of minute marks
on Diatoms appears to be due to this cause. According to Helmholtz the
smallest distance which can be accurately defined depends upon the
interference of light passing through the centres of the bright spaces.
With a theoretically perfect microscope and a dry lense the smallest
visible object would not be less than one 80,000th part of an inch in
red light.

  [304] This curious phenomenon, which I propose to call *pedesis*, or
  the *pedetic movement*, from πηδόω, to jump, is carefully described
  in my paper published in the *Quarterly Journal of Science* for
  April, 1878, vol. viii. (N.S.) p. 167. See also *Proceedings of the
  Literary and Philosophical Society of Manchester*, 25th January,
  1870, vol. ix. p. 78, *Nature*, 22nd August, 1878, vol. xviii.
  p. 440, or the *Quarterly Journal of Science*, vol. viii. (N.S.)
  p. 514.

Of the errors likely to arise in estimating quantities by the senses I
have already spoken, but there are some cases in which we actually see
things differently from what they are. A jet of water appears to be a
continuous thread, when it is really a wonderfully organised succession
of small and large drops, oscillating in form. The drops fall so
rapidly that their impressions upon the eye run into each other, and in
order to see the separate drops we require some device for giving an
instantaneous view.

One insuperable limit to our powers of observation arises from the
impossibility of following and identifying the ultimate atoms of
matter. One atom of oxygen is probably undistinguishable from another
atom; only by keeping a certain volume of oxygen safely inclosed in a
bottle can we assure ourselves of its identity; allow it to mix with
other oxygen, and we lose all power of identification. Accordingly
we seem to have no means of directly proving that every gas is in a
constant state of diffusion of every part into every part. We can only
infer this to be the case from observing the behaviour of distinct
gases which we can distinguish in their course, and by reasoning on the
grounds of molecular theory.[305]

  [305] Maxwell, *Theory of Heat*, p. 301.


*External Conditions of Correct Observation.*

Before we proceed to draw inferences from any series of recorded facts,
we must take care to ascertain perfectly, if possible, the external
conditions under which the facts are brought to our notice. Not only
may the observing mind be prejudiced and the senses defective, but
there may be circumstances which cause one kind of event to come more
frequently to our notice than another. The comparative numbers of
objects of different kinds existing may in any degree differ from the
numbers which come to our notice. This difference must if possible be
taken into account before we make any inferences.

There long appeared to be a strong presumption that all comets moved
in elliptic orbits, because no comet had been proved to move in any
other kind of path. The theory of gravitation admitted of the existence
of comets moving in hyperbolic orbits, and the question arose whether
they were really non-existent or were only beyond the bounds of easy
observation. From reasonable suppositions Laplace calculated that
the probability was at least 6000 to 1 against a comet which comes
within the planetary system sufficiently to be visible at the earth’s
surface, presenting an orbit which could be discriminated from a very
elongated ellipse or parabola in the part of its orbit within the reach
of our telescopes.[306] In short, the chances are very much in favour
of our seeing elliptic rather than hyperbolic comets. Laplace’s views
have been confirmed by the discovery of six hyperbolic comets, which
appeared in the years 1729, 1771, 1774, 1818, 1840, and 1843,[307] and
as only about 800 comets altogether have been recorded, the proportion
of hyperbolic ones is quite as large as should be expected.

  [306] Laplace, *Essai Philosophique*, p. 59. Todhunter’s *History*,
  pp. 491–494.

  [307] Chambers’ *Astronomy*, 1st ed. p. 203.

When we attempt to estimate the numbers of objects which may have
existed, we must make large allowances for the limited sphere of our
observations. Probably not more than 4000 or 5000 comets have been seen
in historical times, but making allowance for the absence of observers
in the southern hemisphere, and for the small probability that we see
any considerable fraction of those which are in the neighbourhood of
our system, we must accept Kepler’s opinion, that there are more comets
in the regions of space than fishes in the depths of the ocean. When
like calculations are made concerning the numbers of meteors visible to
us, it is astonishing to find that the number of meteors entering the
earth’s atmosphere in every twenty-four hours is probably not less than
400,000,000, of which 13,000 exist in every portion of space equal to
that filled by the earth.

Serious fallacies may arise from overlooking the inevitable conditions
under which the records of past events are brought to our notice.
Thus it is only the durable objects manufactured by former races of
men, such as flint implements, which can have come to our notice as a
general rule. The comparative abundance of iron and bronze articles
used by an ancient nation must not be supposed to be coincident with
their comparative abundance in our museums, because bronze is far the
more durable. There is a prevailing fallacy that our ancestors built
more strongly than we do, arising from the fact that the more fragile
structures have long since crumbled away. We have few or no relics of
the habitations of the poorer classes among the Greeks or Romans, or in
fact of any past race; for the temples, tombs, public buildings, and
mansions of the wealthier classes alone endure. There is an immense
expanse of past events necessarily lost to us for ever, and we must
generally look upon records or relics as exceptional in their character.

The same considerations apply to geological relics. We could not
generally expect that animals would be preserved unless as regards the
bones, shells, strong integuments, or other hard and durable parts. All
the infusoria and animals devoid of mineral framework have probably
perished entirely, distilled perhaps into oils. It has been pointed
out that the peculiar character of some extinct floras may be due to
the unequal preservation of different families of plants. By various
accidents, however, we gain glimpses of a world that is usually lost
to us--as by insects embedded in amber, the great mammoth preserved in
ice, mummies, casts in solid material like that of the Roman soldier at
Pompeii, and so forth.

We should also remember, that just as there may be conjunctions of the
heavenly bodies that can have happened only once or twice in the period
of history, so remarkable terrestrial conjunctions may take place.
Great storms, earthquakes, volcanic eruptions, landslips, floods,
irruptions of the sea, may, or rather must, have occurred, events of
such unusual magnitude and such extreme rarity that we can neither
expect to witness them nor readily to comprehend their effects. It is
a great advantage of the study of probabilities, as Laplace himself
remarked, to make us mistrust the extent of our knowledge, and pay
proper regard to the probability that events would come within the
sphere of our observations.


*Apparent Sequence of Events.*

De Morgan has excellently pointed out[308] that there are no less than
four modes in which one event may seem to follow or be connected with
another, without being really so. These involve mental, sensual, and
external causes of error, and I will briefly state and illustrate them.

  [308] *Essay on Probabilities*, Cabinet Cyclopædia, p. 121.

Instead of A causing B, it may be *our perception of A that causes B*.
Thus it is that prophecies, presentiments, and the devices of sorcery
and witchcraft often work their own ends. A man dies on the day which
he has always regarded as his last, from his own fears of the day. An
incantation effects its purpose, because care is taken to frighten the
intended victim, by letting him know his fate. In all such cases the
mental condition is the cause of apparent coincidence.

In a second class of cases, *the event A may make our perception of
B follow, which would otherwise happen without being perceived*.
Thus it was believed to be the result of investigation that more
comets appeared in hot than cold summers. No account was taken of
the fact that hot summers would be comparatively cloudless, and
afford better opportunities for the discovery of comets. Here the
disturbing condition is of a purely external character. Certain ancient
philosophers held that the moon’s rays were cold-producing, mistaking
the cold caused by radiation into space for an effect of the moon,
which is more likely to be visible at a time when the absence of clouds
permits radiation to proceed.

In a third class of cases, *our perception of A may make our perception
of B follow*. The event B may be constantly happening, but our
attention may not be drawn to it except by our observing A. This case
seems to be illustrated by the fallacy of the moon’s influence on
clouds. The origin of this fallacy is somewhat complicated. In the
first place, when the sky is densely clouded the moon would not be
visible at all; it would be necessary for us to see the full moon in
order that our attention should be strongly drawn to the fact, and this
would happen most often on those nights when the sky is cloudless. Mr.
W. Ellis,[309] moreover, has ingeniously pointed out that there is a
general tendency for clouds to disperse at the commencement of night,
which is the time when the full moon rises. Thus the change of the sky
and the rise of the full moon are likely to attract attention mutually,
and the coincidence in time suggests the relation of cause and effect.
Mr. Ellis proves from the results of observations at the Greenwich
Observatory that the moon possesses no appreciable power of the kind
supposed, and yet it is remarkable that so sound an observer as Sir
John Herschel was convinced of the connection. In his “Results of
Observations at the Cape of Good Hope,”[310] he mentions many evenings
when a full moon occurred with a peculiarly clear sky.

  [309] *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series (1867), vol. xxxiv. p. 64.

  [310] See *Notes to Measures of Double Stars*, 1204, 1336, 1477,
  1686, 1786, 1816, 1835, 1929, 2081, 2186, pp. 265, &c. See also
  Herschel’s *Familiar Lectures on Scientific Subjects*, p. 147, and
  *Outlines of Astronomy*, 7th ed. p. 285.

There is yet a fourth class of cases, in which *B is really the
antecedent event, but our perception of A, which is a consequence
of B, may be necessary to bring about our perception of B*. There
can be no doubt, for instance, that upward and downward currents are
continually circulating in the lowest stratum of the atmosphere during
the day-time; but owing to the transparency of the atmosphere we have
no evidence of their existence until we perceive cumulous clouds, which
are the consequence of such currents. In like manner an interfiltration
of bodies of air in the higher parts of the atmosphere is probably in
nearly constant progress, but unless threads of cirrous cloud indicate
these motions we remain ignorant of their occurrence.[311] The highest
strata of the atmosphere are wholly imperceptible to us, except when
rendered luminous by auroral currents of electricity, or by the passage
of meteoric stones. Most of the visible phenomena of comets probably
arise from some substance which, existing previously invisible, becomes
condensed or electrified suddenly into a visible form. Sir John
Herschel attempted to explain the production of comet tails in this
manner by evaporation and condensation.[312]

  [311] Jevons, *On the Cirrous Form of Cloud*, Philosophical Magazine,
  July, 1857, 4th Series, vol. xiv. p. 22.

  [312] *Astronomy*, 4th ed. p. 358.


*Negative Arguments from Non-observation.*

From what has been suggested in preceding sections, it will plainly
appear that the non-observation of a phenomenon is not generally to
be taken as proving its non-occurrence. As there are sounds which we
cannot hear, rays of heat which we cannot feel, multitudes of worlds
which we cannot see, and myriads of minute organisms of which not the
most powerful microscope can give us a view, we must as a general rule
interpret our experience in an affirmative sense only. Accordingly
when inferences have been drawn from the non-occurrence of particular
facts or objects, more extended and careful examination has often
proved their falsity. Not many years since it was quite a well credited
conclusion in geology that no remains of man were found in connection
with those of extinct animals, or in any deposit not actually at
present in course of formation. Even Babbage accepted this conclusion
as strongly confirmatory of the Mosaic accounts.[313] While the opinion
was yet universally held, flint implements had been found disproving
such a conclusion, and overwhelming evidence of man’s long-continued
existence has since been forthcoming. At the end of the last century,
when Herschel had searched the heavens with his powerful telescopes,
there seemed little probability that planets yet remained unseen
within the orbit of Jupiter. But on the first day of this century such
an opinion was overturned by the discovery of Ceres, and more than a
hundred other small planets have since been added to the lists of the
planetary system.

  [313] Babbage, *Ninth Bridgewater Treatise*, p. 67.

The discovery of the Eozoön Canadense in strata of much greater age
than any previously known to contain organic remains, has given a shock
to groundless opinions concerning the origin of organic forms; and
the oceanic dredging expeditions under Dr. Carpenter and Sir Wyville
Thomson have modified some opinions of geologists by disclosing the
continued existence of forms long supposed to be extinct. These and
many other cases which might be quoted show the extremely unsafe
character of negative inductions.

But it must not be supposed that negative arguments are of no force and
value. The earth’s surface has been sufficiently searched to render it
highly improbable that any terrestrial animals of the size of a camel
remain to be discovered. It is believed that no new large animal has
been encountered in the last eighteen or twenty centuries,[314] and
the probability that if existent they would have been seen, increases
the probability that they do not exist. We may with somewhat less
confidence discredit the existence of any large unrecognised fish, or
sea animals, such as the alleged sea-serpent. But, as we descend to
forms of smaller size negative evidence loses weight from the less
probability of our seeing smaller objects. Even the strong induction in
favour of the four-fold division of the animal kingdom into Vertebrata,
Annulosa, Mollusca, and Cœlenterata, may break down by the discovery
of intermediate or anomalous forms. As civilisation spreads over the
surface of the earth, and unexplored tracts are gradually diminished,
negative conclusions will increase in force; but we have much to learn
yet concerning the depths of the ocean, almost wholly unexamined as
they are, and covering three-fourths of the earth’s surface.

  [314] Cuvier, *Essay on the Theory of the Earth*, translation, p. 61,
  &c.

In geology there are many statements to which considerable probability
attaches on account of the large extent of the investigations already
made, as, for instance, that true coal is found only in rocks of a
particular geological epoch; that gold occurs in secondary and tertiary
strata only in exceedingly small quantities,[315] probably derived
from the disintegration of earlier rocks. In natural history negative
conclusions are exceedingly treacherous and unsatisfactory. The utmost
patience will not enable a microscopist or the observer of any living
thing to watch the behaviour of the organism under all circumstances
continuously for a great length of time. There is always a chance
therefore that the critical act or change may take place when the
observer’s eyes are withdrawn. This certainly happens in some cases;
for though the fertilisation of orchids by agency of insects is proved
as well as any fact in natural history, Mr. Darwin has never been
able by the closest watching to detect an insect in the performance
of the operation. Mr. Darwin has himself adopted one conclusion on
negative evidence, namely, that the *Orchis pyramidalis* and certain
other orchidaceous flowers secrete no nectar. But his caution and
unwearying patience in verifying the conclusion give an impressive
lesson to the observer. For twenty-three consecutive days, as he tells
us, he examined flowers in all states of the weather, at all hours, in
various localities. As the secretion in other flowers sometimes takes
place rapidly and might happen at early dawn, that inconvenient hour
of observation was specially adopted. Flowers of different ages were
subjected to irritating vapours, to moisture, and to every condition
likely to bring on the secretion; and only after invariable failure of
this exhaustive inquiry was the barrenness of the nectaries assumed to
be proved.[316]

  [315] Murchison’s *Siluria*, 1st ed. p. 432.

  [316] Darwin’s *Fertilisation of Orchids*, p. 48.

In order that a negative argument founded on the non-observation of
an object shall have any considerable force, it must be shown to be
probable that the object if existent would have been observed, and it
is this probability which defines the value of the negative conclusion.
The failure of astronomers to see the planet Vulcan, supposed by some
to exist within Mercury’s orbit, is no sufficient disproof of its
existence. Similarly it would be very difficult, or even impossible, to
disprove the existence of a second satellite of small size revolving
round the earth. But if any person make a particular assertion,
assigning place and time, then observation will either prove or
disprove the alleged fact. If it is true that when a French observer
professed to have seen a planet on the sun’s face, an observer in
Brazil was carefully scrutinising the sun and failed to see it, we have
a negative proof. False facts in science, it has been well said, are
more mischievous than false theories. A false theory is open to every
person’s criticism, and is ever liable to be judged by its accordance
with facts. But a false or grossly erroneous assertion of a fact
often stands in the way of science for a long time, because it may be
extremely difficult or even impossible to prove the falsity of what has
been once recorded.

In other sciences the force of a negative argument will often depend
upon the number of possible alternatives which may exist. It was long
believed that the quality of a musical sound as distinguished from
its pitch, must depend upon the form of the undulation, because no
other cause of it had ever been suggested or was apparently possible.
The truth of the conclusion was proved by Helmholtz, who applied a
microscope to luminous points attached to the strings of various
instruments, and thus actually observed the different modes of
undulation. In mathematics negative inductive arguments have seldom
much force, because the possible forms of expression, or the possible
combinations of lines and circles in geometry, are quite unlimited in
number. An enormous number of attempts were made to trisect the angle
by the ordinary methods of Euclid’s geometry, but their invariable
failure did not establish the impossibility of the task. This was shown
in a totally different manner, by proving that the problem involves an
irreducible cubic equation to which there could be no corresponding
plane geometrical solution.[317] This is a case of *reductio ad
absurdum*, a form of argument of a totally different character.
Similarly no number of failures to obtain a general solution of
equations of the fifth degree would establish the impossibility of the
task, but in an indirect mode, equivalent to a *reductio ad absurdum*,
the impossibility is considered to be proved.[318]

  [317] Peacock, *Algebre*, vol. ii. p. 344.

  [318] Ibid, p. 359. Serret, *Algèbre Supérieure*, 2nd ed. p. 304.




CHAPTER XIX.

EXPERIMENT.


We may now consider the great advantages which we enjoy in examining
the combinations of phenomena when things are within our reach and
capable of being experimented on. We are said *to experiment* when we
bring substances together under various conditions of temperature,
pressure, electric disturbance, chemical action, &c., and then record
the changes observed. Our object in inductive investigation is to
ascertain exactly the group of circumstances or conditions which being
present, a certain other group of phenomena will follow. If we denote
by A the antecedent group, and by X subsequent phenomena, our object
will usually be to discover a law of the form A = AX, the meaning of
which is that where A is X will happen.

The circumstances which might be enumerated as present in the simplest
experiment are very numerous, in fact almost infinite. Rub two sticks
together and consider what would be an exhaustive statement of the
conditions. There are the form, hardness, organic structure, and all
the chemical qualities of the wood; the pressure and velocity of the
rubbing; the temperature, pressure, and all the chemical qualities of
the surrounding air; the proximity of the earth with its attractive
and electric powers; the temperature and other properties of the
persons producing motion; the radiation from the sun, and to and from
the sky; the electric excitement possibly existing in any overhanging
cloud; even the positions of the heavenly bodies must be mentioned.
On *à priori* grounds it is unsafe to assume that any one of these
circumstances is without effect, and it is only by experience that we
can single out those precise conditions from which the observed heat of
friction proceeds.

The great method of experiment consists in removing, one at a time,
each of those conditions which may be imagined to have an influence
on the result. Our object in the experiment of rubbing sticks is to
discover the exact circumstances under which heat appears. Now the
presence of air may be requisite; therefore prepare a vacuum, and
rub the sticks in every respect as before, except that it is done
*in vacuo*. If heat still appears we may say that air is not, in
the presence of the other circumstances, a requisite condition. The
conduction of heat from neighbouring bodies may be a condition. Prevent
this by making all the surrounding bodies ice cold, which is what Davy
aimed at in rubbing two pieces of ice together. If heat still appears
we have eliminated another condition, and so we may go on until it
becomes apparent that the expenditure of energy in the friction of two
bodies is the sole condition of the production of heat.

The great difficulty of experiment arises from the fact that we must
not assume the conditions to be independent. Previous to experiment we
have no right to say that the rubbing of two sticks will produce heat
in the same way when air is absent as before. We may have heat produced
in one way when air is present, and in another when air is absent.
The inquiry branches out into two lines, and we ought to try in both
cases whether cutting off a supply of heat by conduction prevents its
evolution in friction. The same branching out of the inquiry occurs
with regard to every circumstance which enters into the experiment.

Regarding only four circumstances, say A, B, C, D, we ought to test
not only the combinations ABCD, ABC*d*, AB*c*D, A*b*CD, *a*BCD, but
we ought really to go through the whole of the combinations given in
the fifth column of the Logical Alphabet. The effect of the absence
of each condition should be tried both in the presence and absence of
every other condition, and every selection of those conditions. Perfect
and exhaustive experimentation would, in short, consist in examining
natural phenomena in all their possible combinations and registering
all relations between conditions and results which are found capable
of existence. It would thus resemble the exclusion of contradictory
combinations carried out in the Indirect Method of Inference, except
that the exclusion of combinations is grounded not on prior logical
premises, but on *à posteriori* results of actual trial.

The reader will perceive, however, that such exhaustive investigation
is practically impossible, because the number of requisite experiments
would be immensely great. Four antecedents only would require sixteen
experiments; twelve antecedents would require 4096, and the number
increases as the powers of two. The result is that the experimenter
has to fall back upon his own tact and experience in selecting those
experiments which are most likely to yield him significant facts. It
is at this point that logical rules and forms begin to fail in giving
aid. The logical rule is--Try all possible combinations; but this being
impracticable, the experimentalist necessarily abandons strict logical
method, and trusts to his own insight. Analogy, as we shall see, gives
some assistance, and attention should be concentrated on those kinds
of conditions which have been found important in like cases. But we
are now entirely in the region of probability, and the experimenter,
while he is confidently pursuing what he thinks the right clue, may
be overlooking the one condition of importance. It is an impressive
lesson, for instance, that Newton pursued all his exquisite researches
on the spectrum unsuspicious of the fact that if he reduced the hole in
the shutter to a narrow slit, all the mysteries of the bright and dark
lines were within his grasp, provided of course that his prisms were
sufficiently good to define the rays. In like manner we know not what
slight alteration in the most familiar experiments may not open the way
to realms of new discovery.

Practical difficulties, also, encumber the progress of the physicist.
It is often impossible to alter one condition without altering others
at the same time; and thus we may not get the pure effect of the
condition in question. Some conditions may be absolutely incapable of
alteration; others may be with great difficulty, or only in a certain
degree, removable. A very treacherous source of error is the existence
of unknown conditions, which of course we cannot remove except by
accident. These difficulties we will shortly consider in succession.

It is beautiful to observe how the alteration of a single circumstance
sometimes conclusively explains a phenomenon. An instance is found in
Faraday’s investigation of the behaviour of Lycopodium spores scattered
on a vibrating plate. It was observed that these minute spores
collected together at the points of greatest motion, whereas sand and
all heavy particles collected at the nodes, where the motion was least.
It happily occurred to Faraday to try the experiment in the exhausted
receiver of an air-pump, and it was then found that the light powder
behaved exactly like heavy powder. A conclusive proof was thus obtained
that the presence of air was the condition of importance, doubtless
because it was thrown into eddies by the motion of the plate, and
carried the Lycopodium to the points of greatest agitation. Sand was
too heavy to be carried by the air.


*Exclusion of Indifferent Circumstances.*

From what has been already said it will be apparent that the detection
and exclusion of indifferent circumstances is a work of importance,
because it allows the concentration of attention upon circumstances
which contain the principal condition. Many beautiful instances may be
given where all the most obvious antecedents have been shown to have no
part in the production of a phenomenon. A person might suppose that the
peculiar colours of mother-of-pearl were due to the chemical qualities
of the substance. Much trouble might have been spent in following out
that notion by comparing the chemical qualities of various iridescent
substances. But Brewster accidentally took an impression from a piece
of mother-of-pearl in a cement of resin and bees’-wax, and finding
the colours repeated upon the surface of the wax, he proceeded to
take other impressions in balsam, fusible metal, lead, gum arabic,
isinglass, &c., and always found the iridescent colours the same. He
thus proved that the chemical nature of the substance is a matter of
indifference, and that the form of the surface is the real condition
of such colours.[319] Nearly the same may be said of the colours
exhibited by thin plates and films. The rings and lines of colour will
be nearly the same in character whatever may be the nature of the
substance; nay, a void space, such as a crack in glass, would produce
them even though the air were withdrawn by an air-pump. The conditions
are simply the existence of two reflecting surfaces separated by a very
small space, though it should be added that the refractive index of the
intervening substance has some influence on the exact nature of the
colour produced.

  [319] *Treatise on Optics*, by Brewster, Cab. Cyclo. p. 117.

When a ray of light passes close to the edge of an opaque body, a
portion of the light appears to be bent towards it, and produces
coloured fringes within the shadow of the body. Newton attributed
this inflexion of light to the attraction of the opaque body for the
supposed particles of light, although he was aware that the nature
of the surrounding medium, whether air or other pellucid substance,
exercised no apparent influence on the phenomena. Gravesande proved,
however, that the character of the fringes is exactly the same, whether
the body be dense or rare, compound or elementary. A wire produces
exactly the same fringes as a hair of the same thickness. Even the
form of the obstructing edge was subsequently shown to be a matter of
indifference by Fresnel, and the interference spectrum, or the spectrum
seen when light passes through a fine grating, is absolutely the same
whatever be the form or chemical nature of the bars making the grating.
Thus it appears that the stoppage of a portion of a beam of light is
the sole necessary condition for the diffraction or inflexion of light,
and the phenomenon is shown to bear no analogy the refraction of light,
in which the form and nature of the substance are all important.

It is interesting to observe how carefully Newton, in his researches
on the spectrum, ascertained the indifference of many circumstances by
actual trial. He says:[320] “Now the different magnitude of the hole
in the window-shut, and different thickness of the prism where the
rays passed through it, and different inclinations of the prism to the
horizon, made no sensible changes in the length of the image. Neither
did the different matter of the prisms make any: for in a vessel made
of polished plates of glass cemented together in the shape of a prism,
and filled with water, there is the like success of the experiment
according to the quantity of the refraction.” But in the latter
statement, as I shall afterwards remark (p. 432), Newton assumed an
indifference which does not exist, and fell into an unfortunate mistake.

  [320] *Opticks*, 3rd. ed. p. 25.

In the science of sound it is shown that the pitch of a sound depends
solely upon the number of impulses in a second, and the material
exciting those impulses is a matter of indifference. Whatever fluid,
air or water, gas or liquid, be forced into the Siren, the sound
produced is the same; and the material of which an organ-pipe is
constructed does not at all affect the pitch of its sound. In the
science of statical electricity it is an important principle that
the nature of the interior of a conducting body is a matter of no
importance. The electrical charge is confined to the conducting
surface, and the interior remains in a neutral state. A hollow copper
sphere takes exactly the same charge as a solid sphere of the same
metal.

Some of Faraday’s most elegant and successful researches were devoted
to the exclusion of conditions which previous experimenters had
thought essential for the production of electrical phenomena. Davy
asserted that no known fluids, except such as contain water, could be
made the medium of connexion between the poles of a battery; and some
chemists believed that water was an essential agent in electro-chemical
decomposition. Faraday gave abundant experiments to show that other
fluids allowed of electrolysis, and he attributed the erroneous opinion
to the very general use of water as a solvent, and its presence in most
natural bodies.[321] It was, in fact, upon the weakest kind of negative
evidence that the opinion had been founded.

Many experimenters attributed peculiar powers to the poles of a
battery, likening them to magnets, which, by their attractive powers,
tear apart the elements of a substance. By a beautiful series of
experiments,[322] Faraday proved conclusively that, on the contrary,
the substance of the poles is of no importance, being merely the path
through which the electric force reaches the liquid acted upon. Poles
of water, charcoal, and many diverse substances, even air itself,
produced similar results; if the chemical nature of the pole entered at
all into the question, it was as a disturbing agent.

  [321] *Experimental Researches in Electricity*, vol. i. pp. 133, 134.

  [322] Ibid. vol i. pp. 127, 162, &c.

It is an essential part of the theory of gravitation that the proximity
of other attracting particles is without effect upon the attraction
existing between any two molecules. Two pound weights weigh as much
together as they do separately. Every pair of molecules in the world
have, as it were, a private communication, apart from their relations
to all other molecules. Another undoubted result of experience pointed
out by Newton[323] is that the weight of a body does not in the least
depend upon its form or texture. It may be added that the temperature,
electric condition, pressure, state of motion, chemical qualities,
and all other circumstances concerning matter, except its mass, are
indifferent as regards its gravitating power.

  [323] *Principia*, bk. iii. Prop. vi. Corollary i.

As natural science progresses, physicists gain a kind of insight
and tact in judging what qualities of a substance are likely to be
concerned in any class of phenomena. The physical astronomer treats
matter in one point of view, the chemist in another, and the students
of physical optics, sound, mechanics, electricity, &c., make a fair
division of the qualities among them. But errors will arise if too
much confidence be placed in this independence of various kinds of
phenomena, so that it is desirable from time to time, especially
when any unexplained discrepancies come into notice, to question the
indifference which is assumed to exist, and to test its real existence
by appropriate experiments.


*Simplification of Experiments.*

One of the most requisite precautions in experimentation is to
vary only one circumstance at a time, and to maintain all other
circumstances rigidly unchanged. There are two distinct reasons for
this rule, the first and most obvious being that if we vary two
conditions at a time, and find some effect, we cannot tell whether
the effect is due to one or the other condition, or to both jointly.
A second reason is that if no effect ensues we cannot safely conclude
that either of them is indifferent; for the one may have neutralised
the effect of the other. In our symbolic logic AB ꖌ A*b* was shown to
be identical with A (p. 97), so that B denotes a circumstance which is
indifferently present or absent. But if B always goes together with
another antecedent C, we cannot show the same independence, for ABC ꖌ
A*bc* is not identical with A and none of our logical processes enables
us to reduce it to A.

If we want to prove that oxygen is necessary to life, we must not
put a rabbit into a vessel from which the oxygen has been exhausted
by a burning candle. We should then have not only an absence of
oxygen, but an addition of carbonic acid, which may have been the
destructive agent. For a similar reason Lavoisier avoided the use of
atmospheric air in experiments on combustion, because air was not a
simple substance, and the presence of nitrogen might impede or even
alter the effect of oxygen. As Lavoisier remarks,[324] “In performing
experiments, it is a necessary principle, which ought never to be
deviated from, that they be simplified as much as possible, and that
every circumstance capable of rendering their results complicated be
carefully removed.” It has also been well said by Cuvier[325] that
the method of physical inquiry consists in isolating bodies, reducing
them to their utmost simplicity, and bringing each of their properties
separately into action, either mentally or by experiment.

  [324] Lavoisier’s *Chemistry*, translated by Kerr, p. 103.

  [325] Cuvier’s *Animal Kingdom*, introduction, pp. 1, 2.

The electro-magnet has been of the utmost service in the investigation
of the magnetic properties of matter, by allowing of the production
or removal of a most powerful magnetic force without disturbing any
of the other arrangements of the experiment. Many of Faraday’s most
valuable experiments would have been impossible had it been necessary
to introduce a heavy permanent magnet, which could not be suddenly
moved without shaking the whole apparatus, disturbing the air,
producing currents by changes of temperature, &c. The electro-magnet
is perfectly under control, and its influence can be brought into
action, reversed, or stopped by merely touching a button. Thus Faraday
was enabled to prove the rotation of the plane of circularly polarised
light by the fact that certain light ceased to be visible when the
electric current of the magnet was cut off, and re-appeared when the
current was made. “These phenomena,” he says, “could be reversed at
pleasure, and at any instant of time, and upon any occasion, showing a
perfect dependence of cause and effect.”[326]

  [326] *Experimental Researches in Electricity*, vol. iii. p. 4.

It was Newton’s omission to obtain the solar spectrum under the
simplest conditions which prevented him from discovering the dark
lines. Using a broad beam of light which had passed through a round
hole or a triangular slit, he obtained a brilliant spectrum, but one
in which many different coloured rays overlapped each other. In the
recent history of the science of the spectrum, one main difficulty has
consisted in the mixture of the lines of several different substances,
which are usually to be found in the light of any flame or spark. It
is seldom possible to obtain the light of any element in a perfectly
simple manner. Angström greatly advanced this branch of science by
examining the light of the electric spark when formed between poles of
various metals, and in the presence of various gases. By varying the
pole alone, or the gaseous medium alone, he was able to discriminate
correctly between the lines due to the metal and those due to the
surrounding gas.[327]

  [327] *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. ix. p. 327.


*Failure in the Simplification of Experiments.*

In some cases it seems to be impossible to carry out the rule of
varying one circumstance at a time. When we attempt to obtain two
instances or two forms of experiment in which a single circumstance
shall be present in one case and absent in another, it may be found
that this single circumstance entails others. Benjamin Franklin’s
experiment concerning the comparative absorbing powers of different
colours is well known. “I took,” he says, “a number of little square
pieces of broadcloth from a tailor’s pattern card, of various colours.
They were black, deep blue, lighter blue, green, purple, red, yellow,
white, and other colours and shades of colour. I laid them all out upon
the snow on a bright sunshiny morning. In a few hours the black, being
most warmed by the sun, was sunk so low as to be below the stroke of
the sun’s rays; the dark blue was almost as low; the lighter blue not
quite so much as the dark; the other colours less as they were lighter.
The white remained on the surface of the snow, not having entered it at
all.” This is a very elegant and apparently simple experiment; but when
Leslie had completed his series of researches upon the nature of heat,
he came to the conclusion that the colour of a surface has very little
effect upon the radiating power, the mechanical nature of the surface
appearing to be more influential. He remarks[328] that “the question
is incapable of being positively resolved, since no substance can be
made to assume different colours without at the same time changing its
internal structure.” Recent investigation has shown that the subject
is one of considerable complication, because the absorptive power of a
surface may be different according to the character of the rays which
fall upon it; but there can be no doubt as to the acuteness with which
Leslie points out the difficulty. In Well’s investigations concerning
the nature of dew, we have, again, very complicated conditions. If we
expose plates of various material, such as rough iron, glass, polished
metal, to the midnight sky, they will be dewed in various degrees; but
since these plates differ both in the nature of the surface and the
conducting power of the material, it would not be plain whether one
or both circumstances were of importance. We avoid this difficulty by
exposing the same material polished or varnished, so as to present
different conditions of surface;[329] and again by exposing different
substances with the same kind of surface.

  [328] *Inquiry into the Nature of Heat*, p. 95.

  [329] Herschel, *Preliminary Discourse*, p. 161.

When we are quite unable to isolate circumstances we must resort to
the procedure described by Mill under the name of the Joint Method
of Agreement and Difference. We must collect as many instances as
possible in which a given circumstance produces a given result, and
as many as possible in which the absence of the circumstance is
followed by the absence of the result. To adduce his example, we
cannot experiment upon the cause of double refraction in Iceland spar,
because we cannot alter its crystalline condition without altering
it altogether, nor can we find substances exactly like calc spar in
every circumstance except one. We resort therefore to the method
of comparing together all known substances which have the property
of doubly-refracting light, and we find that they agree in being
crystalline.[330] This indeed is nothing but an ordinary process of
perfect or probable induction, already partially described, and to
be further discussed under Classification. It may be added that the
subject does admit of perfect experimental treatment, since glass,
when compressed in one direction, becomes capable of doubly-refracting
light, and as there is probably no alteration in the glass but change
of elasticity, we learn that the power of double refraction is probably
due to a difference of elasticity in different directions.

  [330] *System of Logic*, bk. iii. chap. viii. § 4, 5th ed. vol. i.
  p. 433.


*Removal of Usual Conditions.*

One of the great objects of experiment is to enable us to judge
of the behaviour of substances under conditions widely different
from those which prevail upon the surface of the earth. We live in
an atmosphere which does not vary beyond certain narrow limits in
temperature or pressure. Many of the powers of nature, such as gravity,
which constantly act upon us, are of almost fixed amount. Now it
will afterwards be shown that we cannot apply a quantitative law to
circumstances much differing from those in which it was observed. In
the other planets, the sun, the stars, or remote parts of the Universe,
the conditions of existence must often be widely different from what
we commonly experience here. Hence our knowledge of nature must remain
restricted and hypothetical, unless we can subject substances to
unusual conditions by suitable experiments.

The electric arc is an invaluable means of exposing metals or other
conducting substances to the highest known temperature. By its aid we
learn not only that all the metals can be vaporised, but that they
all give off distinctive rays of light. At the other extremity of the
scale, the intensely powerful freezing mixture devised by Faraday,
consisting of solid carbonic acid and ether mixed *in vacuo*, enables
us to observe the nature of substances at temperatures immensely below
any we meet with naturally on the earth’s surface.

We can hardly realise now the importance of the invention of the
air-pump, previous to which invention it was exceedingly difficult
to experiment except under the ordinary pressure of the atmosphere.
The Torricellian vacuum had been employed by the philosophers of the
Accademia del Cimento to show the behaviour of water, smoke, sound,
magnets, electric substances, &c., *in vacuo*, but their experiments
were often unsuccessful from the difficulty of excluding air.[331]

  [331] *Essayes of Natural Experiments made in the Accademia del
  Cimento.* Englished by Richard Waller, 1684, p. 40, &c.

Among the most constant circumstances under which we live is the force
of gravity, which does not vary, except by a slight fraction of its
amount, in any part of the earth’s crust or atmosphere to which we
can attain. This force is sufficient to overbear and disguise various
actions, for instance, the mutual gravitation of small bodies. It
was an interesting experiment of Plateau to neutralise the action of
gravity by placing substances in liquids of exactly the same specific
gravity. Thus a quantity of oil poured into the middle of a suitable
mixture of alcohol and water assumes a spherical shape; on being made
to rotate it becomes spheroidal, and then successively separates into a
ring and a group of spherules. Thus we have an illustration of the mode
in which the planetary system may have been produced,[332] though the
extreme difference of scale prevents our arguing with confidence from
the experiment to the conditions of the nebular theory.

  [332] Plateau, *Taylor’s Scientific Memoirs*, vol. iv. pp. 16–43.

It is possible that the so-called elements are elementary only to us,
because we are restricted to temperatures at which they are fixed.
Lavoisier carefully defined an element as a substance which cannot be
decomposed *by any known means*; but it seems almost certain that some
series of elements, for instance Iodine, Bromine, and Chlorine, are
really compounds of a simpler substance. We must look to the production
of intensely high temperatures, yet quite beyond our means, for the
decomposition of these so-called elements. Possibly in this age and
part of the universe the dissipation of energy has so far proceeded
that there are no sources of heat sufficiently intense to effect the
decomposition.


*Interference of Unsuspected Conditions.*

It may happen that we are not aware of all the conditions under which
our researches are made. Some substance may be present or some power
may be in action, which escapes the most vigilant examination. Not
being aware of its existence, we are unable to take proper measures
to exclude it, and thus determine the share which it has in the
results of our experiments. There can be no doubt that the alchemists
were misled and encouraged in their vain attempts by the unsuspected
presence of traces of gold and silver in the substances they proposed
to transmute. Lead, as drawn from the smelting furnace, almost always
contains some silver, and gold is associated with many other metals.
Thus small quantities of noble metal would often appear as the result
of experiment and raise delusive hopes.

In more than one case the unsuspected presence of common salt in the
air has caused great trouble. In the early experiments on electrolysis
it was found that when water was decomposed, an acid and an alkali
were produced at the poles, together with oxygen and hydrogen. In
the absence of any other explanation, some chemists rushed to the
conclusion that electricity must have the power of *generating*
acids and alkalies, and one chemist thought he had discovered a new
substance called *electric acid*. But Davy proceeded to a systematic
investigation of the circumstances, by varying the conditions. Changing
the glass vessel for one of agate or gold, he found that far less
alkali was produced; excluding impurities by the use of carefully
distilled water, he found that the quantities of acid and alkali were
still further diminished; and having thus obtained a clue to the cause,
he completed the exclusion of impurities by avoiding contact with his
fingers, and by placing the apparatus under an exhausted receiver,
no acid or alkali being then detected. It would be difficult to meet
with a more elegant case of the detection of a condition previously
unsuspected.[333]

  [333] *Philosophical Transactions* [1826], vol. cxvi. pp. 388, 389.
  Works of Sir Humphry Davy, vol. v. pp. 1–12.

It is remarkable that the presence of common salt in the air, proved
to exist by Davy, nevertheless continued a stumbling-block in the
science of spectrum analysis, and probably prevented men, such as
Brewster, Herschel, and Talbot, from anticipating by thirty years
the discoveries of Bunsen and Kirchhoff. As I pointed out,[334] the
utility of the spectrum was known in the middle of the last century
to Thomas Melvill, a talented Scotch physicist, who died at the early
age of 27 years.[335] But Melvill was struck in his examination of
coloured flames by the extraordinary predominance of homogeneous yellow
light, which was due to some circumstance escaping his attention.
Wollaston and Fraunhofer were equally struck by the prominence of the
yellow line in the spectrum of nearly every kind of light. Talbot
expressly recommended the use of the prism for detecting the presence
of substances by what we now call spectrum analysis, but he found that
all substances, however different the light they yielded in other
respects, were identical as regards the production of yellow light.
Talbot knew that the salts of soda gave this coloured light, but in
spite of Davy’s previous difficulties with salt in electrolysis, it
did not occur to him to assert that where the light is, there sodium
must be. He suggested water as the most likely source of the yellow
light, because of its frequent presence; but even substances which were
apparently devoid of water gave the same yellow light.[336] Brewster
and Herschel both experimented upon flames almost at the same time as
Talbot, and Herschel unequivocally enounced the principle of spectrum
analysis.[337] Nevertheless Brewster, after numerous experiments
attended with great trouble and disappointment, found that yellow light
might be obtained from the combustion of almost any substance. It
was not until 1856 that Swan discovered that an almost infinitesimal
quantity of sodium chloride, say a millionth part of a grain, was
sufficient to tinge a flame of a bright yellow colour. The universal
diffusion of the salts of sodium, joined to this unique light-producing
power, was thus shown to be the unsuspected condition which had
destroyed the confidence of all previous experimenters in the use of
the prism. Some references concerning the history of this curious point
are given below.[338]

  [334] *National Review*, July, 1861, p. 13.

  [335] His published works are contained in *The Edinburgh Physical
  and Literary Essays*, vol. ii. p. 34; *Philosophical Transactions*
  [1753], vol. xlviii. p. 261; see also Morgan’s Papers in
  *Philosophical Transactions* [1785], vol. lxxv. p. 190.

  [336] *Edinburgh Journal of Science*, vol. v. p. 79.

  [337] *Encyclopædia Metropolitana*, art. *Light*, § 524; Herschel’s
  *Familiar Lectures*, p. 266.

  [338] Talbot, *Philosophical Magazine*, 3rd Series, vol. ix. p. 1
  (1836); Brewster, *Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh*
  [1823], vol. ix. pp. 433, 455; Swan, ibid. [1856] vol. xxi. p. 411;
  *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. xx. p. 173 [Sept. 1860];
  Roscoe, *Spectrum Analysis*, Lecture III.

In the science of radiant heat, early inquirers were led to the
conclusion that radiation proceeded only from the surface of a solid,
or from a very small depth below it. But they happened to experiment
upon surfaces covered by coats of varnish, which is highly athermanous
or opaque to heat. Had they properly varied the character of the
surface, using a highly diathermanous substance like rock salt, they
would have obtained very different results.[339]

One of the most extraordinary instances of an erroneous opinion due
to overlooking interfering agents is that concerning the increase of
rainfall near to the earth’s surface. More than a century ago it was
observed that rain-gauges placed upon church steeples, house tops, and
other elevated places, gave considerably less rain than if they were
on the ground, and it has been recently shown that the variation is
most rapid in the close neighbourhood of the ground.[340] All kinds
of theories have been started to explain this phenomenon; but I have
shown[341] that it is simply due to the interference of wind, which
deflects more or less rain from all the gauges which are exposed to it.

  [339] Balfour Stewart, *Elementary Treatise on Heat*, p. 192.

  [340] British Association, Liverpool, 1870. *Report on Rainfall*,
  p. 176.

  [341] *Philosophical Magazine.*, Dec. 1861. 4th Series, vol. xxii.
  p. 421.

The great magnetic power of iron renders it a source of disturbance in
magnetic experiments. In building a magnetic observatory great care
must therefore be taken that no iron is employed in the construction,
and that no masses of iron are near at hand. In some cases magnetic
observations have been seriously disturbed by the existence of masses
of iron ore in the neighbourhood. In Faraday’s experiments upon feebly
magnetic or diamagnetic substances he took the greatest precautions
against the presence of disturbing substances in the copper wire, wax,
paper, and other articles used in suspending the test objects. It was
his custom to try the effect of the magnet upon the apparatus in the
absence of the object of experiment, and without this preliminary trial
no confidence could be placed in the results.[342] Tyndall has also
employed the same mode for testing the freedom of electro-magnetic
coils from iron, and was thus enabled to obtain them devoid of any
cause of disturbance.[343] It is worthy of notice that in the very
infancy of the science of magnetism, the acute experimentalist Gilbert
correctly accounted for the opinion existing in his day that magnets
would attract silver, by pointing out that the silver contained iron.

  [342] *Experimental Researches in Electricity*, vol. iii. p. 84, &c.

  [343] *Lectures on Heat*, p. 21.

Even when we are not aware by previous experience of the probable
presence of a special disturbing agent, we ought not to assume the
absence of unsuspected interference. If an experiment is of really
high importance, so that any considerable branch of science rests
upon it, we ought to try it again and again, in as varied conditions
as possible. We should intentionally disturb the apparatus in various
ways, so as if possible to hit by accident upon any weak point.
Especially when our results are more regular than we have fair grounds
for anticipating, ought we to suspect some peculiarity in the apparatus
which causes it to measure some other phenomenon than that in question,
just as Foucault’s pendulum almost always indicates the movement of the
axes of its own elliptic path instead of the rotation of the globe.

It was in this cautious spirit that Baily acted in his experiments on
the density of the earth. The accuracy of his results depended upon the
elimination of all disturbing influences, so that the oscillation of
his torsion balance should measure gravity alone. Hence he varied the
apparatus in many ways, changing the small balls subject to attraction,
changing the connecting rod, and the means of suspension. He observed
the effect of disturbances, such as the presence of visitors, the
occurrence of violent storms, &c., and as no real alteration was
produced in the results, he confidently attributed them to gravity.[344]

  [344] Baily, *Memoirs of the Royal Astronomical Society*, vol. xiv.
  pp. 29, 30.

Newton would probably have discovered the mode of constructing
achromatic lenses, but for the unsuspected effect of some sugar of
lead which he is supposed to have dissolved in the water of a prism.
He tried, by means of a glass prism combined with a water prism, to
produce dispersion of light without refraction, and if he had succeeded
there would have been an obvious mode of producing refraction without
dispersion. His failure is attributed to his adding lead acetate to
the water for the purpose of increasing its refractive power, the lead
having a high dispersive power which frustrated his purpose.[345]
Judging from Newton’s remarks, in the *Philosophical Transactions*,
it would appear as if he had not, without many unsuccessful trials,
despaired of the construction of achromatic glasses.[346]

  [345] Grant, *History of Physical Astronomy*, p. 531.

  [346] *Philosophical Transactions*, abridged by Lowthorp, 4th
  edition, vol. i. p. 202.

The Academicians of Cimento, in their early and ingenious experiments
upon the vacuum, were often misled by the mechanical imperfections
of their apparatus. They concluded that the air had nothing to do
with the production of sounds, evidently because their vacuum was not
sufficiently perfect. Otto von Guericke fell into a like mistake in the
use of his newly-constructed air-pump, doubtless from the unsuspected
presence of air sufficiently dense to convey the sound of the bell.

It is hardly requisite to point out that the doctrine of spontaneous
generation is due to the unsuspected presence of germs, even after the
most careful efforts to exclude them, and in the case of many diseases,
both of animals and plants, germs which we have no means as yet of
detecting are doubtless the active cause. It has long been a subject
of dispute, again, whether the plants which spring from newly turned
land grow from seeds long buried in that land, or from seeds brought
by the wind. Argument is unphilosophical when direct trial can readily
be applied; for by turning up some old ground, and covering a portion
of it with a glass case, the conveyance of seeds by the wind can be
entirely prevented, and if the same plants appear within and without
the case, it will become clear that the seeds are in the earth. By
gross oversight some experimenters have thought before now that crops
of rye had sprung up where oats had been sown.


*Blind or Test Experiments.*

Every conclusive experiment necessarily consists in the comparison of
results between two different combinations of circumstances. To give a
fair probability that A is the cause of X, we must maintain invariable
all surrounding objects and conditions, and we must then show that
where A is X is, and where A is not X is not. This cannot really be
accomplished in a single trial. If, for instance, a chemist places
a certain suspected substance in Marsh’s test apparatus, and finds
that it gives a small deposit of metallic arsenic, he cannot be sure
that the arsenic really proceeds from the suspected substance; the
impurity of the zinc or sulphuric acid may have been the cause of its
appearance. It is therefore the practice of chemists to make what they
call a *blind experiment*, that is to try whether arsenic appears in
the absence of the suspected substance. The same precaution ought to be
taken in all important analytical operations. Indeed, it is not merely
a precaution, it is an essential part of any experiment. If the blind
trial be not made, the chemist merely assumes that he knows what would
happen. Whenever we assert that because A and X are found together A
is the cause of X, we assume that if A were absent X would be absent.
But wherever it is possible, we ought not to take this as a mere
assumption, or even as a matter of inference. Experience is ultimately
the basis of all our inferences, but if we can bring immediate
experience to bear upon the point in question we should not trust to
anything more remote and liable to error. When Faraday examined the
magnetic properties of the bearing apparatus, in the absence of the
substance to be experimented on, he really made a blind experiment
(p. 431).

We ought, also, to test the accuracy of a method of experiment whenever
we can, by introducing known amounts of the substance or force to be
detected. A new analytical process for the quantitative estimation of
an element should be tested by performing it upon a mixture compounded
so as to contain a known quantity of that element. The accuracy of the
gold assay process greatly depends upon the precaution of assaying
alloys of gold of exactly known composition.[347] Gabriel Plattes’
works give evidence of much scientific spirit, and when discussing the
supposed merits of the divining rod for the discovery of subterranean
treasure, he sensibly suggests that the rod should be tried in places
where veins of metal are known to exist.[348]

  [347] Jevons in Watts’ *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. ii. pp. 936,
  937.

  [348] *Discovery of Subterraneal Treasure.* London, 1639, p. 48.


*Negative Results of Experiment.*

When we pay proper regard to the imperfection of all measuring
instruments and the possible minuteness of effects, we shall see
much reason for interpreting with caution the negative results of
experiments. We may fail to discover the existence of an expected
effect, not because that effect is really non-existent, but because it
is of a magnitude inappreciable to our senses, or confounded with other
effects of much greater amount. As there is no limit on *à priori*
grounds to the smallness of a phenomenon, we can never, by a single
experiment, prove the non-existence of a supposed effect. We are always
at liberty to assume that a certain amount of effect might have been
detected by greater delicacy of measurement. We cannot safely affirm
that the moon has no atmosphere at all. We may doubtless show that the
atmosphere, if present, is less dense than the air in the so-called
vacuum of an air-pump, as did Du Sejour. It is equally impossible to
prove that gravity occupies *no time* in transmission. Laplace indeed
ascertained that the velocity of propagation of the influence was at
least fifty million times greater than that of light;[349] but it does
not really follow that it is instantaneous; and were there any means
of detecting the action of one star upon another exceedingly distant
star, we might possibly find an appreciable interval occupied in the
transmission of the gravitating impulse. Newton could not demonstrate
the absence of all resistance to matter moving through empty space; but
he ascertained by an experiment with the pendulum (p. 443), that if
such resistance existed, it was in amount less than one five-thousandth
part of the external resistance of the air.[350]

  [349] Laplace, *System of the World*, translated by Harte, vol. ii.
  p. 322.

  [350] *Principia*, bk. ii. sect. 6, Prop. xxxi. Motte’s translation,
  vol. ii. p. 108.

A curious instance of false negative inference is furnished by
experiments on light. Euler rejected the corpuscular theory on the
ground that particles of matter moving with the immense velocity of
light would possess momentum, of which there was no evidence. Bennet
had attempted to detect the momentum of light by concentrating the rays
of the sun upon a delicately balanced body. Observing no result, it
was considered to be proved that light had no momentum. Mr. Crookes,
however, having suspended thin vanes, blacked on one side, in a nearly
vacuous globe, found that they move under the influence of light. It
is now allowed that this effect can be explained in accordance with
the undulatory theory of light, and the molecular theory of gases. It
comes to this--that Bennet failed to detect an effect which he might
have detected with a better method of experimenting; but if he had
found it, the phenomenon would have confirmed, not the corpuscular
theory of light, as was expected, but the rival undulatory theory. The
conclusion drawn from Bennet’s experiment was falsely drawn, but it was
nevertheless true in matter.

Many incidents in the history of science tend to show that phenomena,
which one generation has failed to discover, may become accurately
known to a succeeding generation. The compressibility of water which
the Academicians of Florence could not detect, because at a low
pressure the effect was too small to perceive, and at a high pressure
the water oozed through their silver vessel,[351] has now become the
subject of exact measurement and precise calculation. Independently of
Newton, Hooke entertained very remarkable notions concerning the nature
of gravitation. In this and other subjects he showed, indeed, a genius
for experimental investigation which would have placed him in the first
rank in any other age than that of Newton. He correctly conceived that
the force of gravity would decrease as we recede from the centre of
the earth, and he boldly attempted to prove it by experiment. Having
exactly counterpoised two weights in the scales of a balance, or rather
one weight against another weight and a long piece of fine cord, he
removed his balance to the top of the dome of St. Paul’s, and tried
whether the balance remained in equilibrium after one weight was
allowed to hang down to a depth of 240 feet. No difference could be
perceived when the weights were at the same and at different levels,
but Hooke rightly held that the failure arose from the insufficient
elevation. He says, “Yet I am apt to think some difference might be
discovered in greater heights.”[352] The radius of the earth being
about 20,922,000 feet, we can now readily calculate from the law of
gravity that a height of 240 would not make a greater difference than
one part in 40,000 of the weight. Such a difference would doubtless
be inappreciable in the balances of that day, though it could readily
be detected by balances now frequently constructed. Again, the
mutual gravitation of bodies at the earth’s surface is so small that
Newton appears to have made no attempt to demonstrate its existence
experimentally, merely remarking that it was too small to fall under
the observation of our senses.[353] It has since been successfully
detected and measured by Cavendish, Baily, and others.

  [351] *Essayes of Natural Experiments*, &c. p. 117.

  [352] Hooke’s *Posthumous Works*, p. 182.

  [353] *Principia*, bk. iii. Prop. vii. Corollary 1.

The smallness of the quantities which we can sometimes observe is
astonishing. A balance will weigh to one millionth part of the load.
Whitworth can measure to the millionth part of an inch. A rise of
temperature of the 8800th part of a degree centigrade has been
detected by Dr. Joule. The spectroscope has revealed the presence of
the 10,000,000th part of a gram. It is said that the eye can observe
the colour produced in a drop of water by the 50,000,000th part of a
gram of fuschine, and about the same quantity of cyanine. By the sense
of smell we can probably feel still smaller quantities of odorous
matter.[354] We must nevertheless remember that quantitative effects of
far less amount than these must exist, and we should state our negative
results with corresponding caution. We can only disprove the existence
of a quantitative phenomenon by showing deductively from the laws of
nature, that if present it would amount to a perceptible quantity. As
in the case of other negative arguments (p. 414), we must demonstrate
that the effect would appear, where it is by experiment found not to
appear.

  [354] Keill’s *Introduction to Natural Philosophy*, 3rd ed., London,
  1733, pp. 48–54.


*Limits of Experiment.*

It will be obvious that there are many operations of nature which we
are quite incapable of imitating in our experiments. Our object is to
study the conditions under which a certain effect is produced; but
one of those conditions may involve a great length of time. There
are instances on record of experiments extending over five or ten
years, and even over a large part of a lifetime; but such intervals
of time are almost nothing to the time during which nature may have
been at work. The contents of a mineral vein in Cornwall may have been
undergoing gradual change for a hundred million years. All metamorphic
rocks have doubtless endured high temperature and enormous, pressure
for inconceivable periods of time, so that chemical geology is
generally beyond the scope of experiment.

Arguments have been brought against Darwin’s theory, founded upon the
absence of any clear instance of the production of a new species.
During an historical interval of perhaps four thousand years, no
animal, it is said, has been so much domesticated as to become
different in species. It might as well be argued that no geological
changes are taking place, because no new mountain has risen in Great
Britain within the memory of man. Our actual experience of geological
changes is like a point in the infinite progression of time. When we
know that rain water falling on limestone will carry away a minute
portion of the rock in solution, we do not hesitate to multiply that
quantity by millions, and infer that in course of time a mountain may
be dissolved away. We have actual experience concerning the rise of
land in some parts of the globe and its fall in others to the extent
of some feet. Do we hesitate to infer what may thus be done in course
of geological ages? As Gabriel Plattes long ago remarked, “The sea
never resting, but perpetually winning land in one place and losing in
another, doth show what may be done in length of time by a continual
operation, not subject unto ceasing or intermission.”[355] The action
of physical circumstances upon the forms and characters of animals by
natural selection is subject to exactly the same remarks. As regards
animals living in a state of nature, the change of circumstances which
can be ascertained to have occurred is so slight, that we could not
expect to observe any change in those animals whatever. Nature has made
no experiment at all for us within historical times. Man, however, by
taming and domesticating dogs, horses, oxen, pigeons, &c., has made
considerable change in their circumstances, and we find considerable
change also in their forms and characters. Supposing the state of
domestication to continue unchanged, these new forms would continue
permanent so far as we know, and in this sense they are permanent. Thus
the arguments against Darwin’s theory, founded on the non-observation
of natural changes within the historical period, are of the weakest
character, being purely negative.

  [355] *Discovery of Subterraneal Treasure*, 1639, p. 52.




CHAPTER XX.

METHOD OF VARIATIONS.


Experiments may be of two kinds, experiments of simple fact, and
experiments of quantity. In the first class of experiments we combine
certain conditions, and wish to ascertain whether or not a certain
effect of any quantity exists. Hooke wished to ascertain whether or not
there was any difference in the force of gravity at the top and bottom
of St. Paul’s Cathedral. The chemist continually performs analyses for
the purpose of ascertaining whether or not a given element exists in a
particular mineral or mixture; all such experiments and analyses are
qualitative rather than quantitative, because though the result may be
more or less, the particular amount of the result is not the object of
the inquiry.

So soon, however, as a result is known to be discoverable, the
scientific man ought to proceed to the quantitative inquiry, how great
a result follows from a certain amount of the conditions which are
supposed to constitute the cause? The possible numbers of experiments
are now infinitely great, for every variation in a quantitative
condition will usually produce a variation in the amount of the effect.
The method of variation which thus arises is no narrow or special
method, but it is the general application of experiment to phenomena
capable of continuous variation. As Mr. Fowler has well remarked,[356]
the observation of variations is really an integration of a supposed
infinite number of applications of the so-called method of difference,
that is of experiment in its perfect form.

  [356] *Elements of Inductive Logic*, 1st edit. p. 175.

In induction we aim at establishing a general law, and if we deal
with quantities that law must really be expressed more or less
obviously in the form of an equation, or equations. We treat as
before of conditions, and of what happens under those conditions. But
the conditions will now vary, not in quality, but quantity, and the
effect will also vary in quantity, so that the result of quantitative
induction is always to arrive at some mathematical expression involving
the quantity of each condition, and expressing the quantity of the
result. In other words, we wish to know what function the effect is
of its conditions. We shall find that it is one thing to obtain the
numerical results, and quite another thing to detect the law obeyed
by those results, the latter being an operation of an inverse and
tentative character.


*The Variable and the Variant.*

Almost every series of quantitative experiments is directed to obtain
the relation between the different values of one quantity which is
varied at will, and another quantity which is caused thereby to vary.
We may conveniently distinguish these as respectively the *variable*
and the *variant*. When we are examining the effect of heat in
expanding bodies, heat, or one of its dimensions, temperature, is the
variable, length the variant. If we compress a body to observe how much
it is thereby heated, pressure, or it may be the dimensions of the
body, forms the variable, heat the variant. In the thermo-electric pile
we make heat the variable and measure electricity as the variant. That
one of the two measured quantities which is an antecedent condition of
the other will be the variable.

It is always convenient to have the variable entirely under our
command. Experiments may indeed be made with accuracy, provided we
can exactly measure the variable at the moment when the quantity of
the effect is determined. But if we have to trust to the action of
some capricious force, there may be great difficulty in making exact
measurements, and those results may not be disposed over the whole
range of quantity in a convenient manner. It is one prime object of the
experimenter, therefore, to obtain a regular and governable supply
of the force which he is investigating. To determine correctly the
efficiency of windmills, when the natural winds were constantly varying
in force, would be exceedingly difficult. Smeaton, therefore, in his
experiments on the subject, created a uniform wind of the required
force by moving his models against the air on the extremity of a
revolving arm.[357] The velocity of the wind could thus be rendered
greater or less, it could be maintained uniform for any length of
time, and its amount could be exactly ascertained. In determining the
laws of the chemical action of light it would be out of the question
to employ the rays of the sun, which vary in intensity with the
clearness of the atmosphere, and with every passing cloud. One great
difficulty in photometry and the investigation of the chemical action
of light consists in obtaining a uniform and governable source of light
rays.[358]

  [357] *Philosophical Transactions*, vol. li. p. 138; abridgment,
  vol. xi. p. 355.

  [358] See Bunsen and Roscoe’s researches, in *Philosophical
  Transactions* (1859), vol. cxlix. p. 880, &c., where they describe a
  constant flame of carbon monoxide gas.

Fizeau’s method of measuring the velocity of light enabled him
to appreciate the time occupied by light in travelling through a
distance of eight or nine thousand metres. But the revolving mirror
of Wheatstone subsequently enabled Foucault and Fizeau to measure the
velocity in a space of four metres. In this latter method there was
the advantage that various media could be substituted for air, and the
temperature, density, and other conditions of the experiment could be
accurately governed and measured.


*Measurement of the Variable.*

There is little use in obtaining exact measurements of an effect unless
we can also exactly measure its conditions.

It is absurd to measure the electrical resistance of a piece of metal,
its elasticity, tenacity, density, or other physical qualities, if
these vary, not only with the minute impurities of the metal, but also
with its physical condition. If the same bar changes its properties
by being heated and cooled, and we cannot exactly define the state
in which it is at any moment, our care in measuring will be wasted,
because it can lead to no law. It is of little use to determine very
exactly the electric conductibility of carbon, which as graphite or gas
carbon conducts like a metal, as diamond is almost a non-conductor,
and in several other forms possesses variable and intermediate
powers of conduction. It will be of use only for immediate practical
applications. Before measuring these we ought to have something to
measure of which the conditions are capable of exact definition, and
to which at a future time we can recur. Similarly the accuracy of our
measurement need not much surpass the accuracy with which we can define
the conditions of the object treated.

The speed of electricity in passing through a conductor mainly depends
upon the inductive capacity of the surrounding substances, and, except
for technical or special purposes, there is little use in measuring
velocities which in some cases are one hundred times as great as in
other cases. But the maximum speed of electric conduction is probably
a constant quantity of great scientific importance, and according
to Prof. Clerk Maxwell’s determination in 1868 is 174,800 miles per
second, or little less than that of light. The true boiling point of
water is a point on which practical thermometry depends, and it is
highly important to determine that point in relation to the absolute
thermometric scale. But when water free from air and impurity is
heated there seems to be no definite limit to the temperature it may
reach, a temperature of 180° Cent. having been actually observed.
Such temperatures, therefore, do not require accurate measurement.
All meteorological measurements depending on the accidental condition
of the sky are of far less importance than physical measurements in
which such accidental conditions do not intervene. Many profound
investigations depend upon our knowledge of the radiant energy
continually poured upon the earth by the sun; but this must be measured
when the sky is perfectly clear, and the absorption of the atmosphere
at its minimum. The slightest interference of cloud destroys the value
of such a measurement, except for meteorological purposes, which are of
vastly less generality and importance. It is seldom useful, again, to
measure the height of a snow-covered mountain within a foot, when the
thickness of the snow alone may cause it to vary 25 feet or more, when
in short the height itself is indefinite to that extent.[359]

  [359] Humboldt’s *Cosmos* (Bohn), vol. i. p. 7.


*Maintenance of Similar Conditions.*

Our ultimate object in induction must be to obtain the complete
relation between the conditions and the effect, but this relation
will generally be so complex that we can only attack it in detail.
We must, as far as possible, confine the variation to one condition
at a time, and establish a separate relation between each condition
and the effect. This is at any rate the first step in approximating
to the complete law, and it will be a subsequent question how far the
simultaneous variation of several conditions modifies their separate
actions. In many experiments, indeed, it is only one condition which
we wish to study, and the others are interfering forces which we would
avoid if possible. One of the conditions of the motion of a pendulum is
the resistance of the air, or other medium in which it swings; but when
Newton was desirous of proving the equal gravitation of all substances,
he had no interest in the air. His object was to observe a single force
only, and so it is in a great many other experiments. Accordingly,
one of the most important precautions in investigation consists in
maintaining all conditions constant except that which is to be studied.
As that admirable experimental philosopher, Gilbert, expressed it,[360]
“There is always need of similar preparation, of similar figure, and
of equal magnitude, for in dissimilar and unequal circumstances the
experiment is doubtful.”

  [360] Gilbert, *De Magnete*, p. 109.

In Newton’s decisive experiment similar conditions were provided
for, with the simplicity which characterises the highest art. The
pendulums of which the oscillations were compared consisted of equal
boxes of wood, hanging by equal threads, and filled with different
substances, so that the total weights should be equal and the centres
of oscillation at the same distance from the points of suspension.
Hence the resistance of the air became approximately a matter of
indifference; for the outward size and shape of the pendulums being
the same, the absolute force of resistance would be the same, so long
as the pendulums vibrated with equal velocity; and the weights being
equal the resistance would diminish the velocity equally. Hence if any
inequality were observed in the vibrations of the two pendulums, it
must arise from the only circumstance which was different, namely the
chemical nature of the matter within the boxes. No inequality being
observed, the chemical nature of substances can have no appreciable
influence upon the force of gravitation.[361]

  [361] *Principia*, bk. iii. Prop. vi.

A beautiful experiment was devised by Dr. Joule for the purpose of
showing that the gain or loss of heat by a gas is connected, not
with the mere change of its volume and density, but with the energy
received or given out by the gas. Two strong vessels, connected by
a tube and stopcock, were placed in water after the air had been
exhausted from one vessel and condensed in the other to the extent
of twenty atmospheres. The whole apparatus having been brought to a
uniform temperature by agitating the water, and the temperature having
been exactly observed, the stopcock was opened, so that the air at
once expanded and filled the two vessels uniformly. The temperature
of the water being again noted was found to be almost unchanged. The
experiment was then repeated in an exactly similar manner, except that
the strong vessels were placed in separate portions of the water. Now
cold was produced in the vessel from which the air rushed, and an
almost exactly equal quantity of heat appeared in that to which it was
conducted. Thus Dr. Joule clearly proved that rarefaction produces
as much heat as cold, and that only when there is disappearance of
mechanical energy will there be production of heat.[362] What we have
to notice, however, is not so much the result of the experiment, as the
simple manner in which a single change in the apparatus, the separation
of the portions of water surrounding the air vessels, is made to give
indications of the utmost significance.

  [362] *Philosophical Magazine*, 3rd Series, vol. xxvi. p. 375.


*Collective Experiments.*

There is an interesting class of experiments which enable us to observe
a number of quantitative results in one act. Generally speaking, each
experiment yields us but one number, and before we can approach the
real processes of reasoning we must laboriously repeat measurement
after measurement, until we can lay out a curve of the variation of
one quantity as depending on another. We can sometimes abbreviate
this labour, by making a quantity vary in different parts of the same
apparatus through every required amount. In observing the height to
which water rises by the capillary attraction of a glass vessel, we may
take a series of glass tubes of different bore, and measure the height
through which it rises in each. But if we take two glass plates, and
place them vertically in water, so as to be in contact at one vertical
side, and slightly separated at the other side, the interval between
the plates varies through every intermediate width, and the water rises
to a corresponding height, producing at its upper surface a hyperbolic
curve.

The absorption of light in passing through a coloured liquid may be
beautifully shown by enclosing the liquid in a wedge-shaped glass, so
that we have at a single glance an infinite variety of thicknesses in
view. As Newton himself remarked, a red liquid viewed in this manner is
found to have a pale yellow colour at the thinnest part, and it passes
through orange into red, which gradually becomes of a deeper and darker
tint.[363] The effect may be noticed in a conical wine-glass. The
prismatic analysis of light from such a wedge-shaped vessel discloses
the reason, by exhibiting the progressive absorption of different rays
of the spectrum as investigated by Dr. J. H. Gladstone.[364]

  [363] *Opticks*, 3rd edit. p. 159.

  [364] Watts, *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. iii. p. 637.

A moving body may sometimes be made to mark out its own course, like
a shooting star which leaves a tail behind it. Thus an inclined jet
of water exhibits in the clearest manner the parabolic path of a
projectile. In Wheatstone’s Kaleidophone the curves produced by the
combination of vibrations of different ratios are shown by placing
bright reflective buttons on the tops of wires of various forms. The
motions are performed so quickly that the eye receives the impression
of the path as a complete whole, just as a burning stick whirled round
produces a continuous circle. The laws of electric induction are
beautifully shown when iron filings are brought under the influence of
a magnet, and fall into curves corresponding to what Faraday called
the Lines of Magnetic Force. When Faraday tried to define what he
meant by his lines of force, he was obliged to refer to the filings.
“By magnetic curves,” he says,[365] “I mean lines of magnetic forces
which would be depicted by iron filings.” Robison had previously
produced similar curves by the action of frictional electricity, and
from a mathematical investigation of the forms of such curves we may
infer that magnetic and electric attractions obey the general law of
emanation, that of the inverse square of the distance. In the electric
brush we have a similar exhibition of the laws of electric attraction.

  [365] *Faraday’s Life*, by Bence Jones, vol. ii. p. 5.

There are several branches of science in which collective experiments
have been used with great advantage. Lichtenberg’s electric figures,
produced by scattering electrified powder on an electrified resin cake,
so as to show the condition of the latter, suggested to Chladni the
notion of discovering the state of vibration of plates by strewing sand
upon them. The sand collects at the points where the motion is least,
and we gain at a glance a comprehension of the undulations of the
plate. To this method of experiment we owe the beautiful observations
of Savart. The exquisite coloured figures exhibited by plates of
crystal, when examined by polarised light, afford a more complicated
example of the same kind of investigation. They led Brewster and
Fresnel to an explanation of the properties of the optic axes of
crystals. The unequal conduction of heat in crystalline substances has
also been shown in a similar manner, by spreading a thin layer of wax
over the plate of crystal, and applying heat to a single point. The
wax then melts in a circular or elliptic area according as the rate of
conduction is uniform or not. Nor should we forget that Newton’s rings
were an early and most important instance of investigations of the
same kind, showing the effects of interference of light undulations
of all magnitudes at a single view. Herschel gave to all such
opportunities of observing directly the results of a general law, the
name of *Collective Instances*,[366] and I propose to adopt the name
*Collective Experiments*.

  [366] *Preliminary Discourse*, &c., p. 185.

Such experiments will in many subjects only give the first hint of
the nature of the law in question, but will not admit of any exact
measurements. The parabolic form of a jet of water may well have
suggested to Galileo his views concerning the path of a projectile;
but it would not serve now for the exact investigation of the laws of
gravity. It is unlikely that capillary attraction could be exactly
measured by the use of inclined plates of glass, and tubes would
probably be better for precise investigation. As a general rule, these
collective experiments would be most useful for popular illustration.
But when the curves are of a precise and permanent character, as in
the coloured figures produced by crystalline plates, they may admit of
exact measurement. Newton’s rings and diffraction fringes allow of very
accurate measurements.

Under collective experiments we may perhaps place those in which we
render visible the motions of gas or liquid by diffusing some opaque
substance in it. The behaviour of a body of air may often be studied
in a beautiful way by the use of smoke, as in the production of smoke
rings and jets. In the case of liquids lycopodium powder is sometimes
employed. To detect the mixture of currents or strata of liquid, I
employed very dilute solutions of common salt and silver nitrate,
which produce a visible cloud wherever they come into contact.[367]
Atmospheric clouds often reveal to us the movements of great volumes of
air which would otherwise be quite unapparent.

  [367] *Philosophical Magazine*, July, 1857, 4th Series, vol. xiv.
  p. 24.


*Periodic Variations.*

A large class of investigations is concerned with Periodic Variations.
We may define a periodic phenomenon as one which, with the uniform
change of the variable, returns time after time to the same value.
If we strike a pendulum it presently returns to the point from which
we disturbed it, and while time, the variable, progresses uniformly,
it goes on making excursions and returning, until stopped by the
dissipation of its energy. If one body in space approaches by gravity
towards another, they will revolve round each other in elliptic
orbits, and return for an indefinite number of times to the same
relative positions. On the other hand a single body projected into
empty space, free from the action of any extraneous force, would go
on moving for ever in a straight line, according to the first law of
motion. In the latter case the variation is called *secular*, because
it proceeds during ages in a similar manner, and suffers no περίοδος
or going round. It may be doubted whether there really is any motion
in the universe which is not periodic. Mr. Herbert Spencer long since
adopted the doctrine that all motion is ultimately rhythmical,[368] and
abundance of evidence may be adduced in favour of his view.

  [368] *First Principles*, 3rd edit. chap. x. p. 253.

The so-called secular acceleration of the moon’s motion is certainly
periodic, and as, so far as we can tell, no body is beyond the
attractive power of other bodies, rectilinear motion becomes purely
hypothetical, or at least infinitely improbable. All the motions of all
the stars must tend to become periodic. Though certain disturbances
in the planetary system seem to be uniformly progressive, Laplace is
considered to have proved that they really have their limits, so that
after an immense time, all the planetary bodies might return to the
same places, and the stability of the system be established. Such a
theory of periodic stability is really hypothetical, and does not
take into account phenomena resulting in the dissipation of energy,
which may be a really secular process. For our present purposes we
need not attempt to form an opinion on such questions. Any change
which does not present the appearance of a periodic character will be
empirically regarded as a secular change, so that there will be plenty
of non-periodic variations.

The variations which we produce experimentally will often be
non-periodic. When we communicate heat to a gas it increases in
bulk or pressure, and as far as we can go the higher the temperature
the higher the pressure. Our experiments are of course restricted
in temperature both above and below, but there is every reason to
believe that the bulk being the same, the pressure would never return
to the same point at any two different temperatures. We may of course
repeatedly raise and lower the temperature at regular or irregular
intervals entirely at our will, and the pressure of the gas will vary
in like manner and exactly at the same intervals, but such an arbitrary
series of changes would not constitute Periodic Variation. It would
constitute a succession of distinct experiments, which would place
beyond reasonable doubt the connexion of cause and effect.

Whenever a phenomenon recurs at equal or nearly equal intervals, there
is, according to the theory of probability, considerable evidence
of connexion, because if the recurrences were entirely casual it is
unlikely that they would happen at equal intervals. The fact that a
brilliant comet had appeared in the years 1301, 1378, 1456, 1531, 1607,
and 1682 gave considerable presumption in favour of the identity of the
body, apart from similarity of the orbit. There is nothing which so
fascinates the attention of men as the recurrence time after time of
some unusual event. Things and appearances which remain ever the same,
like mountains and valleys, fail to excite the curiosity of a primitive
people. It has been remarked by Laplace that even in his day the rising
of Venus in its brightest phase never failed to excite surprise and
interest. So there is little doubt that the first germ of science
arose in the attention given by Eastern people to the changes of the
moon and the motions of the planets. Perhaps the earliest astronomical
discovery consisted in proving the identity of the morning and evening
stars, on the grounds of their similarity of aspect and invariable
alternation.[369] Periodical changes of a somewhat complicated kind
must have been understood by the Chaldeans, because they were aware
of the cycle of 6585 days or 19 years which brings round the new and
full moon upon the same days, hours, and even minutes of the year.
The earliest efforts of scientific prophecy were founded upon this
knowledge, and if at present we cannot help wondering at the precise
anticipations of the nautical almanack, we may imagine the wonder
excited by such predictions in early times.

  [369] Laplace, *System of the World*, vol. i. pp. 50, 54, &c.


*Combined Periodic Changes.*

We shall seldom find a body subject to a single periodic variation,
and free from other disturbances. We may expect the periodic variation
itself to undergo variation, which may possibly be secular, but is more
likely to prove periodic; nor is there any limit to the complication of
periods beyond periods, or periods within periods, which may ultimately
be disclosed. In studying a phenomenon of rhythmical character we have
a succession of questions to ask. Is the periodic variation uniform? If
not, is the change uniform? If not, is the change itself periodic? Is
that new period uniform, or subject to any other change, or not? and so
on *ad infinitum*.

In some cases there may be many distinct causes of periodic variations,
and according to the principle of the superposition of small effects,
to be afterwards considered, these periodic effects will be simply
added together, or at least approximately so, and the joint result may
present a very complicated subject of investigation. The tides of the
ocean consist of a series of superimposed undulations. Not only are
there the ordinary semi-diurnal tides caused by sun and moon, but a
series of minor tides, such as the lunar diurnal, the solar diurnal,
the lunar monthly, the lunar fortnightly, the solar annual and solar
semi-annual are gradually being disentangled by the labours of Sir W.
Thomson, Professor Haughton and others.

Variable stars present interesting periodic phenomena; while some
stars, δ Cephei for instance, are subject to very regular variations,
others, like Mira Ceti, are less constant in the degrees of brilliancy
which they attain or the rapidity of the changes, possibly on account
of some longer periodic variation.[370] The star β Lyræ presents a
double maximum and minimum in each of its periods of nearly 13 days,
and since the discovery of this variation the period in a period has
probably been on the increase. “At first the variability was more
rapid, then it became gradually slower; and this decrease in the length
of time reached its limit between the years 1840 and 1844. During that
time its period was nearly invariable; at present it is again decidedly
on the decrease.”[371] The tracing out of such complicated variations
presents an unlimited field for interesting investigation. The number
of such variable stars already known is considerable, and there is no
reason to suppose that any appreciable fraction of the whole number has
yet been detected.

  [370] Herschel’s *Outlines of Astronomy*, 4th edit. pp. 555–557.

  [371] Humboldt’s *Cosmos* (Bohn), vol. iii. p. 229.


*Principle of Forced Vibrations.*

Investigations of the connection of periodic causes and effects
rest upon a principle, which has been demonstrated by Sir John
Herschel for some special cases, and clearly explained by him in
several of his works.[372] The principle may be formally stated in
the following manner: “If one part of any system connected together
either by material ties, or by the mutual attractions of its members,
be continually maintained by any cause, whether inherent in the
constitution of the system or external to it, in a state of regular
periodic motion, that motion will be propagated throughout the whole
system, and will give rise, in every member of it, and in every part
of each member, to periodic movements executed in equal periods, with
that to which they owe their origin, though not necessarily synchronous
with them in their maxima and minima.” The meaning of the proposition
is that the effect of a periodic cause will be periodic, and will recur
at intervals equal to those of the cause. Accordingly when we find two
phenomena which do proceed, time after time, through changes of the
same period, there is much probability that they are connected. In
this manner, doubtless, Pliny correctly inferred that the cause of the
tides lies in the sun and the moon, the intervals between successive
high tides being equal to the intervals between the moon’s passage
across the meridian. Kepler and Descartes too admitted the connection
previous to Newton’s demonstration of its precise nature. When Bradley
discovered the apparent motion of the stars arising from the aberration
of light, he was soon able to attribute it to the earth’s annual
motion, because it went through its phases in a year.

  [372] *Encyclopædia Metropolitana*, art. *Sound*, § 323; *Outlines
  of Astronomy*, 4th edit., § 650. pp. 410, 487–88; *Meteorology,
  Encyclopædia Britannica*, Reprint, p. 197.

The most beautiful instance of induction concerning periodic changes
which can be cited, is the discovery of an eleven-year period in
various meteorological phenomena. It would be difficult to mention any
two things apparently more disconnected than the spots upon the sun and
auroras. As long ago as 1826, Schwabe commenced a regular series of
observations of the spots upon the sun, which has been continued to the
present time, and he was able to show that at intervals of about eleven
years the spots increased much in size and number. Hardly was this
discovery made known, when Lamont pointed out a nearly equal period of
variation in the declination of the magnetic needle. Magnetic storms or
sudden disturbances of the needle were next shown to take place most
frequently at the times when sun-spots were prevalent, and as auroras
are generally coincident with magnetic storms, these phenomena were
brought into the cycle. It has since been shown by Professor Piazzi
Smyth and Mr. E. J. Stone, that the temperature of the earth’s surface
as indicated by sunken thermometers gives some evidence of a like
period. The existence of a periodic cause having once been established,
it is quite to be expected, according to the principle of forced
vibrations, that its influence will be detected in all meteorological
phenomena.


*Integrated Variations.*

In considering the various modes in which one effect may depend upon
another, we must set in a distinct class those which arise from the
accumulated effects of a constantly acting cause. When water runs out
of a cistern, the velocity of motion depends, according to Torricelli’s
theorem, on the height of the surface of the water above the vent;
but the amount of water which leaves the cistern in a given time
depends upon the aggregate result of that velocity, and is only to
be ascertained by the mathematical process of integration. When one
gravitating body falls towards another, the force of gravity varies
according to the inverse square of the distance; to obtain the velocity
produced we must integrate or sum the effects of that law; and to
obtain the space passed over by the body in a given time, we must
integrate again.

In periodic variations the same distinction must be drawn. The heating
power of the sun’s rays at any place on the earth varies every day with
the height attained, and is greatest about noon; but the temperature of
the air will not be greatest at the same time. This temperature is an
integrated effect of the sun’s heating power, and as long as the sun
is able to give more heat to the air than the air loses in other ways,
the temperature continues to rise, so that the maximum is deferred
until about 3 P.M. Similarly the hottest day of the year falls, on an
average, about one month later than the summer solstice, and all the
seasons lag about a month behind the motions of the sun. In the case
of the tides, too, the effect of the moon’s attractive power is never
greatest when the power is greatest; the effect always lags more or
less behind the cause. Yet the intervals between successive tides are
equal, in the absence of disturbance, to the intervals between the
passages of the moon across the meridian. Thus the principle of forced
vibrations holds true.

In periodic phenomena, however, curious results sometimes follow from
the integration of effects. If we strike a pendulum, and then repeat
the stroke time after time at the same part of the vibration, all the
strokes concur in adding to the momentum, and we can thus increase the
extent and violence of the vibrations to any degree. We can stop the
pendulum again by strokes applied when it is moving in the opposite
direction, and the effects being added together will soon bring it to
rest. Now if we alter the intervals of the strokes so that each two
successive strokes act in opposite manners they will neutralise each
other, and the energy expended will be turned into heat or sound at the
point of percussion. Similar effects occur in all cases of rhythmical
motion. If a musical note is sounded in a room containing a piano,
the string corresponding to it will be thrown into vibration, because
every successive stroke of the air-waves upon the string finds it in
like position as regards the vibration, and thus adds to its energy of
motion. But the other strings being incapable of vibrating with the
same rapidity are struck at various points of their vibrations, and one
stroke will soon be opposed by one contrary in effect. All phenomena of
*resonance* arise from this coincidence in time of undulation. The air
in a pipe closed at one end, and about 12 inches in length, is capable
of vibrating 512 times in a second. If, then, the note C is sounded in
front of the open end of the pipe, every successive vibration of the
air is treasured up as it were in the motion of the air. In a pipe of
different length the pulses of air would strike each other, and the
mechanical energy being transmuted into heat would become no longer
perceptible as sound.

Accumulated vibrations sometimes become so intense as to lead to
unexpected results. A glass vessel if touched with a violin bow at
a suitable point may be fractured with the violence of vibration. A
suspension bridge may be broken down if a company of soldiers walk
across it in steps the intervals of which agree with the vibrations
of the bridge itself. But if they break the step or march in either
quicker or slower pace, they may have no perceptible effect upon the
bridge. In fact if the impulses communicated to any vibrating body are
synchronous with its vibrations, the energy of those vibrations will be
unlimited, and may fracture any body.

Let us now consider what will happen if the strokes be not exactly at
the same intervals as the vibrations of the body, but, say, a little
slower. Then a succession of strokes will meet the body in nearly but
not quite the same position, and their efforts will be accumulated.
Afterwards the strokes will begin to fall when the body is in the
opposite phase. Imagine that one pendulum moving from one extreme
point to another in a second, should be struck by another pendulum
which makes 61 beats in a minute; then, if the pendulums commence
together, they will at the end of 30-1/2 beats be moving in opposite
directions. Hence whatever energy was communicated in the first half
minute will be neutralised by the opposite effect of that given in the
second half. The effect of the strokes of the second pendulum will
therefore be alternately to increase and decrease the vibrations of
the first, so that a new kind of vibration will be produced running
through its phases in 61 seconds. An effect of this kind was actually
observed by Ellicott, a member of the Royal Society, in the case of two
clocks.[373] He found that through the wood-work by which the clocks
were connected a slight impulse was transmitted, and each pendulum
alternately lost and gained momentum. Each clock, in fact, tended to
stop the other at regular intervals, and in the intermediate times to
be stopped by the other.

  [373] *Philosophical Transactions*, (1739), vol. xli. p. 126.

Many disturbances in the planetary system depend upon the same
principle; for if one planet happens always to pull another in the
same direction in similar parts of their orbits, the effects, however
slight, will be accumulated, and a disturbance of large ultimate
amount and of long period will be produced. The long inequality in
the motions of Jupiter and Saturn is thus due to the fact that five
times the mean motion of Saturn is very nearly equal to twice the mean
motion of Jupiter, causing a coincidence in their relative positions
and disturbing powers. The rolling of ships depends mainly upon the
question whether the period of vibration of the ship corresponds or
not with the intervals at which the waves strike her. Much which seems
at first sight unaccountable in the behaviour of vessels is thus
explained, and the loss of the *Captain* is a sad case in point.




CHAPTER XXI.

THEORY OF APPROXIMATION.


In order that we may gain a true understanding of the kind, degree, and
value of the knowledge which we acquire by experimental investigation,
it is requisite that we should be fully conscious of its approximate
character. We must learn to distinguish between what we can know
and cannot know--between the questions which admit of solution, and
those which only seem to be solved. Many persons may be misled by the
expression *exact science*, and may think that the knowledge acquired
by scientific methods admits of our reaching absolutely true laws,
exact to the last degree. There is even a prevailing impression that
when once mathematical formulæ have been successfully applied to a
branch of science, this portion of knowledge assumes a new nature, and
admits of reasoning of a higher character than those sciences which are
still unmathematical.

The very satisfactory degree of accuracy attained in the science of
astronomy gives a certain plausibility to erroneous notions of this
kind. Some persons no doubt consider it to be *proved* that planets
move in ellipses, in such a manner that all Kepler’s laws hold exactly
true; but there is a double error in any such notions. In the first
place, Kepler’s laws are *not proved*, if by proof we mean certain
demonstration of their exact truth. In the next place, even assuming
Kepler’s laws to be exactly true in a theoretical point of view, the
planets never move according to those laws. Even if we could observe
the motions of a planet, of a perfect globular form, free from all
perturbing or retarding forces, we could never prove that it moved
in a perfect ellipse. To prove the elliptical form we should have to
measure infinitely small angles, and infinitely small fractions of a
second; we should have to perform impossibilities. All we can do is to
show that the motion of an unperturbed planet approaches *very nearly*
to the form of an ellipse, and more nearly the more accurately our
observations are made. But if we go on to assert that the path *is* an
ellipse we pass beyond our data, and make an assumption which cannot be
verified by observation.

But, secondly, as a matter of fact no planet does move in a perfect
ellipse, or manifest the truth of Kepler’s laws exactly. The law of
gravity prevents its own results from being clearly exhibited, because
the mutual perturbations of the planets distort the elliptical paths.
Those laws, again, hold exactly true only of infinitely small bodies,
and when two great globes, like the sun and Jupiter, attract each
other, the law must be modified. The periodic time is then shortened
in the ratio of the square root of the number expressing the sun’s
mass, to that of the sum of the numbers expressing the masses of the
sun and planet, as was shown by Newton.[374] Even at the present day
discrepancies exist between the observed dimensions of the planetary
orbits and their theoretical magnitudes, after making allowance for
all disturbing causes.[375] Nothing is more certain in scientific
method than that approximate coincidence alone can be expected. In
the measurement of continuous quantity perfect correspondence must
be accidental, and should give rise to suspicion rather than to
satisfaction.

  [374] *Principia*, bk. iii. Prop. 15.

  [375] Lockyer’s *Lessons in Elementary Astronomy*, p. 301.

One remarkable result of the approximate character of our observations
is that we could never prove the existence of perfectly circular or
parabolic movement, even if it existed. The circle is a singular case
of the ellipse, for which the eccentricity is zero; it is infinitely
improbable that any planet, even if undisturbed by other bodies, would
have a circle for its orbit; but if the orbit were a circle we could
never prove the entire absence of eccentricity. All that we could
do would be to declare the divergence from the circular form to be
inappreciable. Delambre was unable to detect the slightest ellipticity
in the orbit of Jupiter’s first satellite, but he could only infer
that the orbit was *nearly* circular. The parabola is the singular
limit between the ellipse and the hyperbola. As there are elliptic and
hyperbolic comets, so we might conceive the existence of a parabolic
comet. Indeed if an undisturbed comet fell towards the sun from an
infinite distance it would move in a parabola; but we could never prove
that it so moved.


*Substitution of Simple Hypotheses.*

In truth men never can solve problems fulfilling the complex
circumstances of nature. All laws and explanations are in a certain
sense hypothetical, and apply exactly to nothing which we can know
to exist. In place of the actual objects which we see and feel, the
mathematician substitutes imaginary objects, only partially resembling
those represented, but so devised that the discrepancies are not of
an amount to alter seriously the character of the solution. When we
probe the matter to the bottom physical astronomy is as hypothetical as
Euclid’s elements. There may exist in nature perfect straight lines,
triangles, circles, and other regular geometrical figures; to our
science it is a matter of indifference whether they do or do not exist,
because in any case they must be beyond our powers of perception. If
we submitted a perfect circle to the most rigorous scrutiny, it is
impossible that we should discover whether it were perfect or not.
Nevertheless in geometry we argue concerning perfect curves, and
rectilinear figures, and the conclusions apply to existing objects so
far as we can assure ourselves that they agree with the hypothetical
conditions of our reasoning. This is in reality all that we can do in
the most perfect of the sciences.

Doubtless in astronomy we meet with the nearest approximation to
actual conditions. The law of gravity is not a complex one in itself,
and we believe it with much probability to be exactly true; but we
cannot calculate out in any real case its accurate results. The law
asserts that every particle of matter in the universe attracts every
other particle, with a force depending on the masses of the particles
and their distances. We cannot know the force acting on any particle
unless we know the masses and distances and positions of all other
particles in the universe. The physical astronomer has made a sweeping
assumption, namely, that all the millions of existing systems exert no
perturbing effects on our planetary system, that is to say, no effects
in the least appreciable. The problem at once becomes hypothetical,
because there is little doubt that gravitation between our sun and
planets and other systems does exist. Even when they consider the
relations of our planetary bodies *inter se*, all their processes are
only approximate. In the first place they assume that each of the
planets is a perfect ellipsoid, with a smooth surface and a homogeneous
interior. That this assumption is untrue every mountain and valley,
every sea, every mine affords conclusive evidence. If astronomers are
to make their calculations perfect, they must not only take account
of the Himalayas and the Andes, but must calculate separately the
attraction of every hill, nay, of every ant-hill. So far are they
from having considered any local inequality of the surface, that they
have not yet decided upon the general form of the earth; it is still
a matter of speculation whether or not the earth is an ellipsoid with
three unequal axes. If, as is probable, the globe is irregularly
compressed in some directions, the calculations of astronomers will
have to be repeated and refined, in order that they may approximate
to the attractive power of such a body. If we cannot accurately learn
the form of our own earth, how can we expect to ascertain that of
the moon, the sun, and other planets, in some of which probably are
irregularities of greater proportional amount?

In a further way the science of physical astronomy is merely
approximate and hypothetical. Given homogeneous ellipsoids acting upon
each other according to the law of gravity, the best mathematicians
have never and perhaps never will determine exactly the resulting
movements. Even when three bodies simultaneously attract each other the
complication of effects is so great that only approximate calculations
can be made. Astronomers have not even attempted the general problem
of the simultaneous attractions of four, five, six, or more bodies;
they resolve the general problem into so many different problems of
three bodies. The principle upon which the calculations of physical
astronomy proceed, is to neglect every quantity which does not seem
likely to lead to an effect appreciable in observation, and the
quantities rejected are far more numerous and complex than the few
larger terms which are retained. All then is merely approximate.

Concerning other branches of physical science the same statements are
even more evidently true. We speak and calculate about inflexible
bars, inextensible lines, heavy points, homogeneous substances,
uniform spheres, perfect fluids and gases, and we deduce a great
number of beautiful theorems; but all is hypothetical. There is no
such thing as an inflexible bar, an inextensible line, nor any one
of the other perfect objects of mechanical science; they are to be
classed with those mythical existences, the straight line, triangle,
circle, &c., about which Euclid so freely reasoned. Take the simplest
operation considered in statics--the use of a crowbar in raising a
heavy stone, and we shall find, as Thomson and Tait have pointed
out, that we neglect far more than we observe.[376] If we suppose
the bar to be quite rigid, the fulcrum and stone perfectly hard, and
the points of contact real points, we may give the true relation of
the forces. But in reality the bar must bend, and the extension and
compression of different parts involve us in difficulties. Even if
the bar be homogeneous in all its parts, there is no mathematical
theory capable of determining with accuracy all that goes on; if, as
is infinitely more probable, the bar is not homogeneous, the complete
solution will be immensely more complicated, but hardly more hopeless.
No sooner had we determined the change of form according to simple
mechanical principles, than we should discover the interference of
thermodynamic principles. Compression produces heat and extension
cold, and thus the conditions of the problem are modified throughout.
In attempting a fourth approximation we should have to allow for the
conduction of heat from one part of the bar to another. All these
effects are utterly inappreciable in a practical point of view, if
the bar be a good stout one; but in a theoretical point of view they
entirely prevent our saying that we have solved a natural problem. The
faculties of the human mind, even when aided by the wonderful powers
of abbreviation conferred by analytical methods, are utterly unable to
cope with the complications of any real problem. And had we exhausted
all the known phenomena of a mechanical problem, how can we tell that
hidden phenomena, as yet undetected, do not intervene in the commonest
actions? It is plain that no phenomenon comes within the sphere of
our senses unless it possesses a momentum capable of irritating the
appropriate nerves. There may then be worlds of phenomena too slight to
rise within the scope of our consciousness.

  [376] *Treatise on Natural Philosophy*, vol. i. pp. 337, &c.

All the instruments with which we perform our measurements are faulty.
We assume that a plumb-line gives a vertical line; but this is never
true in an absolute sense, owing to the attraction of mountains
and other inequalities in the surface of the earth. In an accurate
trigonometrical survey, the divergencies of the plumb-line must be
approximately determined and allowed for. We assume a surface of
mercury to be a perfect plane, but even in the breadth of 5 inches
there is a calculable divergence from a true plane of about one
ten-millionth part of an inch; and this surface further diverges from
true horizontality as the plumb-line does from true verticality.
That most perfect instrument, the pendulum, is not theoretically
perfect, except for infinitely small arcs of vibration, and the
delicate experiments performed with the torsion balance proceed on the
assumption that the force of torsion of a wire is proportional to the
angle of torsion, which again is only true for infinitely small angles.

Such is the purely approximate character of all our operations that it
is not uncommon to find the theoretically worse method giving truer
results than the theoretically perfect method. The common pendulum
which is not isochronous is better for practical purposes than the
cycloidal pendulum, which is isochronous in theory but subject to
mechanical difficulties. The spherical form is not the correct form for
a speculum or lense, but it differs so slightly from the true form, and
is so much more easily produced mechanically, that it is generally
best to rest content with the spherical surface. Even in a six-feet
mirror the difference between the parabola and the sphere is only about
one ten-thousandth part of an inch, a thickness which would be taken
off in a few rubs of the polisher. Watts’ ingenious parallel motion was
intended to produce rectilinear movement of the piston-rod. In reality
the motion was always curvilinear, but for his purposes a certain part
of the curve approximated sufficiently to a straight line.


*Approximation to Exact Laws.*

Though we can not prove numerical laws with perfect accuracy, it would
be a great mistake to suppose that there is any inexactness in the laws
of nature. We may even discover a law which we believe to represent
the action of forces with perfect exactness. The mind may seem to pass
in advance of its data, and choose out certain numerical results as
absolutely true. We can never really pass beyond our data, and so far
as assumption enters in, so far want of certainty will attach to our
conclusions; nevertheless we may sometimes rightly prefer a probable
assumption of a precise law to numerical results, which are at the best
only approximate. We must accordingly draw a strong distinction between
the laws of nature which we believe to be accurately stated in our
formulas, and those to which our statements only make an approximation,
so that at a future time the law will be differently stated.

The law of gravitation is expressed in the form F = Mm/D^{2},
meaning that gravity is proportional directly to the product of
the gravitating masses, and indirectly to the square of their
distance. The latent heat of steam is expressed by the equation
log F = *a* + *b*α^{t} + *c*β^{t}, in which are five quantities *a*,
*b*, *c*, α, β, to be determined by experiment. There is every reason
to believe that in the progress of science the law of gravity will
remain entirely unaltered, and the only effect of further inquiry will
be to render it a more and more probable expression of the absolute
truth. The law of the latent heat of steam on the other hand, will be
modified by every new series of experiments, and it may not improbably
be shown that the assumed law can never be made to agree exactly with
the results of experiment.

Philosophers have not always supposed that the law of gravity was
exactly true. Newton, though he had the highest confidence in its
truth, admitted that there were motions in the planetary system which
he could not reconcile with the law. Euler and Clairaut who were, with
D’Alembert, the first to apply the full powers of mathematical analysis
to the theory of gravitation as explaining the perturbations of the
planets, did not think the law sufficiently established to attribute
all discrepancies to the errors of calculation and observation. They
did not feel certain that the force of gravity exactly obeyed the
well-known rule. The law might involve other powers of the distance. It
might be expressed in the form

  F = ... + *a*/D + *b*/D^{2} + *c*/D^{3} + ...

and the coefficients *a* and *c* might be so small that those terms
would become apparent only in very accurate comparisons with fact.
Attempts have been made to account for difficulties, by attributing
value to such neglected terms. Gauss at one time thought the even more
fundamental principle of gravity, that the force is dependent only on
mass and distance, might not be exactly true, and he undertook accurate
pendulum experiments to test this opinion. Only as repeated doubts have
time after time been resolved in favour of the law of Newton, has it
been assumed as precisely correct. But this belief does not rest on
experiment or observation only. The calculations of physical astronomy,
however accurate, could never show that the other terms of the above
expression were absolutely devoid of value. It could only be shown that
they had such slight value as never to become apparent.

There are, however, other reasons why the law is probably complete
and true as commonly stated. Whatever influence spreads from a point,
and expands uniformly through space, will doubtless vary inversely
in intensity as the square of the distance, because the area over
which it is spread increases as the square of the radius. This part
of the law of gravity may be considered as due to the properties of
space, and there is a perfect analogy in this respect between gravity
and all other *emanating* forces, as was pointed out by Keill.[377]
Thus the undulations of light, heat, and sound, and the attractions
of electricity and magnetism obey the very same law so far as we
can ascertain. If the molecules of a gas or the particles of matter
constituting odour were to start from a point and spread uniformly,
their distances would increase and their density decrease according to
the same principle.

  [377] *An Introduction to Natural Philosophy*, 3rd edit. 1733, p. 5.

Other laws of nature stand in a similar position. Dalton’s laws of
definite combining proportions never have been, and never can be,
exactly proved; but chemists having shown, to a considerable degree of
approximation, that the elements combine together as if each element
had atoms of an invariable mass, assume that this is exactly true. They
go even further. Prout pointed out in 1815 that the equivalent weights
of the elements appeared to be simple numbers; and the researches of
Dumas, Pelouze, Marignac, Erdmann, Stas, and others have gradually
rendered it likely that the atomic weights of hydrogen, carbon, oxygen,
nitrogen, chlorine, and silver, are in the ratios of the numbers 1,
12, 16, 14, 35·5, and 108. Chemists then step beyond their data; they
throw aside their actual experimental numbers, and assume that the true
ratios are not those exactly indicated by any weighings, but the simple
ratios of these numbers. They boldly assume that the discrepancies are
due to experimental errors, and they are justified by the fact that
the more elaborate and skilful the researches on the subject, the more
nearly their assumption is verified. Potassium is the only element
whose atomic weight has been determined with great care, but which has
not shown an approach to a simple ratio with the other elements. This
exception may be due to some unsuspected cause of error.[378] A similar
assumption is made in the law of definite combining volumes of gases,
and Brodie has clearly pointed out the line of argument by which the
chemist, observing that the discrepancies between the law and fact are
within the limits of experimental error, assumes that they are due to
error.[379]

  [378] Watts, *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. i. p. 455.

  [379] *Philosophical Transactions*, (1866) vol. clvi. p. 809.

Faraday, in one of his researches, expressly makes an assumption
of the same kind. Having shown, with some degree of experimental
precision, that there exists a simple proportion between quantities of
electrical energy and the quantities of chemical substances which it
can decompose, so that for every atom dissolved in the battery cell an
atom ought theoretically, that is without regard to dissipation of some
of the energy, to be decomposed in the electrolytic cell, he does not
stop at his numerical results. “I have not hesitated,” he says,[380]
“to apply the more strict results of chemical analysis to correct the
numbers obtained as electrolytic results. This, it is evident, may be
done in a great number of cases, without using too much liberty towards
the due severity of scientific research.”

  [380] *Experimental Researches in Electricity*, vol. i. p. 246.

The law of the conservation of energy, one of the widest of all
physical generalisations, rests upon the same footing. The most that
we can do by experiment is to show that the energy entering into any
experimental combination is almost equal to what comes out of it,
and more nearly so the more accurately we perform the measurements.
Absolute equality is always a matter of assumption. We cannot even
prove the indestructibility of matter; for were an exceedingly minute
fraction of existing matter to vanish in any experiment, say one part
in ten millions, we could never detect the loss.


*Successive Approximations to Natural Conditions.*

When we examine the history of scientific problems, we find that one
man or one generation is usually able to make but a single step at
a time. A problem is solved for the first time by making some bold
hypothetical simplification, upon which the next investigator makes
hypothetical modifications approaching more nearly to the truth. Errors
are successively pointed out in previous solutions, until at last there
might seem little more to be desired. Careful examination, however,
will show that a series of minor inaccuracies remain to be corrected
and explained, were our powers of reasoning sufficiently great, and the
purpose adequate in importance.

Newton’s successful solution of the problem of the planetary movements
entirely depended at first upon a great simplification. The law of
gravity only applies directly to two infinitely small particles, so
that when we deal with vast globes like the earth, Jupiter, and the
sun, we have an immense aggregate of separate attractions to deal with,
and the law of the aggregate need not coincide with the law of the
elementary particles. But Newton, by a great effort of mathematical
reasoning, was able to show that two homogeneous spheres of matter act
as if the whole of their masses were concentrated at the centres; in
short, that such spheres are centrobaric bodies (p. 364). He was then
able with comparative ease to calculate the motions of the planets on
the hypothesis of their being spheres, and to show that the results
roughly agreed with observation. Newton, indeed, was one of the few men
who could make two great steps at once. He did not rest contented with
the spherical hypothesis; having reason to believe that the earth was
really a spheroid with a protuberance around the equator, he proceeded
to a second approximation, and proved that the attraction of the
protuberant matter upon the moon accounted for the precession of the
equinoxes, and led to various complicated effects. But, (p. 459), even
the spheroidal hypothesis is far from the truth. It takes no account
of the irregularities of surface, the great protuberance of land in
Central Asia and South America, and the deficiency in the bed of the
Atlantic.

To determine the law according to which a projectile, such as a cannon
ball, moves through the atmosphere is a problem very imperfectly
solved at the present day, but in which many successive advances have
been made. So little was known concerning the subject three or four
centuries ago that a cannon ball was supposed to move at first in a
straight line, and after a time to be deflected into a curve. Tartaglia
ventured to maintain that the path was curved throughout, as by the
principle of continuity it should be; but the ingenuity of Galileo
was required to prove this opinion, and to show that the curve was
approximately a parabola. It is only, however, under forced hypotheses
that we can assert the path of a projectile to be truly a parabola: the
path must be through a perfect vacuum, where there is no resisting
medium of any kind; the force of gravity must be uniform and act in
parallel lines; or else the moving body must be either a mere point, or
a perfect centrobaric body, that is a body possessing a definite centre
of gravity. These conditions cannot be really fulfilled in practice.
The next great step in the problem was made by Newton and Huyghens, the
latter of whom asserted that the atmosphere would offer a resistance
proportional to the velocity of the moving body, and concluded that
the path would have in consequence a logarithmic character. Newton
investigated in a general manner the subject of resisting media, and
came to the conclusion that the resistance is more nearly proportional
to the square of the velocity. The subject then fell into the hands
of Daniel Bernoulli, who pointed out the enormous resistance of the
air in cases of rapid movement, and calculated that a cannon ball, if
fired vertically in a vacuum, would rise eight times as high as in the
atmosphere. In recent times an immense amount both of theoretical and
experimental investigation has been spent upon the subject, since it is
one of importance in the art of war. Successive approximations to the
true law have been made, but nothing like a complete and final solution
has been achieved or even hoped for.[381]

  [381] Hutton’s *Mathematical Dictionary*, vol. ii. pp. 287–292.

It is quite to be expected that the earliest experimenters in any
branch of science will overlook errors which afterwards become most
apparent. The Arabian astronomers determined the meridian by taking the
middle point between the places of the sun when at equal altitudes on
the same day. They overlooked the fact that the sun has its own motion
in the time between the observations. Newton thought that the mutual
disturbances of the planets might be disregarded, excepting perhaps the
effect of the mutual attraction of the greater planets, Jupiter and
Saturn, near their conjunction.[382] The expansion of quicksilver was
long used as the measure of temperature, no clear idea being possessed
of temperature apart from some of its more obvious effects. Rumford,
in the first experiment leading to a determination of the mechanical
equivalent of heat, disregarded the heat absorbed by the apparatus,
otherwise he would, in Dr. Joule’s opinion, have come nearly to the
correct result.

  [382] *Principia*, bk. iii. Prop. 13.

It is surprising to learn the number of causes of error which enter
into the simplest experiment, when we strive to attain rigid accuracy.
We cannot accurately perform the simple experiment of compressing gas
in a bent tube by a column of mercury, in order to test the truth
of Boyle’s Law, without paying regard to--(1) the variations of
atmospheric pressure, which are communicated to the gas through the
mercury; (2) the compressibility of mercury, which causes the column
of mercury to vary in density; (3) the temperature of the mercury
throughout the column; (4) the temperature of the gas, which is with
difficulty maintained invariable; (5) the expansion of the glass tube
containing the gas. Although Regnault took all these circumstances
into account in his examination of the law,[383] there is no reason to
suppose that he exhausted the sources of inaccuracy.

  [383] Jamin, *Cours de Physique*, vol. i. pp. 282, 283.

The early investigations concerning the nature of waves in elastic
media proceeded upon the assumption that waves of different lengths
would travel with equal speed. Newton’s theory of sound led him to
this conclusion, and observation (p. 295) had verified the inference.
When the undulatory theory came to be applied at the commencement of
this century to explain the phenomena of light, a great difficulty was
encountered. The angle at which a ray of light is refracted in entering
a denser medium depends, according to that theory, on the velocity
with which the wave travels, so that if all waves of light were to
travel with equal velocity in the same medium, the dispersion of mixed
light by the prism and the production of the spectrum could not take
place. Some most striking phenomena were thus in direct conflict with
the theory. Cauchy first pointed out the explanation, namely, that all
previous investigators had made an arbitrary assumption for the sake
of simplifying the calculations. They had assumed that the particles
of the vibrating medium are so close together that the intervals are
inconsiderable compared with the length of the wave. This hypothesis
happened to be approximately true in the case of air, so that no error
was discovered in experiments on sound. Had it not been so, the earlier
analysts would probably have failed to give any solution, and the
progress of the subject might have been retarded. Cauchy was able to
make a new approximation under the more difficult supposition, that
the particles of the vibrating medium are situated at considerable
distances, and act and react upon the neighbouring particles by
attractive and repulsive forces. To calculate the rate of propagation
of disturbance in such a medium is a work of excessive difficulty. The
complete solution of the problem appears indeed to be beyond human
power, so that we must be content, as in the case of the planetary
motions, to look forward to successive approximations. All that Cauchy
could do was to show that certain quantities, neglected in previous
theories, became of considerable amount under the new conditions of
the problem, so that there will exist a relation between the length
of the wave, and the velocity at which it travels. To remove, then,
the difficulties in the way of the undulatory theory of light, a new
approach to probable conditions was needed.[384]

  [384] Lloyd’s *Lectures on the Wave Theory*, pp. 22, 23.

In a similar manner Fourier’s theory of the conduction and radiation
of heat was based upon the hypothesis that the quantity of heat
passing along any line is simply proportional to the rate of change
of temperature. But it has since been shown by Forbes that the
conductivity of a body diminishes as its temperature increases. All
the details of Fourier’s solution therefore require modification, and
the results are in the meantime to be regarded as only approximately
true.[385]

  [385] Tait’s *Thermodynamics*, p. 10.

We ought to distinguish between those problems which are physically and
those which are merely mathematically incomplete. In the latter case
the physical law is correctly seized, but the mathematician neglects,
or is more often unable to follow out the law in all its results.
The law of gravitation and the principles of harmonic or undulatory
movement, even supposing the data to be correct, can never be followed
into all their ultimate results. Young explained the production of
Newton’s rings by supposing that the rays reflected from the upper and
lower surfaces of a thin film of a certain thickness were in opposite
phases, and thus neutralised each other. It was pointed out, however,
that as the light reflected from the nearer surface must be undoubtedly
a little brighter than that from the further surface, the two rays
ought not to neutralise each other so completely as they are observed
to do. It was finally shown by Poisson that the discrepancy arose only
from incomplete solution of the problem; for the light which has once
got into the film must be to a certain extent reflected backwards and
forwards *ad infinitum*; and if we follow out this course of the light
by perfect mathematical analysis, absolute darkness may be shown to
result from the interference of the rays.[386] In this case the natural
laws concerned, those of reflection and refraction, are accurately
known, and the only difficulty consists in developing their full
consequences.

  [386] Lloyd’s *Lectures on the Wave Theory*, pp. 82, 83.


*Discovery of Hypothetically Simple Laws.*

In some branches of science we meet with natural laws of a simple
character which are in a certain point of view exactly true and yet can
never be manifested as exactly true in natural phenomena. Such, for
instance, are the laws concerning what is called a *perfect gas*. The
gaseous state of matter is that in which the properties of matter are
exhibited in the simplest manner. There is much advantage accordingly
in approaching the question of molecular mechanics from this side.
But when we ask the question--What is a gas? the answer must be a
hypothetical one. Finding that gases *nearly* obey the law of Boyle
and Mariotte; that they *nearly* expand by heat at the uniform rate of
one part in 272·9 of their volume at 0° for each degree centigrade;
and that they *more nearly* fulfil these conditions the more distant
the point of temperature at which we examine them from the liquefying
point, we pass by the principle of continuity to the conception of a
perfect gas. Such a gas would probably consist of atoms of matter at
so great a distance from each other as to exert no attractive forces
upon each other; but for this condition to be fulfilled the distances
must be infinite, so that an absolutely perfect gas cannot exist. But
the perfect gas is not merely a limit to which we may approach, it is a
limit passed by at least one real gas. It has been shown by Despretz,
Pouillet, Dulong, Arago, and finally Regnault, that all gases diverge
from the Boylean law, and in nearly all cases the density of the gas
increases in a somewhat greater ratio than the pressure, indicating
a tendency on the part of the molecules to approximate of their own
accord. In the more condensable gases such as sulphurous acid, ammonia,
and cyanogen, this tendency is strongly apparent near the liquefying
point. Hydrogen, on the contrary, diverges from the law of a perfect
gas in the opposite direction, that is, the density increases less than
in the ratio of the pressure.[387] This is a singular exception, the
bearing of which I am unable to comprehend.

  [387] Jamin, *Cours de Physique*, vol. i. pp. 283–288.

All gases diverge again from the law of uniform expansion by heat, but
the divergence is less as the gas in question is less condensable, or
examined at a temperature more removed from its liquefying point. Thus
the perfect gas must have an infinitely high temperature. According
to Dalton’s law each gas in a mixture retains its own properties
unaffected by the presence of any other gas.[388] This law is probably
true only by approximation, but it is obvious that it would be true of
the perfect gas with infinitely distant particles.[389]

  [388] Joule and Thomson, *Philosophical Transactions*, 1854,
  vol. cxliv. p. 337.

  [389] The properties of a perfect gas have been described by Rankine,
  *Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh*, vol. xxv. p. 561.


*Mathematical Principles of Approximation.*

The approximate character of physical science will be rendered more
plain if we consider it from a mathematical point of view. Throughout
quantitative investigations we deal with the relation of one quantity
to other quantities, of which it is a function; but the subject is
sufficiently complicated if we view one quantity as a function of
one other. Now, as a general rule, a function can be developed or
expressed as the sum of quantities, the values of which depend upon the
successive powers of the variable quantity. If *y* be a function of *x*
then we may say that

  *y* = A + B*x* + C*x*^{2} + D*x*^{3} + E*x*^{4} ....

In this equation, A, B, C, D, &c., are fixed quantities, of different
values in different cases. The terms may be infinite in number or
after a time may cease to have any value. Any of the coefficients A,
B, C, &c., may be zero or negative; but whatever they be they are
fixed. The quantity *x* on the other hand may be made what we like,
being variable. Suppose, in the first place, that *x* and *y* are both
lengths. Let us assume that 1/10,000 part of an inch is the least that
we can take note of. Then when *x* is one hundredth of an inch, we have
*x*^{2} = 1/10,000, and if C be less than unity, the term C*x*^{2} will
be inappreciable, being less than we can measure. Unless any of the
quantities D, E, &c., should happen to be very great, it is evident
that all the succeeding terms will also be inappreciable, because the
powers of *x* become rapidly smaller in geometrical ratio. Thus when
*x* is made small enough the quantity *y* seems to obey the equation

  *y* = A + B*x*.

If *x* should be still less, if it should become as small, for
instance, as 1/1,000,000 of an inch, and B should not be very great,
then *y* would appear to be the fixed quantity A, and would not seem to
vary with *x* at all. On the other hand, were x to grow greater, say
equal to 1/10 inch, and C not be very small, the term C*x*^{2} would
become appreciable, and the law would now be more complicated.

We can invert the mode of viewing this question, and suppose that
while the quantity *y* undergoes variations depending on many powers
of *x*, our power of detecting the changes of value is more or less
acute. While our powers of observation remain very rude we may be
unable to detect any change in the quantity at all, that is to say,
B*x* may always be too small to come within our notice, just as in
former days the fixed stars were so called because they remained at
apparently fixed distances from each other. With the use of telescopes
and micrometers we become able to detect the existence of some motion,
so that the distance of one star from another may be expressed by
A + B*x*, the term including *x*^{2} being still inappreciable. Under
these circumstances the star will seem to move uniformly, or in simple
proportion to the time *x*. With much improved means of measurement it
will probably be found that this uniformity of motion is only apparent,
and that there exists some acceleration or retardation. More careful
investigation will show the law to be more and more complicated than
was previously supposed.

There is yet another way of explaining the apparent results of a
complicated law. If we take any curve and regard a portion of it free
from any kind of discontinuity, we may represent the character of such
portion by an equation of the form

  *y* = A + B*x* + C*x*^{2} + D*x*^{3} + ....

Restrict the attention to a very small portion of the curve, and the
eye will be unable to distinguish its difference from a straight
line, which amounts to saying that in the portion examined the term
C*x*^{2} has no value appreciable by the eye. Take a larger portion of
the curve and it will be apparent that it possesses curvature, but it
will be possible to draw a parabola or ellipse so that the curve shall
apparently coincide with a portion of that parabola or ellipse. In the
same way if we take larger and larger arcs of the curve it will assume
the character successively of a curve of the third, fourth, and perhaps
higher degrees; that is to say, it corresponds to equations involving
the third, fourth, and higher powers of the variable quantity.

We have arrived then at the conclusion that every phenomenon, when its
amount can only be rudely measured, will either be of fixed amount,
or will seem to vary uniformly like the distance between two inclined
straight lines. More exact measurement may show the error of this first
assumption, and the variation will then appear to be like that of the
distance between a straight line and a parabola or ellipse. We may
afterwards find that a curve of the third or higher degrees is really
required to represent the variation. I propose to call the variation
of a quantity *linear*, *elliptic*, *cubic*, *quartic*, *quintic*, &c.,
according as it is discovered to involve the first, second, third,
fourth, fifth, or higher powers of the variable. It is a general
rule in quantitative investigation that we commence by discovering
linear, and afterwards proceed to elliptic or more complicated laws of
variation. The approximate curves which we employ are all, according
to De Morgan’s use of the name, parabolas of some order or other; and
since the common parabola of the second order is approximately the same
as a very elongated ellipse, and is in fact an infinitely elongated
ellipse, it is convenient and proper to call variation of the second
order *elliptic*. It might also be called *quadric* variation.

As regards many important phenomena we are yet only in the first stage
of approximation. We know that the sun and many so-called fixed stars,
especially 61 Cygni, have a proper motion through space, and the
direction of this motion at the present time is known with some degree
of accuracy. But it is hardly consistent with the theory of gravity
that the path of any body should really be a straight line. Hence, we
must regard a rectilinear path as only a provisional description of
the motion, and look forward to the time when its curvature will be
detected, though centuries perhaps must first elapse.

We are accustomed to assume that on the surface of the earth the force
of gravity is uniform, because the variation is of so slight an amount
that we are scarcely able to detect it. But supposing we could measure
the variation, we should find it simply proportional to the height.
Taking the earth’s radius to be unity, let *h* be the height at which
we measure the force of gravity. Then by the well-known law of the
inverse square, that force will be proportional to

  *g*/(1 + *h*)^{2}, or to *g*(1 - 2*h* + 3*h*^{2} - 4*h*^{3} + ...).

But at all heights to which we can attain *h* will be so small a
fraction of the earth’s radius that 3*h*^{2} will be inappreciable, and
the force of gravity will seem to follow the law of linear variation,
being proportional to 1 - 2*h*.

When the circumstances of an experiment are much altered, different
powers of the variable may become prominent. The resistance of a liquid
to a body moving through it may be approximately expressed as the sum
of two terms respectively involving the first and second powers of the
velocity. At very low velocities the first power is of most importance,
and the resistance, as Professor Stokes has shown, is nearly in simple
proportion to the velocity. When the motion is rapid the resistance
increases in a still greater degree, and is more nearly proportional to
the square of the velocity.


*Approximate Independence of Small Effects.*

One result of the theory of approximation possesses such importance
in physical science, and is so often applied, that we may consider
it separately. The investigation of causes and effects is immensely
simplified when we may consider each cause as producing its own effect
invariably, whether other causes are acting or not. Thus, if the
body P produces *x*, and Q produces *y*, the question is whether P
and Q acting together will produce the sum of the separate effects,
*x* + *y*. It is under this supposition that we treated the methods of
eliminating error (Chap. XV.), and errors of a less amount would still
remain if the supposition was a forced one. There are probably some
parts of science in which the supposition of independence of effects
holds rigidly true. The mutual gravity of two bodies is entirely
unaffected by the presence of other gravitating bodies. People do not
usually consider that this important principle is involved in such a
simple thing as putting two pound weights in the scale of a balance.
How do we know that two pounds together will weigh twice as much as
one? Do we know it to be exactly so? Like other results founded on
induction we cannot prove it absolutely, but all the calculations of
physical astronomy proceed upon the assumption, so that we may consider
it proved to a very high degree of approximation. Had not this been
true, the calculations of physical astronomy would have been infinitely
more complex than they actually are, and the progress of knowledge
would have been much slower.

It is a general principle of scientific method that if effects be of
small amount, comparatively to our means of observation, all joint
effects will be of a higher order of smallness, and may therefore
be rejected in a first approximation. This principle was employed
by Daniel Bernoulli in the theory of sound, under the title of *The
Principle of the Coexistence of Small Vibrations*. He showed that if
a string is affected by two kinds of vibrations, we may consider each
to be going on as if the other did not exist. We cannot perceive that
the sounding of one musical instrument prevents or even modifies the
sound of another, so that all sounds would seem to travel through the
air, and act upon the ear in independence of each other. A similar
assumption is made in the theory of tides, which are great waves. One
wave is produced by the attraction of the moon, and another by the
attraction of the sun, and the question arises, whether when these
waves coincide, as at the time of spring tides, the joint wave will be
simply the sum of the separate waves. On the principle of Bernoulli
this will be so, because the tides on the ocean are very small compared
with the depth of the ocean.

The principle of Bernoulli, however, is only approximately true. A wave
never is exactly the same when another wave is interfering with it,
but the less the displacement of particles due to each wave, the less
in a still higher degree is the effect of one wave upon the other. In
recent years Helmholtz was led to suspect that some of the phenomena
of sound might after all be due to resultant effects overlooked by the
assumption of previous physicists. He investigated the secondary waves
which would arise from the interference of considerable disturbances,
and was able to show that certain summation of resultant tones ought to
be heard, and experiments subsequently devised for the purpose showed
that they might be heard.

[Illustration]

Throughout the mechanical sciences the *Principle of the Superposition
of Small Motions* is of fundamental importance,[390] and it may be
thus explained. Suppose that two forces, acting from the points B and
C, are simultaneously moving a body A. Let the force acting from B be
such that in one second it would move A to *p*, and similarly let the
second force, acting alone, move A to *r*. The question arises, then,
whether their joint action will urge A to *q* along the diagonal of the
parallelogram. May we say that A will move the distance A*p* in the
direction AB, and A*r* in the direction AC, or, what is the same thing,
along the parallel line *pq*? In strictness we cannot say so; for when
A has moved towards *p*, the force from C will no longer act along the
line AC, and similarly the motion of A towards *r* will modify the
action of the force from B. This interference of one force with the
line of action of the other will evidently be greater the larger is
the extent of motion considered; on the other hand, as we reduce the
parallelogram A*pqr*, compared with the distances AB and AC, the less
will be the interference of the forces. Accordingly mathematicians
avoid all error by considering the motions as infinitely small, so that
the interference becomes of a still higher order of infinite smallness,
and may be entirely neglected. By the resources of the differential
calculus it is possible to calculate the motion of the particle A, as
if it went through an infinite number of infinitely small diagonals
of parallelograms. The great discoveries of Newton really arose from
applying this method of calculation to the movements of the moon round
the earth, which, while constantly tending to move onward in a straight
line, is also deflected towards the earth by gravity, and moves
through an elliptic curve, composed as it were of the infinitely small
diagonals of infinitely numerous parallelograms. The mathematician,
in his investigation of a curve, always treats it as made up of a
great number of straight lines, and it may be doubted whether he could
treat it in any other manner. There is no error in the final results,
because having obtained the formulæ flowing from this supposition, each
straight line is then regarded as becoming infinitely small, and the
polygonal line becomes undistinguishable from a perfect curve.[391]

  [390] Thomson and Tait’s *Natural Philosophy*, vol. i. p. 60.

  [391] Challis, *Notes on the Principles of Pure and Applied
  Calculation*, 1869, p. 83.

In abstract mathematical theorems the approximation to absolute truth
is perfect, because we can treat of infinitesimals. In physical
science, on the contrary, we treat of the least quantities which are
perceptible. Nevertheless, while carefully distinguishing between these
two different cases, we may fearlessly apply to both the principle
of the superposition of small effects. In physical science we have
only to take care that the effects really are so small that any joint
effect will be unquestionably imperceptible. Suppose, for instance,
that there is some cause which alters the dimensions of a body in the
ratio of 1 to 1 + α, and another cause which produces an alteration in
the ratio of 1 to 1 + β. If they both act at once the change will be
in the ratio of 1 to (1 + α)(1 + β), or as 1 to 1 + α + β + αβ. But if
α and β be both very small fractions of the total dimensions, αβ will
be yet far smaller and may be disregarded; the ratio of change is then
approximately that of 1 to 1 + α + β, or the joint effect is the sum of
the separate effects. Thus if a body were subjected to three strains,
at right angles to each other, the total change in the volume of the
body would be approximately equal to the sum of the changes produced
by the separate strains, provided that these are very small. In like
manner not only is the expansion of every solid and liquid substance
by heat approximately proportional to the change of temperature, when
this change is very small in amount, but the cubic expansion may also
be considered as being three times as great as the linear expansion.
For if the increase of temperature expands a bar of metal in the ratio
of 1 to 1 + α, and the expansion be equal in all directions, then a
cube of the same metal would expand as 1 to (1 + α)^{3}, or as 1 to
1 + 3α + 3α^{2} + α^{3}. When α is a very small quantity the third term
3α^{2} will be imperceptible, and still more so the fourth term α^{3}.
The coefficients of expansion of solids are in fact so small, and so
imperfectly determined, that physicists seldom take into account their
second and higher powers.

It is a result of these principles that all small errors may be assumed
to vary in simple proportion to their causes--a new reason why, in
eliminating errors, we should first of all make them as small as
possible. Let us suppose that there is a right-angled triangle of which
the two sides containing the right angle are really of the lengths 3
and 4, so that the hypothenuse is √(3^{2} + 4^{2}) or 5. Now,
if in two measurements of the first side we commit slight errors,
making it successively 4·001 and 4·002, then calculation will give the
lengths of the hypothenuse as almost exactly 5·0008 and 5·0016, so that
the error in the hypothenuse will seem to vary in simple proportion
to that of the side, although it does not really do so with perfect
exactness. The logarithm of a number does not vary in proportion to
that number--nevertheless we find the difference between the logarithms
of the numbers 100000 and 100001 to be almost exactly equal to that
between the numbers 100001 and 100002. It is thus a general rule that
very small differences between successive values of a function are
approximately proportional to the small differences of the variable
quantity.

On these principles it is easy to draw up a series of rules such as
those given by Kohlrausch[392] for performing calculations in an
abbreviated form when the variable quantity is very small compared with
unity. Thus for 1 ÷ (1 + α) we may substitute 1 - α; for 1 ÷ (1 - α) we
may put 1 + α; 1 ÷ √(1 + α) becomes 1 - (1/2)α, and so forth.

  [392] *An Introduction to Physical Measurements*, translated by
  Waller and Procter, 1873, p. 10.


*Four Meanings of Equality.*

Although it might seem that there are few terms more free from
ambiguity than the term *equal*, yet scientific men do employ it with
at least four meanings, which it is desirable to distinguish. These
meanings I may describe as

  (1) Absolute Equality.
  (2) Sub-equality.
  (3) Apparent Equality.
  (4) Probable Equality.

By *absolute equality* we signify that which is complete and perfect
to the last degree; but it is obvious that we can only know such
equality in a theoretical or hypothetical manner. The areas of two
triangles standing upon the same base and between the same parallels
are absolutely equal. Hippocrates beautifully proved that the area
of a lunula or figure contained between two segments of circles was
absolutely equal to that of a certain right-angled triangle. As a
general rule all geometrical and other elementary mathematical theorems
involve absolute equality.

De Morgan proposed to describe as *sub-equal* those quantities which
are equal within an infinitely small quantity, so that *x* is sub-equal
to *x* + *dx*. The differential calculus may be said to arise out
of the neglect of infinitely small quantities, and in mathematical
science other subtle distinctions may have to be drawn between kinds of
equality, as De Morgan has shown in a remarkable memoir “On Infinity;
and on the sign of Equality.”[393]

  [393] *Cambridge Philosophical Transactions* (1865), vol. xi. Part I.

*Apparent equality* is that with which physical science deals. Those
magnitudes are apparently equal which differ only by an imperceptible
quantity. To the carpenter anything less than the hundredth part of
an inch is non-existent; there are few arts or artists to which the
hundred-thousandth of an inch is of any account. Since all coincidence
between physical magnitudes is judged by one or other sense, we must be
restricted to a knowledge of apparent equality.

In reality even apparent equality is rarely to be expected. More
commonly experiments will give only *probable equality*, that is
results will come so near to each other that the difference may be
ascribed to unimportant disturbing causes. Physicists often assume
quantities to be equal provided that they fall within the limits of
probable error of the processes employed. We cannot expect observations
to agree with theory more closely than they agree with each other, as
Newton remarked of his investigations concerning Halley’s Comet.


*Arithmetic of Approximate Quantities.*

Considering that almost all the quantities which we treat in physical
and social science are approximate only, it seems desirable that
attention should be paid in the teaching of arithmetic to the correct
interpretation and treatment of approximate numerical statements. We
seem to need notation for expressing the approximateness or exactness
of decimal numbers. The fraction ·025 may mean either precisely one
40th part, or it may mean anything between ·0245 and ·0255. I propose
that when a decimal fraction is completely and exactly given, a *small
cipher* or circle should be added to indicate that there is nothing
more to come, as in ·025◦. When the first figure of the decimals
rejected is 5 or more, the first figure retained should be raised by
a unit, according to a rule approved by De Morgan, and now generally
recognised. To indicate that the fraction thus retained is more than
the truth, a point has been placed over the last figure in some tables
of logarithms; but a similar point is used to denote the period of a
repeating decimal, and I should therefore propose to employ a colon
*after* the figure; thus ·025: would mean that the true quantity lies
between ·0245° and ·025° inclusive of the lower but not the higher
limit. When the fraction is less than the truth, two dots might be
placed horizontally as in 025.. which would mean anything between ·025°
and ·0255° not inclusive.

When approximate numbers are added, subtracted, multiplied, or divided,
it becomes a matter of some complexity to determine the degree of
accuracy of the result. There are few persons who could assert off-hand
that the sum of the approximate numbers 34·70, 52·693, 80·1, is 167·5
*within less than* ·07. Mr. Sandeman has traced out the rules of
approximate arithmetic in a very thorough manner, and his directions
are worthy of careful attention.[394] The third part of Sonnenschein
and Nesbitt’s excellent book on arithmetic[395] describes fully all
kinds of approximate calculations, and shows both how to avoid needless
labour and how to take proper account of inaccuracy in operating with
approximate decimal fractions. A simple investigation of the subject is
to be found in Sonnet’s *Algèbre Elémentaire* (Paris, 1848) chap. xiv.,
“Des Approximations Absolues et Relatives.” There is also an American
work on the subject.[396]

  [394] Sandeman, *Pelicotetics*, p. 214.

  [395] *The Science and Art of Arithmetic for the Use of Schools.*
  (Whitaker and Co.)

  [396] *Principles of Approximate Calculations*, by J. J. Skinner,
  C.E. (New York, Henry Holt), 1876.

Although the accuracy of measurement has so much advanced since the
time of Leslie, it is not superfluous to repeat his protest against
the unfairness of affecting by a display of decimal fractions a
greater degree of accuracy than the nature of the case requires and
admits.[397] I have known a scientific man to register the barometer
to a second of time when the nearest quarter of an hour would have
been amply sufficient. Chemists often publish results of analysis to
the ten-thousandth or even the millionth part of the whole, when in
all probability the processes employed cannot be depended on beyond
the hundredth part. It is seldom desirable to give more than one
place of figures of uncertain amount; but it must be allowed that a
nice perception of the degree of accuracy possible and desirable is
requisite to save misapprehension and needless computation on the one
hand, and to secure all attainable exactness on the other hand.

  [397] Leslie, *Inquiry into the Nature of Heat*, p. 505.




CHAPTER XXII.

QUANTITATIVE INDUCTION.


We have not yet formally considered any processes of reasoning
which have for their object to disclose laws of nature expressed in
quantitative equations. We have been inquiring into the modes by which
a phenomenon may be measured, and, if it be a composite phenomenon, may
be resolved, by the aid of several measurements, into its component
parts. We have also considered the precautions to be taken in the
performance of observations and experiments in order that we may know
what phenomena we really do measure, but we must remember that, no
number of facts and observations can by themselves constitute science.
Numerical facts, like other facts, are but the raw materials of
knowledge, upon which our reasoning faculties must be exerted in order
to draw forth the principles of nature. It is by an inverse process of
reasoning that we can alone discover the mathematical laws to which
varying quantities conform. By well-conducted experiments we gain a
series of values of a variable, and a corresponding series of values
of a variant, and we now want to know what mathematical function the
variant is as regards the variable. In the usual progress of a science
three questions will have to be answered as regards every important
quantitative phenomenon:--

(1) Is there any constant relation between a variable and a variant?

(2) What is the empirical formula expressing this relation?

(3) What is the rational formula expressing the law of nature involved?


*Probable Connection of Varying Quantities.*

We find it stated by Mill,[398] that “Whatever phenomenon varies in any
manner whenever another phenomenon varies in some particular manner, is
either a cause or an effect of that phenomenon, or is connected with
it through some fact of causation.” This assertion may be considered
true when it is interpreted with sufficient caution; but it might
otherwise lead us into error. There is nothing whatever in the nature
of things to prevent the existence of two variations which should
apparently follow the same law, and yet have no connection with each
other. One binary star might be going through a revolution which, so
far as we could tell, was of equal period with that of another binary
star, and according to the above rule the motion of one would be the
cause of the motion of the other, which would not be really the case.
Two astronomical clocks might conceivably be made so nearly perfect
that, for several years, no difference could be detected, and we might
then infer that the motion of one clock was the cause or effect of the
motion of the other. This matter requires careful discrimination. We
must bear in mind that the continuous quantities of space, time, force,
&c., which we measure, are made up of an infinite number of infinitely
small units. We may then meet with two variable phenomena which follow
laws so nearly the same, that in no part of the variations open to
our observation can any discrepancy be discovered. I grant that if
two clocks could be shown to have kept *exactly* the same time during
any finite interval, the probability would become infinitely high
that there was a connection between their motions. But we can never
absolutely prove such coincidences to exist. Allow that we may observe
a difference of one-tenth of a second in their time, yet it is possible
that they were independently regulated so as to go together within
less than that quantity of time. In short, it would require either an
infinitely long time of observation, or infinitely acute powers of
measuring discrepancy, to decide positively whether two clocks were or
were not in relation with each other.

  [398] *System of Logic*, bk. iii. chap. viii § 6.

A similar question actually occurs in the case of the moon’s motion. We
have no record that any other portion of the moon was ever visible to
men than such as we now see. This fact sufficiently proves that within
the historical period the rotation of the moon on its own axis has
coincided with its revolutions round the earth. Does this coincidence
prove a relation of cause and effect to exist? The answer must be in
the negative, because there might have been so slight a discrepancy
between the motions that there has not yet been time to produce any
appreciable effect. There may nevertheless be a high probability of
connection.

The whole question of the relation of quantities thus resolves itself
into one of probability. When we can only rudely measure a quantitative
result, we can assign but slight importance to any correspondence.
Because the brightness of two stars seems to vary in the same manner,
there is no considerable probability that they have any relation with
each other. Could it be shown that their periods of variation were
the same to infinitely small quantities it would be certain, that
is infinitely probable, that they were connected, however unlikely
this might be on other grounds. The general mode of estimating such
probabilities is identical with that applied to other inductive
problems. That any two periods of variation should by chance become
*absolutely equal* is infinitely improbable; hence if, in the case of
the moon or other moving bodies, we could prove absolute coincidence
we should have certainty of connection.[399] With approximate
measurements, which alone are within our power, we must hope for
approximate certainty at the most.

  [399] Laplace, *System of the World*, translated by Harte, vol. ii.
  p. 366.

The principles of inference and probability, according to which we
treat causes and effects varying in amount, are exactly the same as
those by which we treated simple experiments. Continuous quantity,
however, affords us an infinitely more extensive sphere of observation,
because every different amount of cause, however little different,
ought to be followed by a different amount of effect. If we can measure
temperature to the one-hundredth part of a degree centigrade, then
between 0° and 100° we have 10,000 possible trials. If the precision
of our measurements is increased, so that the one-thousandth part of
a degree can be appreciated, our trials may be increased tenfold. The
probability of connection will be proportional to the accuracy of our
measurements.

When we can vary the quantity of a cause at will it is easy to discover
whether a certain effect is due to that cause or not. We can then
make as many irregular changes as we like, and it is quite incredible
that the supposed effect should by chance go through exactly the
corresponding series of changes except by dependence. If we have a
bell ringing *in vacuo*, the sound increases as we let in the air, and
it decreases again as we exhaust the air. Tyndall’s singing flames
evidently obeyed the directions of his own voice; and Faraday when he
discovered the relation of magnetism and light found that, by making
or breaking or reversing the current of the electro-magnet, he had
complete command over a ray of light, proving beyond all reasonable
doubt the dependence of cause and effect. In such cases it is the
perfect coincidence in time between the change in the effect and that
in the cause which raises a high improbability of casual coincidence.

It is by a simple case of variation that we infer the existence of
a material connection between two bodies moving with exactly equal
velocity, such as the locomotive engine and the train which follows
it. Elaborate observations were requisite before astronomers could all
be convinced that the red hydrogen flames seen during solar eclipses
belonged to the sun, and not to the moon’s atmosphere as Flamsteed
assumed. As early as 1706, Stannyan noticed a blood-red streak in
an eclipse which he witnessed at Berne, and he asserted that it
belonged to the sun; but his opinion was not finally established until
photographs of the eclipse in 1860, taken by Mr. De la Rue, showed that
the moon’s dark body gradually covered the red prominences on one side,
and uncovered those on the other; in short, that these prominences
moved precisely as the sun moved, and not as the moon moved.

Even when we have no means of accurately measuring the variable
quantities we may yet be convinced of their connection, if one always
varies perceptibly at the same time as the other. Fatigue increases
with exertion; hunger with abstinence from food; desire and degree of
utility decrease with the quantity of commodity consumed. We know that
the sun’s heating power depends upon his height of the sky; that the
temperature of the air falls in ascending a mountain; that the earth’s
crust is found to be perceptibly warmer as we sink mines into it; we
infer the direction in which a sound comes from the change of loudness
as we approach or recede. The facility with which we can time after
time observe the increase or decrease of one quantity with another
sufficiently shows the connection, although we may be unable to assign
any precise law of relation. The probability in such cases depends upon
frequent coincidence in time.


*Empirical Mathematical Laws.*

It is important to acquire a clear comprehension of the part which
is played in scientific investigation by empirical formulæ and laws.
If we have a table containing certain values of a variable and the
corresponding values of the variant, there are mathematical processes
by which we can infallibly discover a mathematical formula yielding
numbers in more or less exact agreement with the table. We may
generally assume that the quantities will approximately conform to a
law of the form

  *y* = A + B*x* + C*x*^{2},

in which *x* is the variable and *y* the variant. We can then select
from the table three values of *y*, and the corresponding values of
*x*; inserting them in the equation, we obtain three equations by the
solution of which we gain the values of A, B, and C. It will be found
as a general rule that the formula thus obtained yields the other
numbers of the table to a considerable degree of approximation.

In many cases even the second power of the variable will be
unnecessary; Regnault found that the results of his elaborate inquiry
into the latent heat of steam at different pressures were represented
with sufficient accuracy by the empirical formula

  λ = 606·5 + 0·305 *t*,

in which λ is the total heat of the steam, and *t* the
temperature.[400] In other cases it may be requisite to include the
third power of the variable. Thus physicists assume the law of the
dilatation of liquids to be of the form

  δ_{t} = *at* + *bt*^{2} + *ct*^{3},

  [400] *Chemical Reports and Memoirs*, Cavendish Society, p. 294.

and they calculate from results of observation the values of the
three constants *a*, *b*, *c*, which are usually small quantities
not exceeding one-hundredth part of a unit, but requiring to be
determined with great accuracy.[401] Theoretically speaking, this
process of empirical representation might be applied with any degree of
accuracy; we might include still higher powers in the formula, and with
sufficient labour obtain the values of the constants, by using an equal
number of experimental results. The method of least squares may also be
employed to obtain the most probable values of the constants.

  [401] Jamin, *Cours de Physique*, vol. ii. p. 38.

In a similar manner all periodic variations may be represented with any
required degree of accuracy by formulæ involving the sines and cosines
of angles and their multiples. The form of any tidal or other wave may
thus be expressed, as Sir G. B. Airy has explained.[402] Almost all
the phenomena registered by meteorologists are periodic in character,
and when freed from disturbing causes may be embodied in empirical
formulæ. Bessel has given a rule by which from any regular series of
observations we may, on the principle of the method of least squares,
calculate out with a moderate amount of labour a formula expressing the
variation of the quantity observed, in the most probable manner. In
meteorology three or four terms are usually sufficient for representing
any periodic phenomenon, but the calculation might be carried to any
higher degree of accuracy. As the details of the process have been
described by Herschel in his treatise on Meteorology,[403] I need not
further enter into them.

  [402] *On Tides and Waves*, Encyclopædia Metropolitana, p. 366*.

  [403] *Encyclopædia Britannica*, art. *Meteorology*. Reprint, §§
  152–156.

The reader might be tempted to think that in these processes of
calculation we have an infallible method of discovering inductive
laws, and that my previous statements (Chap. VII.) as to the purely
tentative and inverse character of the inductive process are negatived.
Were there indeed any general method of inferring laws from facts it
would overturn my statement, but it must be carefully observed that
these empirical formulæ do not coincide with natural laws. They are
only approximations to the results of natural laws founded upon the
general principles of approximation. It has already been pointed out
that however complicated be the nature of a curve, we may examine so
small a portion of it, or we may examine it with such rude means of
measurement, that its divergence from an elliptic curve will not be
apparent. As a still ruder approximation a portion of a straight line
will always serve our purpose; but if we need higher precision a curve
of the third or fourth degree will almost certainly be sufficient. Now
empirical formulæ really represent these approximate curves, but they
give us no information as to the precise nature of the curve itself to
which we are approximating. We do not learn what function the variant
is of the variable, but we obtain another function which, within the
bounds of observation, gives nearly the same values.


*Discovery of Rational Formulæ.*

Let us now proceed to consider the modes in which from numerical
results we can establish the actual relation between the quantity of
the cause and that of the effect. What we want is a *rational* formula
or function, which will exhibit the *reason* or exact nature and
origin of the law in question. There is no word more frequently used
by mathematicians than the word *function*, and yet it is difficult
to define its meaning with perfect accuracy. Originally it meant
performance or execution, being equivalent to the Greek λειτουργία
or τέλεσμα. Mathematicians at first used it to mean *any power of a
quantity*, but afterwards generalised it so as to include “any quantity
formed in any manner whatsoever from another quantity.”[404] Any
quantity, then, which depends upon and varies with another quantity may
be called a function of it, and either may be considered a function of
the other.

  [404] Lagrange, *Leçons sur le Calcul des Fonctions*, 1806, p. 4.

Given the quantities, we want the function of which they are the
values. Simple inspection of the numbers cannot as a general rule
disclose the function. In an earlier chapter (p. 124) I put before the
reader certain numbers, and requested him to point out the law which
they obey, and the same question will have to be asked in every case of
quantitative induction. There are perhaps three methods, more or less
distinct, by which we may hope to obtain an answer:

(1) By purely haphazard trial.

(2) By noting the general character of the variation of the quantities,
and trying by preference functions which give a similar form of
variation.

(3) By deducing from previous knowledge the form of the function which
is most likely to suit.

Having numerical results we are always at liberty to invent any kind
of mathematical formula we like, and then try whether, by the suitable
selection of values for the unknown constant quantities, we can make it
give the required results. If ever we fall upon a formula which does
so, to a fair degree of approximation, there is a presumption in favour
of its being the true function, although there is no certainty whatever
in the matter. In this way I discovered a simple mathematical law which
closely agreed with the results of my experiments on muscular exertion.
This law was afterwards shown by Professor Haughton to be the true
rational law according to his theory of muscular action.[405]

  [405] Haughton, *Principles of Animal Mechanics*, 1873, pp. 444–450.
  Jevons, *Nature*, 30th of June, 1870, vol. ii. p. 158. See also the
  experiments of Professor Nipher, of Washington University, St. Louis,
  in *American Journal of Science*, vol. ix. p. 130, vol. x. p. 1;
  *Nature*, vol. xi. pp. 256, 276.

But the chance of succeeding in this manner is small. The number of
possible functions is infinite, and even the number of comparatively
simple functions is so large that the probability of falling upon the
correct one by mere chance is very slight. Even when we obtain the law
it is by a deductive process, not by showing that the numbers give the
law, but that the law gives the numbers.

In the second way, we may, by a survey of the numbers, gain a general
notion of the kind of law they are likely to obey, and we may be much
assisted in this process by drawing them out in the form of a curve.
We can in this way ascertain with some probability whether the curve
is likely to return into itself, or whether it has infinite branches;
whether such branches are asymptotic, that is, approach infinitely
towards straight lines; whether it is logarithmic in character, or
trigonometric. This indeed we can only do if we remember the results of
previous investigations. The process is still inversely deductive, and
consists in noting what laws give particular curves, and then inferring
inversely that such curves belong to such laws. If we can in this way
discover the class of functions to which the required law belongs,
our chances of success are much increased, because our haphazard
trials are now reduced within a narrower sphere. But, unless we have
almost the whole curve before us, the identification of its character
must be a matter of great uncertainty; and if, as in most physical
investigations, we have a mere fragment of the curve, the assistance
given would be quite illusory. Curves of almost any character can be
made to approximate to each other for a limited extent, so that it is
only by a kind of *divination* that we fall upon the actual function,
unless we have theoretical knowledge of the kind of function applicable
to the case.

When we have once obtained what we believe to be the correct form of
function, the remainder of the work is mere mathematical computation to
be performed infallibly according to fixed rules,[406] which include
those employed in the determination of empirical formulæ (p. 487).
The function will involve two or three or more unknown constants, the
values of which we need to determine by our experimental results.
Selecting some of our results widely apart and nearly equidistant,
we form by means of them as many equations as there are constant
quantities to be determined. The solution of these equations will then
give us the constants required, and having now the actual function we
can try whether it gives with sufficient accuracy the remainder of
our experimental results. If not, we must either make a new selection
of results to give a new set of equations, and thus obtain a new set
of values for the constants, or we must acknowledge that our form
of function has been wrongly chosen. If it appears that the form of
function has been correctly ascertained, we may regard the constants
as only approximately accurate and may proceed by the Method of Least
Squares (p. 393) to determine the most probable values as given by the
whole of the experimental results.

  [406] Jamin, *Cours de Physique*, vol. ii. p. 50.

In most cases we shall find ourselves obliged to fall back upon the
third mode, that is, anticipation of the form of the law to be expected
on the ground of previous knowledge. Theory and analogical reasoning
must be our guides. The general nature of the phenomenon will often
indicate the kind of law to be looked for. If one form of energy or one
kind of substance is being converted into another, we may expect the
law of direct simple proportion. In one distinct class of cases the
effect already produced influences the amount of the ensuing effect,
as for instance in the cooling of a heated body, when the law will be
of an exponential form. When the direction of a force influences its
action, trigonometrical functions enter. Any influence which spreads
freely through tridimensional space will be subject to the law of
the inverse square of the distance. From such considerations we may
sometimes arrive deductively and analogically at the general nature of
the mathematical law required.


*The Graphical Method.*

In endeavouring to discover the mathematical law obeyed by
experimental results it is often desirable to call in the aid of
space-representations. Every equation involving two variable quantities
corresponds to some kind of plane curve, and every plane curve may
be represented symbolically in an equation containing two unknown
quantities. Now in an experimental research we obtain a number of
values of the variant corresponding to an equal number of values of the
variable; but all the numbers are affected by more or less error, and
the values of the variable will often be irregularly disposed. Even if
the numbers were absolutely correct and disposed at regular intervals,
there is, as we have seen, no direct mode of discovering the law, but
the difficulty of discovery is much increased by the uncertainty and
irregularity of the results.

Under such circumstances, the best mode of proceeding is to prepare a
paper divided into equal rectangular spaces, a convenient size for the
spaces being one-tenth of an inch square. The values of the variable
being marked off on the lowest horizontal line, a point is marked for
each corresponding value of the variant perpendicularly above that of
the variable, and at such a height as corresponds to the value of the
variant.

The exact scale of the drawing is not of much importance, but it may
require to be adjusted according to circumstances, and different values
must often be attributed to the upright and horizontal divisions, so
as to make the variations conspicuous but not excessive. If a curved
line be drawn through all the points or ends of the ordinates, it will
probably exhibit irregular inflections, owing to the errors which
affect the numbers. But, when the results are numerous, it becomes
apparent which results are more divergent than others, and guided by a
so-called *sense of continuity*, it is possible to trace a line among
the points which will approximate to the true law more nearly than the
points themselves. The accompanying figure sufficiently explains itself.

[Illustration]

Perkins employed this graphical method with much care in exhibiting
the results of his experiments on the compression of water.[407] The
numerical results were marked upon a sheet of paper very exactly ruled
at intervals of one-tenth of an inch, and the original marks were left
in order that the reader might judge of the correctness of the curve
drawn, or choose another for himself. Regnault carried the method to
perfection by laying off the points with a screw dividing engine;[408]
and he then formed a table of results by drawing a continuous curve,
and measuring its height for equidistant values of the variable. Not
only does a curve drawn in this manner enable us to infer numerical
results more free from accidental errors than any of the numbers
obtained directly from experiment, but the form of the curve sometimes
indicates the class of functions to which our results belong.

  [407] *Philosophical Transactions*, 1826, p. 544.

  [408] Jamin, *Cours de Physique*, vol. ii. p. 24, &c.

Engraved sheets of paper prepared for the drawing of curves may be
obtained from Mr. Stanford at Charing Cross, Messrs. W. and A. K.
Johnston, of London and Edinburgh, Waterlow and Sons, Letts and Co.,
and probably other publishers. When we do not require great accuracy,
paper ruled by the common machine-ruler into equal squares of about
one-fifth or one-sixth of an inch square will serve well enough. I
have met with engineers’ and surveyors’ memorandum books ruled with
one-twelfth inch squares. When a number of curves have to be drawn, I
have found it best to rule a good sheet of drawing paper with lines
carefully adjusted at the most convenient distances, and then to
prick the points of the curve through it upon another sheet fixed
underneath. In this way we obtain an accurate curve upon a blank sheet,
and need only introduce such division lines as are requisite to the
understanding of the curve.

In some cases our numerical results will correspond, not to the
height of single ordinates, but to the area of the curve between two
ordinates, or the average height of ordinates between certain limits.
If we measure, for instance, the quantities of heat absorbed by water
when raised in temperature from 0° to 5°, from 5° to 10°, and so on,
these quantities will really be represented by *areas* of the curve
denoting the specific heat of water; and since the specific heat varies
continuously between every two points of temperature, we shall not get
the correct curve by simply laying off the quantities of heat at the
mean temperatures, namely 2-1/2°, and 7-1/2°, and so on. Lord Rayleigh
has shown that if we have drawn such an incorrect curve, we can with
little trouble correct it by a simple geometrical process, and obtain
to a close approximation the true ordinates instead of those denoting
areas.[409]

  [409] J. W. Strutt, *On a correction sometimes required in curves
  professing to represent the connexion between two physical
  magnitudes*. Philosophical Magazine, 4th Series, vol. xlii. p. 441.


*Interpolation and Extrapolation.*

When we have by experiment obtained two or more numerical results,
and endeavour, without further experiment, to calculate intermediate
results, we are said to *interpolate*. If we wish to assign by
reasoning results lying beyond the limits of experiment, we may be
said, using an expression of Sir George Airy, to *extrapolate*. These
two operations are the same in principle, but differ in practicability.
It is a matter of great scientific importance to apprehend precisely
how far we can practise interpolation or extrapolation, and on what
grounds we proceed.

In the first place, if the interpolation is to be more than empirical,
we must have not only the experimental results, but the laws which they
obey--we must in fact go through the complete process of scientific
investigation. Having discovered the laws of nature applying to the
case, and verified them by showing that they agree with the experiments
in question, we are then in a position to anticipate the results of
similar experiments. Our knowledge even now is not certain, because we
cannot completely prove the truth of any assumed law, and we cannot
possibly exhaust all the circumstances which may affect the result. At
the best then our interpolations will partake of the want of certainty
and precision attaching to all our knowledge of nature. Yet, having the
supposed laws, our results will be as sure and accurate as any we can
attain to. But such a complete procedure is more than we commonly mean
by interpolation, which usually denotes some method of estimating in a
merely approximate manner the results which might have been expected
independently of a theoretical investigation.

Regarded in this light, interpolation is in reality an indeterminate
problem. From given values of a function it is impossible to determine
that function; for we can invent an infinite number of functions which
will give those values if we are not restricted by any conditions, just
as through a given series of points we can draw an infinite number of
curves, if we may diverge between or beyond the points into bends and
cusps as we think fit.[410] In interpolation we must in fact be guided
more or less by *à priori* considerations; we must know, for instance,
whether or not periodical fluctuations are to be expected. Supposing
that the phenomenon is non-periodic, we proceed to assume that the
function can be expressed in a limited series of the powers of the
variable. The number of powers which can be included depends upon the
number of experimental results available, and must be at least one less
than this number. By processes of calculation, which have been already
alluded to in the section on empirical formulæ, we then calculate the
coefficients of the powers, and obtain an empirical formula which will
give the required intermediate results. In reality, then, we return
to the methods treated under the head of approximation and empirical
formulæ; and interpolation, as commonly understood, consists in
assuming that a curve of simple character is to pass through certain
determined points. If we have, for instance, two experimental results,
and only two, we assume that the curve is a straight line; for the
parabolas which can be passed through two points are infinitely various
in magnitude, and quite indeterminate. One straight line alone can
pass through two points, and it will have an equation of the form,
*y* = *mx* + *n*, the constant quantities of which can be determined
from two results. Thus, if the two values for *x*, 7 and 11, give
the values for *y*, 35 and 53, the solution of two equations gives
*y* = 4·5 × *x* + 3·5 as the equation, and for any other value of *x*,
for instance 10, we get a value of *y*, that is 48·5. When we take a
mean value of *x*, namely 9, this process yields a simple mean result,
namely 44. Three experimental results being given, we assume that they
fall upon a portion of a parabola and algebraic calculation gives the
position of any intermediate point upon the parabola. Concerning the
process of interpolation as practised in the science of meteorology
the reader will find some directions in the French edition of Kaëmtz’s
Meteorology.[411]

  [410] Herschel: Lacroix’ *Differential Calculus*, p. 551.

  [411] *Cours complet de Météorologie*, Note A, p. 449.

When we have, either by direct experiment or by the use of a curve,
a series of values of the variant for equidistant values of the
variable, it is instructive to take the differences between each
value of the variant and the next, and then the differences between
those differences, and so on. If any series of differences approaches
closely to zero it is an indication that the numbers may be correctly
represented by a finite empirical formula; if the *n*th differences
are zero, then the formula will contain only the first *n* - 1 powers
of the variable. Indeed we may sometimes obtain by the calculus of
differences a correct empirical formula; for if *p* be the first term
of the series of values, and Δ*p*, Δ^{2}*p*, Δ^{3}*p*, be the first
number in each column of differences, then the *m*th term of the series
of values will be

  *p* + *m*Δ*p* + *m*[(*m* - 1)/2]Δ^{2}*p* +
  *m*[(*m* - 1)/2][(*m* - 2)/3]Δ^{3}*p* + &c.

A closely equivalent but more practicable formula for interpolation
by differences, as devised by Lagrange, will be found in Thomson and
Tait’s *Elements of Natural Philosophy*, p. 115.

If no column of differences shows any tendency to become zero
throughout, it is an indication that the law is of a more complicated,
for instance of an exponential character, so that it requires different
treatment. Dr. J. Hopkinson has suggested a method of arithmetical
interpolation,[412] which is intended to avoid much that is arbitrary
in the graphical method. His process will yield the same results in all
hands.

  [412] *On the Calculation of Empirical Formulæ. The Messenger of
  Mathematics*, New Series, No. 17, 1872.

So far as we can infer the results likely to be obtained by variations
beyond the limits of experiment, we must proceed upon the same
principles. If possible we must detect the exact laws in action,
and then trust to them as a guide when we have no experience. If
not, an empirical formula of the same character as those employed in
interpolation is our only resource. But to extend our inference far
beyond the limits of experience is exceedingly unsafe. Our knowledge is
at the best only approximate, and takes no account of small tendencies.
Now it usually happens that tendencies small within our limits of
observation become perceptible or great under extreme circumstances.
When the variable in our empirical formula is small, we are justified
in overlooking the higher powers, and taking only two or three lower
powers. But as the variable increases, the higher powers gain in
importance, and in time yield the principal part of the value of the
function.

This is no mere theoretical inference. Excepting the few primary
laws of nature, such as the law of gravity, of the conservation of
energy, &c., there is hardly any natural law which we can trust in
circumstances widely different from those with which we are practically
acquainted. From the expansion or contraction, fusion or vaporisation
of substances by heat at the surface of the earth, we can form a most
imperfect notion of what would happen near the centre of the earth,
where the pressure almost infinitely exceeds anything possible in our
experiments. The physics of the earth give us a feeble, and probably a
misleading, notion of a body like the sun, in which an inconceivably
high temperature is united with an inconceivably high pressure. If
there are in the realms of space nebulæ consisting of incandescent
and unoxidised vapours of metals and other elements, so highly heated
perhaps that chemical composition is out of the question, we are
hardly able to treat them as subjects of scientific inference. Hence
arises the great importance of experiments in which we investigate the
properties of substances under extreme circumstances of cold or heat,
density or rarity, intense electric excitation, &c. This insecurity
in extending our inferences arises from the approximate character
of our measurements. Had we the power of appreciating infinitely
small quantities, we should by the principle of continuity discover
some trace of every change which a substance could undergo under
unattainable circumstances. By observing, for instance, the tension of
aqueous vapour between 0° and 100° C., we ought theoretically to be
able to infer its tension at every other temperature; but this is out
of the question practically because we cannot really ascertain the law
precisely between those temperatures.

Many instances might be given to show that laws which appear to
represent correctly the results of experiments within certain limits
altogether fail beyond those limits. The experiments of Roscoe and
Dittmar, on the absorption of gases in water[413] afford interesting
illustrations, especially in the case of hydrochloric acid, the
quantity of which dissolved in water under different pressures
follows very closely a linear law of variation, from which however it
diverges widely at low pressures.[414] Herschel, having deduced from
observations of the double star γ Virginis an elliptic orbit for the
motion of one component round the centre of gravity of both, found that
for a time the motion of the star agreed very well with this orbit.
Nevertheless divergence began to appear and after a time became so
great that an entirely new orbit, of more than double the dimensions of
the old one, had ultimately to be adopted.[415]

  [413] Watts’ *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. ii. p. 790.

  [414] *Quarterly Journal of the Chemical Society*, vol. viii. p. 15.

  [415] *Results of Observations at the Cape of Good Hope*, p. 293.


*Illustrations of Empirical Quantitative Laws.*

Although our object in quantitative inquiry is to discover the exact or
rational formulæ, expressing the laws which apply to the subject, it
is instructive to observe in how many important branches of science,
no precise laws have yet been detected. The tension of aqueous vapour
at different temperatures has been determined by a succession of
eminent experimentalists--Dalton, Kaëmtz, Dulong, Arago, Magnus, and
Regnault--and by the last mentioned the measurements were conducted
with extraordinary care. Yet no incontestable general law has been
established. Several functions have been proposed to express the
elastic force of the vapour as depending on the temperature. The first
form is that of Young, namely F = (*a* + *b t*)^{m}, in which *a*,
*b*, and *m* are unknown quantities to be determined by observation.
Roche proposed, on theoretical grounds, a complicated formula of an
exponential form, and a third form of function is that of Biot,[416] as
follows--log F = *a* + *b*α^{t} + *c*β^{t}. I mention these formulæ,
because they well illustrate the feeble powers of empirical inquiry.
None of the formulæ can be made to correspond closely with experimental
results, and the two last forms correspond almost equally well. There
is very little probability that the real law has been reached, and
it is unlikely that it will be discovered except by deduction from
mechanical theory.

  [416] Jamin, *Cours de Physique*, vol. ii. p. 138.

Much ingenious labour has been spent upon the discovery of some general
law of atmospheric refraction. Tycho Brahe and Kepler commenced the
inquiry: Cassini first formed a table of refractions, calculated on
theoretical grounds: Newton entered into some profound investigations
upon the subject: Brooke Taylor, Bouguer, Simpson, Bradley, Mayer,
and Kramp successively attacked the question, which is of the highest
practical importance as regards the correction of astronomical
observations. Laplace next laboured on the subject without exhausting
it, and Brinkley and Ivory have also treated it. The true law is
yet undiscovered. A closely connected problem, that regarding the
relation between the pressure and elevation in different strata of
the atmosphere, has received the attention of a long succession of
physicists and was most carefully investigated by Laplace. Yet no
invariable and general law has been detected. The same may be said
concerning the law of human mortality; abundant statistics on this
subject are available, and many hypotheses more or less satisfactory
have been put forward as to the form of the curve of mortality, but it
seems to be impossible to discover more than an approximate law.

It may perhaps be urged that in such subjects no single invariable
law can be expected. The atmosphere may be divided into several
variable strata which by their unconnected changes frustrate the exact
calculations of astronomers. Human life may be subject at different
ages to a succession of different influences incapable of reduction
under any one law. The results observed may in fact be aggregates of an
immense number of separate results each governed by its own separate
laws, so that the subjects may be complicated beyond the possibility of
complete resolution by empirical methods. This is certainly true of the
mathematical functions which must some time or other be introduced into
the science of political economy.


*Simple Proportional Variation.*

When we first treat numerical results in any novel kind of
investigation, our impression will probably be that one quantity
varies in *simple proportion* to another, so as to obey the law
*y* = *mx* + *n*. We must learn to distinguish carefully between the
cases where this proportionality is really, and where it is only
apparently true. In considering the principles of approximation we
found that a small portion of any curve will appear to be a straight
line. When our modes of measurement are comparatively rude, we must
expect to be unable to detect the curvature. Kepler made meritorious
attempts to discover the law of refraction, and he approximated to it
when he observed that the angles of incidence and refraction *if small*
bear a constant ratio to each other. Angles when small are nearly as
their sines, so that he reached an approximate result of the true law.
Cardan assumed, probably as a mere guess, that the force required to
sustain a body on an inclined plane was simply proportional to the
angle of elevation of the plane. This is approximately the case when
the angle is small, but in reality the law is much more complicated,
the power required being proportional to the sine of the angle. The
early thermometer-makers were unaware whether the expansion of mercury
was proportional or not to the heat communicated to it, and it is only
in the present century that we have learnt it to be not so. We now
know that even gases obey the law of uniform expansion by heat only
in an approximate manner. Until reason to the contrary is shown, we
should do well to look upon every law of simple proportion as only
provisionally true.

Nevertheless many important laws of nature are in the form of simple
proportions. Wherever a cause acts in independence of its previous
effects, we may expect this relation. An accelerating force acts
equally upon a moving and a motionless body. Hence the velocity
produced is in simple proportion to the force, and to the duration of
its uniform action. As gravitating bodies never interfere with each
other’s gravity, this force is in direct simple proportion to the
mass of each of the attracting bodies, the mass being measured by, or
proportional to inertia. Similarly, in all cases of “direct unimpeded
action,” as Herschel has remarked,[417] we may expect simple proportion
to manifest itself. In such cases the equation expressing the relation
may have the simple form *y* = *mx*.

  [417] *Preliminary Discourse*, &c., p. 152.

A similar relation holds true when there is conversion of one substance
or form of energy into another. The quantity of a compound is equal
to the quantity of the elements which combine. The heat produced in
friction is exactly proportional to the mechanical energy absorbed.
It was experimentally proved by Faraday that “the chemical power of
the current of electricity is in direct proportion to the quantity of
electricity which passes.” When an electric current is produced, the
quantity of electric energy is simply proportional to the weight of
metal dissolved. If electricity is turned into heat, there is again
simple proportion. Wherever, in fact, one thing is but another thing
with a new aspect, we may expect to find the law of simple proportion.
But it is only in the most elementary cases that this simple relation
will hold true. Simple conditions do not, generally speaking, produce
simple results. The planets move in approximate circles round the sun,
but the apparent motions, as seen from the earth, are very various. All
those motions, again, are summed up in the law of gravity, of no great
complexity; yet men never have been, and never will be, able to exhaust
the complications of action and reaction arising from that law, even
among a small number of planets. We should be on our guard against a
tendency to assume that the connection of cause and effect is one of
direct proportion. Bacon reminds us of the woman in Æsop’s fable, who
expected that her hen, with a double measure of barley, would lay two
eggs a day instead of one, whereas it grew fat, and ceased to lay any
eggs at all. It is a wise maxim that the half is often better than the
whole.




CHAPTER XXIII.

THE USE OF HYPOTHESIS.


If the views upheld in this work be correct, all inductive
investigation consists in the marriage of hypothesis and experiment.
When facts are in our possession, we frame an hypothesis to explain
their relations, and by the success of this explanation is the value
of the hypothesis to be judged. In the invention and treatment of
such hypotheses, we must avail ourselves of the whole body of science
already accumulated, and when once we have obtained a probable
hypothesis, we must not rest until we have verified it by comparison
with new facts. We must endeavour by deductive reasoning to anticipate
such phenomena, especially those of a singular and exceptional nature,
as would happen if the hypothesis be true. Out of the infinite number
of experiments which are possible, theory must lead us to select those
critical ones which are suitable for confirming or negativing our
anticipations.

This work of inductive investigation cannot be guided by any system of
precise and infallible rules, like those of deductive reasoning. There
is, in fact, nothing to which we can apply rules of method, because
the laws of nature must be in our possession before we can treat them.
If there were any rule of inductive method, it would direct us to make
an exhaustive arrangement of facts in all possible orders. Given the
specimens in a museum, we might arrive at the best classification by
going systematically through all possible classifications, and, were
we endowed with infinite time and patience, this would be an effective
method. It is the method by which the first simple steps are taken in
an incipient branch of science. Before the dignified name of science is
applicable, some coincidences will force themselves upon the attention.
Before there was a science of meteorology observant persons learned
to associate clearness of the atmosphere with coming rain, and a
colourless sunset with fine weather. Knowledge of this kind is called
*empirical*, as seeming to come directly from experience; and there is
a considerable portion of knowledge which bears this character.

We may be obliged to trust to the casual detection of coincidences
in those branches of knowledge where we are deprived of the aid of
any guiding notions; but a little reflection will show the utter
insufficiency of haphazard experiment, when applied to investigations
of a complicated nature. At the best, it will be the simple identity,
or partial identity, of classes, as illustrated in pages 127 or 134,
which can be thus detected. It was pointed out that, even when a law
of nature involves only two circumstances, and there are one hundred
distinct circumstances which may possibly be connected, there will be
no less than 4,950 pairs of circumstances between which coincidence may
exist. When a law involves three or more circumstances, the possible
number of relations becomes vastly greater. When considering the
subject of combinations and permutations, it became apparent that we
could never cope with the possible variety of nature. An exhaustive
examination of the possible metallic alloys, or chemical compounds, was
found to be out of the question (p. 191).

It is on such considerations that we can explain the very small
additions made to our knowledge by the alchemists. Many of them were
men of the greatest acuteness, and their indefatigable labours were
pursued through many centuries. A few things were discovered by them,
but a true insight into nature, now enables chemists to discover more
useful facts in a year than were yielded by the alchemists during
many centuries. There can be no doubt that Newton was an alchemist,
and that he often laboured night and day at alchemical experiments.
But in trying to discover the secret by which gross metals might be
rendered noble, his lofty powers of deductive investigation were wholly
useless. Deprived of all guiding clues, his experiments were like
those of all the alchemists, purely tentative and haphazard. While his
hypothetical and deductive investigations have given us the true system
of the Universe, and opened the way in almost all the great branches of
natural philosophy, the whole results of his tentative experiments are
comprehended in a few happy guesses, given in his celebrated “Queries.”

Even when we are engaged in apparently passive observation of a
phenomenon, which we cannot modify experimentally, it is advantageous
that our attention should be guided by theoretical anticipations. A
phenomenon which seems simple is, in all probability, really complex,
and unless the mind is actively engaged in looking for particular
details, it is likely that the critical circumstances will be passed
over. Bessel regretted that no distinct theory of the constitution
of comets had guided his observations of Halley’s comet;[418] in
attempting to verify or refute a hypothesis, not only would there be a
chance of establishing a true theory, but if confuted, the confutation
would involve a store of useful observations.

  [418] Tyndall, *On Cometary Theory*, Philosophical Magazine, April
  1869. 4th Series, vol. xxxvii. p. 243.

It would be an interesting work, but one which I cannot undertake, to
trace out the gradual reaction which has taken place in recent times
against the purely empirical or Baconian theory of induction. Francis
Bacon, seeing the futility of the scholastic logic, which had long
been predominant, asserted that the accumulation of facts and the
orderly abstraction of axioms, or general laws from them, constituted
the true method of induction. Even Bacon was not wholly unaware of
the value of hypothetical anticipation. In one or two places he
incidentally acknowledges it, as when he remarks that the subtlety of
nature surpasses that of reason, adding that “axioms abstracted from
particular facts in a careful and orderly manner, readily suggest and
mark out new particulars.”

Nevertheless Bacon’s method, as far as we can gather the meaning of
the main portions of his writings, would correspond to the process of
empirically collecting facts and exhaustively classifying them, to
which I alluded. The value of this method may be estimated historically
by the fact that it has not been followed by any of the great masters
of science. Whether we look to Galileo, who preceded Bacon, to Gilbert,
his contemporary, or to Newton and Descartes, Leibnitz and Huyghens,
his successors, we find that discovery was achieved by the opposite
method to that advocated by Bacon. Throughout Newton’s works, as
I shall show, we find deductive reasoning wholly predominant, and
experiments are employed, as they should be, to confirm or refute
hypothetical anticipations of nature. In my “Elementary Lessons in
Logic” (p. 258), I stated my belief that there was no kind of reference
to Bacon in Newton’s works. I have since found that Newton does once or
twice employ the expression *experimentum crucis* in his “Opticks,” but
this is the only expression, so far as I am aware, which could indicate
on the part of Newton direct or indirect acquaintance with Bacon’s
writings.[419]

  [419] See *Philosophical Transactions*, abridged by Lowthorp. 4th
  edit. vol. i. p. 130. I find that opinions similar to those in the
  text have been briefly expressed by De Morgan in his remarkable
  preface to *From Matter to Spirit*, by C.D., pp. xxi. xxii.

Other great physicists of the same age were equally prone to the use
of hypotheses rather than the blind accumulation of facts in the
Baconian manner. Hooke emphatically asserts in his posthumous work
on Philosophical Method, that the first requisite of the Natural
Philosopher is readiness at guessing the solution of phenomena and
making queries. “He ought to be very well skilled in those several
kinds of philosophy already known, to understand their several
hypotheses, suppositions, collections, observations, &c., their various
ways of ratiocinations and proceedings, the several failings and
defects, both in their way of raising and in their way of managing
their several theories: for by this means the mind will be somewhat
more ready at guessing at the solution of many phenomena almost at
first sight, and thereby be much more prompt at making queries, and at
tracing the subtlety of Nature, and in discovering and searching into
the true reason of things.”

We find Horrocks, again, than whom no one was more filled with the
scientific spirit, telling us how he tried theory after theory in order
to discover one which was in accordance with the motions of Mars.[420]
Huyghens, who possessed one of the most perfect philosophical
intellects, followed the deductive process combined with continual
appeal to experiment, with a skill closely analogous to that of Newton.
As to Descartes and Leibnitz, they fell into excess in the use of
hypothesis, since they sometimes adopted hypothetical reasoning to
the exclusion of experimental verification. Throughout the eighteenth
century science was supposed to be advancing by the pursuance of the
Baconian method, but in reality hypothetical investigation was the
main instrument of progress. It is only in the present century that
physicists began to recognise this truth. So much opprobrium had been
attached by Bacon to the use of hypotheses, that we find Young speaking
of them in an apologetic tone. “The practice of advancing general
principles and applying them to particular instances is so far from
being fatal to truth in all sciences, that when those principles are
advanced on sufficient grounds, it constitutes the essence of true
philosophy;”[421] and he quotes cases in which Davy trusted to his
theories rather than his experiments.

  [420] Horrocks, *Opera Posthuma* (1673), p. 276.

  [421] Young’s *Works*, vol. i. p. 593.

Herschel, who was both a practical physicist and an abstract logician,
entertained the deepest respect for Bacon, and made the “Novum
Organum” as far as possible the basis of his own admirable *Discourse
on the Study of Natural Philosophy*. Yet we find him in Chapter VII.
recognising the part which the formation and verification of theories
takes in the higher and more general investigations of physical
science. J. S. Mill carried on the reaction by describing the Deductive
Method in which ratiocination, that is deductive reasoning, is employed
for the discovery of new opportunities of testing and verifying an
hypothesis. Nevertheless throughout the other parts of his system
he inveighed against the value of the deductive process, and even
asserted that empirical inference from particulars to particulars is
the true type of reasoning. The irony of fate will probably decide
that the most original and valuable part of Mill’s System of Logic is
irreconcilable with those views of the syllogism and of the nature of
inference which occupy the main part of the treatise, and are said to
have effected a revolution in logical science. Mill would have been
saved from much confusion of thought had he not failed to observe that
the inverse use of deduction constitutes induction. In later years
Professor Huxley has strongly insisted upon the value of hypothesis.
When he advocates the use of “working hypotheses” he means no doubt
that any hypothesis is better that none, and that we cannot avoid being
guided in our observations by some hypothesis or other. Professor
Tyndall’s views as to the use of the Imagination in the pursuit of
Science put the same truth in another light.

It ought to be pointed out that Neil in his *Art of Reasoning*, a
popular but able exposition of the principles of Logic, published
in 1853, fully recognises in Chapter XI. the value and position of
hypothesis in the discovery of truth. He endeavours to show, too
(p. 109), that Francis Bacon did not object to the use of hypothesis.

The true course of inductive procedure is that which has yielded
all the more lofty results of science. It consists in *Anticipating
Nature*, in the sense of forming hypotheses as to the laws which are
probably in operation; and then observing whether the combinations
of phenomena are such as would follow from the laws supposed. The
investigator begins with facts and ends with them. He uses facts to
suggest probable hypotheses; deducing other facts which would happen if
a particular hypothesis is true, he proceeds to test the truth of his
notion by fresh observations. If any result prove different from what
he expects, it leads him to modify or to abandon his hypothesis; but
every new fact may give some new suggestion as to the laws in action.
Even if the result in any case agrees with his anticipations, he does
not regard it as finally confirmatory of his theory, but proceeds to
test the truth of the theory by new deductions and new trials.

In such a process the investigator is assisted by the whole body of
science previously accumulated. He may employ analogy, as I shall
point out, to guide him in the choice of hypotheses. The manifold
connections between one science and another give him clues to the kind
of laws to be expected, and out of the infinite number of possible
hypotheses he selects those which are, as far as can be foreseen at the
moment, most probable. Each experiment, therefore, which he performs
is that most likely to throw light upon his subject, and even if it
frustrate his first views, it tends to put him in possession of the
correct clue.


*Requisites of a good Hypothesis.*

There is little difficulty in pointing out to what condition an
hypothesis must conform in order to be accepted as probable and
valid. That condition, as I conceive, is the single one of enabling
us to infer the existence of phenomena which occur in our experience.
*Agreement with fact is the sole and sufficient test of a true
hypothesis.*

Hobbes has named two conditions which he considers requisite in an
hypothesis, namely (1) That it should be conceivable and not absurd;
(2) That it should allow of phenomena being necessarily inferred.
Boyle, in noticing Hobbes’ views, proposed to add a third condition,
to the effect that the hypothesis should not be inconsistent with any
other truth on phenomenon of nature.[422] I think that of these three
conditions, the first cannot be accepted, unless by *inconceivable* and
*absurd* we mean self-contradictory or inconsistent with the laws of
thought and nature. I shall have to point out that some satisfactory
theories involve suppositions which are wholly *inconceivable* in
a certain sense of the word, because the mind cannot sufficiently
extend its ideas to frame a notion of the actions supposed to take
place. That the force of gravity should act instantaneously between
the most distant parts of the planetary system, or that a ray of
violet light should consist of about 700 billions of vibrations in a
second, are statements of an inconceivable and absurd character in
one sense; but they are so far from being opposed to fact that we
cannot on any other suppositions account for phenomena observed. But
if an hypothesis involve self-contradiction, or is inconsistent with
known laws of nature, it is self-condemned. We cannot even apply
deductive reasoning to a self-contradictory notion; and being opposed
to the most general and certain laws known to us, the primary laws of
thought, it thereby conspicuously fails to agree with facts. Since
nature, again, is never self-contradictory, we cannot at the same time
accept two theories which lead to contradictory results. If the one
agrees with nature, the other cannot. Hence if there be a law which we
believe with high probability to be verified by observation, we must
not frame an hypothesis in conflict with it, otherwise the hypothesis
will necessarily be in disagreement with observation. Since no law or
hypothesis is proved, indeed, with absolute certainty, there is always
a chance, however slight, that the new hypothesis may displace the
old one; but the greater the probability which we assign to that old
hypothesis, the greater must be the evidence required in favour of the
new and conflicting one.

  [422] Boyle’s *Physical Examen*, p. 84.

I assert, then, that there is but one test of a good hypothesis,
namely, *its conformity with observed facts*; but this condition may
be said to involve three constituent conditions, nearly equivalent to
those suggested by Hobbes and Boyle, namely:--

(1) That it allow of the application of deductive reasoning and the
inference of consequences capable of comparison with the results of
observation.

(2) That it do not conflict with any laws of nature, or of mind, which
we hold to be true.

(3) That the consequences inferred do agree with facts of observation.


*Possibility of Deductive Reasoning.*

As the truth of an hypothesis is to be proved by its conformity with
fact, the first condition is that we be able to apply methods of
deductive reasoning, and learn what should happen according to such
an hypothesis. Even if we could imagine an object acting according to
laws hitherto wholly unknown it would be useless to do so, because we
could never decide whether it existed or not. We can only infer what
would happen under supposed conditions by applying the knowledge of
nature we possess to those conditions. Hence, as Boscovich truly said,
we are to understand by hypotheses “not fictions altogether arbitrary,
but suppositions conformable to experience or analogy.” It follows that
every hypothesis worthy of consideration must suggest some likeness,
analogy, or common law, acting in two or more things. If, in order to
explain certain facts, *a*, *a′*, *a″*, &c., we invent a cause A, then
we must in some degree appeal to experience as to the mode in which A
will act. As the laws of nature are not known to the mind intuitively,
we must point out some other cause, B, which supplies the requisite
notions, and all we do is to invent a fourth term to an analogy. As B
is to its effects *b*, *b′*, *b″*, &c., so is A to its effects *a*,
*a′*, *a″*, &c. When we attempt to explain the passage of light and
heat radiations through space unoccupied by matter, we imagine the
existence of the so-called *ether*. But if this ether were wholly
different from anything else known to us, we should in vain try to
reason about it. We must apply to it at least the laws of motion, that
is we must so far liken it to matter. And as, when applying those laws
to the elastic medium air, we are able to infer the phenomena of sound,
so by arguing in a similar manner concerning ether we are able to infer
the existence of light phenomena corresponding to what do occur. All
that we do is to take an elastic substance, increase its elasticity
immensely, and denude it of gravity and some other properties of
matter, but we must retain sufficient likeness to matter to allow of
deductive calculations.

The force of gravity is in some respects an incomprehensible existence,
but in other respects entirely conformable to experience. We observe
that the force is proportional to mass, and that it acts in entire
independence of other matter which may be present or intervening.
The law of the decrease of intensity, as the square of the distance
increases, is observed to hold true of light, sound, and other
influences emanating from a point, and spreading uniformly through
space. The law is doubtless connected with the properties of space, and
is so far in agreement with our necessary ideas.

It may be said, however, that no hypothesis can be so much as framed
in the mind unless it be more or less conformable to experience. As
the material of our ideas is derived from sensation we cannot figure
to ourselves any agent, but as endowed with some of the properties of
matter. All that the mind can do in the creation of new existences is
to alter combinations, or the intensity of sensuous properties. The
phenomenon of motion is familiar to sight and touch, and different
degrees of rapidity are also familiar; we can pass beyond the limits of
sense, and imagine the existence of rapid motion, such as our senses
could not observe. We know what is elasticity, and we can therefore
in a way figure to ourselves elasticity a thousand or a million times
greater than any which is sensuously known to us. The waves of the
ocean are many times higher than our own bodies; other waves, are
many times less; continue the proportion, and we ultimately arrive
at waves as small as those of light. Thus it is that the powers of
mind enable us from a sensuous basis to reason concerning agents and
phenomena different in an unlimited degree. If no hypothesis then can
be absolutely opposed to sense, accordance with experience must always
be a question of degree.

In order that an hypothesis may allow of satisfactory comparison with
experience, it must possess definiteness and in many cases mathematical
exactness allowing of the precise calculation of results. We must
be able to ascertain whether it does or does not agree with facts.
The theory of vortices is an instance to the contrary, for it did
not present any mode of calculating the exact relations between the
distances and periods of the planets and satellites; it could not,
therefore, undergo that rigorous testing to which Newton scrupulously
submitted his theory of gravity before its promulgation. Vagueness
and incapability of precise proof or disproof often enable a false
theory to live; but with those who love truth, vagueness should
excite suspicion. The upholders of the ancient doctrine of Nature’s
abhorrence of a vacuum, had been unable to anticipate the important
fact that water would not rise more than 33 feet in a common suction
pump. Nor when the fact was pointed out could they explain it, except
by introducing a special alteration of the theory to the effect that
Nature’s abhorrence of a vacuum was limited to 33 feet.


*Consistency with the Laws of Nature.*

In the second place an hypothesis must not be contradictory to
what we believe to be true concerning Nature. It must not involve
self-inconsistency which is opposed to the highest and simplest laws,
namely, those of Logic. Neither ought it to be irreconcilable with
the simple laws of motion, of gravity, of the conservation of energy,
nor any parts of physical science which we consider to be established
beyond reasonable doubt. Not that we are absolutely forbidden to
entertain such an hypothesis, but if we do so we must be prepared to
disprove some of the best demonstrated truths in the possession of
mankind. The fact that conflict exists means that the consequences of
the theory are not verified if previous discoveries are correct, and we
must therefore show that previous discoveries are incorrect before we
can verify our theory.

An hypothesis will be exceedingly improbable, not to say absurd, if
it supposes a substance to act in a manner unknown in other cases;
for it then fails to be verified in our knowledge of that substance.
Several physicists, especially Euler and Grove, have supposed that
we might dispense with an ethereal basis of light, and infer from
the interstellar passage of rays that there was a kind of rare gas
occupying space. But if so, that gas must be excessively rare, as we
may infer from the apparent absence of an atmosphere around the moon,
and from other facts known to us concerning gases and the atmosphere;
yet it must possess an elastic force at least a billion times as great
as atmospheric air at the earth’s surface, in order to account for the
extreme rapidity of light rays. Such an hypothesis then is inconsistent
with our knowledge concerning gases.

Provided that there be no clear and absolute conflict with known
laws of nature, there is no hypothesis so improbable or apparently
inconceivable that it may not be rendered probable, or even
approximately certain, by a sufficient number of concordances. In
fact the two best founded and most successful theories in physical
science involve the most absurd suppositions. Gravity is a force which
appears to act between bodies through vacuous space; it is in positive
contradiction to the old dictum that nothing can act but through
some medium. It is even more puzzling that the force acts in perfect
indifference to intervening obstacles. Light in spite of its extreme
velocity shows much respect to matter, for it is almost instantaneously
stopped by opaque substances, and to a considerable extent absorbed
and deflected by transparent ones. But to gravity all media are, as
it were, absolutely transparent, nay non-existent; and two particles
at opposite points of the earth affect each other exactly as if the
globe were not between. The action is, so far as we can observe,
instantaneous, so that every particle of the universe is at every
moment in separate cognisance, as it were, of the relative position of
every other particle throughout the universe at that same moment of
time. Compared with such incomprehensible conditions, the theory of
vortices deals with commonplace realities. Newton’s celebrated saying
*hypotheses non fingo*, bears the appearance of irony; and it was not
without apparent grounds that Leibnitz and the continental philosophers
charged Newton with re-introducing occult powers and qualities.

The undulatory theory of light presents almost equal difficulties
of conception. We are asked by physical philosophers to give up our
prepossessions, and to believe that interstellar space which seems
empty is not empty at all, but filled with *something* immensely
more solid and elastic than steel. As Young himself remarked,[423]
“the luminiferous ether, pervading all space, and penetrating almost
all substances, is not only highly elastic, but absolutely solid!!!”
Herschel calculated the force which may be supposed, according to the
undulatory theory of light, to be constantly exerted at each point in
space, and finds it to be 1,148,000,000,000 times the elastic force
of ordinary air at the earth’s surface, so that the pressure of ether
per square inch must be about seventeen billions of pounds.[424] Yet
we live and move without appreciable resistance through this medium,
immensely harder and more elastic than adamant. All our ordinary
notions must be laid aside in contemplating such an hypothesis; yet it
is no more than the observed phenomena of light and heat force us to
accept. We cannot deny even the strange suggestion of Young, that there
may be independent worlds, some possibly existing in different parts
of space, but others perhaps pervading each other unseen and unknown
in the same space.[425] For if we are bound to admit the conception
of this adamantine firmament, it is equally easy to admit a plurality
of such. We see, then, that mere difficulties of conception must not
discredit a theory which otherwise agrees with facts, and we must only
reject hypotheses which are inconceivable in the sense of breaking
distinctly the primary laws of thought and nature.

  [423] Young’s *Works*, vol. i. p. 415.

  [424] *Familiar Lectures on Scientific Subjects*, p. 282.

  [425] Young’s *Works*, vol. i. p. 417.


*Conformity with Facts.*

Before we accept a new hypothesis it must be shown to agree not only
with the previously known laws of nature, but also with the particular
facts which it is framed to explain. Assuming that these facts are
properly established, it must agree with all of them. A single absolute
conflict between fact and hypothesis, is fatal to the hypothesis;
*falsa in uno, falsa in omnibus*.

Seldom, indeed, shall we have a theory free from difficulties and
apparent inconsistency with facts. Though one real inconsistency
would overturn the most plausible theory, yet there is usually some
probability that the fact may be misinterpreted, or that some supposed
law of nature, on which we are relying, may not be true. It may be
expected, moreover, that a good hypothesis, besides agreeing with
facts already noticed, will furnish us with distinct credentials by
enabling us to anticipate deductively series of facts which are not
already connected and accounted for by any equally probable hypothesis.
We cannot lay down any precise rule as to the number of accordances
which can establish the truth of an hypothesis, because the accordances
will vary much in value. While, on the one hand, no finite number
of accordances will give entire certainty, the probability of the
hypothesis will increase very rapidly with the number of accordances.
Almost every problem in science thus takes the form of a balance of
probabilities. It is only when difficulty after difficulty has been
successfully explained away, and decisive *experimenta crucis* have,
time after time, resulted in favour of our theory, that we can venture
to assert the falsity of all objections.

The sole real test of an hypothesis is its accordance with fact.
Descartes’ celebrated system of vortices is exploded, not because it
was intrinsically absurd and inconceivable, but because it could not
give results in accordance with the actual motions of the heavenly
bodies. The difficulties of conception involved in the apparatus of
vortices, are child’s play compared with those of gravitation and
the undulatory theory already described. Vortices are on the whole
plausible suppositions; for planets and satellites bear at first sight
much resemblance to objects carried round in whirlpools, an analogy
which doubtless suggested the theory. The failure was in the first and
third requisites; for, as already remarked, the theory did not allow
of precise calculation of planetary motions, and was thus incapable of
rigorous verification. But so far as we can institute a comparison,
facts are entirely against the vortices. Newton did not ridicule the
theory as absurd, but showed[426] that it was “pressed with many
difficulties.” He carefully pointed out that the Cartesian theory was
inconsistent with the laws of Kepler, and would represent the planets
as moving more rapidly at their aphelia than at their perihelia.[427]
The rotatory motion of the sun and planets on their own axes is in
striking conflict with the revolutions of the satellites carried round
them; and comets, the most flimsy of bodies, calmly pursue their
courses in elliptic paths, irrespective of the vortices which they pass
through. We may now also point to the interlacing orbits of the minor
planets as a new and insuperable difficulty in the way of the Cartesian
ideas.

  [426] *Principia*, bk. iii. Prop. 43. General Scholium.

  [427] Ibid. bk. ii. Sect. ix. Prop. 53.

Newton, though he established the best of theories, was also capable
of proposing one of the worst; and if we want an instance of a theory
decisively contradicted by facts, we have only to turn to his views
concerning the origin of natural colours. Having analysed, with
incomparable skill, the origin of the colours of thin plates, he
suggests that the colours of all bodies are determined in like manner
by the size of their ultimate particles. A thin plate of a definite
thickness will reflect a definite colour; hence, if broken up into
fragments it will form a powder of the same colour. But, if this be
a sufficient explanation of coloured substances, then every coloured
fluid ought to reflect the complementary colour of that which it
transmits. Colourless transparency arises, according to Newton, from
particles being too minute to reflect light; but if so, every black
substance should be transparent. Newton himself so acutely felt this
last difficulty as to suggest that true blackness is due to some
internal refraction of the rays to and fro, and an ultimate stifling
of them, which he did not attempt to explain further. Unless some
other process comes into operation, neither refraction nor reflection,
however often repeated, will destroy the energy of light. The theory
therefore gives no account, as Brewster shows, of 24 parts out of 25 of
the light which falls upon a black coal, and the remaining part which
is reflected from the lustrous surface is equally inconsistent with the
theory, because fine coal-dust is almost entirely devoid of reflective
power.[428] It is now generally believed that the colours of natural
bodies are due to the unequal absorption of rays of light of different
refrangibility.

  [428] Brewster’s *Life of Newton*, 1st edit. chap. vii.


*Experimentum Crucis.*

As we deduce more and more conclusions from a theory, and find them
verified by trial, the probability of the theory increases in a rapid
manner; but we never escape the risk of error altogether. Absolute
certainty is beyond the powers of inductive investigation, and the
most plausible supposition may ultimately be proved false. Such is the
groundwork of similarity in nature, that two very different conditions
may often give closely similar results. We sometimes find ourselves
therefore in possession of two or more hypotheses which both agree
with so many experimental facts as to have great appearance of truth.
Under such circumstances we have need of some new experiment, which
shall give results agreeing with one hypothesis but not with the other.

Any such experiment which decides between two rival theories may be
called an *Experimentum Crucis*, an Experiment of the Finger Post.
Whenever the mind stands, as it were, at cross-roads and knows not
which way to select, it needs some decisive guide, and Bacon therefore
assigned great importance and authority to instances which serve in
this capacity. The name given by Bacon has become familiar; it is
almost the only one of Bacon’s figurative expressions which has passed
into common use. Even Newton, as I have mentioned (p. 507), used the
name.

I do not think, indeed, that the common use of the word at all agrees
with that intended by Bacon. Herschel says that “we make an experiment
of the crucial kind when we form combinations, and put in action
causes from which some particular one shall be deliberately excluded,
and some other purposely admitted.”[429] This, however, seems to be
the description of any special experiment not made at haphazard.
Pascal’s experiment of causing a barometer to be carried to the top of
the Puy-de-Dôme has often been considered as a perfect *experimentum
crucis*, if not the first distinct one on record;[430] but if so, we
must dignify the doctrine of Nature’s abhorrence of a vacuum with
the position of a rival theory. A crucial experiment must not simply
confirm one theory, but must negative another; it must decide a mind
which is in equilibrium, as Bacon says,[431] between two equally
plausible views. “When in search of any nature, the understanding comes
to an equilibrium, as it were, or stands suspended as to which of two
or more natures the cause of nature inquired after should be attributed
or assigned, by reason of the frequent and common occurrence of several
natures, then these Crucial Instances show the true and inviolable
association of one of these natures to the nature sought, and the
uncertain and separable alliance of the other, whereby the question
is decided, the former nature admitted for the cause, and the other
rejected. These instances, therefore, afford great light, and have a
kind of overruling authority, so that the course of interpretation will
sometimes terminate in them, or be finished by them.”

  [429] *Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy*, p. 151.

  [430] Ibid. p. 229.

  [431] *Novum Organum*, bk. ii. Aphorism 36.

The long-continued strife between the Corpuscular and Undulatory
theories of light forms the best possible illustration of an
Experimentum Crucis. It is remarkable in how plausible a manner both
these theories agreed with the ordinary laws of geometrical optics,
relating to reflection and refraction. According to the first law of
motion a moving particle proceeds in a perfectly straight line, when
undisturbed by extraneous forces. If the particle being perfectly
elastic, strike a perfectly elastic plane, it will bound off in such
a path that the angles of incidence and reflection will be equal.
Now a ray of light proceeds in a straight line, or appears to do
so, until it meets a reflecting body, when its path is altered in a
manner exactly similar to that of the elastic particle. Here is a
remarkable correspondence which probably suggested to Newton’s mind
the hypothesis that light consists of minute elastic particles moving
with excessive rapidity in straight lines. The correspondence was found
to extend also to the law of simple refraction; for if particles of
light be supposed capable of attracting matter, and being attracted
by it at insensibly small distances, then a ray of light, falling on
the surface of a transparent medium, will suffer an increase in its
velocity perpendicular to the surface, and the law of sines is the
consequence. This remarkable explanation of the law of refraction had
doubtless a very strong effect in leading Newton to entertain the
corpuscular theory, and he appears to have thought that the analogy
between the propagation of rays of light and the motion of bodies was
perfectly exact, whatever might be the actual nature of light.[432]
It is highly remarkable, again, that Newton was able to give by his
corpuscular theory, a plausible explanation of the inflection of light
as discovered by Grimaldi. The theory would indeed have been a very
probable one could Newton’s own law of gravity have applied; but this
was out of the question, because the particles of light, in order that
they may move in straight lines, must be devoid of any influence upon
each other.

  [432] *Principia*, bk. i. Sect. xiv. Prop. 96. Scholium. *Opticks*,
  Prop. vi. 3rd edit. p. 70.

The Huyghenian or Undulatory theory of light was also able to explain
the same phenomena, but with one remarkable difference. If the
undulatory theory be true, light must move more slowly in a dense
refracting medium than in a rarer one; but the Newtonian theory assumed
that the attraction of the dense medium caused the particles of light
to move more rapidly than in the rare medium. On this point, then,
there was complete discrepancy between the theories, and observation
was required to show which theory was to be preferred. Now by simply
cutting a uniform plate of glass into two pieces, and slightly
inclining one piece so as to increase the length of the path of a ray
passing through it, experimenters were able to show that light does
move more slowly in glass than in air.[433] More recently Fizeau and
Foucault independently measured the velocity of light in air and in
water, and found that the velocity is greater in air.[434]

  [433] Airy’s *Mathematical Tracts*, 3rd edit. pp. 286–288.

  [434] Jamin, *Cours de Physique*, vol. iii. p. 372.

There are a number of other points at which experience decides against
Newton, and in favour of Huyghens and Young. Laplace pointed out that
the attraction supposed to exist between matter and the corpuscular
particles of light would cause the velocity of light to vary with the
size of the emitting body, so that if a star were 250 times as great
in diameter as our sun, its attraction would prevent the emanation of
light altogether.[435] But experience shows that the velocity of light
is uniform, and independent of the magnitude of the emitting body,
as it should be according to the undulatory theory. Lastly, Newton’s
explanation of diffraction or inflection fringes of colours was only
*plausible*, and not true; for Fresnel ascertained that the dimensions
of the fringes are not what they would be according to Newton’s theory.

  [435] Young’s *Lectures on Natural Philosophy* (1845), vol. i. p. 361.

Although the Science of Light presents us with the most beautiful
examples of crucial experiments and observations, instances are
not wanting in other branches of science. Copernicus asserted, in
opposition to the ancient Ptolemaic theory, that the earth moved round
the sun, and he predicted that if ever the sense of sight could be
rendered sufficiently acute and powerful, we should see phases in
Mercury and Venus. Galileo with his telescope was able, in 1610 to
verify the prediction as regards Venus, and subsequent observations
of Mercury led to a like conclusion. The discovery of the aberration
of light added a new proof, still further strengthened by the more
recent determination of the parallax of fixed stars. Hooke proposed
to prove the existence of the earth’s diurnal motion by observing the
deviation of a falling body, an experiment successfully accomplished by
Benzenberg; and Foucault’s pendulum has since furnished an additional
indication of the same motion, which is indeed also apparent in the
trade winds. All these are crucial facts in favour of the Copernican
theory.


*Descriptive Hypotheses.*

There are hypotheses which we may call *descriptive hypotheses*,
and which serve for little else than to furnish convenient names.
When a phenomenon is of an unusual kind, we cannot even speak of
it without using some analogy. Every word implies some resemblance
between the thing to which it is applied, and some other thing, which
fixes the meaning of the word. If we are to speak of what constitutes
electricity, we must search for the nearest analogy, and as electricity
is characterised by the rapidity and facility of its movements, the
notion of a fluid of a very subtle character presents itself as
appropriate. There is the single-fluid and the double-fluid theory of
electricity, and a great deal of discussion has been uselessly spent
upon them. The fact is, that if these theories be understood as more
than convenient modes of describing the phenomena, they are altogether
invalid. The analogy extends only to the rapidity of motion, or rather
the fact that a phenomenon occurs successively at different points of
the body. The so-called electric fluid adds nothing to the weight of
the conductor, and to suppose that it really consists of particles of
matter is even more absurd than to reinstate the corpuscular theory
of light. A far closer analogy exists between electricity and light
undulations, which are about equally rapid in propagation. We shall
probably continue for a long time to talk of the *electric fluid*, but
there can be no doubt that this expression represents merely a phase of
molecular motion, a wave of disturbance. The invalidity of these fluid
theories is shown moreover in the fact that they have not led to the
invention of a single new experiment.

Among these merely descriptive hypotheses I should place Newton’s
theory of Fits of Easy Reflection and Refraction. That theory did not
do more than describe what took place. It involved no analogy to other
phenomena of nature, for Newton could not point to any other substance
which went through these extraordinary fits. We now know that the true
analogy would have been waves of sound, of which Newton had acquired in
other respects so complete a comprehension. But though the notion of
interference of waves had distinctly occurred to Hooke, Newton failed
to see how the periodic phenomena of light could be connected with the
periodic character of waves. His hypothesis fell because it was out
of analogy with everything else in nature, and it therefore did not
allow him, as in other cases, to descend by mathematical deduction to
consequences which could be verified or refuted.

We are at freedom to imagine the existence of a new agent, and to
give it an appropriate name, provided there are phenomena incapable
of explanation from known causes. We may speak of *vital force* as
occasioning life, provided that we do not take it to be more than a
name for an undefined something giving rise to inexplicable facts, just
as the French chemists called Iodine the Substance X, so long as they
were unaware of its real character and place in chemistry.[436] Encke
was quite justified in speaking of the *resisting medium* in space so
long as the retardation of his comet could not be otherwise accounted
for. But such hypotheses will do much harm whenever they divert us from
attempts to reconcile the facts with known laws, or when they lead us
to mix up discrete things. Because we speak of vital force we must not
assume that it is a really existing physical force like electricity; we
do not know what it is. We have no right to confuse Encke’s supposed
resisting medium with the basis of light without distinct evidence of
identity. The name protoplasm, now so familiarly used by physiologists,
is doubtless legitimate so long as we do not mix up different
substances under it, or imagine that the name gives us any knowledge
of the obscure origin of life. To name a substance protoplasm no more
explains the infinite variety of forms of life which spring out of the
substance, than does the *vital force* which may be supposed to reside
in the protoplasm. Both expressions are mere names for an inexplicable
series of causes which out of apparently similar conditions produce the
most diverse results.

  [436] Paris, *Life of Davy*, p. 274.

Hardly to be distinguished from descriptive hypotheses are certain
imaginary objects which we frame for the ready comprehension of
a subject. The mathematician, in treating abstract questions of
probability, finds it convenient to represent the conditions by a
concrete hypothesis in the shape of a ballot-box. Poisson proved the
principle of the inverse method of probabilities by imagining a number
of ballot-boxes to have their contents mixed in one great ballot-box
(p. 244). Many such devices are used by mathematicians. The Ptolemaic
theory of *cycles* and *epi-cycles* was no grotesque and useless work
of the imagination, but a perfectly valid mode of analysing the motions
of the heavenly bodies; in reality it is used by mathematicians at the
present day. Newton employed the pendulum as a means of representing
the nature of an undulation. Centres of gravity, oscillation, &c.,
poles of the magnet, lines of force, are other imaginary existences
employed to assist our thoughts (p. 364). Such devices may be called
*Representative Hypotheses*, and they are only permissible so far as
they embody analogies. Their further consideration belongs either to
the subject of Analogy, or to that of language and representation,
founded upon analogy.




CHAPTER XXIV.

EMPIRICAL KNOWLEDGE, EXPLANATION, AND PREDICTION.


Inductive investigation, as we have seen, consists in the union of
hypothesis and experiment, deductive reasoning being the link by which
experimental results are made to confirm or confute the hypothesis. Now
when we consider this relation between hypothesis and experiment it is
obvious that we may classify our knowledge under four heads.

(1) We may be acquainted with facts which have not yet been brought
into accordance with any hypothesis. Such facts constitute what is
called *Empirical Knowledge*.

(2) Another extensive portion of our knowledge consists of facts which
having been first observed empirically, have afterwards been brought
into accordance with other facts by an hypothesis concerning the
general laws applying to them. This portion of our knowledge may be
said to be *explained*, *reasoned*, or *generalised*.

(3) In the third place comes the collection of facts, minor in number,
but most important as regards their scientific interest, which have
been anticipated by theory and afterwards verified by experiment.

(4) Lastly, there exists knowledge which is accepted solely on the
ground of theory, and is incapable of experimental confirmation, at
least with the instrumental means in our possession.

It is a work of much interest to compare and illustrate the relative
extent and value of these four groups of knowledge. We shall observe
that as a general rule a great branch of science originates in facts
observed accidentally, or without distinct consciousness of what is to
be expected. As a science progresses, its power of foresight rapidly
increases, until the mathematician in his library acquires the power of
anticipating nature, and predicting what will happen in circumstances
which the eye of man has never examined.


*Empirical Knowledge.*

By empirical knowledge we mean such as is derived directly from the
examination of detached facts, and rests entirely on those facts,
without corroboration from other branches of knowledge. It is
contrasted with generalised and theoretical knowledge, which embraces
many series of facts under a few comprehensive principles, so that each
series serves to throw light upon each other series of facts. Just
as, in the map of a half-explored country, we see detached bits of
rivers, isolated mountains, and undefined plains, not connected into
any complete plan, so a new branch of knowledge consists of groups of
facts, each group standing apart, so as not to allow us to reason from
one to another.

Before the time of Descartes, and Newton, and Huyghens, there was
much empirical knowledge of the phenomena of light. The rainbow had
always struck the attention of the most careless observers, and there
was no difficulty in perceiving that its conditions of occurrence
consisted in rays of the sun shining upon falling drops of rain. It
was impossible to overlook the resemblance of the ordinary rainbow
to the comparatively rare lunar rainbow, to the bow which appears
upon the spray of a waterfall, or even upon beads of dew suspended on
grass and spiders’ webs. In all these cases the uniform conditions
are rays of light and round drops of water. Roger Bacon had noticed
these conditions, as well as the analogy of the rainbow colours to
those produced by crystals.[437] But the knowledge was empirical until
Descartes and Newton showed how the phenomena were connected with facts
concerning the refraction of light.

  [437] *Opus Majus.* Edit. 1733. Cap. x. p. 460.

There can be no better instance of an empirical truth than that
detected by Newton concerning the high refractive powers of combustible
substances. Newton’s chemical notions were almost as vague as those
prevalent in his day, but he observed that certain “fat, sulphureous,
unctuous bodies,” as he calls them, such as camphor, oils spirit of
turpentine, amber, &c., have refractive powers two or three times
greater than might be anticipated from their densities.[438] The
enormous refractive index of diamond, led him with great sagacity to
regard this substance as of the same unctuous or inflammable nature,
so that he may be regarded as predicting the combustibility of the
diamond, afterwards demonstrated by the Florentine Academicians
in 1694. Brewster having entered into a long investigation of the
refractive powers of different substances, confirmed Newton’s
assertions, and found that the three elementary combustible substances,
diamond, phosphorus, and sulphur, have, in comparison with their
densities, by far the highest known refractive indices,[439] and
there are only a few substances, such as chromate of lead or glass of
antimony, which exceed them in absolute power of refraction. The oils
and hydrocarbons generally possess excessive indices. But all this
knowledge remains to the present day purely empirical, no connection
having been pointed out between this coincidence of inflammability
and high refractive power, with other laws of chemistry or optics.
It is worth notice, as pointed out by Brewster, that if Newton had
argued concerning two minerals, Greenockite and Octahedrite, as he did
concerning diamond, his predictions would have proved false, showing
sufficiently that he did not make any sure induction on the subject. In
the present day, the relation of the refractive index to the density
and atomic weight of a substance is becoming a matter of theory; yet
there remain specific differences of refracting power known only on
empirical grounds, and it is curious that in hydrogen an abnormally
high refractive power has been found to be joined to inflammability.

  [438] Newton’s *Opticks*. Third edit. p. 249.

  [439] Brewster. *Treatise on New Philosophical Instruments*, p. 266,
  &c.

The science of chemistry, however much its theory may have progressed,
still presents us with a vast body of empirical knowledge. Not only
is it as yet hopeless to attempt to account for the particular group
of qualities belonging to each element, but there are multitudes of
particular facts of which no further account can be given. Why should
the sulphides of many metals be intensely black? Why should a slight
amount of phosphoric acid have so great a power of interference with
the crystallisation of vanadic acid?[440] Why should the compound
silicates of alkalies and alkaline metals be transparent? Why should
gold be so highly ductile, and gold and silver the only two sensibly
translucent metals? Why should sulphur be capable of so many peculiar
changes into allotropic modifications?

  [440] Roscoe, Bakerian Lecture, *Philosophical Transactions* (1868),
  vol. clviii. p. 6.

There are whole branches of chemical knowledge which are mere
collections of disconnected facts. The properties of alloys are
often remarkable; but no laws have yet been detected, and the laws
of combining proportions seem to have no clear application.[441] Not
the slightest explanation can be given of the wonderful variations of
the qualities of iron, according as it contains more or less carbon
and silicon, nay, even the facts of the case are often involved in
uncertainty. Why, again, should the properties of steel be remarkably
affected by the presence of a little tungsten or manganese? All
that was determined by Matthiessen concerning the conducting powers
of copper, was of a purely empirical character.[442] Many animal
substances cannot be shown to obey the laws of combining proportions.
Thus for the most part chemistry is yet an empirical science occupied
with the registration of immense numbers of disconnected facts, which
may at some future time become the basis of a greatly extended theory.

  [441] *Life of Faraday*, vol. ii. p. 104.

  [442] Watts, *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. ii, p. 39, &c.

We must not indeed suppose that any science will ever entirely cease
to be empirical. Multitudes of phenomena have been explained by the
undulatory theory of light; but there yet remain many facts to be
treated. The natural colours of bodies and the rays given off by them
when heated, are unexplained, and yield few empirical coincidences.
The theory of electricity is partially understood, but the conditions
of the production of frictional electricity defy explanation, although
they have been studied for two centuries. I shall subsequently point
out that even the establishment of a wide and true law of nature is
but the starting-point for the discovery of exceptions and divergences
giving a new scope to empirical discovery.

There is probably no science, I have said, which is entirely free
from empirical and unexplained facts. Logic approaches most nearly to
this position, as it is merely a deductive development of the laws
of thought and the principle of substitution. Yet some of the facts
established in the investigation of the inverse logical problem may
be considered empirical. That a proposition of the form A = BC ꖌ *b
c* possesses the least number of distinct logical variations, and
the greatest number of logical equivalents of the same form among
propositions involving three classes (p. 141), is a case in point. So
also is the fact discovered by Professor Clifford that in regard to
statements involving four classes, there is only one example of two
dissimilar statements having the same distances (p. 144). Mathematical
science often yields empirical truths. Why, for instance, should the
value of π, when expressed to a great number of figures, contain the
digit 7 much less frequently than any other digit?[443] Even geometry
may allow of empirical truths, when the matter does not involve
quantities of space, but numerical results and the positive or negative
character of quantities, as in De Morgan’s theorem concerning negative
areas.

  [443] De Morgan’s *Budget of Paradoxes*, p. 291.


*Accidental Discovery.*

There are not a few cases where almost pure accident has determined
the moment when a new branch of knowledge was to be created. The laws
of the structure of crystals were not discovered until Haüy happened
to drop a beautiful crystal of calc-spar upon a stone pavement. His
momentary regret at destroying a choice specimen was quickly removed
when, in attempting to join the fragments together, he observed
regular geometrical faces, which did not correspond with the external
facets of the crystals. A great many more crystals were soon broken
intentionally, to observe the planes of cleavage, and the discovery of
the internal structure of crystalline substances was the result. Here
we see how much more was due to the reasoning power of the philosopher,
than to an accident which must often have happened to other persons.

In a similar manner, a fortuitous occurrence led Malus to discover
the polarisation of light by reflection. The phenomena of double
refraction had been long known, and when engaged in Paris in 1808, in
investigating the character of light thus polarised, Malus chanced to
look through a double refracting prism at the light of the setting
sun, reflected from the windows of the Luxembourg Palace. In turning
the prism round, he was surprised to find that the ordinary image
disappeared at two opposite positions of the prism. He remarked that
the reflected light behaved like light which had been polarised by
passing through another prism. He was induced to test the character of
light reflected under other circumstances, and it was eventually proved
that polarisation is invariably connected with reflection. Some of the
general laws of optics, previously unsuspected, were thus discovered by
pure accident. In the history of electricity, accident has had a large
part. For centuries some of the more common effects of magnetism and
of frictional electricity had presented themselves as unaccountable
deviations from the ordinary course of Nature. Accident must have
first directed attention to such phenomena, but how few of those who
witnessed them had any conception of the all-pervading character of the
power manifested. The very existence of galvanism, or electricity of
low tension, was unsuspected until Galvani accidentally touched the leg
of a frog with pieces of metal. The decomposition of water by voltaic
electricity also was accidentally discovered by Nicholson in 1801, and
Davy speaks of this discovery as the foundation of all that had since
been done in electro-chemical science.

It is otherwise with the discovery of electro-magnetism. Oersted, in
common with many others, had suspected the existence of some relation
between the magnet and electricity, and he appears to have tried to
detect its exact nature. Once, as we are told by Hansteen, he had
employed a strong galvanic battery during a lecture, and at the close
it occurred to him to try the effect of placing the conducting wire
parallel to a magnetic needle, instead of at right angles, as he had
previously done. The needle immediately moved and took up a position
nearly at right angles to the wire; he inverted the direction of the
current, and the needle deviated in a contrary direction. The great
discovery was made, and if by accident, it was such an accident as
happens, as Lagrange remarked of Newton, only to those who deserve
it.[444] There was, in fact, nothing accidental, except that, as in
all totally new discoveries, Oersted did not know what to look for. He
could not infer from previous knowledge the nature of the relation,
and it was only repeated trial in different modes which could lead him
to the right combination. High and happy powers of inference, and not
accident, subsequently led Faraday to reverse the process, and to show
that the motion of the magnet would occasion an electric current in the
wire.

  [444] *Life of Faraday*, vol. ii p. 396.

Sufficient investigation would probably show that almost every branch
of art and science had an accidental beginning. In historical times
almost every important new instrument as the telescope, the microscope,
or the compass, was probably suggested by some accidental occurrence.
In pre-historic times the germs of the arts must have arisen still more
exclusively in the same way. Cultivation of plants probably arose, in
Mr. Darwin’s opinion, from some such accident as the seeds of a fruit
falling upon a heap of refuse, and producing an unusually fine variety.
Even the use of fire must, some time or other, have been discovered in
an accidental manner.

With the progress of a branch of science, the element of chance becomes
much reduced. Not only are laws discovered which enable results to be
predicted, as we shall see, but the systematic examination of phenomena
and substances often leads to discoveries which can in no sense be said
to be accidental. It has been asserted that the anæsthetic properties
of chloroform were disclosed by a little dog smelling at a saucerful
of the liquid in a chemist’s shop in Linlithgow, the singular effects
upon the dog being reported to Simpson, who turned the incident to
good account. This story, however, has been shown to be a fabrication,
the fact being that Simpson had for many years been endeavouring to
discover a better anæsthetic than those previously employed, and that
he tested the properties of chloroform, among other substances, at
the suggestion of Waldie, a Liverpool chemist. The valuable powers
of chloral hydrate have since been discovered in a like manner, and
systematic inquiries are continually being made into the therapeutic or
economic values of new chemical compounds.

If we must attempt to draw a conclusion concerning the part which
chance plays in scientific discovery, it must be allowed that it more
or less affects the success of all inductive investigation, but becomes
less important with the progress of science. Accident may bring a new
and valuable combination to the notice of some person who had never
expressly searched for a discovery of the kind, and the probabilities
are certainly in favour of a discovery being occasionally made in this
manner. But the greater the tact and industry with which a physicist
applies himself to the study of nature, the greater is the probability
that he will meet with fortunate accidents, and will turn them to good
account. Thus it comes to pass that, in the refined investigations
of the present day, genius united to extensive knowledge, cultivated
powers, and indomitable industry, constitute the characteristics of the
successful discoverer.


*Empirical Observations subsequently Explained.*

The second great portion of scientific knowledge consists of facts
which have been first learnt in a purely empirical manner, but have
afterwards been shown to follow from some law of nature, that is,
from some highly probable hypothesis. Facts are said to be explained
when they are thus brought into harmony with other facts, or bodies
of general knowledge. There are few words more familiarly used in
scientific phraseology than this word *explanation*, and it is
necessary to decide exactly what we mean by it, since the question
touches the deepest points concerning the nature of science. Like most
terms referring to mental actions, the verbs *to explain*, or *to
explicate*, involve material similes. The action is *ex plicis plana
reddere*, to take out the folds, and render a thing plain or even.
Explanation thus renders a thing clearly comprehensible in all its
points, so that there is nothing left outstanding or obscure.

Every act of explanation consists in pointing out a resemblance
between facts, or in showing that similarity exists between apparently
diverse phenomena. This similarity may be of any extent and depth; it
may be a general law of nature, which harmonises the motions of all
the heavenly bodies by showing that there is a similar force which
governs all those motions, or the explanation may involve nothing more
than a single identity, as when we explain the appearance of shooting
stars by showing that they are identical with portions of a comet.
Wherever we detect resemblance, there is a more or less explanation.
The mind is disquieted when it meets a novel phenomenon, one which is
*sui generis*; it seeks at once for parallels which may be found in
the memory of past sensations. The so-called sulphurous smell which
attends a stroke of lightning often excited attention, and it was not
explained until the exact similarity of the smell to that of ozone was
pointed out. The marks upon a flagstone are explained when they are
shown to correspond with the feet of an extinct animal, whose bones
are elsewhere found. Explanation, in fact, generally commences by the
discovery of some simple resemblance; the theory of the rainbow began
as soon as Antonio de Dominis pointed out the resemblance between its
colours and those presented by a ray of sunlight passing through a
glass globe full of water.

The nature and limits of explanation can only be fully considered,
after we have entered upon the subjects of generalisation and analogy.
It must suffice to remark, in this place, that the most important
process of explanation consists in showing that an observed fact is one
case of a general law or tendency. Iron is always found combined with
sulphur, when it is in contact with coal, whereas in other parts of
the carboniferous strata it always occurs as a carbonate. We explain
this empirical fact as being due to the reducing power of carbon and
hydrogen, which prevents the iron from combining with oxygen, and
leaves it open to the affinity of sulphur. The uniform strength and
direction of the trade-winds were long familiar to mariners, before
they were explained by Halley on hydrostatical principles. The winds
were found to arise from the action of gravity, which causes a heavier
body to displace a lighter one, while the direction from east to west
was explained as a result of the earth’s rotation. Whatever body in
the northern hemisphere changes its latitude, whether it be a bird, or
a railway train, or a body of air, must tend towards the right hand.
Dove’s law of the winds is that the winds tend to veer in the northern
hemisphere in the direction N.E.S.W., and in the southern hemisphere
in the direction N.W.S.E. This tendency was shown by him to be the
necessary effect of the same conditions which apply to the trade winds.
Whenever, then, any fact is connected by resemblance, law, theory, or
hypothesis, with other facts, it is explained.

Although the great mass of recorded facts must be empirical, and
awaiting explanation, such knowledge is of minor value, because it does
not admit of safe and extensive inference. Each recorded result informs
us exactly what will be experienced again in the same circumstances,
but has no bearing upon what will happen in other circumstances.


*Overlooked Results of Theory.*

We must by no means suppose that, when a scientific truth is in our
possession, all its consequences will be foreseen. Deduction is certain
and infallible, in the sense that each step in deductive reasoning will
lead us to some result, as certain as the law itself. But it does not
follow that deduction will lead the reasoner to every result of a law
or combination of laws. Whatever road a traveller takes, he is sure to
arrive somewhere, but unless he proceeds in a systematic manner, it is
unlikely that he will reach every place to which a network of roads
will conduct him.

In like manner there are many phenomena which were virtually within
the reach of philosophers by inference from their previous knowledge,
but were never discovered until accident or systematic empirical
observation disclosed their existence.

That light travels with a uniform high velocity was proved by Roemer
from observations of the eclipses of Jupiter’s satellites. Corrections
were thenceforward made in all astronomical observations requiring it,
for the difference of absolute time at which an event happened, and
that at which it would be seen on the earth. But no person happened
to remark that the motion of light compounded with that of the earth
in its orbit would occasion a small apparent displacement of the
greater part of the heavenly bodies. Fifty years elapsed before Bradley
empirically discovered this effect, called by him aberration, when
reducing his observations of the fixed stars.

When once the relation between an electric current and a magnet had
been detected by Oersted and Faraday, it ought to have been possible
for them to foresee the diverse results which must ensue in different
circumstances. If, for instance, a plate of copper were placed beneath
an oscillating magnetic needle, it should have been seen that the
needle would induce currents in the copper, but as this could not take
place without a certain reaction against the needle, it ought to have
been seen that the needle would come to rest more rapidly than in the
absence of the copper. This peculiar effect was accidentally discovered
by Gambey in 1824. Arago acutely inferred from Gambey’s experiment that
if the copper were set in rotation while the needle was stationary the
motion would gradually be communicated to the needle. The phenomenon
nevertheless puzzled the whole scientific world, and it required
the deductive genius of Faraday to show that it was a result of the
principles of electro-magnetism.[445]

  [445] *Experimental Researches in Electricity*, 1st Series, pp. 24–44.

Many other curious facts might be mentioned which when once noticed
were explained as the effects of well-known laws. It was accidentally
discovered that the navigation of canals of small depth could be
facilitated by increasing the speed of the boats, the resistance being
actually reduced by this increase of speed, which enables the boat
to ride as it were upon its own forced wave. Now mathematical theory
might have predicted this result had the right application of the
formulæ occurred to any one.[446] Giffard’s injector for supplying
steam boilers with water by the force of their own steam, was, I
believe, accidentally discovered, but no new principles of mechanics
are involved in it, so that it might have been theoretically invented.
The same may be said of the curious experiment in which a stream of
air or steam issuing from a pipe is made to hold a free disc upon the
end of the pipe and thus obstruct its own outlet. The possession then
of a true theory does not by any means imply the foreseeing of all the
results. The effects of even a few simple laws may be manifold, and
some of the most curious and useful effects may remain undetected until
accidental observation brings them to our notice.

  [446] Airy, *On Tides and Waves*, Encyclopædia Metropolitana, p. 348*.


*Predicted Discoveries.*

The most interesting of the four classes of facts specified in p. 525,
is probably the third, containing those the occurrence of which has
been first predicted by theory and then verified by observation. There
is no more convincing proof of the soundness of knowledge than that it
confers the gift of foresight. Auguste Comte said that “Prevision is
the test of true theory;” I should say that it is *one test* of true
theory, and that which is most likely to strike the public attention.
Coincidence with fact is the test of true theory, but when the result
of theory is announced before-hand, there can be no doubt as to the
unprejudiced spirit in which the theorist interprets the results of his
own theory.

The earliest instance of scientific prophecy is naturally furnished
by the science of Astronomy, which was the earliest in development.
Herodotus[447] narrates that, in the midst of a battle between the
Medes and Lydians, the day was suddenly turned into night, and the
event had been foretold by Thales, the Father of Philosophy. A
cessation of the combat and peace confirmed by marriages were the
consequences of this happy scientific effort. Much controversy has
taken place concerning the date of this occurrence, Baily assigning
the year 610 B.C., but Airy has calculated that the exact day was
the 28th of May, 584 B.C. There can be no doubt that this and other
predictions of eclipses attributed to ancient philosophers were due to
a knowledge of the Metonic Cycle, a period of 6,585 days, or 223 lunar
months, or about 19 years, after which a nearly perfect recurrence of
the phases and eclipses of the moon takes place; but if so, Thales must
have had access to long series of astronomical records of the Egyptians
or the Chaldeans. There is a well-known story as to the happy use which
Columbus made of the power of predicting eclipses in overawing the
islanders of Jamaica who refused him necessary supplies of food for his
fleet. He threatened to deprive them of the moon’s light. “His threat
was treated at first with indifference, but when the eclipse actually
commenced, the barbarians vied with each other in the production of the
necessary supplies for the Spanish fleet.”

  [447] Lib. i. cap. 74.

Exactly the same kind of awe which the ancients experienced at the
prediction of eclipses, has been felt in modern times concerning the
return of comets. Seneca asserted in distinct terms that comets would
be found to revolve in periodic orbits and return to sight. The ancient
Chaldeans and the Pythagoreans are also said to have entertained a
like opinion. But it was not until the age of Newton and Halley that
it became possible to calculate the path of a comet in future years. A
great comet appeared in 1682, a few years before the first publication
of the *Principia*, and Halley showed that its orbit corresponded
with that of remarkable comets recorded to have appeared in the years
1531 and 1607. The intervals of time were not quite equal, but Halley
conceived the bold idea that this difference might be due to the
disturbing power of Jupiter, near which the comet had passed in the
interval 1607–1682. He predicted that the comet would return about
the end of 1758 or the beginning of 1759, and though Halley did not
live to enjoy the sight, it was actually detected on the night of
Christmas-day, 1758. A second return of the comet was witnessed in 1835
nearly at the anticipated time.

In recent times the discovery of Neptune has been the most remarkable
instance of prevision in astronomical science. A full account of this
discovery may be found in several works, as for instance Herschel’s
*Outlines of Astronomy*, and *Grant’s History of Physical Astronomy*,
Chapters XII and XIII.


*Predictions in the Science of Light.*

Next after astronomy the science of physical optics has furnished the
most beautiful instances of the prophetic power of correct theory.
These cases are the more striking because they proceed from the
profound application of mathematical analysis and show an insight
into the mysterious workings of matter which is surprising to all,
but especially to those who are unable to comprehend the methods
of research employed. By its power of prevision the truth of the
undulatory theory of light has been conspicuously proved, and the
contrast in this respect between the undulatory and Corpuscular
theories is remarkable. Even Newton could get no aid from his
corpuscular theory in the invention of new experiments, and to his
followers who embraced that theory we owe little or nothing in the
science of light. Laplace did not derive from the theory a single
discovery. As Fresnel remarks:[448]

  [448] Taylor’s *Scientific Memoirs*, vol. v. p. 241.

“The assistance to be derived from a good theory is not to be confined
to the calculation of the forces when the laws of the phenomena
are known. There are certain laws so complicated and so singular,
that observation alone, aided by analogy, could never lead to their
discovery. To divine these enigmas we must be guided by theoretical
ideas founded on a *true* hypothesis. The theory of luminous vibrations
presents this character, and these precious advantages; for to it
we owe the discovery of optical laws the most complicated and most
difficult to divine.”

Physicists who embraced the corpuscular theory had nothing but their
own quickness of observation to rely upon. Fresnel having once seized
the conditions of the true undulatory theory, as previously stated
by Young, was enabled by the mere manipulation of his mathematical
symbols to foresee many of the complicated phenomena of light. Who
could possibly suppose, that by stopping a portion of the rays
passing through a circular aperture, the illumination of a point upon
a screen behind the aperture might be many times multiplied. Yet this
paradoxical effect was predicted by Fresnel, and verified both by
himself, and in a careful repetition of the experiment, by Billet.
Few persons are aware that in the middle of the shadow of an opaque
circular disc is a point of light sensibly as bright as if no disc
had been interposed. This startling fact was deduced from Fresnel’s
theory by Poisson, and was then verified experimentally by Arago.
Airy, again, was led by pure theory to predict that Newton’s rings
would present a modified appearance if produced between a lens of
glass and a plate of metal. This effect happened to have been observed
fifteen years before by Arago, unknown to Airy. Another prediction of
Airy, that there would be a further modification of the rings when
made between two substances of very different refractive indices, was
verified by subsequent trial with a diamond. A reversal of the rings
takes place when the space intervening between the plates is filled
with a substance of intermediate refractive power, another phenomenon
predicted by theory and verified by experiment. There is hardly a limit
to the number of other complicated effects of the interference of rays
of light under different circumstances which might be deduced from
the mathematical expressions, if it were worth while, or which, being
previously observed, can be explained. An interesting case was observed
by Herschel and explained by Airy.[449]

  [449] Airy’s *Mathematical Tracts*, 3rd edit. p. 312.

By a somewhat different effort of scientific foresight, Fresnel
discovered that any solid transparent medium might be endowed with the
power of double refraction by mere compression. As he attributed the
double refracting power of crystals to unequal elasticity in different
directions, he inferred that unequal elasticity, if artificially
produced, would give similar phenomena. With a powerful screw and a
piece of glass, he then produced not only the colours due to double
refraction, but the actual duplication of images. Thus, by a great
scientific generalisation, are the remarkable properties of Iceland
spar shown to belong to all transparent substances under certain
conditions.[450]

  [450] Young’s *Works*, vol. i. p. 412.

All other predictions in optical science are, however, thrown into the
shade by the theoretical discovery of conical refraction by the late
Sir W. R. Hamilton, of Dublin. In investigating the passage of light
through certain crystals, Hamilton found that Fresnel had slightly
misinterpreted his own formulæ, and that, when rightly understood,
they indicated a phenomenon of a kind never witnessed. A small ray of
light sent into a crystal of arragonite in a particular direction,
becomes spread out into an infinite number of rays, which form a hollow
cone within the crystal, and a hollow cylinder when emerging from the
opposite side. In another case, a different, but equally strange,
effect is produced, a ray of light being spread out into a hollow cone
at the point where it quits the crystal. These phenomena are peculiarly
interesting, because cones and cylinders of light are not produced
in any other cases. They are opposed to all analogy, and constitute
singular exceptions, of a kind which we shall afterwards consider more
fully. Their strangeness rendered them peculiarly fitted to test the
truth of the theory by which they were discovered; and when Professor
Lloyd, at Hamilton’s request, succeeded, after considerable difficulty,
in witnessing the new appearances, no further doubt could remain of
the validity of the wave theory which we owe to Huyghens, Young, and
Fresnel.[451]

  [451] Lloyd’s *Wave Theory*, Part ii. pp. 52–58. Babbage, *Ninth
  Bridgewater Treatise*, p. 104, quoting Lloyd, *Transactions of the
  Royal Irish Academy*, vol. xvii. Clifton, *Quarterly Journal of Pure
  and Applied Mathematics*, January 1860.


*Predictions from the Theory of Undulations.*

It is curious that the undulations of light, although inconceivably
rapid and small, admit of more accurate measurement than waves of any
other kind. But so far as we can carry out exact experiments on other
kinds of waves, we find the phenomena of interference repeated, and
analogy gives considerable power of prediction. Herschel was perhaps
the first to suggest that two sounds might be made to destroy each
other by interference.[452] For if one-half of a wave travelling
through a tube could be separated, and conducted by a longer passage,
so as, on rejoining the other half, to be one-quarter of a vibration
behind-hand, the two portions would exactly neutralise each other.
This experiment has been performed with success. The interference
arising between the waves from the two prongs of a tuning-fork was
also predicted by theory, and proved to exist by Weber; indeed it may
be observed by merely holding a vibrating fork close to the ear and
turning it round.[453]

  [452] *Encyclopædia Metropolitana*, art. *Sound*, p. 753.

  [453] Tyndall’s *Sound*, pp. 261, 273.

It is a result of the theory of sound that, if we move rapidly towards
a sounding body, or if it move rapidly towards us, the pitch of the
sound will be a little more acute; and, *vice versâ*, when the relative
motion is in the opposite direction, the pitch will be more grave. This
arises from the less or greater intervals of time elapsing between the
successive strokes of waves upon the auditory nerve, according as the
ear moves towards or from the source of sound relatively speaking.
This effect was predicted by theory, and afterwards verified by the
experiments of Buys Ballot, on Dutch railways, and of Scott Russell, in
England. Whenever one railway train passes another, on the locomotive
of which the whistle is being sounded, the drop in the acuteness of
the sound may be noticed at the moment of passing. This change gives
the sound a peculiar howling character, which many persons must have
noticed. I have calculated that with two trains travelling thirty miles
an hour, the effect would amount to rather more than half a tone, and
with some express trains it would amount to a tone. A corresponding
effect is produced in the case of light undulations, when the eye and
the luminous body approach or recede from each other. It is shown by
a slight change in the refrangibility of the rays of light, and a
consequent change in the place of the lines of the spectrum, which has
been made to give important and unexpected information concerning the
relative approach or recession of stars.

Tides are vast waves, and were the earth’s surface entirely covered
by an ocean of uniform depth, they would admit of exact theoretical
investigation. The irregular form of the seas introduces unknown
quantities and complexities with which theory cannot cope.
Nevertheless, Whewell, observing that the tides of the German Ocean
consist of interfering waves, which arrive partly round the North of
Scotland and partly through the British Channel, was enabled to predict
that at a point about midway between Brill on the coast of Holland,
and Lowestoft no tides would be found to exist. At that point the two
waves would be of the same amount, but in opposite phases, so as to
neutralise each other. This prediction was verified by a surveying
vessel of the British navy.[454]

  [454] Whewell’s *History of the Inductive Sciences*, vol. ii. p. 471.
  Herschel’s *Physical Geography*, § 77.


*Prediction in other Sciences.*

Generations, or even centuries, may elapse before mankind are
in possession of a mathematical theory of the constitution of
matter as complete as the theory of gravitation. Nevertheless,
mathematical physicists have in recent years acquired a hold of some
of the relations of the physical forces, and the proof is found in
anticipations of curious phenomena which had never been observed.
Professor James Thomson deduced from Carnot’s theory of heat that the
application of pressure would lower the melting-point of ice. He even
ventured to assign the amount of this effect, and his statement was
afterwards verified by Sir W. Thomson.[455] “In this very remarkable
speculation, an entirely novel physical phenomenon was *predicted*, in
anticipation of any direct experiments on the subject; and the actual
observation of the phenomenon was pointed out as a highly interesting
object for experimental research.” Just as liquids which expand in
solidifying will have the temperature of solidification lowered by
pressure, so liquids which contract in solidifying will exhibit the
reverse effect. They will be assisted in solidifying, as it were,
by pressure, so as to become solid at a higher temperature, as the
pressure is greater. This latter result was verified by Bunsen and
Hopkins, in the case of paraffin, spermaceti, wax, and stearin. The
effect upon water has more recently been carried to such an extent by
Mousson, that under the vast pressure of 1300 atmospheres, water did
not freeze until cooled down to -18°C. Another remarkable prediction
of Professor Thomson was to the effect that, if a metallic spring
be weakened by a rise of temperature, work done against the spring
in bending it will cause a cooling effect. Although the effect to
be expected in a certain apparatus was only about four-thousandths
of a degree Centigrade, Dr. Joule[456] succeeded in measuring it to
the extent of three-thousandths of a degree, such is the delicacy of
modern heat measurements. I cannot refrain from quoting Dr. Joule’s
reflections upon this fact. “Thus even in the above delicate case,” he
says, “is the formula of Professor Thomson completely verified. The
mathematical investigation of the thermo-elastic qualities of metals
has enabled my illustrious friend to predict with certainty a whole
class of highly interesting phenomena. To him especially do we owe
the important advance which has been recently made to a new era in
the history of science, when the famous philosophical system of Bacon
will be to a great extent superseded, and when, instead of arriving at
discovery by induction from experiment, we shall obtain our largest
accessions of new facts by reasoning deductively from fundamental
principles.”

  [455] Maxwell’s *Theory of Heat*, p. 174. *Philosophical Magazine*,
  August 1850. Third Series, vol. xxxvii. p. 123.

  [456] *Philosophical Transactions*, 1858, vol. cxlviii. p. 127.

The theory of electricity is a necessary part of the general theory of
matter, and is rapidly acquiring the power of prevision. As soon as
Wheatstone had proved experimentally that the conduction of electricity
occupies time, Faraday remarked in 1838, with wonderful sagacity,
that if the conducting wires were connected with the coatings of a
large Leyden jar, the rapidity of conduction would be lessened. This
prediction remained unverified for sixteen years, until the submarine
cable was laid beneath the Channel. A considerable retardation of the
electric spark was then detected, and Faraday at once pointed out that
the wire surrounded by water resembles a Leyden jar on a large scale,
so that each message sent through the cable verified his remark of
1838.[457]

  [457] Tyndall’s *Faraday*, pp. 73, 74; *Life of Faraday*, vol. ii.
  pp. 82, 83.

The joint relations of heat and electricity to the metals constitute a
new science of thermo-electricity by which Sir W. Thomson was enabled
to anticipate the following curious effect, namely, that an electric
current passing in an iron bar from a hot to a cold part produces a
cooling effect, but in a copper bar the effect is exactly opposite in
character, that is, the bar becomes heated.[458] The action of crystals
with regard to heat and electricity was partly foreseen on the grounds
of theory by Poisson.

  [458] Tait’s *Thermodynamics*, p. 77.

Chemistry, although to a great extent an empirical science, has not
been without prophetic triumphs. The existence of the metals potassium
and sodium was foreseen by Lavoisier, and their elimination by Davy was
one of the chief *experimenta crucis* which established Lavoisier’s
system. The existence of many other metals which eye had never seen
was a natural inference, and theory has not been at fault. In the
above cases the compounds of the metal were well known, and it was the
result of decomposition that was foretold. The discovery in 1876 of the
metal gallium is peculiarly interesting because the existence of this
metal, previously wholly unknown, had been inferred from theoretical
considerations by M. Mendelief, and some of its properties had been
correctly predicted. No sooner, too, had a theory of organic compounds
been conceived by Professor A. W. Williamson than he foretold the
formation of a complex substance consisting of water in which both
atoms of hydrogen are replaced by atoms of acetyle. This substance,
known as the acetic anhydride, was afterwards produced by Gerhardt. In
the subsequent progress of organic chemistry occurrences of this kind
have become common. The theoretical chemist by the classification of
his specimens and the manipulation of his formulæ can plan out whole
series of unknown oils, acids, and alcohols, just as a designer might
draw out a multitude of patterns. Professor Cayley has even calculated
for certain cases the possible numbers of chemical compounds.[459] The
formation of many such substances is a matter of course; but there is
an interesting prediction given by Hofmann, concerning the possible
existence of new compounds of sulphur and selenium, and even oxides of
ammonium, which it remains for chemists to verify.[460]

  [459] *On the Analytical Forms called Trees, with Application to the
  Theory of Chemical Combinations.* Report of the British Association,
  1875, p. 257.

  [460] Hofmann’s *Introduction to Chemistry*, pp. 224, 225.


*Prediction by Inversion of Cause and Effect.*

There is one process of experiment which has so often led to important
discoveries as to deserve separate illustration--I mean the inversion
of Cause and Effect. Thus if A and B in one experiment produce C as a
consequent, then antecedents of the nature of B and C may usually be
made to produce a consequent of the nature of A inverted in direction.
When we apply heat to a gas it tends to expand; hence if we allow the
gas to expand by its own elastic force, cold is the result; that is,
B (air) and C (expansion) produce the negative of A (heat). Again, B
(air) and compression, the negative of C, produce A (heat). Similar
results may be expected in a multitude of cases. It is a familiar
law that heat expands iron. What may be expected, then, if instead
of increasing the length of an iron bar by heat we use mechanical
force and stretch the bar? Having the bar and the former consequent,
expansion, we should expect the negative of the former antecedent,
namely cold. The truth of this inference was proved by Dr. Joule, who
investigated the amount of the effect with his usual skill.[461]

  [461] *Philosophical Transactions* (1855), vol. cxlv. pp. 100, &c.

This inversion of cause and effect in the case of heat may be itself
inverted in a highly curious manner. It happens that there are a
few substances which are unexplained exceptions to the general law
of expansion by heat. India-rubber especially is remarkable for
*contracting* when heated. Since, then, iron and india-rubber are
oppositely related to heat, we may expect that as distension of the
iron produced cold, distension of the india-rubber will produce heat.
This is actually found to be the case, and anyone may detect the effect
by suddenly stretching an india-rubber band while the middle part is
in the mouth. When being stretched it grows slightly warm, and when
relaxed cold.

The reader will see that some of the scientific predictions mentioned
in preceding sections were due to the principle of inversion; for
instance, Thomson’s speculations on the relation between pressure and
the melting-point. But many other illustrations could be adduced.
The usual agent by which we melt a substance is heat; but if we can
melt a substance without heat, then we may expect the negative of
heat as an effect. This is the foundation of all freezing mixtures.
The affinity of salt for water causes it to melt ice, and we may thus
reduce the temperature to Fahrenheit’s zero. Calcium chloride has so
much higher an attraction for water that a temperature of -45° C. may
be attained by its use. Even the solution of a certain alloy of lead,
tin, and bismuth in mercury, may be made to reduce the temperature
through 27° C. All the other modes of producing cold are inversions of
more familiar uses of heat. Carré’s freezing machine is an inverted
distilling apparatus, the distillation being occasioned by chemical
affinity instead of heat. Another kind of freezing machine is the exact
inverse of the steam-engine.

A very paradoxical effect is due to another inversion. It is hard to
believe that a current of steam at 100° C. can raise a body of liquid
to a higher temperature than the steam itself possesses. But Mr. Spence
has pointed out that if the boiling-point of a saline solution be
above 100°, it will continue, on account of its affinity for water, to
condense steam when above 100° in temperature. It will condense the
steam until heated to the point at which the tension of its vapour is
equal to that of the atmosphere, that is, its own boiling-point.[462]
Again, since heat melts ice, we might expect to produce heat by the
inverse change from water into ice. This is accomplished in the
phenomenon of suspended freezing. Water may be cooled in a clean glass
vessel many degrees below the freezing-point, and yet retained in the
liquid condition. But if disturbed, and especially if brought into
contact with a small particle of ice, it instantly solidifies and rises
in temperature to 0° C. The effect is still better displayed in the
lecture-room experiment of the suspended crystallisation of a solution
of sodium sulphate, in which a sudden rise of temperature of 15° or
20° C. is often manifested.

  [462] *Proceedings of the Manchester Philosophical Society*, Feb.
  1870.

The science of electricity is full of most interesting cases of
inversion. As Professor Tyndall has remarked, Faraday had a profound
belief in the reciprocal relations of the physical forces. The great
starting-point of his researches, the discovery of electro-magnetism,
was clearly an inversion. Oersted and Ampère had proved that with
an electric current and a magnet in a particular position as
antecedents, motion is the consequent. If then a magnet, a wire and
motion be the antecedents, an *opposite* electric current will be the
consequent. It would be an endless task to trace out the results of
this fertile relationship. Another part of Faraday’s researches was
occupied in ascertaining the direct and inverse relations of magnetic
and diamagnetic, amorphous and crystalline substances in various
circumstances. In all other relations of electricity the principle of
inversion holds. The voltameter or the electro-plating cell is the
inverse of the galvanic battery. As heat applied to a junction of
antimony and bismuth bars produces electricity, it follows that an
electric current passed through such a junction will produce cold. But
it is now sufficiently apparent that inversion of cause and effect is a
most fertile means of discovery and prediction.


*Facts known only by Theory.*

Of the four classes of facts enumerated in p. 525 the last remains
unconsidered. It includes the unverified predictions of science.
Scientific prophecy arrests the attention of the world when it refers
to such striking events as an eclipse, the appearance of a great comet,
or any phenomenon which people can verify with their own eyes. But
it is surely a matter for greater wonder that a physicist describes
and measures phenomena which eye cannot see, nor sense of any kind
detect. In most cases this arises from the effect being too small in
amount to affect our organs of sense, or come within the powers of our
instruments as at present constructed. But there is a class of yet more
remarkable cases, in which a phenomenon cannot possibly be observed,
and yet we can say what it would be if it were observed.

In astronomy, systematic aberration is an effect of the sun’s proper
motion almost certainly known to exist, but which we have no hope of
detecting by observation in the present age of the world. As the
earth’s motion round the sun combined with the motion of light causes
the stars to deviate apparently from their true positions to the extent
of about 18″ at the most, so the motion of the whole planetary system
through space must occasion a similar displacement of at most 5″. The
ordinary aberration can be readily detected with modern astronomical
instruments, because it goes through a yearly change in direction or
amount; but systematic aberration is constant so long as the planetary
system moves uniformly in a sensibly straight line. Only then in the
course of ages, when the curvature of the sun’s path becomes apparent,
can we hope to verify the existence of this kind of aberration. A
curious effect must also be produced by the sun’s proper motion upon
the apparent periods of revolution of the binary stars.

To my mind, some of the most interesting truths in the whole range of
science are those which have not been, and in many cases probably never
can be, verified by trial. Thus the chemist assigns, with a very high
degree of probability, the vapour densities of such elements as carbon
and silicon, which have never been observed separately in a state of
vapour. The chemist is also familiar with the vapour densities of
elements at temperatures at which the elements in question never have
been, and probably never can be, submitted to experiment in the form of
vapour.

Joule and others have calculated the actual velocity of the molecules
of a gas, and even the number of collisions which must take place per
second during their constant circulation. Physicists have not yet given
us the exact magnitudes of the particles of matter, but they have
ascertained by several methods the limits within which their magnitudes
must lie. Such scientific results must be for ever beyond the power of
verification by the senses. I have elsewhere had occasion to remark
that waves of light, the intimate processes of electrical changes,
the properties of the ether which is the base of all phenomena, are
necessarily determined in a hypothetical, but not therefore a less
certain manner.

Though only two of the metals, gold and silver, have ever been
observed to be transparent, we know on the grounds of theory that
they are all more or less so; we can even estimate by theory their
refractive indices, and prove that they are exceedingly high. The
phenomena of elliptic polarisation, and perhaps also those of internal
radiation,[463] depend upon the refractive index, and thus, even when
we cannot observe any refracted rays, we can indirectly learn how they
would be refracted.

  [463] Balfour Stewart, *Elementary Treatise on Heat*, 1st edit.
  p. 198.

In many cases large quantities of electricity must be produced, which
we cannot observe because it is instantly discharged. In the common
electric machine the cylinder and rubber are made of non-conductors,
so that we can separate and accumulate the electricity. But a little
damp, by serving as a conductor, prevents this separation from enduring
any sensible time. Hence there is no doubt that when we rub two good
conductors against each other, for instance two pieces of metals,
much electricity is produced, but instantaneously converted into some
other form of energy. Joule believes that all the heat of friction is
transmuted electricity.

As regards phenomena of insensible amount, nature is absolutely
full of them. We must regard those changes which we can observe as
the comparatively rare aggregates of minuter changes. On a little
reflection we must allow that no object known to us remains for two
instants of exactly the same temperature. If so, the dimensions of
objects must be in a perpetual state of variation. The minor planetary
and lunar perturbations are infinitely numerous, but usually too
small to be detected by observation, although their amounts may be
assigned by theory. There is every reason to believe that chemical
and electric actions of small amount are constantly in progress. The
hardest substances, if reduced to extremely small particles, and
diffused in pure water, manifest oscillatory movements which must be
due to chemical and electric changes, so slight that they go on for
years without affecting appreciably the weight of the particles.[464]
The earth’s magnetism must more or less affect every object which we
handle. As Tyndall remarks, “An upright iron stone influenced by the
earth’s magnetism becomes a magnet, with its bottom a north and its
top a south pole. Doubtless, though in an immensely feebler degree,
every erect marble statue is a true diamagnet, with its head a north
pole and its feet a south pole. The same is certainly true of man as
he stands upon the earth’s surface, for all the tissues of the human
body are diamagnetic.”[465] The sun’s light produces a very quick and
perceptible effect upon the photographic plate; in all probability it
has a less effect upon a great variety of substances. We may regard
every phenomenon as an exaggerated and conspicuous case of a process
which is, in infinitely numerous cases, beyond the means of observation.

  [464] Jevons, *Proceedings of the Manchester Literary and
  Philosophical Society*, 25th January, 1870, vol. ix. p. 78.

  [465] *Philosophical Transactions*, vol. cxlvi. p. 249.




CHAPTER XXV.

ACCORDANCE OF QUANTITATIVE THEORIES.


In the preceding chapter we found that facts may be classed under
four heads as regards their connection with theory, and our powers
of explanation or prediction. The facts hitherto considered were
generally of a qualitative rather than a quantitative nature; but when
we look exclusively to the quantity of a phenomenon, and the various
modes in which we may determine its amount, nearly the same system of
classification will hold good. There will, however, be five possible
cases:--

(1) We may directly and empirically measure a phenomenon, without being
able to explain why it should have any particular quantity, or to
connect it by theory with other quantities.

(2) In a considerable number of cases we can theoretically predict the
existence of a phenomenon, but are unable to assign its amount, except
by direct measurement, or to explain the amount theoretically when thus
ascertained.

(3) We may measure a quantity, and afterwards explain it as related to
other quantities, or as governed by known quantitative laws.

(4) We may predict the quantity of an effect on theoretical grounds,
and afterwards confirm the prediction by direct measurement.

(5) We may indirectly determine the quantity of an effect without being
able to verity it by experiment.

These classes of quantitative facts might be illustrated by an immense
number of interesting points in the history of physical science. Only
a few instances of each class can be given here.


*Empirical Measurements.*

Under the first head of purely empirical measurements, which have
not been brought under any theoretical system, may be placed the
great bulk of quantitative facts recorded by scientific observers.
The tables of numerical results which abound in books on chemistry
and physics, the huge quartos containing the observations of public
observatories, the multitudinous tables of meteorological observations,
which are continually being published, the more abstruse results
concerning terrestrial magnetism--such results of measurement, for
the most part, remain empirical, either because theory is defective,
or the labour of calculation and comparison is too formidable. In
the Greenwich Observatory, indeed, the salutary practice has been
maintained by the present Astronomer Royal, of always reducing the
observations, and comparing them with the theories of the several
bodies. The divergences from theory thus afford material for the
discovery of errors or of new phenomena; in short, the observations
have been turned to the use for which they were intended. But it is to
be feared that other establishments are too often engaged in merely
recording numbers of which no real use is made, because the labour
of reduction and comparison with theory is too great for private
inquirers to undertake. In meteorology, especially, great waste of
labour and money is taking place, only a small fraction of the results
recorded being ever used for the advancement of the science. For one
meteorologist like Quetelet, Dove, or Baxendell, who devotes himself to
the truly useful labour of reducing other people’s observations, there
are hundreds who labour under the delusion that they are advancing
science by loading our book-shelves with numerical tables. It is to
be feared, in like manner, that almost the whole bulk of statistical
numbers, whether commercial, vital, or moral, is of little scientific
value. Purely empirical measurements may have a direct practical value,
as when tables of the specific gravity, or strength of materials,
assist the engineer; the specific gravities of mixtures of water with
acids, alcohols, salts, &c., are useful in chemical manufactories,
custom-house gauging, &c.; observations of rainfall are requisite for
questions of water supply; the refractive index of various kinds of
glass must be known in making achromatic lenses; but in all such cases
the use made of the measurements is not scientific but practical. It
may be asserted, that no number which remains isolated, and uncompared
by theory with other numbers, is of scientific value. Having tried
the tensile strength of a piece of iron in a particular condition, we
know what will be the strength of the same kind of iron in a similar
condition, provided we can ever meet with that exact kind of iron
again; but we cannot argue from piece to piece, nor lay down any laws
exactly connecting the strength of iron with the quantity of its
impurities.


*Quantities indicated by Theory, but Empirically Measured.*

In many cases we are able to foresee the existence of a quantitative
effect, on the ground of general principles, but are unable, either
from the want of numerical data, or from the entire absence of any
mathematical theory, to assign the amount of such effect. We then
have recourse to direct experiment to determine its amount. Whether
we argued from the oceanic tides by analogy, or deductively from the
theory of gravitation, there could be no doubt that atmospheric tides
of some amount must occur in the atmosphere. Theory, however, even
in the hands of Laplace, was not able to overcome the complicated
mechanical conditions of the atmosphere, and predict the amounts of
such tides; and, on the other hand, these amounts were so small, and
were so masked by far larger undulations arising from the heating power
of the sun, and from other meteorological disturbances, that they would
probably have never been discovered by purely empirical observations.
Theory having, however, indicated their existence and their periods, it
was easy to make series of barometrical observations in places selected
so as to be as free as possible from casual fluctuations, and then, by
the suitable application of the method of means, to detect the small
effects in question. The principal lunar atmospheric tide was thus
proved to amount to between ·003 and ·004 inch.[466]

  [466] Grant’s *History of Physical Astronomy*, p. 162.

Theory yields the greatest possible assistance in applying the method
of means. For if we have a great number of empirical measurements, each
representing the joint effect of a number of causes, our object will
be to take the mean of all those in which the effect to be measured is
present, and compare it with the mean of the remainder in which the
effect is absent, or acts in the opposite direction. The difference
will then represent the amount of the effect, or double the amount
respectively. Thus, in the case of the atmospheric tides, we take
the mean of all the observations when the moon was on the meridian,
and compare it with the mean of all observations when she was on the
horizon. In this case we trust to chance that all other effects will
lie about as often in one direction as the other, and will neutralise
themselves in the drawing of each mean. It is a great advantage,
however, to be able to decide by theory when each principal disturbing
effect is present or absent; for the means may then be drawn so as to
separate each such effect, leaving only minor and casual divergences
to the law of error. Thus, if there be three principal effects, and
we draw means giving respectively the sum of all three, the sum of
the first two, and the sum of the last two, then we gain three simple
equations, by the solution of which each quantity is determined.


*Explained Results of Measurement.*

The second class of measured phenomena contains those which, after
being determined in a direct and purely empirical application of
measuring instruments, are afterwards shown to agree with some
hypothetical explanation. Such results are turned to their proper
use, and several advantages may arise from the comparison. The
correspondence with theory will seldom or never be precise; and, even
if it be so, the coincidence must be regarded as accidental.

If the divergences between theory and experiment be comparatively
small, and variable in amount and direction, they may often be safely
attributed to inconsiderable sources of error in the experimental
processes. The strict method of procedure is to calculate the probable
error of the mean of the observed results (p. 387), and then observe
whether the theoretical result falls within the limits of probable
error. If it does, and if the experimental results agree as well
with theory as they agree with each other, then the probability of
the theory is much increased, and we may employ the theory with more
confidence in the anticipation of further results. The probable error,
it should be remembered, gives a measure only of the effects of
incidental and variable sources of error, but in no degree indicates
the amount of fixed causes of error. Thus, if the mean results of
two modes of determining a quantity are so far apart that the limits
of probable error do not overlap, we may infer the existence of some
overlooked source of fixed error in one or both modes. We will further
consider in a subsequent section the discordance of measurements.


*Quantities determined by Theory and verified by Measurement.*

One of the most satisfactory tests of a theory consists in its
application not only to predict the nature of a phenomenon, and
the circumstances in which it may be observed, but also to assign
the precise quantity of the phenomenon. If we can subsequently
apply accurate instruments and measure the amount of the phenomenon
witnessed, we have an excellent opportunity of verifying or negativing
the theory. It was in this manner that Newton first attempted to verify
his theory of gravitation. He knew approximately the velocity produced
in falling bodies at the earth’s surface, and if the law of the inverse
square of the distance held true, and the reputed distance of the
moon was correct, he could infer that the moon ought to fall towards
the earth at the rate of fifteen feet in one minute. Now, the actual
divergence of the moon from the tangent of its orbit appeared to amount
only to thirteen feet in one minute, and there was a discrepancy of
two feet in fifteen, which caused Newton to lay “aside at that time
any further thoughts of this matter.” Many years afterwards, probably
fifteen or sixteen years, Newton obtained more precise data from which
he could calculate the size of the moon’s orbit, and he then found the
discrepancy to be inconsiderable.

His theory of gravitation was thus verified as far as the moon was
concerned; but this was to him only the beginning of a long course of
deductive calculations, each ending in a verification. If the earth
and moon attract each other, and also the sun and the earth, there
is reason to expect that the sun and moon should attract each other.
Newton followed out the consequences of this inference, and showed
that the moon would not move as if attracted by the earth only, but
sometimes faster and sometimes slower. Comparison with Flamsteed’s
observations of the moon showed that such was the case. Newton argued
again, that as the waters of the ocean are not rigidly attached to
the earth, they might attract the moon, and be attracted in return,
independently of the rest of the earth. Certain daily motions
resembling the tides would then be caused, and there were the tides to
verify the reasoning. It was the extraordinary power with which Newton
traced out geometrically the consequences of his theory, and submitted
them to repeated comparison with experience, which constitutes his
pre-eminence over all physicists.


*Quantities determined by Theory and not verified.*

It will continually happen that we are able, from certain measured
phenomena and a correct theory, to determine the amount of some other
phenomenon which we may either be unable to measure at all, or to
measure with an accuracy corresponding to that required to verify the
prediction. Thus Laplace having worked out a theory of the motions of
Jupiter’s satellites on the hypothesis of gravitation, found that these
motions were greatly affected by the spheroidal form of Jupiter. The
motions of the satellites can be observed with great accuracy owing to
their frequent eclipses and transits, and from these motions he was
able to argue inversely, and assign the ellipticity of the planet. The
ratio of the polar and equatorial axes thus determined was very nearly
that of 13 to 14; and it agrees well with such direct micrometrical
measurements of the planet as have been made; but Laplace believed
that the theory gave a more accurate result than direct observation
could yield, so that the theory could hardly be said to admit of direct
verification.

The specific heat of air was believed on the grounds of direct
experiment to amount to 0·2669, the specific heat of water being taken
as unity; but the methods of experiment were open to considerable
causes of error. Rankine showed in 1850 that it was possible
to calculate from the mechanical equivalent of heat and other
thermodynamic data, what this number should be, and he found it to
be 0·2378. This determination was at the time accepted as the most
satisfactory result, although not verified; subsequently in 1853
Regnault obtained by direct experiment the number 0·2377, proving that
the prediction had been well grounded.

It is readily seen that in quantitative questions verification is a
matter of degree and probability. A less accurate method of measurement
cannot verify the results of a more accurate method, so that if we
arrive at a determination of the same physical quantity in several
distinct modes it is often a delicate matter to decide which result
is most reliable, and should be used for the indirect determination
of other quantities. For instance, Joule’s and Thomson’s ingenious
experiments upon the thermal phenomena of fluids in motion[467]
involved, as one physical constant, the mechanical equivalent of
heat; if requisite, then, they might have been used to determine that
important constant. But if more direct methods of experiment give
the mechanical equivalent of heat with superior accuracy, then the
experiments on fluids will be turned to a better use in determining
various quantities relating to the theory of fluids. We will further
consider questions of this kind in succeeding sections.

  [467] *Philosophical Transactions* (1854), vol. cxliv. p. 364.

There are of course many quantities assigned on theoretical grounds
which we are quite unable to verify with corresponding accuracy. The
thickness of a film of gold leaf, the average depths of the oceans,
the velocity of a star’s approach to or regression from the earth as
inferred from spectroscopic data (pp. 296–99), are cases in point; but
many others might be quoted where direct verification seems impossible.
Newton and subsequent physicists have measured light undulations, and
by several methods we learn the velocity with which light travels.
Since an undulation of the middle green is about five ten-millionths
of a metre in length, and travels at the rate of nearly 300,000,000
of metres per second, it follows that about 600,000,000,000,000
undulations must strike in one second the retina of an eye which
perceives such light. But how are we to verify such an astounding
calculation by directly counting pulses which recur six hundred
billions of times in a second?


*Discordance of Theory and Experiment.*

When a distinct want of accordance is found to exist between the
results of theory and direct measurement, interesting questions arise
as to the mode in which we can account for this discordance. The
ultimate explanation of the discrepancy may be accomplished in at least
four ways as follows:--

(1) The direct measurement may be erroneous owing to various sources of
casual error.

(2) The theory may be correct as far as regards the general form of the
supposed laws, but some of the constant numbers or other quantitative
data employed in the theoretical calculations may be inaccurate.

(3) The theory may be false, in the sense that the forms of the
mathematical equations assumed to express the laws of nature are
incorrect.

(4) The theory and the involved quantities may be approximately
accurate, but some regular unknown cause may have interfered, so that
the divergence may be regarded as a *residual effect* representing
possibly a new and interesting phenomenon.

No precise rules can be laid down as to the best mode of proceeding to
explain the divergence, and the experimentalist will have to depend
upon his own insight and knowledge; but the following recommendations
may be made.

If the experimental measurements are not numerous, repeat them and
take a more extensive mean result, the probable accuracy of which,
as regards casual errors, will increase as the square root of the
number of experiments. Supposing that no considerable modification
of the result is thus effected, we may suspect the existence of more
deep-seated sources of error in our method of measurement. The next
resource will be to change the size and form of the apparatus employed,
and to introduce various modifications in the materials employed or the
course of procedure, in the hope (p. 396) that some cause of constant
error may thus be removed. If the inconsistency with theory still
remains unreduced we may attempt to invent some widely different mode
of arriving at the same physical quantity, so that we may be almost
sure that the same cause of error will not affect both the new and old
results. In some cases it is possible to find five or six essentially
different modes of arriving at the same determination.

Supposing that the discrepancy still exists we may begin to suspect
that our direct measurements are correct, and that the data employed
in the theoretical calculations are inaccurate. We must now review the
grounds on which these data depend, consisting as they must ultimately
do of direct measurements. A comparison of the recorded data will
show the degree of probability attaching to the mean result employed;
and if there is any ground for imagining the existence of error, we
should repeat the observations, and vary the forms of experiment just
as in the case of the previous direct measurements. The continued
existence of the discrepancy must show that we have not attained to
a complete acquaintance with the theory of the causes in action, but
two different cases still remain. We may have misunderstood the action
of those causes which we know to exist, or we may have overlooked the
existence of one or more other causes. In the first case our hypothesis
appears to be wrongly chosen and inapplicable; but whether we are to
reject it will depend upon whether we can form another hypothesis which
yields a more accurate accordance. The probability of an hypothesis,
it will be remembered (p. 243), is to be judged, in the absence of *à
priori* grounds of judgment, by the probability that if the supposed
causes exist the observed result follows; but as there is now little
probability of reconciling the original hypothesis with our direct
measurements the field is open for new hypotheses, and any one which
gives a closer accordance with measurement will so far have better
claims to attention. Of course we must never estimate the probability
of an hypothesis merely by its accordance with a few results only. Its
general analogy and accordance with other known laws of nature, and
the fact that it does not conflict with other probable theories, must
be taken into account, as we shall see in the next book. The requisite
condition of a good hypothesis, that it must admit of the deduction
of facts verified in observation, must be interpreted in the widest
manner, as including all ways in which there may be accordance or
discordance. All our attempts at reconciliation having failed, the only
conclusion we can come to is that some unknown cause of a new character
exists. If the measurements be accurate and the theory probable,
then there remains a *residual phenomenon*, which, being devoid of
theoretical explanation, must be set down as a new empirical fact
worthy of further investigation. Outstanding residual discrepancies
have often been found to involve new discoveries of the greatest
importance.


*Accordance of Measurements of Astronomical Distances.*

One of the most instructive instances which we can meet, of the
manner in which different measurements confirm or check each other,
is furnished by the determination of the velocity of light, and the
dimensions of the planetary system. Roemer first discovered that light
requires time to travel, by observing that the eclipses of Jupiter’s
satellites, although they occur at fixed moments of absolute time, are
visible at different moments in different parts of the earth’s orbit,
according to the distance between the earth and Jupiter. The time
occupied by light in traversing the mean semi-diameter of the earth’s
orbit is found to be about eight minutes. The mean distance of the sun
and earth was long assumed by astronomers as being about 95,274,000
miles, this result being deduced by Bessel from the observations of the
transit of Venus, which occurred in 1769, and which were found to give
the solar parallax, or which is the same thing, the apparent angular
magnitude of the earth seen from the sun, as equal to 8″·578. Dividing
the mean distance of the sun and earth by the number of seconds in
8^{m}. 13^{s}.3 we find the velocity of light to be about 192,000 miles
per second.

Nearly the same result was obtained in what seems a different manner.
The aberration of light is the apparent change in the direction of a
ray of light owing to the composition of its motion with that of the
earth’s motion round the sun. If we know the amount of aberration and
the mean velocity of the earth, we can estimate that of light, which
is thus found to be 191,100 miles per second. Now this determination
depends upon a new physical quantity, that of aberration, which is
ascertained by direct observation of the stars, so that the close
accordance of the estimates of the velocity of light as thus arrived
at by different methods might seem to leave little room for doubt, the
difference being less than one per cent.

Nevertheless, experimentalists were not satisfied until they had
succeeded in measuring the velocity of light by direct experiments
performed upon the earth’s surface. Fizeau, by a rapidly revolving
toothed wheel, estimated the velocity at 195,920 miles per second.
As this result differed by about one part in sixty from estimates
previously accepted, there was thought to be room for further
investigation. The revolving mirror, used by Wheatstone in measuring
the velocity of electricity, was now applied in a more refined manner
by Fizeau and by Foucault to determine the velocity of light. The
latter physicist came to the startling conclusion that the velocity
was not really more than 185,172 miles per second. No repetition of
the experiment would shake this result, and there was accordingly a
discrepancy between the astronomical and the experimental results
of about 7,000 miles per second. The latest experiments, those of
M. Cornu, only slightly raise the estimate, giving 186,660 miles
per second. A little consideration shows that both the astronomical
determinations involve the magnitude of the earth’s orbit as one datum,
because our estimate of the earth’s velocity in its orbit depends upon
our estimate of the sun’s mean distance. Accordingly as regards this
quantity the two astronomical results count only for one. Though the
transit of Venus had been considered to give the best data for the
calculation of the sun’s parallax, yet astronomers had not neglected
less favourable opportunities. Hansen, calculating from certain
inequalities in the moon’s motion, had estimated it at 8″·916; Winneke,
from observations of Mars, at 8″·964; Leverrier, from the motions
of Mars, Venus, and the moon, at 8″·950. These independent results
agree much better with each other than with that of Bessel (8″·578)
previously received, or that of Encke (8″·58) deduced from the transits
of Venus in 1761 and 1769, and though each separately might be worthy
of less credit, yet their close accordance renders their mean result
(8″·943) comparable in probability with that of Bessel. It was further
found that if Foucault’s value for the velocity of light were assumed
to be correct, and the sun’s distance were inversely calculated from
that, the sun’s parallax would be 8″·960, which closely agreed with
the above mean result. This further correspondence of independent
results threw the balance of probability strongly against the results
of the transit of Venus, and rendered it desirable to reconsider
the observations made on that occasion. Mr. E. J. Stone, having
re-discussed those observations,[468] found that grave oversights had
been made in the calculations, which being corrected would alter the
estimate of parallax to 8″·91, a quantity in such comparatively close
accordance with the other results that astronomers did not hesitate
at once to reduce their estimate of the sun’s mean distance from
95,274,000 to 91,771,000, miles, although this alteration involved a
corresponding correction in the assumed magnitudes and distances of
most of the heavenly bodies. The solar parallax is now (1875) believed
to be about 8″·878, the number deduced from Cornu’s experiments on the
velocity of light. This result agrees very closely with 8″·879, the
estimate obtained from new observations on the transit of Venus, by the
French observers, and with 8″·873, the result of Galle’s observations
of the planet Flora. When all the observations of the late transit of
Venus are fully discussed the sun’s distance will probably be known to
less than one part in a thousand, if not one part in ten thousand.[469]

  [468] *Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society*,
  vol. xxviii. p. 264.

  [469] It would seem to be absurd to repeat the profuse expenditure of
  1874 at the approaching transit in 1882. The aggregate sum spent in
  1874 by various governments and individuals can hardly be less than
  £200,000, a sum which, wisely expended on scientific investigations,
  would give a hundred important results.

In this question the theoretical relations between the velocity of
light, the constant of aberration, the sun’s parallax, and the sun’s
mean distance, are of the simplest character, and can hardly be
open to any doubt, so that the only doubt was as to which result of
observation was the most reliable. Eventually the chief discrepancy was
found to arise from misapprehension in the reduction of observations,
but we have a satisfactory example of the value of different methods
of estimation in leading to the detection of a serious error. Is it
not surprising that Foucault by measuring the velocity of light when
passing through the space of a few yards, should lead the way to a
change in our estimates of the magnitudes of the whole universe?


*Selection of the best Mode of Measurement.*

When we once obtain command over a question of physical science
by comprehending the theory of the subject, we often have a wide
choice opened to us as regards the methods of measurement, which may
thenceforth be made to give the most accurate results. If we can
measure one fundamental quantity very precisely we may be able by
theory to determine accurately many other quantitative results. Thus,
if we determine satisfactorily the atomic weights of certain elements,
we do not need to determine with equal accuracy the composition and
atomic weights of their several compounds. Having learnt the relative
atomic weights of oxygen and sulphur, we can calculate the composition
by weight of the several oxides of sulphur. Chemists accordingly select
with the greatest care that compound of two elements which seems to
allow of the most accurate analysis, so as to give the ratio of their
atomic weights. It is obvious that we only need the ratio of the atomic
weight of each element to that of some common element, in order to
calculate, that of each to each. Moreover the atomic weight stands
in simple relation to other quantitative facts. The weights of equal
volumes of elementary gases at equal temperature and pressure have
the same ratios as the atomic weights; now, as nitrogen under such
circumstances weighs 14·06 times as much as hydrogen, we may infer that
the atomic weight of nitrogen is about 14·06, or more probably 14·00,
that of hydrogen being unity. There is much evidence, again, that the
specific heats of elements are inversely as their atomic weights, so
that these two classes of quantitative data throw light mutually upon
each other. In fact the atomic weight, the atomic volume, and the
atomic heat of an element, are quantities so closely connected that
the determination of one will lead to that of the others. The chemist
has to solve a complicated problem in deciding in the case of each
of 60 or 70 elements which mode of determination is most accurate.
Modern chemistry presents us with an almost infinitely extensive web of
numerical ratios developed out of a few fundamental ratios.

In hygrometry we have a choice among at least four modes of measuring
the quantity of aqueous vapour contained in a given bulk of air. We
can extract the vapour by absorption in sulphuric acid, and directly
weigh its amount; we can place the air in a barometer tube and observe
how much the absorption of the vapour alters the elastic force of the
air; we can observe the dew-point of the air, that is the temperature
at which the vapour becomes saturated; or, lastly, we can insert a dry
and wet bulb thermometer and observe the temperature of an evaporating
surface. The results of each mode can be connected by theory with
those of the other modes, and we can select for each experiment that
mode which is most accurate or most convenient. The chemical method
of direct measurement is capable of the greatest accuracy, but is
troublesome; the dry and wet bulb thermometer is sufficiently exact for
meteorological purposes and is most easy to use.


*Agreement of Distinct Modes of Measurement.*

Many illustrations might be given of the accordance which has been
found to exist in some cases between the results of entirely different
methods of arriving at the measurement of a physical quantity. While
such accordance must, in the absence of information to the contrary,
be regarded as the best possible proof of the approximate correctness
of the mean result, yet instances have occurred to show that we can
never take too much trouble in confirming results of great importance.
When three or even more distinct methods have given nearly coincident
numbers, a new method has sometimes disclosed a discrepancy which it is
yet impossible to explain.

The ellipticity of the earth is known with considerable approach to
certainty and accuracy, for it has been estimated in three independent
ways. The most direct mode is to measure long arcs extending north and
south upon the earth’s surface, by means of trigonometrical surveys,
and then to compare the lengths of these arcs with their curvature as
determined by observations of the altitude of certain stars at the
terminal points. The most probable ellipticity of the earth deduced
from all measurements of this kind was estimated by Bessel at 1/300,
though subsequent measurements might lead to a slightly different
estimate. The divergence from a globular form causes a small variation
in the force of gravity at different parts of the earth’s surface,
so that exact pendulum observations give the data for an independent
estimate of the ellipticity, which is thus found to be 1/320. In the
third place the spheroidal protuberance about the earth’s equator leads
to a certain inequality in the moon’s motion, as shown by Laplace;
and from the amount of that inequality, as given by observations,
Laplace was enabled to calculate back to the amount of its cause.
He thus inferred that the ellipticity is 1/305, which lies between
the two numbers previously given, and was considered by him the most
satisfactory determination. In this case the accordance is undisturbed
by subsequent results, so that we are obliged to accept Laplace’s
result as a highly probable one.

The mean density of the earth is a constant of high importance, because
it is necessary for the determination of the masses of all the other
heavenly bodies. Astronomers and physicists accordingly have bestowed
a great deal of labour upon the exact estimation of this constant.
The method of procedure consists in comparing the gravitation of the
globe with that of some body of matter of which the mass is known in
terms of the assumed unit of mass. This body of matter, serving as
an intermediate term of comparison, may be variously chosen; it may
consist of a mountain, or a portion of the earth’s crust, or a heavy
ball of metal. The method of experiment varies so much according as
we select one body or the other, that we may be said to have three
independent modes of arriving at the desired result.

The mutual gravitation of two balls is so exceedingly small compared
with their gravitation towards the immense mass of the earth, that it
is usually quite imperceptible, and although asserted by Newton to
exist, on the ground of theory, was never observed until the end of the
18th century. Michell attached two small balls to the extremities of
a delicately suspended torsion balance, and then bringing heavy balls
of lead alternately to either side of these small balls was able to
detect a slight deflection of the torsion balance. He thus furnished a
new verification of the theory of gravitation. Cavendish carried out
the experiment with more care, and estimated the gravitation of the
balls by treating the torsion balance as a pendulum; then taking into
account the respective distances of the balls from each other and from
the centre of the earth, he was able to assign 5·48 (or as re-computed
by Baily, 5·448) as the probable mean density of the earth. Newton’s
sagacious guess to the effect that the density of the earth was between
five and six times that of water, was thus remarkably confirmed. The
same kind of experiment repeated by Reich gave 5·438. Baily having
again performed the experiment with every possible refinement obtained
a slightly higher number, 5·660.

A different method of procedure consisted in ascertaining the effect
of a mountain mass in deflecting the plumb-line; for, assuming that
we can determine the dimensions and mean density of the mountain,
the plumb-line enables us to compare its mass with that of the whole
earth. The mountain Schehallien was selected for the experiment, and
observations and calculations performed by Maskelyne, Hutton, and
Playfair, gave as the most probable result 4·713. The difference from
the experimental results already mentioned is considerable and is
important, because the instrumental operations are of an entirely
different character from those of Cavendish and Baily’s experiments.
Sir Henry James’ similar determination from the attraction of Arthur’s
Seat gave 5·14.

A third distinct method consists in determining the force of gravity
at points elevated above the surface of the earth on mountain ranges,
or sunk below it in mines. Carlini experimented with a pendulum at the
hospice of Mont Cenis, 6,375 feet above the sea, and by comparing the
attractive forces of the earth and the Alps, found the density to be
still smaller, namely, 4·39, or as corrected by Giulio, 4·950. Lastly,
the Astronomer Royal has on two occasions adopted the opposite method
of observing a pendulum at the bottom of a deep mine, so as to compare
the density of the strata penetrated with the density of the whole
earth. On the second occasion he carried his method into effect at the
Harton Colliery, 1,260 feet deep; all that could be done by skill in
measurement and careful consideration of all the causes of error, was
accomplished in this elaborate series of observations[470] (p. 291).
No doubt Sir George Airy was much perplexed when he found that his
new result considerably exceeded that obtained by any other method,
being no less than 6·566, or 6·623 as finally corrected. In this
case we learn an impressive lesson concerning the value of repeated
determinations by distinct methods in disabusing our minds of the
reliance which we are only too apt to place in results which show a
certain degree of coincidence.

  [470] *Philosophical Transactions* (1856), vol. cxlvi. p. 342.

In 1844 Herschel remarked in his memoir of Francis Baily,[471]
“that the mean specific gravity of this our planet is, in all
human probability, quite as well determined as that of an ordinary
hand-specimen in a mineralogical cabinet,--a marvellous result, which
should teach us to despair of nothing which lies within the compass of
number, weight and measure.” But at the same time he pointed out that
Baily’s final result, of which the probable error was only 0·0032, was
the highest of all determinations then known, and Airy’s investigation
has since given a much higher result, quite beyond the limits of
probable error of any of the previous experiments. If we treat all
determinations yet made as of equal weight, the simple mean is about
5·45, the mean error nearly 0·5, and the probable error almost 0·2, so
that it is as likely as not that the truth lies between 5·65 and 5·25
on this view of the matter. But it is remarkable that the two most
recent and careful series of observations by Baily and Airy,[472] lie
beyond these limits, and as with the increase of care the estimate
rises, it seems requisite to reject the earlier results, and look upon
the question as still requiring further investigation. Physicists
often take 5-2/3 or 5·67 as the best guess at the truth, but it is
evident that new experiments are much required. I cannot help thinking
that a portion of the great sums of money which many governments and
private individuals spent upon the transit of Venus expeditions in
1874, and which they will probably spend again in 1882 (p. 562), would
be better appropriated to new determinations of the earth’s density.
It seems desirable to repeat Baily’s experiment in a vacuous case,
and with the greater mechanical refinements which the progress of the
last forty years places at the disposal of the experimentalist. It
would be desirable, also, to renew the pendulum experiments of Airy
in some other deep mine. It might even be well to repeat upon some
suitable mountain the observations performed at Schehallien. All these
operations might be carried out for the cost of one of the superfluous
transit expeditions.

  [471] *Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society*, for 8th
  Nov. 1844, No. X. vol. vi. p. 89.

  [472] *Philosophical Magazine*, 2nd Series, vol. xxvi. p. 61.

Since the establishment of the dynamical theory of heat it has become
a matter of the greatest importance to determine with accuracy the
mechanical equivalent of heat, or the quantity of energy which must
be given, or received, in a definite change of temperature effected
in a definite quantity of a standard substance, such as water. No
less than seven almost entirely distinct modes of determining this
constant have been tried. Dr. Joule first ascertained by the friction
of water that to raise the temperature of one kilogram of water through
one degree centigrade, we must employ energy sufficient to raise
424 kilograms through the height of one metre against the force of
gravity at the earth’s surface. Joule, Mayer, Clausius,[473] Favre
and other experimentalists have made determinations by less direct
methods. Experiments on the mechanical properties of gases give 426
kilogrammetres as the constant; the work done by a steam-engine
gives 413; from the heat evolved in electrical experiments several
determinations have been obtained; thus from induced electric currents
we get 452; from the electro-magnetic engine 443; from the circuit of a
battery 420; and, from an electric current, the lowest result of all,
namely, 400.[474]

  [473] Clausius in *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. ii.
  p. 119.

  [474] Watts’ *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. iii. p. 129.

Considering the diverse and in many cases difficult methods of
observation, these results exhibit satisfactory accordance, and their
mean (423·9) comes very close to the number derived by Dr. Joule from
the apparently most accurate method. The constant generally assumed as
the most probable result is 423·55 kilogrammetres.


*Residual Phenomena.*

Even when the experimental data employed in the verification of a
theory are sufficiently accurate, and the theory itself is sound, there
may exist discrepancies demanding further investigation. Herschel
pointed out the importance of such outstanding quantities, and called
them *residual phenomena*.[475] Now if the observations and the theory
be really correct, such discrepancies must be due to the incompleteness
of our knowledge of the causes in action, and the ultimate explanation
must consist in showing that there is in action, either

  [475] *Preliminary Discourse*, §§ 158, 174. *Outlines of Astronomy*,
  4th edit. § 856.

(1) Some agent of known nature whose presence was not suspected;

Or (2) Some new agent of unknown nature.

In the first case we can hardly be said to make a new discovery, for
our ultimate success consists merely in reconciling the theory with
known facts when our investigation is more comprehensive. But in
the second case we meet with a totally new fact, which may lead us
to realms of new discovery. Take the instance adduced by Herschel.
The theory of Newton and Halley concerning comets was that they
were gravitating bodies revolving round the sun in elliptic orbits,
and the return of Halley’s Comet, in 1758, verified this theory.
But, when accurate observations of Encke’s Comet came to be made,
the verification was not found to be exact. Encke’s Comet returned
each time a little sooner than it ought to do, the period regularly
decreasing from 1212·79 days, between 1786 and 1789, to 1210·44 between
1855 and 1858; and the hypothesis has been started that there is a
resisting medium filling the space through which the comet passes.
This hypothesis is a *deus ex machinâ* for explaining this solitary
phenomenon, and cannot possess much probability unless it can be
shown that other phenomena are deducible from it. Many persons have
identified this medium with that through which light undulations pass,
but I am not aware that there is anything in the undulatory theory of
light to show that the medium would offer resistance to a moving body.
If Professor Balfour Stewart can prove that a rotating disc would
experience resistance in a vacuous receiver, here is an experimental
fact which distinctly supports the hypothesis. But in the mean time
it is open to question whether other known agents, for instance
electricity, may not be brought in, and I have tried to show that if,
as is believed, the tail of a comet is an electrical phenomenon, it
is a necessary result of the conservation of energy that the comet
shall exhibit a loss of energy manifested in a diminution of its mean
distance from the sun and its period of revolution.[476] It should
be added that if Professor Tait’s theory be correct, as seems very
probable, and comets consist of swarms of small meteors, there is no
difficulty in accounting for the retardation. It has long been known
that a collection of small bodies travelling together in an orbit round
a central body will tend to fall towards it. In either case, then, this
residual phenomenon seems likely to be reconciled with known laws of
nature.

  [476] *Proceedings of the Manchester Literary and Philosophical
  Society*, 28th November, 1871, vol. xi. p. 33. Since the above
  remarks were written, Professor Balfour Stewart has pointed out to
  me his paper in the *Proceedings of the Manchester Literary and
  Philosophical Society* for 15th November, 1870 (vol. x. p. 32),
  in which he shows that a body moving in an enclosure of uniform
  temperature would probably experience resistance independently
  of the presence of a ponderable medium, such as gas, between the
  moving body and the enclosure. The proof is founded on the theory
  of the dissipation of energy, and this view is said to be accepted
  by Professors Thomson and Tait. The enclosure is used in this case
  by Professor Stewart simply as a means of obtaining a proof, just
  as it was used by him on a previous occasion to obtain a proof of
  certain consequences of the Theory of Exchanges. He is of opinion
  that in both of these cases when once the proof has been obtained,
  the enclosure may be dispensed with. We know, for instance, that
  the relation between the inductive and absorptive powers of
  bodies--although this relation may have been proved by means of an
  enclosure, does not depend upon its presence, and Professor Stewart
  thinks that in like manner two bodies, or at least two bodies
  possessing heat such as the sun and the earth in motion relative to
  each other, will have the differential motion retarded until perhaps
  it is ultimately destroyed.

In other cases residual phenomena have involved important inferences
not recognised at the time. Newton showed how the velocity of sound in
the atmosphere could be calculated by a theory of pulses or undulations
from the observed tension and density of the air. He inferred that
the velocity in the ordinary state of the atmosphere at the earth’s
surface would be 968 feet per second, and rude experiments made by
him in the cloisters of Trinity College seemed to show that this was
not far from the truth. Subsequently it was ascertained by other
experimentalists that the velocity of sound was more nearly 1,142 feet,
and the discrepancy being one-sixth part of the whole was far too much
to attribute to casual errors in the numerical data. Newton attempted
to explain away this discrepancy by hypotheses as to the reactions of
the molecules of air, but without success.

New investigations having been made from time to time concerning the
velocity of sound, both as observed experimentally and as calculated
from theory, it was found that each of Newton’s results was inaccurate,
the theoretical velocity being 916 feet per second, and the real
velocity about 1,090 feet. The discrepancy, nevertheless, remained
as serious as ever, and it was not until the year 1816 that Laplace
showed it to be due to the heat developed by the sudden compression
of the air in the passage of the wave, this heat having the effect of
increasing the elasticity of the air and accelerating the impulse. It
is now perceived that this discrepancy really involves the doctrine
of the equivalence of heat and energy, and it was applied by Mayer,
at least by implication, to give an estimate of the mechanical
equivalent of heat. The estimate thus derived agrees satisfactorily
with direct determinations by Dr. Joule and other physicists, so that
the explanation of the residual phenomenon which exercised Newton’s
ingenuity is now complete, and forms an important part of the new
science of thermodynamics.

As Herschel observed, almost all great astronomical discoveries
have been disclosed in the form of residual differences. It is the
practice at well-conducted observatories to compare the positions of
the heavenly bodies as actually observed with what might have been
expected theoretically. This practice was introduced by Halley when
Astronomer Royal, and his reduction of the lunar observations gave a
series of residual errors from 1722 to 1739, by the examination of
which the lunar theory was improved. Most of the greater astronomical
variations arising from nutation, aberration, planetary perturbation
were discovered in the same manner. The precession of the equinox was
perhaps the earliest residual difference observed; the systematic
divergence of Uranus from its calculated places was one of the latest,
and was the clue to the remarkable discovery of Neptune. We may also
class under residual phenomena all the so-called *proper motions* of
the stars. A complete star catalogue, such as that of the British
Association, gives a greater or less amount of proper motion for almost
every star, consisting in the apparent difference of position of the
star as derived from the earliest and latest good observations. But
these apparent motions are often due, as explained by Baily,[477] the
author of the catalogue, to errors of observation and reduction. In
many cases the best astronomical authorities have differed as to the
very direction of the supposed proper motion of stars, and as regards
the amount of the motion, for instance of α Polaris, the most different
estimates have been formed. Residual quantities will often be so small
that their very existence is doubtful. Only the gradual progress of
theory and of measurement will show clearly whether a discrepancy
is to be referred to casual errors of observation or to some new
phenomenon. But nothing is more requisite for the progress of science
than the careful recording and investigation of such discrepancies.
In no part of physical science can we be free from exceptions and
outstanding facts, of which our present knowledge can give no account.
It is among such anomalies that we must look for the clues to new
realms of facts worthy of discovery. They are like the floating waifs
which led Columbus to suspect the existence of the new world.

  [477] *British Association Catalogue of Stars*, p. 49.




CHAPTER XXVI.

CHARACTER OF THE EXPERIMENTALIST.


In the present age there seems to be a tendency to believe that the
importance of individual genius is less than it was--

  “The individual withers, and the world is more and more.”

Society, it is supposed, has now assumed so highly developed a form,
that what was accomplished in past times by the solitary exertions of a
great intellect, may now be worked out by the united labours of an army
of investigators. Just as the well-organised power of a modern army
supersedes the single-handed bravery of the mediæval knights, so we are
to believe that the combination of intellectual labour has superseded
the genius of an Archimedes, a Newton, or a Laplace. So-called original
research is now regarded as a profession, adopted by hundreds of
men, and communicated by a system of training. All that we need to
secure additions to our knowledge of nature is the erection of great
laboratories, museums, and observatories, and the offering of pecuniary
rewards to those who can invent new chemical compounds, detect new
species, or discover new comets. Doubtless this is not the real meaning
of the eminent men who are now urging upon Government the endowment of
physical research. They can only mean that the greater the pecuniary
and material assistance given to men of science, the greater the result
which the available genius of the country may be expected to produce.
Money and opportunities of study can no more produce genius than
sunshine and moisture can generate living beings; the inexplicable
germ is wanting in both cases. But as, when the germ is present, the
plant will grow more or less vigorously according to the circumstances
in which it is placed, so it may be allowed that pecuniary assistance
may favour development of intellect. Public opinion however is not
discriminating, and is likely to interpret the agitation for the
endowment of science as meaning that science can be had for money.

All such notions are erroneous. In no branch of human affairs,
neither in politics, war, literature, industry, nor science, is the
influence of genius less considerable than it was. It is possible
that the extension and organisation of scientific study, assisted by
the printing-press and the accelerated means of communication, has
increased the rapidity with which new discoveries are made known, and
their details worked out by many heads and hands. A Darwin now no
sooner propounds original ideas concerning the evolution of living
creatures, than those ideas are discussed and illustrated, and
applied by naturalists in every part of the world. In former days his
discoveries would have been hidden for decades of years in scarce
manuscripts, and generations would have passed away before his theory
had enjoyed the same amount of criticism and corroboration as it has
already received. The result is that the genius of Darwin is more
valuable, not less valuable, than it would formerly have been. The
advance of military science and the organisation of enormous armies
has not decreased the value of a skilful general; on the contrary,
the rank and file are still more in need than they used to be of the
guiding power of a far-seeing intellect. The swift destruction of the
French military power was not due alone to the perfection of the German
army, nor to the genius of Moltke; it was due to the combination of a
well-disciplined multitude with a leader of the highest powers. So in
every branch of human affairs the influence of the individual is not
withering, but is growing with the extent of the material resources
which are at his command.

Turning to our own subject, it is a work of undiminished interest to
reflect upon those qualities of mind which lead to great advances in
natural knowledge. Nothing, indeed, is less amenable than genius to
scientific analysis and explanation. Even definition is out of the
question. Buffon said that “genius is patience,” and certainly patience
is one of its most requisite components. But no one can suppose that
patient labour alone will invariably lead to those conspicuous results
which we attribute to genius. In every branch of science, literature,
art, or industry, there are thousands of men and women who work with
unceasing patience, and thereby ensure moderate success; but it would
be absurd to suppose that equal amounts of intellectual labour yield
equal results. A Newton may modestly attribute his discoveries to
industry and patient thought, and there is reason to believe that
genius is unconscious and unable to account for its own peculiar
powers. As genius is essentially creative, and consists in divergence
from the ordinary grooves of thought and action, it must necessarily be
a phenomenon beyond the domain of the laws of nature. Nevertheless, it
is always an interesting and instructive work to trace out, as far as
possible, the characteristics of mind by which great discoveries have
been achieved, and we shall find in the analysis much to illustrate the
principles of scientific method.


*Error of the Baconian Method.*

Hundreds of investigators may be constantly engaged in experimental
inquiry; they may compile numberless note-books full of scientific
facts, and endless tables of numerical results; but, if the views of
induction here maintained be true, they can never by such work alone
rise to new and great discoveries. By a system of research they may
work out deductively the details of a previous discovery, but to arrive
at a new principle of nature is another matter. Francis Bacon spread
abroad the notion that to advance science we must begin by accumulating
facts, and then draw from them, by a process of digestion, successive
laws of higher and higher generality. In protesting against the false
method of the scholastic logicians, he exaggerated a partially true
philosophy, until it became as false as that which preceded it. His
notion of scientific method was a kind of scientific bookkeeping.
Facts were to be indiscriminately gathered from every source, and
posted in a ledger, from which would emerge in time a balance of
truth. It is difficult to imagine a less likely way of arriving at
great discoveries. The greater the array of facts, the less is the
probability that they will by any routine system of classification
disclose the laws of nature they embody. Exhaustive classification in
all possible orders is out of the question, because the possible orders
are practically infinite in number.

It is before the glance of the philosophic mind that facts must display
their meaning, and fall into logical order. The natural philosopher
must therefore have, in the first place, a mind of impressionable
character, which is affected by the slightest exceptional phenomenon.
His associating and identifying powers must be great, that is, a
strange fact must suggest to his mind whatever of like nature has
previously come within his experience. His imagination must be active,
and bring before his mind multitudes of relations in which the
unexplained facts may possibly stand with regard to each other, or to
more common facts. Sure and vigorous powers of deductive reasoning
must then come into play, and enable him to infer what will happen
under each supposed condition. Lastly, and above all, there must be the
love of certainty leading him diligently and with perfect candour, to
compare his speculations with the test of fact and experiment.


*Freedom of Theorising.*

It would be an error to suppose that the great discoverer seizes at
once upon the truth, or has any unerring method of divining it. In all
probability the errors of the great mind exceed in number those of the
less vigorous one. Fertility of imagination and abundance of guesses at
truth are among the first requisites of discovery; but the erroneous
guesses must be many times as numerous as those which prove well
founded. The weakest analogies, the most whimsical notions, the most
apparently absurd theories, may pass through the teeming brain, and no
record remain of more than the hundredth part. There is nothing really
absurd except that which proves contrary to logic and experience. The
truest theories involve suppositions which are inconceivable, and no
limit can really be placed to the freedom of hypothesis.

Kepler is an extraordinary instance to this effect. No minor laws
of nature are more firmly established than those which he detected
concerning the orbits and motions of planetary masses, and on these
empirical laws the theory of gravitation was founded. Did we not learn
from his own writings the multitude of errors into which he fell, we
might have imagined that he had some special faculty of seizing on the
truth. But, as is well known, he was full of chimerical notions; his
favourite and long-studied theory was founded on a fanciful analogy
between the planetary orbits and the regular solids. His celebrated
laws were the outcome of a lifetime of speculation, for the most part
vain and groundless. We know this because he had a curious pleasure
in dwelling upon erroneous and futile trains of reasoning, which
most persons consign to oblivion. But Kepler’s name was destined to
be immortal, on account of the patience with which he submitted his
hypotheses to comparison with observation, the candour with which he
acknowledged failure after failure, and the perseverance and ingenuity
with which he renewed his attack upon the riddles of nature.

Next after Kepler perhaps Faraday is the physical philosopher who has
given us the best insight into the progress of discovery, by recording
erroneous as well as successful speculations. The recorded notions,
indeed, are probably but a tithe of the fancies which arose in his
active brain. As Faraday himself said--“The world little knows how
many of the thoughts and theories which have passed through the mind
of a scientific investigator, have been crushed in silence and secrecy
by his own severe criticism and adverse examination; that in the most
successful instances not a tenth of the suggestions, the hopes, the
wishes, the preliminary conclusions have been realised.”

Nevertheless, in Faraday’s researches, published in the *Philosophical
Transactions*, in minor papers, in manuscript note-books, or in other
materials, made known in his interesting life by Dr. Bence Jones, we
find invaluable lessons for the experimentalist. These writings are
full of speculations which we must not judge by the light of subsequent
discovery. It may perhaps be said that Faraday committed to the
printing press crude ideas which a friend would have counselled him to
keep back. There was occasionally even a wildness and vagueness in his
notions, which in a less careful experimentalist would have been fatal
to the attainment of truth. This is especially apparent in a curious
paper concerning Ray-vibrations; but fortunately Faraday was aware of
the shadowy character of his speculations, and expressed the feeling in
words which must be quoted. “I think it likely,” he says,[478] “that
I have made many mistakes in the preceding pages, for even to myself
my ideas on this point appear only as the shadow of a speculation, or
as one of those impressions upon the mind, which are allowable for a
time as guides to thought and research. He who labours in experimental
inquiries knows how numerous these are, and how often their apparent
fitness and beauty vanish before the progress and development of real
natural truth.” If, then, the experimentalist has no royal road to the
discovery of the truth, it is an interesting matter to consider by what
logical procedure he attains the truth.

  [478] *Experimental Researches in Chemistry and Physics*, p. 372.
  *Philosophical Magazine*, 3rd Series, May 1846, vol. xxviii. p. 350.

If I have taken a correct view of logical method, there is really no
such thing as a distinct process of induction. The probability is
infinitely small that a collection of complicated facts will fall
into an arrangement capable of exhibiting directly the laws obeyed
by them. The mathematician might as well expect to integrate his
functions by a ballot-box, as the experimentalist to draw deep truths
from haphazard trials. All induction is but the inverse application
of deduction, and it is by the inexplicable action of a gifted mind
that a multitude of heterogeneous facts are ranged in luminous order
as the results of some uniformly acting law. So different, indeed,
are the qualities of mind required in different branches of science,
that it would be absurd to attempt to give an exhaustive description
of the character of mind which leads to discovery. The labours of
Newton could not have been accomplished except by a mind of the utmost
mathematical genius; Faraday, on the other hand, has made the most
extensive additions to human knowledge without passing beyond common
arithmetic. I do not remember meeting in Faraday’s writings with a
single algebraic formula or mathematical problem of any complexity.
Professor Clerk Maxwell, indeed, in the preface to his new *Treatise
on Electricity*, has strongly recommended the reading of Faraday’s
researches by all students of science, and has given his opinion
that though Faraday seldom or never employed mathematical formulæ,
his methods and conceptions were not the less mathematical in their
nature.[479] I have myself protested against the prevailing confusion
between a mathematical and an exact science,[480] yet I certainly think
that Faraday’s experiments were for the most part qualitative, and that
his mathematical ideas were of a rudimentary character. It is true that
he could not possibly investigate such a subject as magne-crystallic
action without involving himself in geometrical relations of some
complexity. Nevertheless I think that he was deficient in mathematical
deductive power, that power which is so highly developed by the modern
system of mathematical training at Cambridge.

  [479] See also *Nature*, September 18, 1873; vol. viii. p. 398.

  [480] *Theory of Political Economy*, pp. 3–14.

Faraday was acquainted with the forms of his celebrated lines of force,
but I am not aware that he ever entered into the algebraic nature
of those curves, and I feel sure that he could not have explained
their forms as depending on the resultant attractions of all the
magnetic particles. There are even occasional indications that he did
not understand some of the simpler mathematical doctrines of modern
physical science. Although he so clearly foresaw the correlation of the
physical forces, and laboured so hard with his own hands to connect
gravity with other forces, it is doubtful whether he understood the
doctrine of the conservation of energy as applied to gravitation.
Faraday was probably equal to Newton in experimental skill, and in that
peculiar kind of deductive power which leads to the invention of simple
qualitative experiments; but it must be allowed that he exhibited
little of that mathematical power which enabled Newton to follow out
intuitively the quantitative results of a complicated problem with such
wonderful facility. Two instances, Newton and Faraday, are sufficient
to show that minds of widely different conformation will meet with
suitable regions of research. Nevertheless, there are certain traits
which we may discover in all the highest scientific minds.


*The Newtonian Method, the True Organum.*

Laplace was of opinion that the *Principia* and the *Opticks* of
Newton furnished the best models then available of the delicate art
of experimental and theoretical investigation. In these, as he says,
we meet with the most happy illustrations of the way in which, from
a series of inductions, we may rise to the causes of phenomena, and
thence descend again to all the resulting details.

The popular notion concerning Newton’s discoveries is that in early
life, when driven into the country by the Great Plague, a falling apple
accidentally suggested to him the existence of gravitation, and that,
availing himself of this hint, he was led to the discovery of the law
of gravitation, the explanation of which constitutes the *Principia*.
It is difficult to imagine a more ludicrous and inadequate picture of
Newton’s labours. No originality, or at least priority, was claimed
by Newton as regards the discovery of the law of the inverse square,
so closely associated with his name. In a well-known Scholium[481]
he acknowledges that Sir Christopher Wren, Hooke, and Halley, had
severally observed the accordance of Kepler’s third law of motion with
the principle of the inverse square.

  [481] *Principia*, bk. i. Prop. iv.

Newton’s work was really that of developing the methods of deductive
reasoning and experimental verification, by which alone great
hypotheses can be brought to the touchstone of fact. Archimedes was the
greatest of ancient philosophers, for he showed how mathematical theory
could be wedded to physical experiments; and his works are the first
true Organum. Newton is the modern Archimedes, and the *Principia*
forms the true Novum Organum of scientific method. The laws which he
established are great, but his example of the manner of establishing
them is greater still. Excepting perhaps chemistry and electricity,
there is hardly a progressive branch of physical and mathematical
science, which has not been developed from the germs of true scientific
procedure which he disclosed in the *Principia* or the *Opticks*.
Overcome by the success of his theory of universal gravitation, we
are apt to forget that in his theory of sound he originated the
mathematical investigation of waves and the mutual action of particles;
that in his corpuscular theory of light, however mistaken, he first
ventured to apply mathematical calculation to molecular attractions
and repulsions; that in his prismatic experiments he showed how far
experimental verification could be pushed; that in his examination
of the coloured rings named after him, he accomplished the most
remarkable instance of minute measurement yet known, a mere practical
application of which by Fizeau was recently deemed worthy of a medal
by the Royal Society. We only learn by degrees how complete was his
scientific insight; a few words in his third law of motion display his
acquaintance with the fundamental principles of modern thermodynamics
and the conservation of energy, while manuscripts long overlooked prove
that in his inquiries concerning atmospheric refraction he had overcome
the main difficulties of applying theory to one of the most complex of
physical problems.

After all, it is only by examining the way in which he effected
discoveries, that we can rightly appreciate his greatness. The
*Principia* treats not of gravity so much as of forces in general, and
the methods of reasoning about them. He investigates not one hypothesis
only, but mechanical hypotheses in general. Nothing so much strikes
the reader of the work as the exhaustiveness of his treatment, and the
unbounded power of his insight. If he treats of central forces, it
is not one law of force which he discusses, but many, or almost all
imaginable laws, the results of each of which he sketches out in a few
pregnant words. If his subject is a resisting medium, it is not air or
water alone, but resisting media in general. We have a good example
of his method in the scholium to the twenty-second proposition of the
second book, in which he runs rapidly over many suppositions as to
the laws of the compressing forces which might conceivably act in an
atmosphere of gas, a consequence being drawn from each case, and that
one hypothesis ultimately selected which yields results agreeing with
experiments upon the pressure and density of the terrestrial atmosphere.

Newton said that he did not frame hypotheses, but, in reality, the
greater part of the *Principia* is purely hypothetical, endless
varieties of causes and laws being imagined which have no counterpart
in nature. The most grotesque hypotheses of Kepler or Descartes were
not more imaginary. But Newton’s comprehension of logical method was
perfect; no hypothesis was entertained unless it was definite in
conditions, and admitted of unquestionable deductive reasoning; and the
value of each hypothesis was entirely decided by the comparison of its
consequences with facts. I do not entertain a doubt that the general
course of his procedure is identical with that view of the nature of
induction, as the inverse application of deduction, which I advocate
throughout this book. Francis Bacon held that science should be founded
on experience, but he mistook the true mode of using experience,
and, in attempting to apply his method, ludicrously failed. Newton
did not less found his method on experience, but he seized the true
method of treating it, and applied it with a power and success never
since equalled. It is a great mistake to say that modern science is
the result of the Baconian philosophy; it is the Newtonian philosophy
and the Newtonian method which have led to all the great triumphs of
physical science, and I repeat that the *Principia* forms the true
“Novum Organum.”

In bringing his theories to a decisive experimental verification,
Newton showed, as a general rule, exquisite skill and ingenuity.
In his hands a few simple pieces of apparatus were made to give
results involving an unsuspected depth of meaning. His most beautiful
experimental inquiry was that by which he proved the differing
refrangibility of rays of light. To suppose that he originally
discovered the power of a prism to break up a beam of white light
would be a mistake, for he speaks of procuring a glass prism to
try the “celebrated phenomena of colours.” But we certainly owe to
him the theory that white light is a mixture of rays differing in
refrangibility, and that lights which differ in colour, differ also in
refrangibility. Other persons might have conceived this theory; in
fact, any person regarding refraction as a quantitative effect must see
that different parts of the spectrum have suffered different amounts
of refraction. But the power of Newton is shown in the tenacity with
which he followed his theory into every consequence, and tested each
result by a simple but conclusive experiment. He first shows that
different coloured spots are displaced by different amounts when viewed
through a prism, and that their images come to a focus at different
distances from the lense, as they should do, if the refrangibility
differed. After excluding by many experiments a variety of indifferent
circumstances, he fixes his attention upon the question whether the
rays are merely shattered, disturbed, and spread out in a chance
manner, as Grimaldi supposed, or whether there is a constant relation
between the colour and the refrangibility.

If Grimaldi was right, it might be expected that a part of the spectrum
taken separately, and subjected to a second refraction, would suffer a
new breaking up, and produce some new spectrum. Newton inferred from
his own theory that a particular ray of the spectrum would have a
constant refrangibility, so that a second prism would merely bend it
more or less, but not further disperse it in any considerable degree.
By simply cutting off most of the rays of the spectrum by a screen,
and allowing the remaining narrow ray to fall on a second prism, he
proved the truth of this conclusion; and then slowly turning the first
prism, so as to vary the colour of the ray falling on the second
one, he found that the spot of light formed by the twice-refracted
ray travelled up and down, a palpable proof that the amount of
refrangibility varies with the colour. For his further satisfaction,
he sometimes refracted the light a third or fourth time, and he found
that it might be refracted upwards or downwards or sideways, and yet
for each colour there was a definite amount of refraction through each
prism. He completed the proof by showing that the separated rays may
again be gathered together into white light by an inverted prism, so
that no number of refractions alters the character of the light. The
conclusion thus obtained serves to explain the confusion arising in the
use of a common lense; he shows that with homogeneous light there is
one distinct focus, with mixed light an infinite number of foci, which
prevent a clear view from being obtained at any point.

What astonishes the reader of the *Opticks* is the persistence with
which Newton follows out the consequences of a preconceived theory, and
tests the one notion by a wonderful variety of simple comparisons with
fact. The ease with which he invents new combinations, and foresees
the results, subsequently verified, produces an insuperable conviction
in the reader that he has possession of the truth. And it is certainly
the theory which leads him to the experiments, most of which could
hardly be devised by accident. Newton actually remarks that it was by
mathematically determining all kinds of phenomena of colours which
could be produced by refraction that he had “invented” almost all the
experiments in the book, and he promises that others who shall “argue
truly,” and try the experiments with care, will not be disappointed in
the results.[482]

  [482] *Opticks*, bk. i. part ii. Prop. 3. 3rd ed. p. 115.

The philosophic method of Huyghens was the same as that of Newton,
and Huyghens’ investigation of double refraction furnishes almost
equally beautiful instances of theory guiding experiment. So far as
we know double refraction was first discovered by accident, and was
described by Erasmus Bartholinus in 1669. The phenomenon then appeared
to be entirely exceptional, and the laws governing the two paths of
the refracted rays were so unapparent and complicated, that Newton
altogether misunderstood the phenomenon, and it was only at the latter
end of the last century that scientific men began to comprehend its
laws.

Nevertheless, Huyghens had, with rare genius, arrived at the true
theory as early as 1678. He regarded light as an undulatory motion of
some medium, and in his *Traité de la Lumière* he pointed out that,
in ordinary refraction, the velocity of propagation of the wave is
equal in all directions, so that the front of an advancing wave is
spherical, and reaches equal distances in equal times. But in crystals,
as he supposed, the medium would be of unequal elasticity in different
directions, so that a disturbance would reach unequal distances in
equal times, and the wave produced would have a spheroidal form.
Huyghens was not satisfied with an unverified theory. He calculated
what might be expected to happen when a crystal of calc-spar was cut
in various directions, and he says: “I have examined in detail the
properties of the extraordinary refraction of this crystal, to see if
each phenomenon which is deduced from theory would agree with what is
really observed. And this being so, it is no slight proof of the truth
of our suppositions and principles; but what I am going to add here
confirms them still more wonderfully; that is, the different modes
of cutting this crystal, in which the surfaces produced give rise to
refraction exactly such as they ought to be, and as I had foreseen
them, according to the preceding theory.”

Newton’s mistaken corpuscular theory of light caused the theories and
experiments of Huyghens to be disregarded for more than a century; but
it is not easy to imagine a more beautiful or successful application of
the true method of inductive investigation, theory guiding experiment,
and yet wholly relying on experiment for confirmation.


*Candour and Courage of the Philosophic Mind.*

Perfect readiness to reject a theory inconsistent with fact is a
primary requisite of the philosophic mind. But it would be a mistake
to suppose that this candour has anything akin to fickleness; on the
contrary, readiness to reject a false theory may be combined with a
peculiar pertinacity and courage in maintaining an hypothesis as long
as its falsity is not actually apparent. There must, indeed, be no
prejudice or bias distorting the mind, and causing it to pass over the
unwelcome results of experiment. There must be that scrupulous honesty
and flexibility of mind, which assigns adequate value to all evidence;
indeed, the more a man loves his theory, the more scrupulous should be
his attention to its faults. It is common in life to meet with some
theorist, who, by long cogitation over a single theory, has allowed it
to mould his mind, and render him incapable of receiving anything but
as a contribution to the truth of his one theory. A narrow and intense
course of thought may sometimes lead to great results, but the adoption
of a wrong theory at the outset is in such a mind irretrievable.
The man of one idea has but a single chance of truth. The fertile
discoverer, on the contrary, chooses between many theories, and is
never wedded to any one, unless impartial and repeated comparison has
convinced him of its validity. He does not choose and then compare; but
he compares time after time, and then chooses.

Having once deliberately chosen, the philosopher may rightly entertain
his theory with the strongest fidelity. He will neglect no objection;
for he may chance at any time to meet a fatal one; but he will bear
in mind the inconsiderable powers of the human mind compared with the
tasks it has to undertake. He will see that no theory can at first be
reconciled with all objections, because there may be many interfering
causes, and the very consequences of the theory may have a complexity
which prolonged investigation by successive generations of men may not
exhaust. If, then, a theory exhibit a number of striking coincidences
with fact, it must not be thrown aside until at least one *conclusive
discordance* is proved, regard being had to possible error in
establishing that discordance. In science and philosophy something must
be risked. He who quails at the least difficulty will never establish a
new truth, and it was not unphilosophic in Leslie to remark concerning
his own inquiries into the nature of heat--

“In the course of investigation, I have found myself compelled to
relinquish some preconceived notions; but I have not abandoned them
hastily, nor, till after a warm and obstinate defence, I was driven
from every post.”[483]

  [483] *Experimental Inquiry into the Nature of Heat.* Preface, p. xv.

Faraday’s life, again, furnishes most interesting illustrations of this
tenacity of the philosophic mind. Though so candid in rejecting some
theories, there were others to which he clung through everything. One
of his favourite notions resulted in a brilliant discovery; another
remains in doubt to the present day.


*The Philosophic Character of Faraday.*

In Faraday’s researches concerning the connection of magnetism and
light, we find an excellent instance of the pertinacity with which a
favourite theory may be pursued, so long as the results of experiment
do not clearly negative the notions entertained. In purely quantitative
questions, as we have seen, the absence of apparent effect can seldom
be regarded as proving the absence of all effect. Now Faraday was
convinced that some mutual relation must exist between magnetism and
light. As early as 1822, he attempted to produce an effect upon a ray
of polarised light, by passing it through water placed between the
poles of a voltaic battery; but he was obliged to record that not the
slightest effect was observable. During many years the subject, we are
told,[484] rose again and again to his mind, and no failure could make
him relinquish his search after this unknown relation. It was in the
year 1845 that he gained the first success; on August 30th he began
to work with common electricity, vainly trying glass, quartz, Iceland
spar, &c. Several days of labour gave no result; yet he did not desist.
Heavy glass, a transparent medium of great refractive powers, composed
of borate of lead, was now tried, being placed between the poles of a
powerful electro-magnet while a ray of polarised light was transmitted
through it. When the poles of the electro-magnet were arranged in
certain positions with regard to the substance under trial, no effects
were apparent; but at last Faraday happened fortunately to place a
piece of heavy glass so that contrary magnetic poles were on the same
side, and now an effect was witnessed. The glass was found to have the
power of twisting the plane of polarisation of the ray of light.

  [484] Bence Jones, *Life of Faraday*, vol. i. p. 362.

All Faraday’s recorded thoughts upon this great experiment are replete
with curious interest. He attributes his success to the opinion,
almost amounting to a conviction, that the various forms, under which
the forces of matter are made manifest, have one common origin,
and are so directly related and mutually dependent that they are
convertible. “This strong persuasion,” he says,[485] “extended to the
powers of light, and led to many exertions having for their object
the discovery of the direct relation of light and electricity. These
ineffectual exertions could not remove my strong persuasion, and I
have at last succeeded.” He describes the phenomenon in somewhat
figurative language as *the magnetisation of a ray of light*, and
also as *the illumination of a magnetic curve or line of force*. He
has no sooner got the effect in one case, than he proceeds, with his
characteristic comprehensiveness of research, to test the existence
of a like phenomenon in all the substances available. He finds that
not only heavy glass, but solids and liquids, acids and alkalis, oils,
water, alcohol, ether, all possess this power; but he was not able to
detect its existence in any gaseous substance. His thoughts cannot be
restrained from running into curious speculations as to the possible
results of the power in certain cases. “What effect,” he says, “does
this force have in the earth where the magnetic curves of the earth
traverse its substance? Also what effect in a magnet?” And then he
falls upon the strange notion that perhaps this force tends to make
iron and oxide of iron transparent, a phenomenon never observed. We can
meet with nothing more instructive as to the course of mind by which
great discoveries are made, than these records of Faraday’s patient
labours, and his varied success and failure. Nor are his unsuccessful
experiments upon the relation of gravity and electricity less
interesting, or less worthy of study.

  [485] Ibid. vol. ii. p. 199.

Throughout a large part of his life, Faraday was possessed by the idea
that gravity cannot be unconnected with the other forces of nature. On
March 19th, 1849, he wrote in his laboratory book,--“Gravity. Surely
this force must be capable of an experimental relation to electricity,
magnetism, and the other forces, so as to bind it up with them in
reciprocal action and equivalent effect?”[486] He filled twenty
paragraphs or more with reflections and suggestions, as to the mode
of treating the subject by experiment. He anticipated that the mutual
approach of two bodies would develop electricity in them, or that a
body falling through a conducting helix would excite a current changing
in direction as the motion was reversed. “*All this is a dream*,”
he remarks; “still examine it by a few experiments. Nothing is too
wonderful to be true, if it be consistent with the laws of nature;
and in such things as these, experiment is the best test of such
consistency.”

  [486] See also his more formal statement in the *Experimental
  Researches in Electricity*, 24th Series, § 2702, vol. iii. p. 161.

He executed many difficult and tedious experiments, which are described
in the 24th Series of Experimental Researches. The result was *nil*,
and yet he concludes: “Here end my trials for the present. The results
are negative; they do not shake my strong feeling of the existence of
a relation between gravity and electricity, though they give no proof
that such a relation exists.”

He returned to the work when he was ten years older, and in 1858–9
recorded many remarkable reflections and experiments. He was much
struck by the fact that electricity is essentially a *dual force*,
and it had always been a conviction of Faraday that no body could be
electrified positively without some other body becoming electrified
negatively; some of his researches had been simple developments of
this relation. But observing that between two mutually gravitating
bodies there was no apparent circumstance to determine which should be
positive and which negative, he does not hesitate to call in question
an old opinion. “The evolution of *one* electricity would be a new
and very remarkable thing. The idea throws a doubt on the whole; but
still try, for who knows what is possible in dealing with gravity?”
We cannot but notice the candour with which he thus acknowledges in
his laboratory book the doubtfulness of the whole thing, and is yet
prepared as a forlorn hope to frame experiments in opposition to
all his previous experience of the course of nature. For a time his
thoughts flow on as if the strange detection were already made, and he
had only to trace out its consequences throughout the universe. “Let us
encourage ourselves by a little more imagination prior to experiment,”
he says; and then he reflects upon the infinity of actions in nature,
in which the mutual relations of electricity and gravity would come
into play; he pictures to himself the planets and the comets charging
themselves as they approach the sun; cascades, rain, rising vapour,
circulating currents of the atmosphere, the fumes of a volcano, the
smoke in a chimney become so many electrical machines. A multitude of
events and changes in the atmosphere seem to be at once elucidated by
such actions; for a moment his reveries have the vividness of fact.
“I think we have been dull and blind not to have suspected some such
results,” and he sums up rapidly the consequences of his great but
imaginary theory; an entirely new mode of exciting heat or electricity,
an entirely new relation of the natural forces, an analysis of
gravitation, and a justification of the conservation of force.

Such were Faraday’s fondest dreams of what might be, and to many a
philosopher they would have been sufficient basis for the writing of
a great book. But Faraday’s imagination was within his full control;
as he himself says, “Let the imagination go, guarding it by judgment
and principle, and holding it in and directing it by experiment.” His
dreams soon took a very practical form, and for many days he laboured
with ceaseless energy, on the staircase of the Royal Institution, in
the clock tower of the Houses of Parliament, or at the top of the Shot
Tower in Southwark, raising and lowering heavy weights, and combining
electrical helices and wires in every conceivable way. His skill and
long experience in experiment were severely taxed to eliminate the
effects of the earth’s magnetism, and time after time he saved himself
from accepting mistaken indications, which to another man might have
seemed conclusive verifications of his theory. When all was done there
remained absolutely no results. “The experiments,” he says, “were well
made, but the results are negative;” and yet, he adds, “I cannot accept
them as conclusive.” In this position the question remains to the
present day; it may be that the effect was too slight to be detected,
or it may be that the arrangements adopted were not suited to develop
the particular relation which exists, just as Oersted could not detect
electro-magnetism, so long as his wire was perpendicular to the plane
of motion of his needle. But these are not matters which concern us
further here. We have only to notice the profound conviction in the
unity of natural laws, the active powers of inference and imagination,
the unbounded licence of theorising, combined above all with the utmost
diligence in experimental verification which this remarkable research
exhibits.


*Reservation of Judgment.*

There is yet another characteristic needed in the philosophic mind; it
is that of suspending judgment when the data are insufficient. Many
people will express a confident opinion on almost any question which is
put before them, but they thereby manifest not strength, but narrowness
of mind. To see all sides of a complicated subject, and to weigh all
the different facts and probabilities correctly, require no ordinary
powers of comprehension. Hence it is most frequently the philosophic
mind which is in doubt, and the ignorant mind which is ready with a
positive decision. Faraday has himself said, in a very interesting
lecture:[487] “Occasionally and frequently the exercise of the judgment
ought to end in *absolute reservation*. It may be very distasteful, and
great fatigue, to suspend a conclusion; but as we are not infallible,
so we ought to be cautious; we shall eventually find our advantage, for
the man who rests in his position is not so far from right as he who,
proceeding in a wrong direction, is ever increasing his distance.”

  [487] Printed in *Modern Culture*, edited by Youmans, p. 219.

Arago presented a conspicuous example of this high quality of mind, as
Faraday remarks; for when he made known his curious discovery of the
relation of a magnetic needle to a revolving copper plate, a number
of supposed men of science in different countries gave immediate and
confident explanations of it, which were all wrong. But Arago, who
had both discovered the phenomenon and personally investigated its
conditions, declined to put forward publicly any theory at all.

At the same time we must not suppose that the truly philosophic mind
can tolerate a state of doubt, while a chance of decision remains open.
In science nothing like compromise is possible, and truth must be one.
Hence, doubt is the confession of ignorance, and involves a painful
feeling of incapacity. But doubt lies between error and truth, so that
if we choose wrongly we are further away than ever from our goal.

Summing up, then, it would seem as if the mind of the great discoverer
must combine contradictory attributes. He must be fertile in
theories and hypotheses, and yet full of facts and precise results of
experience. He must entertain the feeblest analogies, and the merest
guesses at truth, and yet he must hold them as worthless till they are
verified in experiment. When there are any grounds of probability he
must hold tenaciously to an old opinion, and yet he must be prepared
at any moment to relinquish it when a clearly contradictory fact is
encountered. “The philosopher,” says Faraday,[488] “should be a man
willing to listen to every suggestion, but determined to judge for
himself. He should not be biased by appearances; have no favourite
hypothesis; be of no school; and in doctrine have no master. He should
not be a respecter of persons, but of things. Truth should be his
primary object. If to these qualities be added industry, he may indeed
hope to walk within the veil of the temple of nature.”

  [488] *Life of Faraday*, vol. i. p. 225.




BOOK V.

GENERALISATION, ANALOGY, AND CLASSIFICATION.




CHAPTER XXVII.

GENERALISATION.


I have endeavoured to show in preceding chapters that all inductive
reasoning is an inverse application of deductive reasoning, and
consists in demonstrating that the consequences of certain assumed laws
agree with facts of nature gathered by active or passive observation.
The fundamental process of reasoning, as stated in the outset, consists
in inferring of a thing what we know of similar objects, and it is on
this principle that the whole of deductive reasoning, whether simply
logical or mathematico-logical, is founded. All inductive reasoning
must be founded on the same principle. It might seem that by a plain
use of this principle we could avoid the complicated processes of
induction and deduction, and argue directly from one particular case
to another, as Mill proposed. If the Earth, Venus, Mars, Jupiter,
and other planets move in elliptic orbits, cannot we dispense with
elaborate precautions, and assert that Neptune, Ceres, and the last
discovered planet must do so likewise? Do we not know that Mr.
Gladstone must die, because he is like other men? May we not argue
that because some men die therefore he must? Is it requisite to ascend
by induction to the general proposition “all men must die,” and then
descend by deduction from that general proposition to the case of Mr.
Gladstone? My answer undoubtedly is that we must ascend to general
propositions. The fundamental principle of the substitution of similars
gives us no warrant in affirming of Mr. Gladstone what we know of
other men, because we cannot be sure that Mr. Gladstone is exactly
similar to other men. Until his death we cannot be perfectly sure that
he possesses all the attributes of other men; it is a question of
probability, and I have endeavoured to explain the mode in which the
theory of probability is applied to calculate the probability that from
a series of similar events we may infer the recurrence of like events
under identical circumstances. There is then no such process as that
of inferring from particulars to particulars. A careful analysis of
the conditions under which such an inference appears to be made, shows
that the process is really a general one, and that what is inferred of
a particular case might be inferred of all similar cases. All reasoning
is essentially general, and all science implies generalisation. In
the very birth-time of philosophy this was held to be so: “Nulla
scientia est de individuis, sed de solis universalibus,” was the
doctrine of Plato, delivered by Porphyry. And Aristotle[489] held a
like opinion--Οὐδεμία δὲ τέχνη σκοπεȋ τὸ καθ’ ἕκαστον ... τὸ δὲ καθ’
ἕκαστον ἄπειρον καὶ οὐκ ἐπιστητόν. “No art treats of particular cases;
for particulars are infinite and cannot be known.” No one who holds the
doctrine that reasoning may be from particulars to particulars, can
be supposed to have the most rudimentary notion of what constitutes
reasoning and scíence.

  [489] Aristotle’s *Rhetoric*, Liber I. 2. 11.

At the same time there can be no doubt that practically what we find
to be true of many similar objects will probably be true of the next
similar object. This is the result to which an analysis of the Inverse
Method of Probabilities leads us, and, in the absence of precise data
from which we may calculate probabilities, we are usually obliged to
make a rough assumption that similars in some respects are similars
in other respects. Thus it comes to pass that a large part of the
reasoning processes in which scientific men are engaged, consists in
detecting similarities between objects, and then rudely assuming that
the like similarities will be detected in other cases.


*Distinction of Generalisation and Analogy.*

There is no distinction but that of degree between what is known as
reasoning by *generalisation* and reasoning by *analogy*. In both
cases from certain observed resemblances we infer, with more or less
probability, the existence of other resemblances. In generalisation
the resemblances have great extension and usually little intension,
whereas in analogy we rely upon the great intension, the extension
being of small amount (p. 26). If we find that the qualities A and B
are associated together in a great many instances, and have never been
found separate, it is highly probable that on the next occasion when we
meet with A, B will also be present, and *vice versâ*. Thus wherever we
meet with an object possessing gravity, it is found to possess inertia
also, nor have we met with any material objects possessing inertia
without discovering that they also possess gravity. The probability
has therefore become very great, as indicated by the rules founded on
the Inverse Method of Probabilities (p. 257), that whenever in the
future we meet an object possessing either of the properties of gravity
and inertia, it will be found on examination to possess the other
of these properties. This is a clear instance of the employment of
generalisation.

In analogy, on the other hand, we reason from likeness in many points
to likeness in other points. The qualities or points of resemblance are
now numerous, not the objects. At the poles of Mars are two white spots
which resemble in many respects the white regions of ice and snow at
the poles of the earth. There probably exist no other similar objects
with which to compare these, yet the exactness of the resemblance
enables us to infer, with high probability, that the spots on Mars
consist of ice and snow. In short, many points of resemblance imply
many more. From the appearance and behaviour of those white spots we
infer that they have all the chemical and physical properties of
frozen water. The inference is of course only probable, and based upon
the improbability that aggregates of many qualities should be formed in
a like manner in two or more cases, without being due to some uniform
condition or cause.

In reasoning by analogy, then, we observe that two objects ABCDE....
and A′B′C′D′E′.... have many like qualities, as indicated by the
identity of the letters, and we infer that, since the first has another
quality, X, we shall discover this quality in the second case by
sufficiently close examination. As Laplace says,--“Analogy is founded
on the probability that similar things have causes of the same kind,
and produce the same effects. The more perfect this similarity, the
greater is this probability.”[490] The nature of analogical inference
is aptly described in the work on Logic attributed to Kant, where the
rule of ordinary induction is stated in the words, “*Eines in vielen,
also in allen*,” one quality in many things, therefore in all; and
the rule of analogy is “*Vieles in einem, also auch das übrige in
demselben*,”[491] many (qualities) in one, therefore also the remainder
in the same. It is evident that there may be intermediate cases in
which, from the identity of a moderate number of objects in several
properties, we may infer to other objects. Probability must rest either
upon the number of instances or the depth of resemblance, or upon the
occurrence of both in sufficient degrees. What there is wanting in
extension must be made up by intension, and *vice versâ*.

  [490] *Essai Philosophique sur les Probabilités*, p. 86.

  [491] Kant’s *Logik*, § 84, Königsberg, 1800, p. 207.


*Two Meanings of Generalisation.*

The term generalisation, as commonly used, includes two processes which
are of different character, but are often closely associated together.
In the first place, we generalise when we recognise even in two objects
a common nature. We cannot detect the slightest similarity without
opening the way to inference from one case to the other. If we compare
a cubical crystal with a regular octahedron, there is little apparent
similarity; but, as soon as we perceive that either can be produced
by the symmetrical modification of the other, we discover a groundwork
of similarity in the crystals, which enables us to infer many things
of one, because they are true of the other. Our knowledge of ozone
took its rise from the time when the similarity of smell, attending
electric sparks, strokes of lightning, and the slow combustion of
phosphorus, was noticed by Schönbein. There was a time when the rainbow
was an inexplicable phenomenon--a portent, like a comet, and a cause of
superstitious hopes and fears. But we find the true spirit of science
in Roger Bacon, who desires us to consider the objects which present
the same colours as the rainbow; he mentions hexagonal crystals from
Ireland and India, but he bids us not suppose that the hexagonal form
is essential, for similar colours may be detected in many transparent
stones. Drops of water scattered by the oar in the sun, the spray from
a water-wheel, the dewdrops lying on the grass in the summer morning,
all display a similar phenomenon. No sooner have we grouped together
these apparently diverse instances, than we have begun to generalise,
and have acquired a power of applying to one instance what we can
detect of others. Even when we do not apply the knowledge gained to
new objects, our comprehension of those already observed is greatly
strengthened and deepened by learning to view them as particular cases
of a more general property.

A second process, to which the name of generalisation is often
given, consists in passing from a fact or partial law to a multitude
of unexamined cases, which we believe to be subject to the same
conditions. Instead of merely recognising similarity as it is brought
before us, we predict its existence before our senses can detect it, so
that generalisation of this kind endows us with a prophetic power of
more or less probability. Having observed that many substances assume,
like water and mercury, the three states of solid, liquid, and gas, and
having assured ourselves by frequent trial that the greater the means
we possess of heating and cooling, the more substances we can vaporise
and freeze, we pass confidently in advance of fact, and assume that
all substances are capable of these three forms. Such a generalisation
was accepted by Lavoisier and Laplace before many of the corroborative
facts now in our possession were known. The reduction of a single
comet beneath the sway of gravity was considered sufficient indication
that all comets obey the same power. Few persons doubted that the law
of gravity extended over the whole heavens; certainly the fact that
a few stars out of many millions manifest the action of gravity, is
now held to be sufficient evidence of its general extension over the
visible universe.


*Value of Generalisation.*

It might seem that if we know particular facts, there can be little
use in connecting them together by a general law. The particulars
must be more full of useful information than an abstract general
statement. If we know, for instance, the properties of an ellipse, a
circle, a parabola, and hyperbola, what is the use of learning all
these properties over again in the general theory of curves of the
second degree? If we understand the phenomena of sound and light and
water-waves separately, what is the need of erecting a general theory
of waves, which, after all, is inapplicable to practice until resolved
again into particular cases? But, in reality, we never do obtain an
adequate knowledge of particulars until we regard them as cases of
the general. Not only is there a singular delight in discovering the
many in the one, and the one in the many, but there is a constant
interchange of light and knowledge. Properties which are unapparent
in the hyperbola may be readily observed in the ellipse. Most of the
complex relations which old geometers discovered in the circle will
be reproduced *mutatis mutandis* in the other conic sections. The
undulatory theory of light might have been unknown at the present day,
had not the theory of sound supplied hints by analogy. The study of
light has made known many phenomena of interference and polarisation,
the existence of which had hardly been suspected in the case of
sound, but which may now be sought out, and perhaps found to possess
unexpected interest. The careful study of water-waves shows how waves
alter in form and velocity with varying depth of water. Analogous
changes may some time be detected in sound waves. Thus there is mutual
interchange of aid.

“Every study of a generalisation or extension,” De Morgan has well
said,[492] “gives additional power over the particular form by which
the generalisation is suggested. Nobody who has ever returned to
quadratic equations after the study of equations of all degrees,
or who has done the like, will deny my assertion that οὐ βλέπει
βλέπων may be predicated of any one who studies a branch or a case,
without afterwards making it part of a larger whole. Accordingly
it is always worth while to generalise, were it only to give power
over the *particular*. This principle, of daily familiarity to the
mathematician, is almost unknown to the logician.”

  [492] *Syllabus of a Proposed System of Logic*, p. 34.


*Comparative Generality of Properties.*

Much of the value of science depends upon the knowledge which we
gradually acquire of the different degrees of generality of properties
and phenomena of various kinds. The use of science consists in enabling
us to act with confidence, because we can foresee the result. Now this
foresight must rest upon the knowledge of the powers which will come
into play. That knowledge, indeed, can never be certain, because it
rests upon imperfect induction, and the most confident beliefs and
predictions of the physicist may be falsified. Nevertheless, if we
always estimate the probability of each belief according to the due
teaching of the data, and bear in mind that probability when forming
our anticipations, we shall ensure the minimum of disappointment. Even
when he cannot exactly apply the theory of probabilities, the physicist
may acquire the habit of making judgments in general agreement with its
principles and results.

Such is the constitution of nature, that the physicist learns to
distinguish those properties which have wide and uniform extension,
from those which vary between case and case. Not only are certain laws
distinctly laid down, with their extension carefully defined, but a
scientific training gives a kind of tact in judging how far other laws
are likely to apply under any particular circumstances. We learn by
degrees that crystals exhibit phenomena depending upon the directions
of the axes of elasticity, which we must not expect in uniform solids.
Liquids, compared even with non-crystalline solids, exhibit laws of
far less complexity and variety; and gases assume, in many respects,
an aspect of nearly complete uniformity. To trace out the branches of
science in which varying degrees of generality prevail, would be an
inquiry of great interest and importance; but want of space, if there
were no other reason, would forbid me to attempt it, except in a very
slight manner.

Gases, so far as they are really gaseous, not only have exactly the
same properties in all directions of space, but one gas exactly
resembles other gases in many qualities. All gases expand by heat,
according to the same law, and by nearly the same amount; the specific
heats of equivalent weights are equal, and the densities are exactly
proportional to the atomic weights. All such gases obey the general
law, that the volume multiplied by the pressure, and divided by the
absolute temperature, is constant or nearly so. The laws of diffusion
and transpiration are the same in all cases, and, generally speaking,
all physical laws, as distinguished from chemical laws, apply
equally to all gases. Even when gases differ in chemical or physical
properties, the differences are minor in degree. Thus the differences
of viscosity are far less marked than in the liquid and solid states.
Nearly all gases, again, are colourless, the exceptions being chlorine,
the vapours of iodine, bromine, and a few other substances.

Only in one single point, so far as I am aware, do gases present
distinguishing marks unknown or nearly so, in the solid and liquid
states. I mean as regards the light given off when incandescent.
Each gas when sufficiently heated, yields its own peculiar series
of rays, arising from the free vibrations of the constituent parts
of the molecules. Hence the possibility of distinguishing gases by
the spectroscope. But the molecules of solids and liquids appear to
be continually in conflict with each other, so that only a confused
*noise* of atoms is produced, instead of a definite series of luminous
chords. At the same temperature, accordingly, all solids and liquids
give off nearly the same rays when strongly heated, and we have in this
case an exception to the greater generality of properties in gases.

Liquids are in many ways intermediate in character between gases
and solids. While incapable of possessing different elasticity in
different directions, and thus denuded of the rich geometrical
complexity of solids, they retain the variety of density, colour
degrees of transparency, great diversity in surface tension, viscosity,
coefficients of expansion, compressibility, and many other properties
which we observe in solids, but not for the most part in gases. Though
our knowledge of the physical properties of liquids is much wanting in
generality at present, there is ground to hope that by degrees laws
connecting and explaining the variations may be traced out.

Solids are in every way contrasted to gases. Each solid substance
has its own peculiar degree of density, hardness, compressibility,
transparency, tenacity, elasticity, power of conducting heat and
electricity, magnetic properties, capability of producing frictional
electricity, and so forth. Even different specimens of the same kind
of substance will differ widely, according to the accidental treatment
received. And not only has each substance its own specific properties,
but, when crystallised, its properties vary in each direction with
regard to the axes of crystallisation. The velocity of radiation, the
rate of conduction of heat, the coefficients of expansibility and
compressibility, the thermo-electric properties, all vary in different
crystallographic directions.

It is probable that many apparent differences between liquids, and
even between solids, will be explained when we learn to regard them
under exactly corresponding circumstances. The extreme generality of
the properties of gases is in reality only true at an infinitely high
temperature, when they are all equally remote from their condensing
points. Now, it is found that if we compare liquids--for instance,
different kinds of alcohols--not at equal temperatures, but at points
equally distant from their respective boiling points, the laws and
coefficients of expansion are nearly equal. The vapour-tensions of
liquids also are more nearly equal, when compared at corresponding
points, and the boiling-points appear in many cases to be simply
related to the chemical composition. No doubt the progress of
investigation will enable us to discover generality, where at present
we only see variety and puzzling complexity.

In some cases substances exhibit the same physical properties in
the liquid as in the solid state. Lead has a high refractive power,
whether in solution, or in solid salts, crystallised or vitreous.
The magnetic power of iron is conspicuous, whatever be its chemical
condition; indeed, the magnetic properties of substances, though
varying with temperature, seem not to be greatly affected by other
physical changes. Colour, absorptive power for heat or light rays,
and a few other properties are also often the same in liquids and
gases. Iodine and bromine possess a deep colour whenever they are
chemically uncombined. Nevertheless, we can seldom argue safely from
the properties of a substance in one condition to those in another
condition. Ice is an insulator, water a conductor of electricity, and
the same contrast exists in most other substances. The conducting power
of a liquid for electricity increases with the temperature, while that
of a solid decreases. By degrees we may learn to distinguish between
those properties of matter which depend upon the intimate construction
of the chemical molecule, and those which depend upon the contact,
conflict, mutual attraction, or other relations of distinct molecules.
The properties of a substance with respect to light seem generally to
depend upon the molecule; thus, the power of certain substances to
cause the plane of polarisation of a ray of light to rotate, is exactly
the same whatever be its degree of density, or the diluteness of the
solution in which it is contained. Taken as a whole, the physical
properties of substances and their quantitative laws, present a problem
of infinite complexity, and centuries must elapse before any moderately
complete generalisations on the subject become possible.


*Uniform Properties of all Matter.*

Some laws are held to be true of all matter in the universe absolutely,
without exception, no instance to the contrary having ever been
noticed. This is the case with the laws of motion, as laid down
by Galileo and Newton. It is also conspicuously true of the law
of universal gravitation. The rise of modern physical science may
perhaps be considered as beginning at the time when Galileo showed,
in opposition to the Aristotelians, that matter is equally affected
by gravity, irrespective of its form, magnitude, or texture. All
objects fall with equal rapidity, when disturbing causes, such as the
resistance of the air, are removed or allowed for. That which was
rudely demonstrated by Galileo from the leaning tower of Pisa, was
proved by Newton to a high degree of approximation, in an experiment
which has been mentioned (p. 443).

Newton formed two pendulums, as nearly as possible the same in outward
shape and size by taking two equal round wooden boxes, and suspending
them by equal threads, eleven feet long. The pendulums were therefore
equally subject to the resistance of the air. He filled one box with
wood, and in the centre of oscillation of the other he placed an equal
weight of gold. The pendulums were then equal in weight as well as in
size; and, on setting them simultaneously in motion, Newton found that
they vibrated for a length of time with equal vibrations. He tried the
same experiment with silver, lead, glass, sand, common salt, water,
and wheat, in place of the gold, and ascertained that the motion of
his pendulum was exactly the same whatever was the kind of matter
inside.[493] He considered that a difference of a thousandth part
would have been apparent. The reader must observe that the pendulums
were made of equal weight only in order that they might suffer equal
retardation from the air. The meaning of the experiment is that all
substances manifest exactly equal acceleration from the force of
gravity, and that therefore the inertia or resistance of matter to
force, which is the only independent measure of mass known to us, is
always proportional to gravity.

  [493] *Principia*, bk. iii. Prop. VI. Motte’s translation, vol. ii.
  p. 220.

These experiments of Newton were considered conclusive up to very
recent times, when certain discordances between the theory and
observations of the movements of planets led Nicolai, in 1826, to
suggest that the equal gravitation of different kinds of matter might
not be absolutely exact. It is perfectly philosophical thus to call
in question, from time to time, some of the best accepted laws. On
this occasion Bessel carefully repeated the experiments of Newton with
pendulums composed of ivory, glass, marble, quartz, meteoric stones,
&c., but was unable to detect the least difference. This conclusion
is also confirmed by the ultimate agreement of all the calculations
of physical astronomy based upon it. Whether the mass of Jupiter be
calculated from the motion of its own satellites, from the effect
upon the small planets, Vesta, Juno, &c., or from the perturbation
of Encke’s Comet, the results are closely accordant, showing that
precisely the same law of gravity applies to the most different bodies
which we can observe. The gravity of a body, again, appears to be
entirely independent of its other physical conditions, being totally
unaffected by any alteration in the temperature, density, electric or
magnetic condition, or other physical properties of the substance.

One paradoxical result of the law of equal gravitation is the theorem
of Torricelli, to the effect that all liquids of whatever density
fall or flow with equal rapidity. If there be two equal cisterns
respectively filled with mercury and water, the mercury, though
thirteen times as heavy, would flow from an aperture neither more
rapidly nor more slowly than the water, and the same would be true of
ether, alcohol, and other liquids, allowance being made, however, for
the resistance of the air, and the differing viscosities of the liquids.

In its exact equality and its perfect independence of all
circumstances, except mass and distance, the force of gravity stands
apart from all the other forces and phenomena of nature, and has
not yet been brought into any relation with them except through the
general principle of the conservation of energy. Magnetic attraction,
as remarked by Newton, follows very different laws, depending upon the
chemical quality and molecular structure of each particular substance.

We must remember that in saying “all matter gravitates,” we exclude
from the term matter the basis of light-undulations, which is
immensely more extensive in amount, and obeys in many respects the
laws of mechanics. This adamantine substance appears, so far as can be
ascertained, to be perfectly uniform in its properties when existing
in space unoccupied by matter. Light and heat are conveyed by it with
equal velocity in all directions, and in all parts of space so far as
observation informs us. But the presence of gravitating matter modifies
the density and mechanical properties of the so-called ether in a way
which is yet quite unexplained.[494]

Leaving gravity, it is somewhat difficult to discover other laws
which are equally true of all matter. Boerhaave was considered to
have established that all bodies expand by heat; but not only is the
expansion very different in different substances, but we now know
positive exceptions. Many liquids and a few solids contract by heat
at certain temperatures. There are indeed other relations of heat to
matter which seem to be universal and uniform; all substances begin
to give off rays of light at the same temperature, according to the
law of Draper; and gases will not be an exception if sufficiently
condensed, as in the experiments of Frankland. Grove considers it to
be universally true that all bodies in combining produce heat; with
the doubtful exception of sulphur and selenium, all solids in becoming
liquids, and all liquids in becoming gases, absorb heat; but the
quantities of heat absorbed vary with the chemical qualities of the
matter. Carnot’s Thermodynamic Law is held to be exactly true of all
matter without distinction; it expresses the fact that the amount of
mechanical energy which might be theoretically obtained from a certain
amount of heat energy depends only upon the change of the temperatures,
so that whether an engine be worked by water, air, alcohol, ammonia, or
any other substance, the result would theoretically be the same, if the
boiler and condenser were maintained at similar temperatures.

  [494] Professor Lovering has pointed out how obscure and uncertain
  the ideas of scientific men about this ether are, in his interesting
  Presidential Address before the American Association at Hartford,
  1874. *Silliman’s Journal*, October 1874, p. 297. *Philosophical
  Magazine*, vol. xlviii. p. 493.


*Variable Properties of Matter.*

I have enumerated some of the few properties of matter, which are
manifested in exactly the same manner by all substances, whatever be
their differences of chemical or physical constitution. But by far
the greater number of qualities vary in degree; substances are more
or less dense, more or less transparent, more or less compressible,
more or less magnetic, and so on. One common result of the progress of
science is to show that qualities supposed to be entirely absent from
many substances are present only in so low a degree of intensity that
the means of detection were insufficient. Newton believed that most
bodies were quite unaffected by the magnet; Faraday and Tyndall have
rendered it very doubtful whether any substance whatever is wholly
devoid of magnetism, including under that term diamagnetism. We are
rapidly learning to believe that there are no substances absolutely
opaque, or non-conducting, non-electric, non-elastic, non-viscous,
non-compressible, insoluble, infusible, or non-volatile. All tends
to become a matter of degree, or sometimes of direction. There may
be some substances oppositely affected to others, as ferro-magnetic
substances are oppositely affected to diamagnetics, or as substances
which contract by heat are opposed to those which expand; but the
tendency is certainly for every affection of one kind of matter to be
represented by something similar in other kinds. On this account one of
Newton’s rules of philosophising seems to lose all validity; he said,
“Those qualities of bodies which are not capable of being heightened,
and remitted, and which are found in all bodies on which experiment can
be made, must be considered as universal qualities of all bodies.” As
far as I can see, the contrary is more probable, namely, that qualities
variable in degree will be found in every substance in a greater or
less degree.

It is remarkable that Newton whose method of investigation was
logically perfect, seemed incapable of generalising and describing
his own procedure. His celebrated “Rules of Reasoning in Philosophy,”
described at the commencement of the third book of the *Principia*, are
of questionable truth, and still more questionable value.


*Extreme Instances of Properties.*

Although substances usually differ only in degree, great interest
may attach to particular substances which manifest a property in a
conspicuous and intense manner. Every branch of physical science
has usually been developed from the attention forcibly drawn to some
singular substance. Just as the loadstone disclosed magnetism and
amber frictional electricity, so did Iceland spar show the existence
of double refraction, and sulphate of quinine the phenomenon of
fluorescence. When one such startling instance has drawn the attention
of the scientific world, numerous less remarkable cases of the
phenomenon will be detected, and it will probably prove that the
property in question is actually universal to all matter. Nevertheless,
the extreme instances retain their interest, partly in a historical
point of view, partly because they furnish the most convenient
substances for experiment.

Francis Bacon was fully aware of the value of such examples, which he
called *Ostensive Instances* or Light-giving, Free and Predominant
Instances. “They are those,” he says,[495] “which show the nature
under investigation naked, in an exalted condition, or in the highest
degree of power; freed from impediments, or at least by its strength
predominating over and suppressing them.” He mentions quicksilver as
an ostensive instance of weight or density, thinking it not much less
dense than gold, and more remarkable than gold as joining density
to liquidity. The magnet is mentioned as an ostensive instance of
attraction. It would not be easy to distinguish clearly between these
ostensive instances and those which he calls *Instantiae Monodicae*,
or *Irregulares*, or *Heteroclitae*, under which he places whatever
is extravagant in its properties or magnitude, or exhibits least
similarity to other things, such as the sun and moon among the heavenly
bodies, the elephant among animals, the letter *s* among letters, or
the magnet among stones.[496]

  [495] *Novum Organum*, bk. ii. Aphorisms, 24, 25.

  [496] Ibid. Aph. 28.

In optical science great use has been made of the high dispersive
power of the transparent compounds of lead, that is, the power of
giving a long spectrum (p. 432). Dollond, having noticed this peculiar
dispersive power in lenses made of flint glass, employed them to
produce an achromatic arrangement. The element strontium presents a
contrast to lead in this respect, being characterised by a remarkably
low dispersive power; but I am not aware that this property has yet
been turned to account.

Compounds of lead have both a high dispersive and a high refractive
index, and in the latter respect they proved very useful to Faraday.
Having spent much labour in preparing various kinds of optical glass,
Faraday happened to form a compound of lead, silica, and boracic
acid, now known as *heavy glass*, which possessed an intensely high
refracting power. Many years afterwards in attempting to discover the
action of magnetism upon light he failed to detect any effect, as has
been already mentioned, (p. 588), until he happened to test a piece of
the heavy glass. The peculiar refractive power of this medium caused
the magnetic strain to be apparent, and the rotation of the plane of
polarisation was discovered.

In almost every part of physical science there is some substance
of powers pre-eminent for the special purpose to which it is put.
Rock-salt is invaluable for its extreme diathermancy or transparency to
the least refrangible rays of the spectrum. Quartz is equally valuable
for its transparency, as regards the ultra-violet or most refrangible
rays. Diamond is the most highly refracting substance which is at the
same time transparent; were it more abundant and easily worked it would
be of great optical importance. Cinnabar is distinguished by possessing
a power of rotating the plane of polarisation of light, from 15 to 17
times as much as quartz. In electric experiments copper is employed for
its high conducting powers and exceedingly low magnetic properties;
iron is of course indispensable for its enormous magnetic powers; while
bismuth holds a like place as regards its diamagnetic powers, and was
of much importance in Tyndall’s decisive researches upon the polar
character of the diamagnetic force.[497] In regard to magne-crystallic
action the mineral cyanite is highly remarkable, being so powerfully
affected by the earth’s magnetism, that, when delicately suspended, it
assumes a constant position with regard to the magnetic meridian, and
may almost be used like the compass needle. Sodium is distinguished
by its unique light-giving powers, which are so extraordinary that
probably one half of the whole number of stars in the heavens have a
yellow tinge in consequence.

  [497] *Philosophical Transactions* (1856) vol. cxlvi. p. 246.

It is remarkable that water, though the most common of all fluids,
is distinguished in almost every respect by extreme qualities. Of
all known substances water has the highest specific heat, being thus
peculiarly fitted for the purpose of warming and cooling, to which
it is often put. It rises by capillary attraction to a height more
than twice that of any other liquid. In the state of ice it is nearly
twice as dilatable by heat as any other known solid substance.[498] In
proportion to its density it has a far higher surface tension than any
other substance, being surpassed in absolute tension only by mercury;
and it would not be difficult to extend considerably the list of its
remarkable and useful properties.

  [498] *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, January 1870, vol. xxxix.
  p. 2.

Under extreme instances we may include cases of remarkably low powers
or qualities. Such cases seem to correspond to what Bacon calls
*Clandestine Instances*, which exhibit a given nature in the least
intensity, and as it were in a rudimentary state.[499] They may often
be important, he thinks, as allowing the detection of the cause of
the property by difference. I may add that in some cases they may be
of use in experiments. Thus hydrogen is the least dense of all known
substances, and has the least atomic weight. Liquefied nitrous oxide
has the lowest refractive index of all known fluids.[500] The compounds
of strontium have the lowest dispersive power. It is obvious that
a property of very low degree may prove as curious and valuable a
phenomenon as a property of very high degree.

  [499] *Novum Organum*, bk. ii. Aphorism 25.

  [500] Faraday’s *Experimental Researches in Chemistry and Physics*,
  p. 93.


*The Detection of Continuity.*

We should bear in mind that phenomena which are in reality of a
closely similar or even identical nature, may present to the senses
very different appearances. Without a careful analysis of the changes
which take place, we may often be in danger of widely separating facts
and processes, which are actually instances of the same law. Extreme
difference of degree or magnitude is a frequent cause of error. It is
truly difficult at the first moment to recognise any similarity between
the gradual rusting of a piece of iron, and the rapid combustion of a
heap of straw. Yet Lavoisier’s chemical theory was founded upon the
similarity of the oxydising process in one case and the other. We have
only to divide the iron into excessively small particles to discover
that it is really the more combustible of the two, and that it actually
takes fire spontaneously and burns like tinder. It is the excessive
slowness of the process in the case of a massive piece of iron which
disguises its real character.

If Xenophon reports truly, Socrates was misled by not making sufficient
allowance for extreme differences of degree and quantity. Anaxagoras
held that the sun is a fire, but Socrates rejected this opinion, on the
ground that we can look at a fire, but not at the sun, and that plants
grow by sunshine while they are killed by fire. He also pointed out
that a stone heated in a fire is not luminous, and soon cools, whereas
the sun ever remains equally luminous and hot.[501] All such mistakes
evidently arise from not perceiving that difference of quantity may be
so extreme as to assume the appearance of difference of quality. It is
the least creditable thing we know of Socrates, that after pointing
out these supposed mistakes of earlier philosophers, he advised his
followers not to study astronomy.

  [501] *Memorabilia*, iv. 7.

Masses of matter of very different size may be expected to exhibit
apparent differences of conduct, arising from the various intensity of
the forces brought into play. Many persons have thought it requisite
to imagine occult forces producing the suspension of the clouds, and
there have even been absurd theories representing cloud particles as
minute water-balloons buoyed up by the warm air within them. But we
have only to take proper account of the enormous comparative resistance
which the air opposes to the fall of minute particles, to see that
all cloud particles are probably constantly falling through the air,
but so slowly that there is no apparent effect. Mineral matter again
is always regarded as inert and incapable of spontaneous movement. We
are struck by astonishment on observing in a powerful microscope, that
every kind of solid matter suspended in extremely minute particles
in pure water, acquires an oscillatory movement, often so marked as
to resemble dancing or skipping. I conceive that this movement is due
to the comparatively vast intensity of chemical action when exerted
upon minute particles, the effect being 5,000 or 10,000 greater in
proportion to the mass than in fragments of an inch diameter (p. 406).

Much that was formerly obscure in the science of electricity arose from
the extreme differences of intensity and quantity in which this form of
energy manifests itself. Between the brilliant explosive discharge of a
thunder-cloud and the gentle continuous current produced by two pieces
of metal and some dilute acid, there is no apparent analogy whatever.
It was therefore a work of great importance when Faraday demonstrated
the identity of the forces in action, showing that common frictional
electricity would decompose water like that from the voltaic battery.
The relation of the phenomena became plain when he succeeded in showing
that it would require 800,000 discharges of his large Leyden battery
to decompose one single grain of water. Lightning was now seen to be
electricity of excessively high tension, but extremely small quantity,
the difference being somewhat analogous to that between the force of
one million gallons of water falling through one foot, and one gallon
of water falling through one million feet. Faraday estimated that one
grain of water acting on four grains of zinc, would yield electricity
enough for a great thunderstorm.

It was long believed that electrical conductors and insulators belonged
to two opposed classes of substances. Between the inconceivable
rapidity with which the current passes through pure copper wire,
and the apparently complete manner in which it is stopped by a
thin partition of gutta-percha or gum-lac, there seemed to be no
resemblance. Faraday again laboured successfully to show that these
were but the extreme cases of a chain of substances varying in all
degrees in their powers of conduction. Even the best conductors, such
as pure copper or silver, offer resistance to the electric current. The
other metals have considerably higher powers of resistance, and we pass
gradually down through oxides and sulphides. The best insulators, on
the other hand, allow of an atomic induction which is the necessary
antecedent of conduction. Hence Faraday inferred that whether we can
measure the effect or not, all substances discharge electricity more
or less.[502] One consequence of this doctrine must be, that every
discharge of electricity produces an induced current. In the case of
the common galvanic current we can readily detect the induced current
in any parallel wire or other neighbouring conductor, and can separate
the opposite currents which arise at the moments when the original
current begins and ends. But a discharge of high tension electricity
like lightning, though it certainly occupies time and has a beginning
and an end, yet lasts so minute a fraction of a second, that it would
be hopeless to attempt to detect and separate the two opposite induced
currents, which are nearly simultaneous and exactly neutralise each
other. Thus an apparent failure of analogy is explained away, and
we are furnished with another instance of a phenomenon incapable of
observation and yet theoretically known to exist.[503]

  [502] *Experimental Researches in Electricity*, Series xii. vol. i.
  p. 420.

  [503] *Life of Faraday*, vol. ii. p. 7.

Perhaps the most extraordinary case of the detection of unsuspected
continuity is found in the discovery of Cagniard de la Tour and
Professor Andrews, that the liquid and gaseous conditions of matter
are only remote points in a continuous course of change. Nothing is
at first sight more apparently distinct than the physical condition
of water and aqueous vapour. At the boiling-point there is an
entire breach of continuity, and the gas produced is subject to
laws incomparably more simple than the liquid from which it arose.
But Cagniard de la Tour showed that if we maintain a liquid under
sufficient pressure its boiling point may be indefinitely raised, and
yet the liquid will ultimately assume the gaseous condition with but
a small increase of volume. Professor Andrews, recently following out
this course of inquiry, has shown that liquid carbonic acid may, at
a particular temperature (30°·92 C.), and under the pressure of 74
atmospheres, be at the same time in a state indistinguishable from
that of liquid and gas. At higher pressures carbonic acid may be
made to pass from a palpably liquid state to a truly gaseous state
without any abrupt change whatever. As the pressure is greater the
abruptness of the change from liquid to gas gradually decreases, and
finally vanishes. Similar phenomena or an approximation to them have
been observed in other liquids, and there is little doubt that we may
make a wide generalisation, and assert that, under adequate pressure,
every liquid might be made to pass into a gas without breach of
continuity.[504] The liquid state, moreover, is considered by Professor
Andrews to be but an intermediate step between the solid and gaseous
conditions. There are various indications that the process of melting
is not perfectly abrupt; and could experiments be made under adequate
pressures, it is believed that every solid could be made to pass by
insensible degrees into the state of liquid, and subsequently into that
of gas.

  [504] *Nature*, vol. ii. p. 278.

These discoveries appear to open the way to most important and
fundamental generalisations, but it is probable that in many other
cases phenomena now regarded as discrete may be shown to be different
degrees of the same process. Graham was of opinion that chemical
affinity differs but in degree from the ordinary attraction which
holds different particles of a body together. He found that sulphuric
acid continued to evolve heat when mixed even with the fiftieth
equivalent of water, so that there seemed to be no distinct limit to
chemical affinity. He concludes, “There is reason to believe that
chemical affinity passes in its lowest degree into the attraction of
aggregation.”[505]

  [505] *Journal of the Chemical Society*, vol. viii. p. 51.

The atomic theory is well established, but its limits are not marked
out. As Grove points out, we may by selecting sufficiently high
multipliers express any combination or mixture of elements in terms
of their equivalent weights.[506] Sir W. Thomson has suggested that
the power which vegetable fibre, oatmeal, and other substances possess
of attracting and condensing aqueous vapour is probably continuous,
or, in fact, identical with capillary attraction, which is capable
of interfering with the pressure of aqueous vapour and aiding its
condensation.[507] There are many cases of so-called catalytic or
surface action, such as the extraordinary power of animal charcoal
for attracting organic matter, or of spongy platinum for condensing
hydrogen, which can only be considered as exalted cases of a more
general power of attraction. The number of substances which are
decomposed by light in a striking manner is very limited; but many
other substances, such as vegetable colours, are affected by long
exposure; on the principle of continuity we might expect to find that
all kinds of matter are more or less susceptible of change by the
incidence of light rays.[508] It is the opinion of Grove that wherever
an electric current passes there is a tendency to decomposition, a
strain on the molecules, which when sufficiently intense leads to
disruption. Even a metallic conducting wire may be regarded as tending
to decomposition. Davy was probably correct in describing electricity
as chemical affinity acting on masses, or rather, as Grove suggests,
creating a disturbance through a chain of particles.[509] Laplace went
so far as to suggest that all chemical phenomena may be results of
the Newtonian law of attraction, applied to atoms of various mass and
position; but the time is probably far distant when the progress of
molecular philosophy and of mathematical methods will enable such a
generalisation to be verified or refuted.

  [506] *Correlation of Physical Forces*, 3rd edit. p. 184.

  [507] *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. xlii. p. 451.

  [508] Grove, *Correlation of Physical Forces*, 3rd edit. p. 118.

  [509] Ibid. pp. 166, 199, &c.


*The Law of Continuity.*

Under the title of the Law of Continuity we may place many applications
of the general principle of reasoning, that what is true of one case
will be true of similar cases, and probably true of what are probably
similar. Whenever we find that a law or similarity is rigorously
fulfilled up to a certain point in time or space, we expect with a high
degree of probability that it will continue to be fulfilled at least a
little further. If we see part only of a circle, we naturally expect
that the circular form will be continued in the part hidden from us. If
a body has moved uniformly over a certain space, we expect that it will
continue to move uniformly. The ground of such inferences is doubtless
identical with that of other inductive inferences. In continuous
motion every infinitely small space passed over constitutes a separate
constituent fact, and had we perfect powers of observation the smallest
finite motion would include an infinity of information, which, by the
principles of the inverse method of probabilities, would enable us to
infer with certainty to the next infinitely small portion of the path.
But when we attempt to infer from one finite portion of a path to
another finite portion, inference will be only more or less probable,
according to the comparative lengths of the portions and the accuracy
of observation; the longer our experience is, the more probable our
inference will be; the greater the length of time or space over which
the inference extends, the less probable.

This principle of continuity presents itself in nature in a great
variety of forms and cases. It is familiarly expressed in the dictum
*Natura non agit per saltum*. As Graham expressed the maxim, there are
in nature no abrupt transitions, and the distinctions of class are
never absolute.[510] There is always some notice--some forewarning
of every phenomenon, and every change begins by insensible degrees,
could we observe it with perfect accuracy. The cannon ball, indeed, is
forced from the cannon in an inappreciable portion of time; the trigger
is pulled, the fuze fired, the powder inflamed, the ball expelled,
all simultaneously to our senses. But there is no doubt that time is
occupied by every part of the process, and that the ball begins to
move at first with infinite slowness. Captain Noble is able to measure
by his chronoscope the progress of the shot in a 300-pounder gun, and
finds that the whole motion within the barrel takes place in something
less than one 200th part of a second. It is certain that no finite
force can produce motion, except in a finite space of time. The amount
of momentum communicated to a body is proportional to the accelerating
force multiplied by the time during which it acts uniformly. Thus a
slight force produces a great velocity only by long-continued action.
In a powerful shock, like that of a railway collision, the stroke of a
hammer on an anvil, or the discharge of a gun, the time is very short,
and therefore the accelerating forces brought into play are exceedingly
great, but never infinite. In the case of a large gun the powder in
exploding is said to exert for a moment a force equivalent to at least
2,800,000 horses.

  [510] *Philosophical Transactions*, 1861. *Chemical and Physical
  Researches*, p. 598.

Our belief in some of the fundamental laws of nature rests upon the
principle of continuity. Galileo is held to be the first philosopher
who consciously employed this principle in his arguments concerning
the nature of motion, and it is certain that we can never by mere
experience assure ourselves of the truth even of the first law of
motion. *A material particle*, we are told, *when not acted on by
extraneous forces will continue in the same state of rest or motion.*
This may be true, but as we can find no body which is free from the
action of extraneous causes, how are we to prove it? Only by observing
that the less the amount of those forces the more nearly is the law
found to be true. A ball rolled along rough ground is soon stopped;
along a smooth pavement it continues longer in movement. A delicately
suspended pendulum is almost free from friction against its supports,
but it is gradually stopped by the resistance of the air; place it
in the vacuous receiver of an air-pump and we find the motion much
prolonged. A large planet like Jupiter experiences almost infinitely
less friction, in comparison to its vast momentum, than we can produce
experimentally, and we find in such a case that there is not the least
evidence of the falsity of the law. Experience, then, informs us that
we may approximate indefinitely to a uniform motion by sufficiently
decreasing the disturbing forces. It is an act of inference which
enables us to travel on beyond experience, and assert that, in the
total absence of any extraneous force, motion would be absolutely
uniform. The state of rest, again, is a limiting case in which motion
is infinitely small or zero, to which we may attain, on the principle
of continuity, by successively considering cases of slower and slower
motion. There are many classes of phenomena, in which, by gradually
passing from the apparent to the obscure, we can assure ourselves of
the nature of phenomena which would otherwise be a matter of great
doubt. Thus we can sufficiently prove in the manner of Galileo, that
a musical sound consists of rapid uniform pulses, by causing strokes
to be made at intervals which we gradually diminish until the separate
strokes coalesce into a uniform hum or note. With great advantage we
approach, as Tyndall says, the sonorous through the grossly mechanical.
In listening to a great organ we cannot fail to perceive that the
longest pipes, or their partial tones, produce a tremor and fluttering
of the building. At the other extremity of the scale, there is no fixed
limit to the acuteness of sounds which we can hear; some individuals
can hear sounds too shrill for other ears, and as there is nothing in
the nature of the atmosphere to prevent the existence of undulations
far more rapid than any of which we are conscious, we may infer, by the
principle of continuity, that such undulations probably exist.

There are many habitual actions which we perform we know not how. So
rapidly are acts of minds accomplished that analysis seems impossible.
We can only investigate them when in process of formation, observing
that the best formed habit is slowly and continuously acquired, and
it is in the early stages that we can perceive the rationale of the
process.

Let it be observed that this principle of continuity must be held of
much weight only in exact physical laws, those which doubtless repose
ultimately upon the simple laws of motion. If we fearlessly apply
the principle to all kinds of phenomena, we may often be right in
our inferences, but also often wrong. Thus, before the development
of spectrum analysis, astronomers had observed that the more they
increased the powers of their telescopes the more nebulæ they could
resolve into distinct stars. This result had been so often found
true that they almost irresistibly assumed that all nebulæ would be
ultimately resolved by telescopes of sufficient power; yet Huggins has
in recent years proved by the spectroscope, that certain nebulæ are
actually gaseous, and in a truly nebulous state.

The principle of continuity must have been continually employed in the
inquiries of Galileo, Newton, and other experimental philosophers,
but it appears to have been distinctly formulated for the first time
by Leibnitz. He at least claims to have first spoken of “the law of
continuity” in a letter to Bayle, printed in the *Nouvelles de la
République des Lettres*, an extract from which is given in Erdmann’s
edition of Leibnitz’s works, p. 104, under the title “Sur un Principe
Général utile à l’explication des Lois de la Nature.”[511] It has
indeed been asserted that the doctrine of the *latens processus* of
Francis Bacon involves the principle of continuity,[512] but I think
that this doctrine, like that of the *natures* of substances, is merely
a vague statement of the principle of causation.

  [511] *Life of Sir W. Hamilton*, p. 439.

  [512] Powell’s *History of Natural Philosophy*, p. 201. *Novum
  Organum*, bk. ii. Aphorisms 5–7.


*Failure of the Law of Continuity.*

There are certain cautions which must be given as to the application of
the principle of continuity. In the first place, where this principle
really holds true, it may seem to fail owing to our imperfect means
of observation. Though a physical law may not admit of perfectly
abrupt change, there is no limit to the approach which it may make to
abruptness. When we warm a piece of very cold ice, the absorption of
heat, the temperature, and the dilatation of the ice vary according
to apparently simple laws until we come to the zero of the Centigrade
scale. Everything is then changed; an enormous absorption of heat
takes place without any rise of temperature, and the volume of the ice
decreases as it changes into water. Unless carefully investigated, this
change appears to be perfectly abrupt; but accurate observation seems
to show that there is a certain forewarning; the ice does not turn into
water all at once, but through a small fraction of a degree the change
is gradual. All the phenomena concerned, if measured very exactly,
would be represented not by angular lines, but continuous curves,
undergoing rapid flexures; and we may probably assert with safety that
between whatever points of temperature we examine ice, there would be
found some indication, though almost infinitesimally small, of the
apparently abrupt change which was to occur at a higher temperature.
It might also be pointed out that the important and apparently simple
physical laws, such as those of Boyle and Mariotte, Dalton and
Gay-Lussac, &c., are only approximately true, and the divergences
from the simple laws are forewarnings of abrupt changes, which would
otherwise break the law of continuity.

Secondly, it must be remembered that mathematical laws of some
complexity will probably present singular cases or negative results,
which may bear the appearance of discontinuity, as when the law of
retraction suddenly yields us with perfect abruptness the phenomenon of
total internal reflection. In the undulatory theory, however, there is
no real change of law between refraction and reflection. Faraday in the
earlier part of his career found so many substances possessing magnetic
power, that he ventured on a great generalisation, and asserted that
all bodies shared in the magnetic property of iron. His mistake, as he
afterwards discovered, consisted in overlooking the fact that though
magnetic in a certain sense, some substances have negative magnetism,
and are repelled instead of being attracted by the magnet.

Thirdly, where we might expect to find a uniform mathematical law
prevailing, the law may undergo abrupt change at singular points,
and actual discontinuity may arise. We may sometimes be in danger of
treating under one law phenomena which really belong to different laws.
For instance, a spherical shell of uniform matter attracts an external
particle of matter with a force varying inversely as the square of the
distance from the centre of the sphere. But this law only holds true
so long as the particle is external to the shell. Within the shell
the law is wholly different, and the aggregate gravity of the sphere
becomes zero, the force in every direction being neutralised by an
exactly equal opposite force. If an infinitely small particle be in the
superficies of a sphere, the law is again different, and the attractive
power of the shell is half what it would be with regard to particles
infinitely close to the surface of the shell. Thus in approaching the
centre of a shell from a distance, the force of gravity shows double
discontinuity in passing through the shell.[513]

  [513] Thomson and Tait, *Treatise on Natural Philosophy*, vol. i. pp.
  346–351.

It may admit of question, too, whether discontinuity is really unknown
in nature. We perpetually do meet with events which are real breaks
upon the previous law, though the discontinuity may be a sign that
some independent cause has come into operation. If the ordinary
course of the tides is interrupted by an enormous irregular wave, we
attribute it to an earthquake, or some gigantic natural disturbance.
If a meteoric stone falls upon a person and kills him, it is clearly a
discontinuity in his life, of which he could have had no anticipation.
A sudden sound may pass through the air neither preceded nor followed
by any continuous effect. Although, then, we may regard the Law of
Continuity as a principle of nature holding rigorously true in many of
the relations of natural forces, it seems to be a matter of difficulty
to assign the limits within which the law is verified. Much caution is
required in its application.


*Negative Arguments on the Principle of Continuity.*

Upon the principle of continuity we may sometimes found arguments of
great force which prove an hypothesis to be impossible, because it
would involve a continual repetition of a process *ad infinitum*, or
else a purely arbitrary breach at some point. Bonnet’s famous theory
of reproduction represented every living creature as containing
germs which were perfect representatives of the next generation, so
that on the same principle they necessarily included germs of the
next generation, and so on indefinitely. The theory was sufficiently
refuted when once clearly stated, as in the following poem called the
Universe,[514] by Henry Baker:--

  “Each seed includes a plant: that plant, again,
   Has other seeds, which other plants contain:
   Those other plants have all their seeds, and those
   More plants again, successively inclose.

  “Thus, ev’ry single berry that we find,
   Has, really, in itself whole forests of its kind,
   Empire and wealth one acorn may dispense,
   By fleets to sail a thousand ages hence.”

  [514] *Philosophical Transactions* (1740), vol. xli. p. 454.

The general principle of inference, that what we know of one case must
be true of similar cases, so far as they are similar, prevents our
asserting anything which we cannot apply time after time under the same
circumstances. On this principle Stevinus beautifully demonstrated
that weights resting on two inclined planes and balancing each other
must be proportional to the lengths of the planes between their apex
and a horizontal plane. He imagined a uniform endless chain to be hung
over the planes, and to hang below in a symmetrical festoon. If the
chain were ever to move by gravity, there would be the same reason
for its moving on for ever, and thus producing a perpetual motion. As
this is absurd, the portions of the chain lying on the planes, and
equal in length to the planes, must balance each other. On similar
grounds we may disprove the existence of any *self-moving machine*;
for if it could once alter its own state of motion or rest, in however
small a degree, there is no reason why it should not do the like
time after time *ad infinitum*. Newton’s proof of his third law of
motion, in the case of gravity, is of this character. For he remarks
that if two gravitating bodies do not exert exactly equal forces in
opposite directions, the one exerting the strongest pull will carry
both away, and the two bodies will move off into space together with
velocity increasing *ad infinitum*. But though the argument might
seem sufficiently convincing, Newton in his characteristic way made
an experiment with a loadstone and iron floated upon the surface of
water.[515] In recent years the very foundation of the principle of
conservation of energy has been placed on the assumption that it is
impossible by any combination of natural bodies to produce force
continually from nothing.[516] The principle admits of application in
various subtle forms.

  [515] *Principia*, bk. i. Law iii. Corollary 6.

  [516] Helmholtz, Taylor’s *Scientific Memoirs* (1853), vol. vi.
  p. 118.

Lucretius attempted to prove, by a most ingenious argument of this
kind, that matter must be indestructible. For if a finite quantity,
however small, were to fall out of existence in any finite time, an
equal quantity might be supposed to lapse in every equal interval of
time, so that in the infinity of past time the universe must have
ceased to exist.[517] But the argument, however ingenious, seems to
fail at several points. If past time be infinite, why may not matter
have been created infinite also? It would be most reasonable, again,
to suppose the matter destroyed in any time to be proportional to the
matter then remaining, and not to the original quantity; under this
hypothesis even a finite quantity of original matter could never wholly
disappear from the universe. For like reasons we cannot hold that the
doctrine of the conservation of energy is really proved, or can ever be
proved to be absolutely true, however probable it may be regarded.

  [517] *Lucretius*, bk. i. lines 232–264.


*Tendency to Hasty Generalisation.*

In spite of all the powers and advantages of generalisation, men
require no incitement to generalise; they are too apt to draw hasty and
ill-considered inferences. As Francis Bacon said, our intellects want
not wings, but rather weights of lead to moderate their course.[518]
The process is inevitable to the human mind; it begins with childhood
and lasts through the second childhood. The child that has once been
hurt fears the like result on all similar occasions, and can with
difficulty be made to distinguish between case and case. It is caution
and discrimination in the adoption of conclusions that we have chiefly
to learn, and the whole experience of life is one continued lesson
to this effect. Baden Powell has excellently described this strong
natural propensity to hasty inference, and the fondness of the human
mind for tracing resemblances real or fanciful. “Our first inductions,”
he says,[519] “are always imperfect and inconclusive; we advance
towards real evidence by successive approximations; and accordingly we
find false generalisation the besetting error of most first attempts
at scientific research. The faculty to generalise accurately and
philosophically requires large caution and long training, and is not
fully attained, especially in reference to more general views, even
by some who may properly claim the title of very accurate scientific
observers in a more limited field. It is an intellectual habit which
acquires immense and accumulating force from the contemplation of wider
analogies.”

  [518] *Novum Organum*, bk. 1 Aphorism 104.

  [519] *The Unity of Worlds and of Nature*, 2nd edit. p. 116.

Hasty and superficial generalisations have always been the bane
of science, and there would be no difficulty in finding endless
illustrations. Between things which are the same in number there is a
certain resemblance, namely in number; but in the infancy of science
men could not be persuaded that there was not a deeper resemblance
implied in that of number. Pythagoras was not the inventor of a
mystical science of number. In the ancient Oriental religions the seven
metals were connected with the seven planets, and in the seven days
of the week we still have, and probably always shall have, a relic of
the septiform system ascribed by Dio Cassius to the ancient Egyptians.
The disciples of Pythagoras carried the doctrine of the number seven
into great detail. Seven days are mentioned in Genesis; infants acquire
their teeth at the end of seven months; they change them at the end
of seven years; seven feet was the limit of man’s height; every
seventh year was a climacteric or critical year, at which a change
of disposition took place. Then again there were the seven sages of
Greece, the seven wonders of the world, the seven rites of the Grecian
games, the seven gates of Thebes, and the seven generals destined to
conquer that city.

In natural science there were not only the seven planets, and the seven
metals, but also the seven primitive colours, and the seven tones
of music. So deep a hold did this doctrine take that we still have
its results in many customs, not only in the seven days of the week,
but the seven years’ apprenticeship, puberty at fourteen years, the
second climacteric, and legal majority at twenty-one years, the third
climacteric. The idea was reproduced in the seven sacraments of the
Roman Catholic Church, and the seven year periods of Comte’s grotesque
system of domestic worship. Even in scientific matters the loftiest
intellects have occasionally yielded, as when Newton was misled by the
analogy between the seven tones of music and the seven colours of his
spectrum. Other numerical analogies, though rejected by Galileo, held
Kepler in thraldom; no small part of Kepler’s labours during seventeen
years was spent upon numerical and geometrical analogies of the most
baseless character; and he gravely held that there could not be more
than six planets, because there were not more than five regular solids.
Even the genius of Huyghens did not prevent him from inferring that
but one satellite could belong to Saturn, because, with those of
Jupiter and the Earth, it completed the perfect number of six. A whole
series of other superstitions and fallacies attach to the numbers six
and nine.

It is by false generalisation, again, that the laws of nature have
been supposed to possess that perfection which we attribute to simple
forms and relations. The heavenly bodies, it was held, must move in
circles, for the circle was the perfect figure. Newton seemed to adopt
the questionable axiom that nature always proceeds in the simplest way;
in stating his first rule of philosophising, he adds:[520] “To this
purpose the philosophers say, that nature does nothing in vain, when
less will serve; for nature is pleased with simplicity, and affects
not the pomp of superfluous causes.” Keill lays down[521] as an axiom
that “The causes of natural things are such, as are the most simple,
and are sufficient to explain the phenomena: for nature always proceeds
in the simplest and most expeditious method; because by this manner of
operating the Divine Wisdom displays itself the more.” If this axiom
had any clear grounds of truth, it would not apply to proximate laws;
for even when the ultimate law is simple the results may be infinitely
diverse, as in the various elliptic, hyperbolic, parabolic, or circular
orbits of the heavenly bodies. Simplicity is naturally agreeable to a
mind of limited powers, but to an infinite mind all things are simple.

  [520] *Principia*, bk. iii, *ad initium*.

  [521] Keill, *Introduction to Natural Philosophy*, p. 89.

Every great advance in science consists in a great generalisation,
pointing out deep and subtle resemblances. The Copernican system was
a generalisation, in that it classed the earth among the planets; it
was, as Bishop Wilkins expressed it, “the discovery of a new planet,”
but it was opposed by a more shallow generalisation. Those who argued
from the condition of things upon the earth’s surface, thought that
every object must be attached to and rest upon something else. Shall
the earth, they said, alone be free? Accustomed to certain special
results of gravity they could not conceive its action under widely
different circumstances.[522] No hasty thinker could seize the deep
analogy pointed out by Horrocks between a pendulum and a planet,
true in substance though mistaken in some details. All the advances
of modern science rise from the conception of Galileo, that in the
heavenly bodies, however apparently different their condition, we shall
ultimately recognise the same fundamental principles of mechanical
science which are true on earth.

  [522] Jeremiæ Horroccii *Opera Posthuma* (1673), pp. 26, 27.

Generalisation is the great prerogative of the intellect, but it
is a power only to be exercised safely with much caution and after
long training. Every mind must generalise, but there are the widest
differences in the depth of the resemblances discovered and the care
with which the discovery is verified. There seems to be an innate
power of insight which a few men have possessed pre-eminently, and
which enabled them, with no exemption indeed from labour or temporary
error, to discover the one in the many. Minds of excessive acuteness
may exist, which have yet only the powers of minute discrimination,
and of storing up, in the treasure-house of memory, vast accumulations
of words and incidents. But the power of discovery belongs to a
more restricted class of minds. Laplace said that, of all inventors
who had contributed the most to the advancement of human knowledge,
Newton and Lagrange appeared to possess in the highest degree the
happy tact of distinguishing general principles among a multitude of
objects enveloping them, and this tact he conceived to be the true
characteristic of scientific genius.[523]

  [523] Young’s *Works*, vol. ii. p. 564.




CHAPTER XXVIII.

ANALOGY.


As we have seen in the previous chapter, generalisation passes
insensibly into reasoning by analogy, and the difference is one of
degree. We are said to generalise when we view many objects as agreeing
in a few properties, so that the resemblance is extensive rather
than deep. When we have only a few objects of thought, but are able
to discover many points of resemblance, we argue by analogy that the
correspondence will be even deeper than appears. It may not be true
that the words are always used in such distinct senses, and there is
great vagueness in the employment of these and many logical terms; but
if any clear discrimination can be drawn between generalisation and
analogy, it is as indicated above.

It has been said, indeed, that analogy denotes not a resemblance
between things, but between the relations of things. A pilot is a very
different man from a prime minister, but he bears the same relation to
a ship that the minister does to the state, so that we may analogically
describe the prime minister as the pilot of the state. A man differs
still more from a horse, nevertheless four men bear to three men the
same relation as four horses bear to three horses. There is a real
analogy between the tones of the Monochord, the Sages of Greece, and
the Gates of Thebes, but it does not extend beyond the fact that they
were all seven in number. Between the most discrete notions, as, for
instance, those of time and space, analogy may exist, arising from
the fact that the mathematical conditions of the lapse of time and
of motion along a line are similar. There is no identity of nature
between a word and the thing it signifies; the substance *iron* is
a heavy solid, the word *iron* is either a momentary disturbance of
the air, or a film of black pigment on white paper; but there is
analogy between words and their significates. The substance iron is
to the substance iron-carbonate, as the name iron is to the name
iron-carbonate, when these names are used according to their scientific
definitions. The whole structure of language and the whole utility
of signs, marks, symbols, pictures, and representations of various
kinds, rest upon analogy. I may hope perhaps to enter more fully upon
this important subject at some future time, and to attempt to show how
the invention of signs enables us to express, guide, and register our
thoughts. It will be sufficient to observe here that the use of words
constantly involves analogies of a subtle kind; we should often be at
a loss how to describe a notion, were we not at liberty to employ in
a metaphorical sense the name of anything sufficiently resembling it.
There would be no expression for the sweetness of a melody, or the
brilliancy of an harangue, unless it were furnished by the taste of
honey and the brightness of a torch.

A cursory examination of the way in which we popularly use the
word analogy, shows that it includes all degrees of resemblance or
similarity. The analogy may consist only in similarity of number or
ratio, or in like relations of time and space. It may also consist in
simple resemblance between physical properties. We should not be using
the word inconsistently with custom, if we said that there was an
analogy between iron, nickel, and cobalt, manifested in the strength of
their magnetic powers. There is a still more perfect analogy between
iodine and chlorine; not that every property of iodine is identical
with the corresponding property of chlorine; for then they would
be one and the same kind of substance, and not two substances; but
every property of iodine resembles in all but degree some property of
chlorine. For almost every substance in which iodine forms a component,
a corresponding substance may be discovered containing chlorine, so
that we may confidently infer from the compounds of the one to the
compounds of the other substance. Potassium iodide crystallises in
cubes; therefore it is to be expected that potassium chloride will
also crystallise in cubes. The science of chemistry as now developed
rests almost entirely upon a careful and extensive comparison of the
properties of substances, bringing deep-lying analogies to light.
When any new substance is encountered, the chemist is guided in his
treatment of it by the analogies which it seems to present with
previously known substances.

In this chapter I cannot hope to illustrate the all-pervading influence
of analogy in human thought and science. All science, it has been said,
at the outset, arises from the discovery of identity, and analogy is
but one name by which we denote the deeper-lying cases of resemblance.
I shall only try to point out at present how analogy between apparently
diverse classes of phenomena often serves as a guide in discovery. We
thus commonly gain the first insight into the nature of an apparently
unique object, and thus, in the progress of a science, we often
discover that we are treating over again, in a new form, phenomena
which were well known to us in another form.


*Analogy as a Guide in Discovery.*

There can be no doubt that discovery is most frequently accomplished
by following up hints received from analogy, as Jeremy Bentham
remarked.[524] Whenever a phenomenon is perceived, the first impulse
of the mind is to connect it with the most nearly similar phenomenon.
If we could ever meet a thing wholly *sui generis*, presenting no
analogy to anything else, we should be incapable of investigating its
nature, except by purely haphazard trial. The probability of success
by such a process is so slight, that it is preferable to follow up the
faintest clue. As I have pointed out already (p. 418), the possible
experiments are almost infinite in number, and very numerous also are
the hypotheses upon which we may proceed. Now it is self-evident that,
however slightly superior the probability of success by one course of
procedure may be over another, the most probable one should always be
adopted first.

  [524] *Essay on Logic*, *Works*, vol. viii. p. 276.

The chemist having discovered what he believes to be a new element,
will have before him an infinite variety of modes of treating and
investigating it. If in any of its qualities the substance displays
a resemblance to an alkaline metal, for instance, he will naturally
proceed to try whether it possesses other properties of the alkaline
metals. Even the simplest phenomenon presents so many points for notice
that we have a choice from among many hypotheses.

It would be difficult to find a more instructive instance of the way in
which the mind is guided by analogy than in the description by Sir John
Herschel of the course of thought by which he was led to anticipate in
theory one of Faraday’s greatest discoveries. Herschel noticed that
a screw-like form, technically called helicoidal dissymmetry, was
observed in three cases, namely, in electrical helices, plagihedral
quartz crystals, and the rotation of the plane of polarisation of
light. As he said,[525] “I reasoned thus: Here are three phenomena
agreeing in a *very strange peculiarity*. Probably, this peculiarity
is a connecting link, physically speaking, among them. Now, in the
case of the crystals and the light, this probability has been turned
into certainty by my own experiments. Therefore, induction led me to
conclude that a similar connection exists, and must turn up, somehow
or other, between the electric current and polarised light, and that
the plane of polarisation would be deflected by magneto-electricity.”
By this course of analogical thought Herschel had actually been led
to anticipate Faraday’s great discovery of the influence of magnetic
strain upon polarised light. He had tried in 1822–25 to discover the
influence of electricity on light, by sending a ray of polarised light
through a helix, or near a long wire conveying an electric current.
Such a course of inquiry, followed up with the persistency of Faraday,
and with his experimental resources, would doubtless have effected the
discovery. Herschel also suggests that the plagihedral form of quartz
crystals must be due to a screw-like strain during crystallisation; but
the notion remains unverified by experiment.

  [525] *Life of Faraday*, by Bence Jones, vol. ii. p. 206.


*Analogy in the Mathematical Sciences.*

Whoever wishes to acquire a deep acquaintance with Nature must observe
that there are analogies which connect whole branches of science in a
parallel manner, and enable us to infer of one class of phenomena what
we know of another. It has thus happened on several occasions that the
discovery of an unsuspected analogy between two branches of knowledge
has been the starting-point for a rapid course of discovery. The truths
readily observed in the one may be of a different character from those
which present themselves in the other. The analogy, once pointed out,
leads us to discover regions of one science yet undeveloped, to which
the key is furnished by the corresponding truths in the other science.
An interchange of aid most wonderful in its results may thus take
place, and at the same time the mind rises to a higher generalisation,
and a more comprehensive view of nature.

No two sciences might seem at first sight more different in their
subject matter than geometry and algebra. The first deals with circles,
squares, parallelograms, and other forms in space; the latter with
mere symbols of number. Prior to the time of Descartes, the sciences
were developed slowly and painfully in almost entire independence of
each other. The Greek philosophers indeed could not avoid noticing
occasional analogies, as when Plato in the Thæetetus describes a square
number as *equally equal*, and a number produced by multiplying two
unequal factors as *oblong*. Euclid, in the 7th and 8th books of his
Elements, continually uses expressions displaying a consciousness
of the same analogies, as when he calls a number of two factors a
*plane number*, ἐπίπεδος ἀριθμός, and distinguishes a square number of
which the two factors are equal as an equal-sided and plane number,
ἰσόπλευρος καὶ ἐπίπεδος ἀριθμός. He also calls the root of a cubic
number its side, πλευρά. In the Diophantine algebra many problems of a
geometrical character were solved by algebraic or numerical processes;
but there was no general system, so that the solutions were of an
isolated character. In general the ancients were far more advanced in
geometric than symbolic methods; thus Euclid in his 4th book gives the
means of dividing a circle by purely geometric means into 2, 3, 4, 5,
6, 8, 10, 12, 15, 16, 20, 24, 30 parts, but he was totally unacquainted
with the theory of the roots of unity exactly corresponding to this
division of the circle.

During the middle ages, on the contrary, algebra advanced beyond
geometry, and modes of solving equations were gradually discovered
by those who had no notion that at every step they were implicitly
solving geometric problems. It is true that Regiomontanus, Tartaglia,
Bombelli, and possibly other early algebraists, solved isolated
geometrical problems by the aid of algebra, but particular numbers were
always used, and no consciousness of a general method was displayed.
Vieta in some degree anticipated the final discovery, and occasionally
represented the roots of an equation geometrically, but it was
reserved for Descartes to show, in the most general manner, that every
equation may be represented by a curve or figure in space, and that
every bend, point, cusp, or other peculiarity in the curve indicates
some peculiarity in the equation. It is impossible to describe in any
adequate manner the importance of this discovery. The advantage was
two-fold: algebra aided geometry, and geometry gave reciprocal aid
to algebra. Curves such as the well-known sections of the cone were
found to correspond to quadratic equations; and it was impossible
to manipulate the equations without discovering properties of those
all-important curves. The way was thus opened for the algebraic
treatment of motions and forces, without which Newton’s *Principia*
could never have been worked out. Newton indeed was possessed by a
strong infatuation in favour of the ancient geometrical methods; but
it is well known that he employed symbolic methods to discover his
theorems, and he now and then, by some accidental use of algebraic
expression, confessed its greater power and generality.

Geometry, on the other hand, gave great assistance to algebra, by
affording concrete representations of relations which would otherwise
be too abstract for easy comprehension. A curve of no great complexity
may give the whole history of the variations of value of a troublesome
mathematical expression. As soon as we know, too, that every regular
geometrical curve represents some algebraic equation, we are presented
by observation of mechanical movements with abundant suggestions
towards the discovery of mathematical problems. Every particle of a
carriage-wheel when moving on a level road is constantly describing
a cycloidal curve, the curious properties of which exercised the
ingenuity of all the most skilful mathematicians of the seventeenth
century, and led to important advancements in algebraic power. It may
be held that the discovery of the Differential Calculus was mainly
due to geometrical analogy, because mathematicians, in attempting to
treat algebraically the tangent of a curve, were obliged to entertain
the notion of infinitely small quantities.[526] There can be no doubt
that Newton’s fluxional, that is, geometrical mode of stating the
differential calculus, however much it subsequently retarded its
progress in England, facilitated its apprehension at first, and I
should think it almost certain that Newton discovered the principles of
the calculus geometrically.

  [526] Lacroix, *Traité Élémentaire de Calcul Différentiel et de
  Calcul Intégral*, 5^{me} édit. p. 699.

We may accordingly look upon this discovery of analogy, this happy
alliance, as Bossut calls it,[527] between geometry and algebra,
as the chief source of discoveries which have been made for three
centuries past in mathematical methods. This is certainly the opinion
of Lagrange, who says, “So long as algebra and geometry have been
separate, their progress was slow, and their employment limited; but
since these two sciences have been united, they have lent each other
mutual strength, and have marched together with a rapid step towards
perfection.”

  [527] *Histoire des Mathématiques*, vol. i. p. 298.

The advancement of mechanical science has also been greatly aided by
analogy. An abstract and intangible existence like force demands much
power of conception, but it has a perfect concrete representative in
a line, the end of which may denote the point of application, and
the direction the line of action of the force, while the length can
be made arbitrarily to denote the amount of the force. Nor does the
analogy end here; for the moment of the force about any point, or its
product into the perpendicular distance of its line of action from the
point, is found to be represented by an area, namely twice the area
of the triangle contained between the point and the ends of the line
representing the force. Of late years a great generalisation has been
effected; the Double Algebra of De Morgan is true not only of space
relations, but of forces, so that the triangle of forces is reduced
to a case of pure geometrical addition. Nay, the triangle of lines,
the triangle of velocities, the triangle of forces, the triangle of
couples, and perhaps other cognate theorems, are reduced by analogy to
one simple theorem, which amounts to this, that there are two ways of
getting from one angular point of a triangle to another, which ways,
though different in length, are identical in their final results.[528]
In the system of quaternions of the late Sir W. R. Hamilton, these
analogies are embodied and carried out in the most general manner, so
that whatever problem involves the threefold dimensions of space, or
relations analogous to those of space, is treated by a symbolic method
of the most comprehensive simplicity.

  [528] See Goodwin, *Cambridge Philosophical Transactions* (1845),
  vol. viii. p. 269. O’Brien, “On Symbolical Statics,” *Philosophical
  Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. i. pp. 491, &c. See also Professor
  Clerk Maxwell’s delightful *Manual of Elementary Science*, called
  *Matter and Motion*, published by the Society for Promoting Christian
  Knowledge. In this admirable little work some of the most advanced
  results of mechanical and physical science are explained according
  to the method of quaternions, but with hardly any use of algebraic
  symbols.

It ought to be added that to the discovery of analogy between the forms
of mathematical and logical expressions, we owe the greatest advance
in logical science. Boole based his extension of logical processes
upon the notion that logic is an algebra of two quantities 0 and 1.
His profound genius for symbolic investigation led him to perceive by
analogy that there must exist a general system of logical deduction, of
which the old logicians had seized only a few fragments. Mistaken as
he was in placing algebra as a higher science than logic, no one can
deny that the development of the more complex and dependent science
had advanced far beyond that of the simpler science, and that Boole,
in drawing attention to the connection, made one of the most important
discoveries in the history of science. As Descartes had wedded algebra
and geometry, so did Boole accomplish the marriage of logic and
algebra.


*Analogy in the Theory of Undulations.*

There is no class of phenomena which more thoroughly illustrates alike
the power and weakness of analogy than the waves which agitate every
kind of medium. All waves, whatsoever be the matter through which
they pass, obey the principles of rhythmical or harmonic motion,
and the subject therefore presents a fine field for mathematical
generalisation. Each kind of medium may allow of waves peculiar in
their conditions, so that it is a beautiful exercise in analogical
reasoning to decide how, in making inferences from one kind of medium
to another, we must make allowance for difference of circumstances. The
waves of the ocean are large and visible, and there are the yet greater
tidal waves which extend around the globe. From such palpable cases of
rhythmical movement we pass to waves of sound, varying in length from
about 32 feet to a small fraction of an inch. We have but to imagine,
if we can, the fortieth octave of the middle C of a piano, and we reach
the undulations of yellow light, the ultra-violet being about the
forty-first octave. Thus we pass from the palpable and evident to that
which is obscure, if not incomprehensible. Yet the same phenomena of
reflection, interference, and refraction, which we find in some kinds
of waves, may be expected to occur, *mutatis mutandis*, in other kinds.

From the great to the small, from the evident to the obscure, is not
only the natural order of inference, but it is the historical order of
discovery. The physical science of the Greek philosophers must have
remained incomplete, and their theories groundless, because they did
not understand the nature of undulations. Their systems were based
upon the notion of movement of translation from place to place. Modern
science tends to the opposite notion that all motion is alternating or
rhythmical, energy flowing onwards but matter remaining comparatively
fixed in position. Diogenes Laertius indeed correctly compared the
propagation of sound with the spreading of waves on the surface of
water when disturbed by a stone, and Vitruvius displayed a more
complete comprehension of the same analogy. It remained for Newton
to create the theory of undulatory motion in showing by mathematical
deductive reasoning that the particles of an elastic fluid by vibrating
backwards and forwards, might carry a pulse or wave moving from
the source of disturbance, while the disturbed particles return to
their place of rest. He was even able to make a first approximation
by theoretical calculation to the velocity of sound-waves in the
atmosphere. His theory of sound formed a hardly less important epoch in
science than his far more celebrated theory of gravitation. It opened
the way to all the subsequent applications of mechanical principles
to the insensible motion of molecules. He seems to have been, too,
upon the brink of another application of the same principles which
would have advanced science by a century of progress, and made him the
undisputed founder of all the theories of matter. He expressed opinions
at various times that light might be due to undulatory movements of
a medium occupying space, and in one intensely interesting sentence
remarks[529] that colours are probably vibrations of different lengths,
“much after the manner that, in the sense of hearing, nature makes
use of aërial vibrations of several bignesses to generate sounds
of divers tones, for the analogy of nature is to be observed.” He
correctly foresaw that red and yellow light would consist of the longer
undulations, and blue and violet of the shorter, while white light
would be composed of an indiscriminate mixture of waves of various
lengths. Newton almost overcame the strongest apparent difficulty of
the undulatory theory of light, namely, the propagation of light in
straight lines. For he observed that though waves of sound bend round
an obstacle to some extent, they do not do so in the same degree as
water-waves.[530] He had but to extend the analogy proportionally to
light-waves, and not only would the difficulty have vanished, but the
true theory of diffraction would have been open to him. Unfortunately
he had a preconceived theory that rays of light are bent from and
not towards the shadow of a body, a theory which for once he did not
sufficiently compare with observation to detect its falsity. I am
not aware, too, that Newton has, in any of his works, displayed an
understanding of the phenomena of interference without which his notion
of waves must have been imperfect.

  [529] Birch, *History of the Royal Society*, vol. iii. p. 262, quoted
  by Young, *Works*, vol. i. p. 246.

  [530] *Opticks*, Query 28, 3rd edit. p. 337.

While the general principles of undulatory motion will be the same
in whatever medium the motion takes place, the circumstances may be
excessively different. Between light travelling 186,000 miles per
second and sound travelling in air only about 1,100 feet in the same
time, or almost 900,000 times as slowly, we cannot expect a close
outward resemblance. There are great differences, too, in the character
of the vibrations. Gases scarcely admit of transverse vibration, so
that sound travelling in air is a longitudinal wave, the particles of
air moving backwards and forwards in the same line in which the wave
moves onwards. Light, on the other hand, appears to consist entirely
in the movement of points of force transversely to the direction of
propagation of the ray. The light-wave is partially analogous to the
bending of a rod or of a stretched cord agitated at one end. Now this
bending motion may take place in any one of an infinite number of
planes, and waves of which the planes are perpendicular to each other
cannot interfere any more than two perpendicular forces can interfere.
The complicated phenomena of polarised light arise out of this
transverse character of the luminous wave, and we must not expect to
meet analogous phenomena in atmospheric sound-waves. It is conceivable
that in solids we might produce transverse sound undulations, in which
phenomena of polarisation might be reproduced. But it would appear that
even between transverse sound and light-waves the analogy holds true
rather of the principles of harmonic motion than the circumstances of
the vibrating medium; from experiment and theory it is inferred that
the plane of polarisation in plane polarised light is perpendicular
to instead of being coincident with the direction of vibration, as it
would be in the case of transverse sound undulations. If so the laws
of elastic forces are essentially different in application to the
luminiferous ether and to ordinary solid bodies.[531]

  [531] Rankine, *Philosophical Transactions* (1856), vol. cxlvi.
  p. 282.


*Analogy in Astronomy.*

We shall be much assisted in gaining a true appreciation of the value
of analogy in its feebler degrees, by considering how much it has
contributed to the progress of astronomical science. Our point of
observation is so fixed with regard to the universe, and our means of
examining distant bodies are so restricted, that we are necessarily
guided by limited and apparently feeble resemblances. In many cases the
result has been confirmed by subsequent direct evidence of the most
forcible character.

While the scientific world was divided in opinion between the
Copernican and Ptolemaic systems, it was analogy which furnished the
most satisfactory argument. Galileo discovered, by the use of his new
telescope, the four small satellites which circulate round Jupiter,
and make a miniature planetary world. These four Medicean Stars, as
they were called, were plainly seen to revolve round Jupiter in various
periods, but approximately in one plane, and astronomers irresistibly
inferred that what might happen on the smaller scale might also be
found true of the greater planetary system. This discovery gave “the
holding turn,” as Herschel expressed it, to the opinions of mankind.
Even Francis Bacon, who, little to the credit of his scientific
sagacity, had previously opposed the Copernican views, now became
convinced, saying “We affirm the solisequium of Venus and Mercury;
since it has been found by Galileo that Jupiter also has attendants.”
Nor did Huyghens think it superfluous to adopt the analogy as a valid
argument.[532] Even in an advanced stage of physical astronomy, the
Jovian system has not lost its analogical interest; for the mutual
perturbations of the four satellites pass through all their phases
within a few centuries, and thus enable us to verify in a miniature
case the principles of stability, which Laplace established for the
great planetary system. Oscillations or disturbances which in the
motions of the planets appear to be secular, because their periods
extend over millions of years, can be watched, in the case of Jupiter’s
satellites, through complete revolutions within the historical period
of astronomy.[533]

  [532] *Cosmotheoros* (1699), p. 16.

  [533] Laplace, *System of the World*, vol. ii. p. 316.

In obtaining a knowledge of the stellar universe we must sometimes
depend upon precarious analogies. We still hold upon this ground the
opinion, entertained by Bruno as long ago as 1591, that the stars may
be suns attended by planets like our earth. This is the most probable
first assumption, and it is supported by spectrum observations, which
show the similarity of light derived from many stars with that of the
sun. But at the same time we learn by the prism that there are nebulæ
and stars in conditions widely different from anything known in our
system. In the course of time the analogy may perhaps be restored to
comparative completeness by the discovery of suns in various stages
of nebulous condensation. The history of the evolution of our own
world may be traced back in bodies less developed, or traced forwards
in systems more advanced towards the dissipation of energy, and the
extinction of life. As in a great workshop, we may perhaps see the
material work of Creation as it has progressed through thousands of
millions of years.

In speculations concerning the physical condition of the planets and
their satellites, we depend upon analogies of a weak character. We may
be said to know that the moon has mountains and valleys, plains and
ridges, volcanoes and streams of lava, and, in spite of the absence of
air and water, the rocky surface of the moon presents so many familiar
appearances that we do not hesitate to compare them with the features
of our globe. We infer with high probability that Mars has polar snow
and an atmosphere absorbing blue rays like our own; Jupiter undoubtedly
possesses a cloudy atmosphere, possibly not unlike a magnified copy
of that surrounding the earth, but our tendency to adopt analogies
receives a salutary correction in the recently discovered fact that the
atmosphere of Uranus contains hydrogen.

Philosophers have not stopped at these comparatively safe inferences,
but have speculated on the existence of living creatures in other
planets. Huyghens remarked that as we infer by analogy from the
dissected body of a dog to that of a pig and ox or other animal of
the same general form, and as we expect to find the same viscera, the
heart, stomach, lungs, intestines, &c., in corresponding positions,
so when we notice the similarity of the planets in many respects,
we must expect to find them alike in other respects.[534] He even
enters into an inquiry whether the inhabitants of other planets would
possess reason and knowledge of the same sort as ours, concluding in
the affirmative. Although the power of intellect might be different,
he considers that they would have the same geometry if they had any
at all, and that what is true with us would be true with them.[535]
As regards the sun, he wisely observes that every conjecture fails.
Laplace entertained a strong belief in the existence of inhabitants on
other planets. The benign influence of the sun gives birth to animals
and plants upon the surface of the earth, and analogy induces us to
believe that his rays would tend to have a similar effect elsewhere.
It is not probable that matter which is here so fruitful of life would
be sterile upon so great a globe as Jupiter, which, like the earth,
has its days and nights and years, and changes which indicate active
forces. Man indeed is formed for the temperature and atmosphere in
which he lives, and, so far as appears, could not live upon the other
planets. But there might be an infinity of organisations relative to
the diverse constitutions of the bodies of the universe. The most
active imagination cannot form any idea of such various creatures, but
their existence is not unlikely.[536]

  [534] *Cosmotheoros* (1699), p. 17.

  [535] Ibid. p. 36.

  [536] *System of the World*, vol. ii. p. 326. *Essai Philosophique*,
  p. 87.

We now know that many metals and other elements never found in organic
structures are yet capable of forming compounds with substances of
vegetable or animal origin. It is therefore just possible that at
different temperatures creatures formed of different yet analogous
compounds might exist, but it would seem indispensable that carbon
should form the basis of organic structures. We have no analogies to
lead us to suppose that in the absence of that complex element life
can exist. Could we find globes surrounded by atmospheres resembling
our own in temperature and composition, we should be almost forced to
believe them inhabited, but the probability of any analogical argument
decreases rapidly as the condition of a globe diverges from that of our
own. The Cardinal Nicholas de Cusa held long ago that the moon was
inhabited, but the absence of any appreciable atmosphere renders the
existence of inhabitants highly improbable. Speculations resting upon
weak analogies hardly belong to the scope of true science, and can only
be tolerated as an antidote to the far worse dogmas which assert that
the thousand million of persons on earth, or rather a small fraction
of them, are the sole objects of care of the Power which designed this
limitless Universe.


*Failures of Analogy.*

So constant is the aid which we derive from the use of analogy in all
attempts at discovery or explanation, that it is most important to
observe in what cases it may lead us into difficulties. That which we
expect by analogy to exist

(1) May be found to exist;

(2) May seem not to exist, but nevertheless may really exist;

(3) May actually be non-existent.

In the second case the failure is only apparent, and arises from
our obtuseness of perception, the smallness of the phenomenon to be
noticed, or the disguised character in which it appears. I have already
pointed out that the analogy of sound and light seems to fail because
light does not apparently bend round a corner, the fact being that it
does so bend in the phenomena of diffraction, which present the effect,
however, in such an unexpected and minute form, that even Newton was
misled, and turned from the correct hypothesis of undulations which he
had partially entertained.

In the third class of cases analogy fails us altogether, and we
expect that to exist which really does not exist. Thus we fail to
discover the phenomena of polarisation in sound travelling through the
atmosphere, since air is not capable of any appreciable transverse
undulations. These failures of analogy are of peculiar interest,
because they make the mind aware of its superior powers. There have
been many philosophers who said that we can conceive nothing in the
intellect which we have not previously received through the senses.
This is true in the sense that we cannot *image* them to the mind in
the concrete form of a shape or a colour; but we can speak of them
and reason concerning them; in short, we often know them in everything
but a sensuous manner. Accurate investigation shows that all material
substances retard the motion of bodies through them by subtracting
energy by impact. By the law of continuity we can frame the notion of
a vacuous space in which there is no resistance whatever, nor need we
stop there; for we have only to proceed by analogy to the case where
a medium should accelerate the motion of bodies passing through it,
somewhat in the mode which Aristotelians attributed falsely to the air.
Thus we can frame the notion of *negative density*, and Newton could
reason exactly concerning it, although no such thing exists.[537]

  [537] *Principia*, bk. ii. Section ii. Prop. x.

In every direction of thought we may meet ultimately with similar
failures of analogy. A moving point generates a line, a moving line
generates a surface, a moving surface generates a solid, but what does
a moving solid generate? When we compare a polyhedron, or many-sided
solid, with a polygon, or plane figure of many sides, the volume of the
first is analogous to the area of the second; the face of the solid
answers to the side of the polygon; the edge of the solid to the point
of the figure; but the corner, or junction of edges in the polyhedron,
is left wholly unrepresented in the plane of the polygon. Even if
we attempted to draw the analogies in some other manner, we should
still find a geometrical notion embodied in the solid which has no
representative in the figure of two dimensions.[538]

  [538] De Morgan, *Cambridge Philosophical Transactions*, vol. xi.
  Part ii. p. 246.

Faraday was able to frame some notion of matter in a fourth condition,
which should be to gas what gas is to liquid.[539] Such substance,
he thought, would not fall far short of *radiant matter*, by which
apparently he meant the supposed caloric or matter assumed to
constitute heat, according to the corpuscular theory. Even if we could
frame the notion, matter in such a state cannot be known to exist, and
recent discoveries concerning the continuity of the solid, liquid, and
gaseous states remove the basis of the speculation.

  [539] *Life of Faraday*, vol. i. p. 216.

From these and many other instances which might be adduced, we learn
that analogical reasoning leads us to the conception of many things
which, so far as we can ascertain, do not exist. In this way great
perplexities have arisen in the use of language and mathematical
symbols. All language depends upon analogy; for we join and arrange
words so that they may represent the corresponding junctions or
arrangements of things and their equalities. But in the use of language
we are obviously capable of forming many combinations of words to which
no corresponding meaning apparently exists. The same difficulty arises
in the use of mathematical signs, and mathematicians have needlessly
puzzled themselves about the square root of a negative quantity, which
is, in many applications of algebraic calculation, simply a sign
without any analogous meaning, there being a failure of analogy.




CHAPTER XXIX.

EXCEPTIONAL PHENOMENA.


If science consists in the detection of identity and the recognition
of uniformity existing in many objects, it follows that the progress
of science depends upon the study of exceptional phenomena. Such new
phenomena are the raw material upon which we exert our faculties of
observation and reasoning, in order to reduce the new facts beneath
the sway of the laws of nature, either those laws already well known,
or those to be discovered. Not only are strange and inexplicable
facts those which are on the whole most likely to lead us to some
novel and important discovery, but they are also best fitted to
arouse our attention. So long as events happen in accordance with
our anticipations, and the routine of every-day observation is
unvaried, there is nothing to impress upon the mind the smallness of
its knowledge, and the depth of mystery, which may be hidden in the
commonest sights and objects. In early times the myriads of stars which
remained in apparently fixed relative positions upon the heavenly
sphere, received less notice from astronomers than those few planets
whose wandering and inexplicable motions formed a riddle. Hipparchus
was induced to prepare the first catalogue of stars, because a single
new star had been added to those nightly visible; and in the middle
ages two brilliant but temporary stars caused more popular interest
in astronomy than any other events, and to one of them we owe all the
observations of Tycho Brahe, the mediæval Hipparchus.

In other sciences, as well as in that of the heavens, exceptional
events are commonly the points from which we start to explore new
regions of knowledge. It has been beautifully said that Wonder is the
daughter of Ignorance, but the mother of Invention; and though the most
familiar and slight events, if fully examined, will afford endless food
for wonder and for wisdom, yet it is the few peculiar and unlooked-for
events which most often lead to a course of discovery. It is true,
indeed, that it requires much philosophy to observe things which are
too near to us.

The high scientific importance attaching, then, to exceptions, renders
it desirable that we should carefully consider the various modes in
which an exception may be disposed of; while some new facts will be
found to confirm the very laws to which they seem at first sight
clearly opposed, others will cause us to limit the generality of our
previous statements. In some cases the exception may be proved to be
no exception; occasionally it will prove fatal to our previous most
confident speculations; and there are some new phenomena which, without
really destroying any of our former theories, open to us wholly new
fields of scientific investigation. The study of this subject is
especially interesting and important, because, as I have before said
(p. 587), no important theory can be built up complete and perfect all
at once. When unexplained phenomena present themselves as objections
to the theory, it will often demand the utmost judgment and sagacity
to assign to them their proper place and force. The acceptance
or rejection of a theory will depend upon discriminating the one
insuperable contradictory fact from many, which, however singular and
inexplicable at first sight, may afterwards be shown to be results of
different causes, or possibly the most striking results of the very law
with which they stand in apparent conflict.

I can enumerate at least eight classes or kinds of exceptional
phenomena, to one or other of which any supposed exception to the known
laws of nature can usually be referred; they may be briefly described
as below, and will be sufficiently illustrated in the succeeding
sections.

(1) Imaginary, or false exceptions, that is, facts, objects, or events
which are not really what they are supposed to be.

(2) Apparent, but congruent exceptions, which, though apparently in
conflict with a law of nature, are really in agreement with it.

(3) Singular exceptions, which really agree with a law of nature, but
exhibit remarkable and unique results of it.

(4) Divergent exceptions, which really proceed from the ordinary action
of known processes of nature, but which are excessive in amount or
monstrous in character.

(5) Accidental exceptions, arising from the interference of some
entirely distinct but known law of nature.

(6) Novel and unexplained exceptions, which lead to the discovery of a
new series of laws and phenomena, modifying or disguising the effects
of previously known laws, without being inconsistent with them.

(7) Limiting exceptions showing the falsity of a supposed law in some
cases to which it had been extended, but not affecting its truth in
other cases.

(8) Contradictory or real exceptions which lead us to the conclusion
that a supposed hypothesis or theory is in opposition to the phenomena
of nature, and must therefore be abandoned.

It ought to be clearly understood that in no case is a law of nature
really thwarted or prevented from being fulfilled. The effects of a
law may be disguised and hidden from our view in some instances: in
others the law itself may be rendered inapplicable altogether; but if
a law is applicable it must be carried out. Every law of nature must
therefore be stated with the utmost generality of all the instances
really coming under it. Babbage proposed to distinguish between
*universal principles*, which do not admit of a single exception, such
as that every number ending in 5 is divisible by five, and *general
principles* which are more frequently obeyed than violated, as that
“men will be governed by what they believe to be their interest.”[540]
But in a scientific point of view general principles must be universal
as regards some distinct class of objects, or they are not principles
at all. If a law to which exceptions exist is stated without allusion
to those exceptions, the statement is erroneous. I have no right to
say that “All liquids expand by heat,” if I know that water below
4° C. does not; I ought to say, “All liquids, except water below 4° C.,
expand by heat;” and every new exception discovered will falsify
the statement until inserted in it. To speak of some laws as being
*generally* true, meaning not universally but in the majority of cases,
is a hurtful abuse of the word, but is quite usual. *General* should
mean that which is true of a whole *genus* or class, and every true
statement must be true of some assigned or assignable class.

  [540] Babbage, *The Exposition of 1851*, p. 1.


*Imaginary or False Exceptions.*

When a supposed exception to a law of nature is brought to our notice,
the first inquiry ought properly to be--Is there any breach of the law
at all? It may be that the supposed exceptional fact is not a fact at
all, but a mere figment of the imagination. When King Charles requested
the Royal Society to investigate the curious fact that a live fish put
into a bucket of water does not increase the weight of the bucket and
its contents, the Royal Society wisely commenced their deliberations
by inquiring whether the fact was so or not. Every statement, however
false, must have some cause or prior condition, and the real question
for the Royal Society to investigate was, how the King came to think
that the fact was so. Mental conditions, as we have seen, enter into
all acts of observation, and are often a worthy subject of inquiry. But
there are many instances in the history of science, in which trouble
and error have been caused by false assertions carelessly made, and
carelessly accepted without verification.

The reception of the Copernican theory was much impeded by the
objection, that if the earth were moving, a stone dropped from the
top of a high tower should be left behind, and should appear to move
towards the west, just as a stone dropped from the mast-head of a
moving ship would fall behind, owing to the motion of the ship. The
Copernicans attempted to meet this grave objection in every way but
the true one, namely, showing by trial that the asserted facts are not
correct. In the first place, if a stone had been dropped with suitable
precautions from the mast-head of a moving ship, it would have fallen
close to the foot of the mast, because, by the first law of motion, it
would remain in the same state of horizontal motion communicated to it
by the mast. As the anti-Copernicans had assumed the contrary result as
certain to ensue, their argument would of course have fallen through.
Had the Copernicans next proceeded to test with great care the other
assertion involved, they would have become still better convinced of
the truth of their own theory. A stone dropped from the top of a high
tower, or into a deep well, would certainly not have been deflected
from the vertical direction in the considerable degree required to
agree with the supposed consequences of the Copernican views; but, with
very accurate observation, they might have discovered, as Benzenberg
subsequently did, a very small deflection towards the east, showing
that the eastward velocity is greater at the top than the bottom. Had
the Copernicans then been able to detect and interpret the meaning
of the small divergence thus arising, they would have found in it
corroboration of their own views.

Multitudes of cases might be cited in which laws of nature seem to
be evidently broken, but in which the apparent breach arises from a
misapprehension of the case. It is a general law, absolutely true
of all crystals yet submitted to examination, that no crystal has
a re-entrant angle, that is an angle which towards the axis of the
crystal is greater than two right angles. Wherever the faces of a
crystal meet they produce a projecting edge, and wherever edges
meet they produce a corner. Many crystals, however, when carelessly
examined, present exceptions to this law, but closer observation
always shows that the apparently re-entrant angle really arises from
the oblique union of two distinct crystals. Other crystals seem to
possess faces contradicting all the principles of crystallography;
but careful examination shows that the supposed faces are not true
faces, but surfaces produced by the orderly junction of an immense
number of distinct thin crystalline plates, each plate being in fact
a separate crystal, in which the laws of crystallography are strictly
observed. The roughness of the supposed face, the striæ detected by
the microscope, or inference by continuity from other specimens where
the true faces of the plates are clearly seen, prove the mistaken
character of the supposed exceptions. Again, four of the faces of a
regular octahedron may become so enlarged in the crystallisation
of iron pyrites and some other substances, that the other four
faces become imperceptible and a regular tetrahedron appears to be
produced, contrary to the laws of crystallographic symmetry. Many other
crystalline forms are similarly modified, so as to produce a series of
what are called *hemihedral* forms.

In tracing out the isomorphic relations of the elements, great
perplexity has often been caused by mistaking one substance for
another. It was pointed out that though arsenic was supposed to be
isomorphous with phosphorus, the arseniate of soda crystallised in a
form distinct from that of the corresponding phosphate. Some chemists
held this to be a fatal objection to the doctrine of isomorphism;
but it was afterwards pointed out by Clarke, that the arseniate and
phosphate in question were not corresponding compounds, as they
differed in regard to the water of crystallisation.[541] Vanadium again
appeared to be an exception to the laws of isomorphism, until it was
proved by Professor Roscoe, that what Berzelius supposed to be metallic
vanadium was really an oxide of vanadium.[542]

  [541] Daubeny’s *Atomic Theory*, p. 76.

  [542] *Bakerian Lecture, Philosophical Transactions* (1868),
  vol. clviii. p. 2.


*Apparent but Congruent Exceptions.*

Not unfrequently a law of nature will present results in certain
circumstances which appear to be entirely in conflict with the law
itself. Not only may the action of the law be much complicated and
disguised, but it may in various ways be reversed or inverted, so that
careless observers are misled. Ancient philosophers generally believed
that while some bodies were heavy by nature, others, such as flame,
smoke, bubbles, clouds, &c., were essentially light, or possessed a
tendency to move upwards. So acute an inquirer as Aristotle failed to
perceive the true nature of buoyancy, and the doctrine of intrinsic
lightness, expounded in his works, became the accepted view for many
centuries. It is true that Lucretius was aware why flame tends to rise,
holding that--

  “The flame has weight, though highly rare,
  Nor mounts but when compelled by heavier air.”

Archimedes also was so perfectly acquainted with the buoyancy of bodies
immersed in water, that he could not fail to perceive the existence
of a parallel effect in air. Yet throughout the early middle ages
the light of true science could not contend with the glare of the
Peripatetic doctrine. The genius of Galileo and Newton was required to
convince people of the simple truth that all matter is heavy, but that
the gravity of one substance may be overborne by that of another, as
one scale of a balance is carried up by the preponderating weight in
the opposite scale. It is curious to find Newton gravely explaining
the difference of absolute and relative gravity, as if it were a new
discovery proceeding from his theory.[543] More than a century elapsed
before other apparent exceptions to the Newtonian philosophy were
explained away.

  [543] *Principia*, bk. ii. Prop. 20. Corollaries, 5 and 6.

Newton himself allowed that the motion of the apsides of the moon’s
orbit appeared to be irreconcilable with the law of gravity, and
it remained for Clairaut to remove the difficulty by more complete
mathematical analysis. There must always remain, in the motions of
the heavenly bodies, discrepancies of some amount between theory and
observation; but such discrepancies have so often yielded in past times
to prolonged investigation that physicists now regard them as merely
apparent exceptions, which will afterwards be found to agree with the
law of gravity.

The most beautiful instance of an apparent exception, is found in the
total reflection of light, which occurs when a beam of light within
a medium falls very obliquely upon the boundary separating it from a
rarer medium. The general law is that when a ray strikes the limit
between two media of different refractive indices, part of the light
is reflected and part is refracted; but when the obliquity of the ray
within the denser medium passes beyond a certain point, there is a
sudden apparent breach of continuity, and the whole of the light is
reflected. A clear reason can be given for this exceptional conduct
of the light. According to the law of refraction, the sine of the
angle of incidence bears a fixed ratio to the sine of the angle of
refraction, so that the greater of the two angles, which is always that
in the less dense medium, may increase up to a right angle; but when
the media differ in refractive power, the less angle cannot become a
right angle, as this would require the sine of an angle to be greater
than the radius. It might seem that this is an exception of the kind
described below as a limiting exception, by which a law is shown to
be inapplicable beyond certain limits; but in the explanation of the
exception according to the undulatory theory, we find that there is
really no breach of the general law. When an undulation strikes a point
in a bounding surface, spherical waves are produced and spread from
the point. The refracted ray is the resultant of an infinite number of
such spherical waves, and the bending of the ray at the common surface
of two media depends upon the comparative velocities of propagation of
the undulations in those media. But if a ray falls very obliquely upon
the surface of a rarer medium, the waves proceeding from successive
points of the surface spread so rapidly as never to intersect, and
no resultant wave will then be produced. We thus perceive that from
similar mathematical conditions arise distinct apparent effects.

There occur from time to time failures in our best grounded
predictions. A comet, of which the orbit has been well determined, may
fail, like Lexell’s Comet, to appear at the appointed time and place in
the heavens. In the present day we should not allow such an exception
to our successful predictions to weigh against our belief in the theory
of gravitation, but should assume that some unknown body had through
the action of gravitation deflected the comet. As Clairaut remarked,
in publishing his calculations concerning the expected reappearance of
Halley’s Comet, a body which passes into regions so remote, and which
is hidden from our view during such long periods, might be exposed to
the influence of forces totally unknown to us, such as the attraction
of other comets, or of planets too far removed from the sun to be
ever perceived by us. In the case of Lexell’s Comet it was afterwards
shown, curiously enough, that its appearance was not one of a regular
series of periodical returns within the sphere of our vision, but a
single exceptional visit never to be repeated, and probably due to
the perturbing powers of Jupiter. This solitary visit became a strong
confirmation of the law of gravity with which it seemed to be in
conflict.


*Singular Exceptions.*

Among the most interesting of apparent exceptions are those which I
call *singular exceptions*, because they are more or less analogous to
the singular cases or solutions which occur in mathematical science.
A general mathematical law embraces an infinite multitude of cases
which perfectly agree with each other in a certain respect. It may
nevertheless happen that a single case, while really obeying the
general law, stands out as apparently different from all the rest.
The rotation of the earth upon its axis gives to all the stars an
apparent motion of rotation from east to west; but while countless
thousands obey the rule, the Pole Star alone seems to break it. Exact
observations indeed show that it also revolves in a small circle, but
a star might happen for a short time to exist so close to the pole
that no appreciable change of place would be caused by the earth’s
rotation. It would then constitute a perfect singular exception; while
really obeying the law, it would break the terms in which it is usually
stated. In the same way the poles of every revolving body are singular
points.

Whenever the laws of nature are reduced to a mathematical form we
may expect to meet with singular cases, and, as all the physical
sciences will meet in the mathematical principles of mechanics, there
is no part of nature where we may not encounter them. In mechanical
science the motion of rotation may be considered an exception to the
motion of translation. It is a general law that any number of parallel
forces, whether acting in the same or opposite directions, will have
a resultant which may be substituted for them with like effect. This
resultant will be equal to the algebraic sum of the forces, or the
difference of those acting in one direction and the other; it will pass
through a point which is determined by a simple formula, and which may
be described as the mean point of all the points of application of the
parallel forces (p. 364). Thus we readily determine the resultant of
parallel forces except in one peculiar case, namely, when two forces
are equal and opposite but not in the same straight line. Being equal
and opposite the amount of the resultant is nothing, yet, as the forces
are not in the same straight line, they do not balance each other.
Examining the formula for the point of application of the resultant,
we find that it gives an infinitely great magnitude, so that the
resultant is nothing at all, and acts at an infinite distance, which
is practically the same as to say that there is no resultant. Two such
forces constitute what is known in mechanical science as a *couple*,
which occasions rotatory instead of rectilinear motion, and can only be
neutralised by an equal and opposite couple of forces.

The best instances of singular exceptions are furnished by the science
of optics. It is a general law that in passing through transparent
media the plane of vibration of polarised light remains unchanged. But
in certain liquids, some peculiar crystals of quartz, and transparent
solid media subjected to a magnetic strain, as in Faraday’s experiment
(pp. 588, 630), the plane of polarisation is rotated in a screw-like
manner. This effect is so entirely *sui generis*, so unlike any other
phenomena in nature, as to appear truly exceptional; yet mathematical
analysis shows it to be only a single case of much more general laws.
As stated by Thomson and Tait,[544] it arises from the composition
of two uniform circular motions. If while a point is moving round a
circle, the centre of that circle move upon another circle, a great
variety of curious curves will be produced according as we vary the
dimensions of the circles, the rapidity or the direction of the
motions. When the two circles are exactly equal, the rapidities nearly
so, and the directions opposite, the point will be found to move
gradually round the centre of the stationary circle, and describe a
curious star-like figure connected with the molecular motions out of
which the rotational power of the media rises. Among other singular
exceptions in optics may be placed the conical refraction of light,
already noticed (p. 540), arising from the peculiar form assumed by a
wave of light when passing through certain double-refracting crystals.
The laws obeyed by the wave are exactly the same as in other cases,
yet the results are entirely *sui generis*. So far are such cases from
contradicting the law of ordinary cases, that they afford the best
opportunities for verification.

  [544] *Treatise on Natural Philosophy*, vol. i. p. 50.

In astronomy singular exceptions might occur, and in an approximate
manner they do occur. We may point to the rings of Saturn as objects
which, though undoubtedly obeying the law of gravity, are yet unique,
as far as our observation of the universe has gone. They agree, indeed,
with the other bodies of the planetary system in the stability of their
movements, which never diverge far from the mean position. There seems
to be little doubt that these rings are composed of swarms of small
meteoric stones; formerly they were thought to be solid continuous
rings, and mathematicians proved that if so constituted an entirely
exceptional event might have happened under certain circumstances.
Had the rings been exactly uniform all round, and with a centre of
gravity coinciding for a moment with that of Saturn, a singular case of
unstable equilibrium would have arisen, necessarily resulting in the
sudden collapse of the rings, and the fall of their debris upon the
surface of the planet. Thus in one single case the theory of gravity
would give a result wholly unlike anything else known in the mechanism
of the heavens.

It is possible that we might meet with singular exceptions in
crystallography. If a crystal of the second or dimetric system, in
which the third axis is usually unequal to either of the other two,
happened to have the three axes equal, it might be mistaken for a
crystal of the cubic system, but would exhibit different faces and
dissimilar properties. There is, again, a possible class of diclinic
crystals in which two axes are at right angles and the third axis
inclined to the other two. This class is chiefly remarkable for its
non-existence, since no crystals have yet been proved to have such
axes. It seems likely that the class would constitute only a singular
case of the more general triclinic system, in which all three axes are
inclined to each other at various angles. Now if the diclinic form were
merely accidental, and not produced by any general law of molecular
constitution, its actual occurrence would be infinitely improbable,
just as it is infinitely improbable that any star should indicate the
North Pole with perfect exactness.

In the curves denoting the relation between the temperature and
pressure of water there is, as shown by Professor J. Thomson, one very
remarkable point entirely unique, at which alone water can remain in
the three conditions of gas, liquid, and solid in the same vessel. It
is the triple point at which three lines meet, namely (1) the steam
line, which shows at what temperatures and pressures water is just
upon the point of becoming gaseous; (2) the ice line, showing when ice
is just about to melt; and (3) the hoar-frost line, which similarly
indicates the pressures and temperatures at which ice is capable of
passing directly into the state of gaseous vapour.[545]

  [545] Maxwell’s *Theory of Heat*, (1871), p. 175.


*Divergent Exceptions.*

Closely analogous to singular exceptions are those divergent
exceptions, in which a phenomenon manifests itself in unusual magnitude
or character, without becoming subject to peculiar laws. Thus in
throwing ten coins, it happened in four cases out of 2,048 throws,
that all the coins fell with heads uppermost (p. 208); these would
usually be regarded as very singular events, and, according to the
theory of probabilities, they would be rare; yet they proceed only
from an unusual conjunction of accidental events, and from no really
exceptional causes. In all classes of natural phenomena we may expect
to meet with similar divergencies from the average, sometimes due
merely to the principles of probability, sometimes to deeper reasons.
Among every large collection of persons, we shall probably find some
persons who are remarkably large or remarkably small, giants or dwarfs,
whether in bodily or mental conformation. Such cases appear to be
not mere *lusus naturæ*, since they occur with a frequency closely
accordant with the law of error or divergence from an average, as shown
by Quetelet and Mr. Galton.[546] The rise of genius, and the occurrence
of extraordinary musical or mathematical faculties, are attributed by
Mr. Galton to the same principle of divergence.

  [546] Galton, on the Height and Weight of Boys. *Journal of the
  Anthropological Institute*, 1875, p. 174.

When several distinct forces happen to concur together, we may have
surprising or alarming results. Great storms, floods, droughts, and
other extreme deviations from the average condition of the atmosphere
thus arise. They must be expected to happen from time to time, and will
yet be very infrequent compared with minor disturbances. They are not
anomalous but only extreme events, analogous to extreme runs of luck.
There seems, indeed, to be a fallacious impression in the minds of many
persons, that the theory of probabilities necessitates uniformity in
the happening of events, so that in the same space of time there will
always be nearly the same number of railway accidents and murders.
Buckle has superficially remarked upon the constancy of such events
as ascertained by Quetelet, and some of his readers acquire the false
notion that there is a mysterious inexorable law producing uniformity
in human affairs. But nothing can be more opposed to the teachings of
the theory of probability, which always contemplates the occurrence of
unusual runs of luck. That theory shows the great improbability that
the number of railway accidents per month should be always equal, or
nearly so. The public attention is strongly attracted to any unusual
conjunction of events, and there is a fallacious tendency to suppose
that such conjunction must be due to a peculiar new cause coming
into operation. Unless it can be clearly shown that such unusual
conjunctions occur more frequently than they should do according to
the theory of probabilities, we should regard them as merely divergent
exceptions.

Eclipses and remarkable conjunctions of the heavenly bodies may also
be regarded as results of ordinary laws which nevertheless appear to
break the regular course of nature, and never fail to excite surprise.
Such events vary greatly in frequency. One or other of the satellites
of Jupiter is eclipsed almost every day, but the simultaneous eclipse
of three satellites can only take place, according to the calculations
of Wargentin, after the lapse of 1,317,900 years. The relations of the
four satellites are so remarkable, that it is actually impossible,
according to the theory of gravity, that they should all suffer eclipse
simultaneously. But it may happen that while some of the satellites are
really eclipsed by entering Jupiter’s shadow, the others are either
occulted or rendered invisible by passing over his disk. Thus on four
occasions, in 1681, 1802, 1826, and 1843, Jupiter has been witnessed in
the singular condition of being apparently deprived of satellites. A
close conjunction of two planets always excites admiration, though such
conjunctions must occur at intervals in the ordinary course of their
motions. We cannot wonder that when three or four planets approach
each other closely, the event is long remembered. A most remarkable
conjunction of Mars, Jupiter, Saturn, and Mercury, which took place in
the year 2446 B.C., was adopted by the Chinese Emperor, Chuen Hio, as a
new epoch for the chronology of his Empire, though there is some doubt
whether the conjunction was really observed, or was calculated from the
supposed laws of motion of the planets. It is certain that on the 11th
November, 1524, the planets Venus, Jupiter, Mars, and Saturn were seen
very close together, while Mercury was only distant by about 16° or
thirty apparent diameters of the sun, this conjunction being probably
the most remarkable which has occurred in historical times.

Among the perturbations of the planets we find divergent exceptions
arising from the peculiar accumulation of effects, as in the case of
the long inequality of Jupiter and Saturn (p. 455). Leverrier has shown
that there is one place between the orbits of Mercury and Venus, and
another between those of Mars and Jupiter, in either of which, if a
small planet happened to exist, it would suffer comparatively immense
disturbance in the elements of its orbit. Now between Mars and Jupiter
there do occur the minor planets, the orbits of which are in many cases
exceptionally divergent.[547]

  [547] Grant’s *History of Physical Astronomy*, p. 116.

Under divergent exceptions we might place all or nearly all the
instances of substances possessing physical properties in a very high
or low degree, which were described in the chapter on Generalisation
(p. 607). Quicksilver is divergent among metals as regards its
melting point, and potassium and sodium as regards their specific
gravities. Monstrous productions and variations, whether in the animal
or vegetable kingdoms, should probably be assigned to this class of
exceptions.

It is worthy of notice that even in such a subject as formal logic,
divergent exceptions seem to occur, not of course due to chance,
but exhibiting in an unusual degree a phenomenon which is more or
less manifested in all other cases. I pointed out in p. 141 that
propositions of the general type A = BC ꖌ *bc* are capable of
expression in six equivalent logical forms, so that they manifest in a
higher degree than any other proposition yet discovered the phenomenon
of logical equivalence.


*Accidental Exceptions.*

The third and largest class of exceptions contains those which arise
from the casual interference of extraneous causes. A law may be in
operation, and, if so, must be perfectly fulfilled; but, while we
conceive that we are examining its results, we may have before us
the effects of a different cause, possessing no connexion with the
subject of our inquiry. The law is not really broken, but at the same
time the supposed exception is not illusory. It may be a phenomenon
which cannot occur but under the condition of the law in question, yet
there has been such interference that there is an apparent failure of
science. There is, for instance, no subject in which more rigorous and
invariable laws have been established than in crystallography. As a
general rule, each chemical substance possesses its own definite form,
by which it can be infallibly recognised; but the mineralogist has to
be on his guard against what are called *pseudomorphic* crystals. In
some circumstances a substance, having assumed its proper crystalline
form, may afterwards undergo chemical change; a new ingredient may be
added, a former one removed, or one element may be substituted for
another. In calcium carbonate the carbonic acid is sometimes replaced
by sulphuric acid, so that we find gypsum in the form of calcite;
other cases are known where the change is inverted and calcite is
found in the form of gypsum. Mica, talc, steatite, hematite, are
other minerals subject to these curious transmutations. Sometimes a
crystal embedded in a matrix is entirely dissolved away, and a new
mineral is subsequently deposited in the cavity as in a mould. Quartz
is thus found cast in many forms wholly unnatural to it. A still
more perplexing case sometimes occurs. Calcium carbonate is capable
of assuming two distinct forms of crystallisation, in which it bears
respectively the names of calcite and arragonite. Now arragonite, while
retaining its outward form unchanged, may undergo an internal molecular
change into calcite, as indicated by the altered cleavage. Thus we may
come across crystals apparently of arragonite, which seem to break all
the laws of crystallography, by possessing the cleavage of a different
system of crystallisation.

Some of the most invariable laws of nature are disguised by
interference of unlooked-for causes. While the barometer was yet a
new and curious subject of investigation, its theory, as stated by
Torricelli and Pascal, seemed to be contradicted by the fact that
in a well-constructed instrument the mercury would often stand far
above 31 inches in height. Boyle showed[548] that mercury could be
made to stand as high as 75 inches in a perfectly cleansed tube, or
about two and a half times as high as could be due to the pressure of
the atmosphere. Many theories about the pressure of imaginary fluids
were in consequence put forth,[549] and the subject was involved in
much confusion until the adhesive or cohesive force between glass and
mercury, when brought into perfect contact, was pointed out as the real
interfering cause. It seems to me, however, that the phenomenon is not
thoroughly understood as yet.

  [548] *Discourse to the Royal Society*, 28th May, 1684.

  [549] Robert Hooke’s *Posthumous Works*, p. 365.

Gay-Lussac observed that the temperature of boiling water was very
different in some kinds of vessels from what it was in others. It is
only when in contact with metallic surfaces or sharply broken edges
that the temperature is fixed at 100° C. The suspended freezing of
liquids is another case where the action of a law of nature appears
to be interrupted. Spheroidal ebullition was at first sight a most
anomalous phenomenon; it was almost incredible that water should not
boil in a red-hot vessel, or that ice could actually be produced in a
red-hot crucible. These paradoxical results are now fully explained as
due to the interposition of a non-conducting film of vapour between the
globule of liquid and the sides of the vessel. The feats of conjurors
who handle liquid metals are accounted for in the same manner. At one
time the *passive state* of steel was regarded as entirely anomalous.
It may be assumed as a general law that when pieces of electro-negative
and electro-positive metal are placed in nitric acid, and made to touch
each other, the electro-negative metal will undergo rapid solution. But
when iron is the electro-negative and platinum the electro-positive,
the solution of the iron entirely and abruptly ceases. Faraday
ingeniously proved that this effect is due to a thin film of oxide of
iron, which forms upon the surface of the iron and protects it.[550]

  [550] *Experimental Researches in Electricity*, vol. ii. pp. 240–245.

The law of gravity is so simple, and disconnected from the other laws
of nature, that it never suffers any disturbance, and is in no way
disguised, but by the complication of its own effects. It is otherwise
with those secondary laws of the planetary system which have only
an empirical basis. The fact that all the long known planets and
satellites have a similar motion from west to east is not necessitated
by any principles of mechanics, but points to some common condition
existing in the nebulous mass from which our system has been evolved.
The retrograde motions of the satellites of Uranus constituted a
distinct breach in this law of uniform direction, which became all
the more interesting when the single satellite of Neptune was also
found to be retrograde. It now became probable, as Baden Powell well
observed, that the anomaly would cease to be singular, and become a
case of another law, pointing to some general interference which has
taken place on the bounds of the planetary system. Not only have the
satellites suffered from this perturbance, but Uranus is also anomalous
in having an axis of rotation lying nearly in the ecliptic; and Neptune
constitutes a partial exception to the empirical law of Bode concerning
the distances of the planets, which circumstance may possibly be due to
the same disturbance.

Geology is a science in which accidental exceptions are likely to
occur. Only when we find strata in their original relative positions
can we surely infer that the order of succession is the order of
time. But it not uncommonly happens that strata are inverted by the
bending and doubling action of extreme pressure. Landslips may carry
one body of rock into proximity with an unrelated series, and produce
results apparently inexplicable.[551] Floods, streams, icebergs, and
other casual agents, may lodge remains in places where they would be
wholly unexpected. Though such interfering causes have been sometimes
wrongly supposed to explain important discoveries, the geologist must
bear the possibility of interference in mind. Scarcely more than a
century ago it was held that fossils were accidental productions of
nature, mere forms into which minerals had been shaped by no peculiar
cause. Voltaire appears not to have accepted such an explanation; but
fearing that the occurrence of fossil fishes on the Alps would support
the Mosaic account of the deluge, he did not hesitate to attribute
them to the remains of fishes accidentally brought there by pilgrims.
In archæological investigations the greatest caution is requisite
in allowing for secondary burials in ancient tombs and tumuli, for
imitations, forgeries, casual coincidences, disturbance by subsequent
races or by other archæologists. In common life extraordinary events
will happen from time to time, as when a shepherdess in France was
astonished at an iron chain falling out of the sky close to her, the
fact being that Gay-Lussac had thrown it out of his balloon, which was
passing over her head at the time.

  [551] Murchison’s *Silurian System*, vol. ii. p. 733, &c.


*Novel and Unexplained Exceptions.*

When a law of nature appears to fail because some other law has
interfered with its action, two cases may present themselves;--the
interfering law may be a known one, or it may have been previously
undetected. In the first case, which we have sufficiently considered in
the preceding section, we have nothing to do but calculate as exactly
as possible the amount of interference, and make allowance for it; the
apparent failure of the law under examination should then disappear.
But in the second case the results may be much more important. A
phenomenon which cannot be explained by any known laws may indicate the
interference of undiscovered natural forces. The ancients could not
help perceiving that the general tendency of bodies downwards failed
in the case of the loadstone, nor would the doctrine of essential
lightness explain the exception, since the substance drawn upwards by
the loadstone is a heavy metal. We now see that there was no breach in
the perfect generality of the law of gravity, but that a new form of
energy manifested itself in the loadstone for the first time.

Other sciences show us that laws of nature, rigorously true and exact,
may be developed by those who are ignorant of more complex phenomena
involved in their application. Newton’s comprehension of geometrical
optics was sufficient to explain all the ordinary refractions and
reflections of light. The simple laws of the bending of rays apply
to all rays, whatever the character of the undulations composing
them. Newton suspected the existence of other classes of phenomena
when he spoke of rays as *having sides*; but it remained for later
experimentalists to show that light is a transverse undulation, like
the bending of a rod or cord.

Dalton’s atomic theory is doubtless true of all chemical compounds,
and the essence of it is that the same compound will always be found
to contain the same elements in the same definite proportions. Pure
calcium carbonate contains 48 parts by weight of oxygen to 40 of
calcium and 12 of carbon. But when careful analyses were made of a
great many minerals, this law appeared to fail. What was unquestionably
the same mineral, judging by its crystalline form and physical
properties, would give varying proportions of its components, and
would sometimes contain unusual elements which yet could not be set
down as mere impurities. Dolomite, for instance, is a compound of the
carbonates of magnesia and lime, but specimens from different places
do not exhibit any fixed ratio between the lime and magnesia. Such
facts could be reconciled with the laws of Dalton only by supposing the
interference of a new law, that of Isomorphism.

It is now established that certain elements are related to each other,
so that they can, as it were, step into each other’s places without
apparently altering the shapes of the crystals which they constitute.
The carbonates of iron, calcium, and magnesium, are nearly identical
in their crystalline forms, hence they may crystallise together in
harmony, producing mixed minerals of considerable complexity, which
nevertheless perfectly verify the laws of equivalent proportions. This
principle of isomorphism once established, not only explains what
was formerly a stumbling-block, but gives valuable aid to chemists
in deciding upon the constitution of new salts, since compounds of
isomorphous elements which have identical crystalline forms must
possess corresponding chemical formulæ.

We may expect that from time to time extraordinary phenomena will
be discovered, and will lead to new views of nature. The recent
observation, for instance, that the resistance of a bar of selenium to
a current of electricity is affected in an extraordinary degree by rays
of light falling upon the selenium, points to a new relation between
light and electricity. The allotropic changes which sulphur, selenium,
and phosphorus undergo by an alteration in the amount of latent heat
which they contain, will probably lead at some future time to important
inferences concerning the molecular constitution of solids and liquids.
The curious substance ozone has perplexed many chemists, and Andrews
and Tait thought that it afforded evidence of the decomposition of
oxygen by the electric discharge. The researches of Sir B. C. Brodie
negative this notion, and afford evidence of the real constitution of
the substance,[552] which still, however, remains exceptional in its
properties and relations, and affords a hope of important discoveries
in chemical theory.

  [552] *Philosophical Transactions* (1872), vol. clxii. No. 23.


*Limiting Exceptions.*

We pass to cases where exceptional phenomena are actually
irreconcilable with a law of nature previously regarded as true. Error
must now be allowed to have been committed, but the error may be more
or less extensive. It may happen that a law holding rigorously true of
the facts actually under notice had been extended by generalisation to
other series of facts then unexamined. Subsequent investigation may
show the falsity of this generalisation, and the result must be to
limit the law for the future to those objects of which it is really
true. The contradiction to our previous opinions is partial and not
total.

Newton laid down as a result of experiment that every ray of
homogeneous light has a definite refrangibility, which it preserves
throughout its course until extinguished. This is one case of the
general principle of undulatory movement, which Herschel stated under
the title “Principle of Forced Vibrations” (p. 451), and asserted to
be absolutely without exception. But Herschel himself described in
the *Philosophical Transactions* for 1845 a curious appearance in
a solution of quinine; as viewed by transmitted light the solution
appeared colourless, but in certain aspects it exhibited a beautiful
celestial blue tint. Curiously enough the colour is seen only in the
first portion of liquid which the light enters. Similar phenomena in
fluor-spar had been described by Brewster in 1838. Professor Stokes,
having minutely investigated the phenomena, discovered that they were
more or less present in almost all vegetable infusions, and in a number
of mineral substances. He came to the conclusion that this phenomenon,
called by him Fluorescence, could only be explained by an alteration
in the refrangibility of the rays of light; he asserts that light-rays
of very short length of vibration in falling upon certain atoms excite
undulations of greater length, in opposition to the principle of
forced vibrations. No complete explanation of the mode of change is
yet possible, because it depends upon the intimate constitution of
the atoms of the substances concerned; but Professor Stokes believes
that the principle of forced vibrations is true only so long as the
excursions of an atom are very small compared with the magnitude of the
complex molecules.[553]

  [553] *Philosophical Transactions* (1852), vol. cxlii. pp. 465, 548,
  &c.

It is well known that in Calorescence the refrangibility of rays is
increased and the wave-length diminished. Rays of obscure heat and low
refrangibility may be concentrated so as to heat a solid substance, and
make it give out rays belonging to any part of the spectrum, and it
seems probable that this effect arises from the impact of distinct but
conflicting atoms. Nor is it in light only that we discover limiting
exceptions to the law of forced vibrations; for if we notice gentle
waves lapping upon the stones at the edge of a lake we shall see that
each larger wave in breaking upon a stone gives rise to a series of
smaller waves. Thus there is constantly in progress a degradation in
the magnitude of water-waves. The principle of forced vibrations seems
then to be too generally stated by Herschel, but it must be a difficult
question of mechanical theory to discriminate the circumstances in
which it does and does not hold true.

We sometimes foresee the possible existence of exceptions yet unknown
by experience, and limit the statement of our discoveries accordingly.
Extensive inquiries have shown that all substances yet examined fall
into one of two classes; they are all either ferro-magnetic, that is,
magnetic in the same way as iron, or they are diamagnetic like bismuth.
But it does not follow that every substance must be ferro-magnetic or
diamagnetic. The magnetic properties are shown by Sir W. Thomson[554]
to depend upon the specific inductive capacities of the substance
in three rectangular directions. If these inductive capacities are
all positive, we have a ferro-magnetic substance; if negative, a
diamagnetic substance; but if the specific inductive capacity were
positive in one direction and negative in the others, we should have
an exception to previous experience, and could not place the substance
under either of the present recognised classes.

  [554] *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. i. p. 182.

So many gases have been reduced to the liquid state, and so many solids
fused, that scientific men rather hastily adopted the generalisation
that all substances could exist in all three states. A certain number
of gases, such as oxygen, hydrogen, and nitrogen, have resisted all
efforts to liquefy them, and it now seems probable from the experiments
of Dr. Andrews that they are limiting exceptions. He finds that above
31° C. carbonic acid cannot be liquefied by any pressure he could
apply, whereas below this temperature liquefaction is always possible.
By analogy it becomes probable that even hydrogen might be liquefied if
cooled to a very low temperature. We must modify our previous views,
and either assert that *below a certain critical temperature* every
gas may be liquefied, or else we must assume that a highly condensed
gas is, when above the critical temperature, undistinguishable from
a liquid. At the same time we have an explanation of a remarkable
exception presented by liquid carbonic acid to the general rule that
gases expand more by heat than liquids. Liquid carbonic acid was found
by Thilorier in 1835 to expand more than four times as much as air;
but by the light of Andrews’ experiments we learn to regard the liquid
as rather a highly condensed gas than an ordinary liquid, and it is
actually possible to reduce the gas to the apparently liquid condition
without any abrupt condensation.[555]

  [555] Maxwell, *Theory of Heat*, p. 123.

Limiting exceptions occur most frequently in the natural sciences
of Botany, Zoology, Geology, &c., the laws of which are empirical.
In innumerable instances the confident belief of one generation
has been falsified by the wider observation of a succeeding one.
Aristotle confidently held that all swans are white,[556] and the
proposition seemed true until not a hundred years ago black swans were
discovered in Western Australia. In zoology and physiology we may
expect a fundamental identity to exist in the vital processes, but
continual discoveries show that there is no limit to the apparently
anomalous expedients by which life is reproduced. Alternate generation,
fertilisation for several successive generations, hermaphroditism, are
opposed to all we should expect from induction founded upon the higher
animals. But such phenomena are only limiting exceptions showing that
what is true of one class is not true of another. In certain of the
cephalopoda we meet the extraordinary fact that an arm of the male is
cast off and lives independently until it encounters the female.

  [556] *Prior Analytics*, ii. 2, 8, and elsewhere.


*Real Exceptions to Supposed Laws.*

The exceptions which we have lastly to consider are the most important
of all, since they lead to the entire rejection of a law or theory
before accepted. No law of nature can fail; there are no such things
as real exceptions to real laws. Where contradiction exists it must
be in the mind of the experimentalist. Either the law is imaginary
or the phenomena which conflict with it; if, then, by our senses we
satisfy ourselves of the actual occurrence of the phenomena, the law
must be rejected as illusory. The followers of Aristotle held that
nature abhors a vacuum, and thus accounted for the rise of water
in a pump. When Torricelli pointed out the visible fact that water
would not rise more than 33 feet in a pump, nor mercury more than
about 30 inches in a glass tube, they attempted to represent these
facts as limiting exceptions, saying that nature abhorred a vacuum to
a certain extent and no further. But the Academicians del Cimento
completed their discomfiture by showing that if we remove the pressure
of the surrounding air, and in proportion as we remove it, nature’s
feelings of abhorrence decrease and finally disappear altogether. Even
Aristotelian doctrines could not stand such direct contradiction.

Lavoisier’s ideas concerning the constitution of acids received
complete refutation. He named oxygen the *acid generator*, because he
believed that all acids were compounds of oxygen, a generalisation
based on insufficient data. Berthollet, as early as 1789, proved by
analysis that hydrogen sulphide and prussic acid, both clearly acting
the part of acids, were devoid of oxygen; the former might perhaps have
been interpreted as a limiting exception, but when so powerful an acid
as hydrogen chloride (muriatic acid) was found to contain no oxygen the
theory had to be relinquished. Berzelius’ theory of the dual formation
of chemical compounds met a similar fate.

It is obvious that all conclusive *experimenta crucis* constitute real
exceptions to the supposed laws of the theory which is overthrown.
Newton’s corpuscular theory of light was not rejected on account of its
absurdity or inconceivability, for in these respects it is, as we have
seen, far superior to the undulatory theory. It was rejected because
certain small fringes of colour did not appear in the exact place
and of the exact size in which calculation showed that they ought to
appear according to the theory (pp. 516–521). One single fact clearly
irreconcilable with a theory involves its rejection. In the greater
number of cases, what appears to be a fatal exception may be afterwards
explained away as a singular or disguised result of the laws with which
it seems to conflict, or as due to the interference of extraneous
causes; but if we fail thus to reduce the fact to congruity, it remains
more powerful than any theories or any dogmas.

Of late years not a few of the favourite doctrines of geologists have
been rudely destroyed. It was the general belief that human remains
were to be found only in those deposits which are actually in progress
at the present day, so that the creation of man appeared to have taken
place in this geological age. The discovery of a single worked flint
in older strata and in connexion with the remains of extinct mammals
was sufficient to explode such a doctrine. Similarly, the opinions
of geologists have been altered by the discovery of the Eozoön in the
Laurentian rocks of Canada; it was previously held that no remains of
life occurred in any older strata than those of the Cambrian system. As
the examination of the strata of the globe becomes more complete, our
views of the origin and succession of life upon the globe must undergo
many changes.


*Unclassed Exceptions.*

At every period of scientific progress there will exist a multitude
of unexplained phenomena which we know not how to regard. They are
the outstanding facts upon which the labours of investigators must
be exerted,--the ore from which the gold of future discovery is to
be extracted. It might be thought that, as our knowledge of the laws
of nature increases, the number of such exceptions should decrease;
but, on the contrary, the more we know the more there is yet to
explain. This arises from several reasons; in the first place, the
principal laws and forces in nature are numerous, so that he who bears
in mind the wonderfully large numbers developed in the doctrine of
combinations, will anticipate the existence of immensely numerous
relations of one law to another. When we are once in possession of a
law, we are potentially in possession of all its consequences; but
it does not follow that the mind of man, so limited in its powers
and capacities, can actually work them all out in detail. Just as
the aberration of light was discovered empirically, though it should
have been foreseen, so there are multitudes of unexplained facts, the
connexion of which with laws of nature already known to us, we should
perceive, were we not hindered by the imperfection of our deductive
powers. But, in the second place, as will be more fully pointed out,
it is not to be supposed that we have approximated to an exhaustive
knowledge of nature’s powers. The most familiar facts may teem with
indications of forces, now secrets hidden from us, because we have
not mind-directed eyes to discriminate them. The progress of science
will consist in the discovery from time to time of new exceptional
phenomena, and their assignment by degrees to one or other of the
heads already described. When a new fact proves to be merely a false,
apparent, singular, divergent, or accidental exception, we gain a more
minute and accurate acquaintance with the effects of laws already known
to exist. We have indeed no addition to what was implicitly in our
possession, but there is much difference between knowing the laws of
nature and perceiving all their complicated effects. Should a new fact
prove to be a limiting or real exception, we have to alter, in part or
in whole, our views of nature, and are saved from errors into which we
had fallen. Lastly, the new fact may come under the sixth class, and
may eventually prove to be a novel phenomenon, indicating the existence
of new laws and forces, complicating but not otherwise interfering with
the effects of laws and forces previously known.

The best instance which I can find of an unresolved exceptional
phenomenon, consists in the anomalous vapour-densities of phosphorus,
arsenic, mercury, and cadmium. It is one of the most important
laws of chemistry, discovered by Gay-Lussac, that equal volumes of
gases exactly correspond to equivalent weights of the substances.
Nevertheless phosphorus and arsenic give vapours exactly twice as
dense as they should do by analogy, and mercury and cadmium diverge
in the other direction, giving vapours half as dense as we should
expect. We cannot treat these anomalies as limiting exceptions, and
say that the law holds true of substances generally but not of these;
for the properties of gases (p. 601), usually admit of the widest
generalisations. Besides, the preciseness of the ratio of divergence
points to the real observance of the law in a modified manner. We might
endeavour to reduce the exceptions by doubling the atomic weights of
phosphorus and arsenic, and halving those of mercury and cadmium. But
this step has been maturely considered by chemists, and is found to
conflict with all the other analogies of the substances and with the
principle of isomorphism. One of the most probable explanations is,
that phosphorus and arsenic produce vapour in an allotropic condition,
which might perhaps by intense heat be resolved into a simpler gas of
half the density; but facts are wanting to support this hypothesis, and
it cannot be applied to the other two exceptions without supposing that
gases and vapours generally are capable of resolution into something
simpler. In short, chemists can at present make nothing of these
anomalies. As Hofmann says, “Their philosophical interpretation belongs
to the future.... They may turn out to be typical facts, round which
many others of the like kind may come hereafter to be grouped; and
they may prove to be allied with special properties, or dependent on
particular conditions as yet unsuspected.”[557]

  [557] Hofmann’s *Introduction to Chemistry*, p. 198.

It would be easy to point out a great number of other unexplained
anomalies. Physicists assert, as an absolutely universal law, that
in liquefaction heat is absorbed;[558] yet sulphur is at least an
apparent exception. The two substances, sulphur and selenium, are, in
fact, very anomalous in their relations to heat. Sulphur may be said
to have two melting points, for, though liquid like water at 120° C.,
it becomes quite thick and tenacious between 221° and 249°, and melts
again at a higher temperature. Both sulphur and selenium may be thrown
into several curious states, which chemists conveniently dispose of by
calling them *allotropic*, a term freely used when they are puzzled
to know what has happened. The chemical and physical history of iron,
again, is full of anomalies; not only does it undergo inexplicable
changes of hardness and texture in its alloys with carbon and other
elements, but it is almost the only substance which conveys sound with
greater velocity at a higher than at a lower temperature, the velocity
increasing from 20° to 100° C., and then decreasing. Silver also is
anomalous in regard to sound. These are instances of inexplicable
exceptions, the bearing of which must be ascertained in the future
progress of science.

  [558] Stewart’s *Elementary Treatise on Heat*, p. 80.

When the discovery of new and peculiar phenomena conflicting with
our theories of the constitution of nature is reported to us, it
becomes no easy task to steer a philosophically correct course between
credulity and scepticism. We are not to assume, on the one hand, that
there is any limit to the wonders which nature can present to us.
Nothing except the contradictory is really impossible, and many things
which we now regard as common-place were considered as little short
of the miraculous when first perceived. The electric telegraph was
a visionary dream among mediæval physicists;[559] it has hardly yet
ceased to excite our wonder; to our descendants centuries hence it
will probably appear inferior in ingenuity to some inventions which
they will possess. Now every strange phenomenon may be a secret spring
which, if rightly touched, will open the door to new chambers in the
palace of nature. To refuse to believe in the occurrence of anything
strange would be to neglect the most precious chances of discovery.
We may say with Hooke, that “the believing strange things possible
may perhaps be an occasion of taking notice of such things as another
would pass by without regard as useless.” We are not, therefore,
to shut our ears even to such apparently absurd stories as those
concerning second-sight, clairvoyance, animal magnetism, ode force,
table-turning, or any of the popular delusions which from time to time
are current. The facts recorded concerning these matters are facts in
some sense or other, and they demand explanation, either as new natural
phenomena, or as the results of credulity and imposture. Most of the
supposed phenomena referred to have been, or by careful investigation
would doubtless be, referred to the latter head, and the absence of
scientific ability in many of those who describe them is sufficient to
cast a doubt upon their value.

  [559] Jevons, *Proceedings of the Manchester Literary and
  Philosophical Society*, 6th March, 1877, vol. xvi. p. 164. See also
  Mr. W. E. A. Axon’s note on the same subject, ibid. p. 166.

It is to be remembered that according to the principle of the inverse
method of probability, the probability of any hypothetical explanation
is affected by the probability of each other possible explanation. If
no other reasonable explanation could be suggested, we should be forced
to look upon spiritualist manifestations as indicating mysterious
causes. But as soon as it is shown that fraud has been committed in
several important cases, and that in other cases persons in a credulous
and excited state of mind have deceived themselves, the probability
becomes very considerable that similar explanations may apply to most
like manifestations. The performances of conjurors sufficiently prove
that it requires no very great skill to perform tricks the *modus
operandi* of which shall entirely escape the notice of spectators. It
is on these grounds of probability that we should reject the so-called
spiritualist stories, and not simply because they are strange.

Certainly in the obscure phenomena of mind, those relating to memory,
dreams, somnambulism, and other peculiar states of the nervous
system, there are many inexplicable and almost incredible facts, and
it is equally unphilosophical to believe or to disbelieve without
clear evidence. There are many facts, too, concerning the instincts
of animals, and the mode in which they find their way from place to
place, which are at present quite inexplicable. No doubt there are many
strange things not dreamt of in our philosophy, but this is no reason
why we should believe in every strange thing which is reported to have
happened.




CHAPTER XXX.

CLASSIFICATION.


The extensive subject of Classification has been deferred to a late
part of this treatise, because it involves questions of difficulty, and
did not seem naturally to fall into an earlier place. But it must not
be supposed that, in now formally taking up the subject, we are for
the first time entertaining the notion of classification. All logical
inference involves classification, which is indeed the necessary
accompaniment of the action of judgment. It is impossible to detect
similarity between objects without thereby joining them together in
thought, and forming an incipient class. Nor can we bestow a common
name upon objects without implying the existence of a class. Every
common name is the name of a class, and every name of a class is a
common name. It is evident also that to speak of a general notion or
concept is but another way of speaking of a class. Usage leads us to
employ the word classification in some cases and not in others. We
are said to form the *general notion* parallelogram when we regard
an infinite number of possible four-sided rectilinear figures as
resembling each other in the common property of possessing parallel
sides. We should be said to form a *class*, Trilobite, when we place
together in a museum a number of specimens resembling each other in
certain defined characters. But the logical nature of the operation
is the same in both cases. We form a *class* of figures called
parallelograms and we form a *general notion* of trilobites.

Science, it was said at the outset, is the detection of identify, and
classification is the placing together, either in thought or in actual
proximity of space, those objects between which identity has been
detected. Accordingly, the value of classification is co-extensive with
the value of science and general reasoning. Whenever we form a class
we reduce multiplicity to unity, and detect, as Plato said, the one in
the many. The result of such classification is to yield generalised
knowledge, as distinguished from the direct and sensuous knowledge of
particular facts. Of every class, so far as it is correctly formed, the
principle of substitution is true, and whatever we know of one object
in a class we know of the other objects, so far as identity has been
detected between them. The facilitation and abbreviation of mental
labour is at the bottom of all mental progress. The reasoning faculties
of Newton were not different in nature from those of a ploughman; the
difference lay in the extent to which they were exerted, and the number
of facts which could be treated. Every thinking being generalises more
or less, but it is the depth and extent of his generalisations which
distinguish the philosopher. Now it is the exertion of the classifying
and generalising powers which enables the intellect of man to cope
in some degree with the infinite number of natural phenomena. In the
chapters upon combinations and permutations it was made evident, that
from a few elementary differences immense numbers of combinations
can be produced. The process of classification enables us to resolve
these combinations, and refer each one to its place according to one
or other of the elementary circumstances out of which it was produced.
We restore nature to the simple conditions out of which its endless
variety was developed. As Professor Bowen has said,[560] “The first
necessity which is imposed upon us by the constitution of the mind
itself, is to break up the infinite wealth of Nature into groups and
classes of things, with reference to their resemblances and affinities,
and thus to enlarge the grasp of our mental faculties, even at the
expense of sacrificing the minuteness of information which can be
acquired only by studying objects in detail. The first efforts in
the pursuit of knowledge, then, must be directed to the business
of classification. Perhaps it will be found in the sequel, that
classification is not only the beginning, but the culmination and the
end, of human knowledge.”

  [560] *A Treatise on Logic, or, the Laws of Pure Thought*, by Francis
  Bowen, Professor of Moral Philosophy in Harvard College, Cambridge,
  United States, 1866, p. 315.


*Classification Involving Induction.*

The purpose of classification is the detection of the laws of nature.
However much the process may in some cases be disguised, classification
is not really distinct from the process of perfect induction, whereby
we endeavour to ascertain the connexions existing between properties of
the objects under treatment. There can be no use in placing an object
in a class unless something more than the fact of being in the class is
implied. If we arbitrarily formed a class of metals and placed therein
a selection from the list of known metals made by ballot, we should
have no reason to expect that the metals in question would resemble
each other in any points except that they are metals, and have been
selected by the ballot. But when chemists select from the list the five
metals, potassium, sodium, cæsium, rubidium, and lithium and call them
the Alkaline metals, a great deal is implied in this classification.
On comparing the qualities of these substances they are all found to
combine very energetically with oxygen, to decompose water at all
temperatures, and to form strongly basic oxides, which are highly
soluble in water, yielding powerfully caustic and alkaline hydrates
from which water cannot be expelled by heat. Their carbonates are also
soluble in water, and each metal forms only one chloride. It may also
be expected that each salt of one of the metals will correspond to a
salt of each other metal, there being a general analogy between the
compounds of these metals and their properties.

Now in forming this class of alkaline metals, we have done more than
merely select a convenient order of statement. We have arrived at a
discovery of certain empirical laws of nature, the probability being
very considerable that a metal which exhibits some of the properties
of alkaline metals will also possess the others. If we discovered
another metal whose carbonate was soluble in water, and which
energetically combined with water at all temperatures, producing a
strongly basic oxide, we should infer that it would form only a single
chloride, and that generally speaking, it would enter into a series
of compounds corresponding to the salts of the other alkaline metals.
The formation of this class of alkaline metals then, is no mere matter
of convenience; it is an important and successful act of inductive
discovery, enabling us to register many undoubted propositions as
results of perfect induction, and to make a great number of inferences
depending upon the principles of imperfect induction.

An excellent instance as to what classification can do, is found in
Mr. Lockyer’s researches on the sun.[561] Wanting some guide as to
what more elements to look for in the sun’s photosphere, he prepared
a classification of the elements according as they had or had not
been traced in the sun, together with a detailed statement of the
chief chemical characters of each element. He was then able to observe
that the elements found in the sun were for the most part those
forming stable compounds with oxygen. He then inferred that other
elements forming stable oxides would probably exist in the sun, and
he was rewarded by the discovery of five such metals. Here we have
empirical and tentative classification leading to the detection of the
correlation between existence in the sun, and the power of forming
stable oxides and then leading by imperfect induction to the discovery
of more coincidences between these properties.

  [561] *Proceedings of the Royal Society*, November, 1873, vol. xxi.
  p. 512.

Professor Huxley has defined the process of classification in the
following terms.[562] “By the classification of any series of objects,
is meant the actual or ideal arrangement together of those which are
like and the separation of those which are unlike; the purpose of this
arrangement being to facilitate the operations of the mind in clearly
conceiving and retaining in the memory the characters of the objects in
question.”

  [562] *Lectures on the Elements of Comparative Anatomy*, 1864, p. 1.

This statement is doubtless correct, so far as it goes, but it does
not include all that Professor Huxley himself implicitly treats under
classification. He is fully aware that deep correlations, or in
other terms deep uniformities or laws of nature, will be disclosed
by any well chosen and profound system of classification. I should
therefore propose to modify the above statement, as follows:--“By
the classification of any series of objects, is meant the actual or
ideal arrangement together of those which are like and the separation
of those which are unlike, the purpose of this arrangement being,
primarily, to disclose the correlations or laws of union of properties
and circumstances, and, secondarily, to facilitate the operations
of the mind in clearly conceiving and retaining in the memory the
characters of the objects in question.”


*Multiplicity of Modes of Classification.*

In approaching the question how any given group of objects may be
best classified, let it be remarked that there must generally be an
unlimited number of modes of classifying a group of objects. Misled, as
we shall see, by the problem of classification in the natural sciences,
philosophers seem to think that in each subject there must be one
essentially natural system of classification which is to be selected,
to the exclusion of all others. This erroneous notion probably arises
also in part from the limited powers of thought and the inconvenient
mechanical conditions under which we labour. If we arrange the books
in a library catalogue, we must arrange them in some one order; if we
compose a treatise on mineralogy, the minerals must be successively
described in some one arrangement; if we treat such simple things as
geometrical figures, they must be taken in some fixed order. We shall
naturally select that arrangement which appears to be most convenient
and instructive for our principal purpose. But it does not follow
that this method of arrangement possesses any exclusive excellence,
and there will be usually many other possible arrangements, each
valuable in its own way. A perfect intellect would not confine itself
to one order of thought, but would simultaneously regard a group of
objects as classified in all the ways of which they are capable. Thus
the elements may be classified according to their atomicity into the
groups of monads, dyads, triads, tetrads, pentads, and hexads, and
this is probably the most instructive classification; but it does not
prevent us from also classifying them according as they are metallic
or non-metallic, solid, liquid or gaseous at ordinary temperatures,
useful or useless, abundant or scarce, ferro-magnetic or diamagnetic,
and so on.

Mineralogists have spent a great deal of labour in trying to discover
the supposed natural system of classification for minerals. They have
constantly encountered the difficulty that the chemical composition
does not run together with the crystallographic form, and the various
physical properties of the mineral. Substances identical in the
forms of their crystals, especially those belonging to the first or
cubical system of crystals, are often found to have no resemblance
in chemical composition. The same substance, again, is occasionally
found crystallised in two essentially different crystallographic
forms; calcium carbonate, for instance, appearing as calc-spar and
arragonite. The simple truth is that if we are unable to discover
any correspondence, or, as we may call it, any *correlation* between
the properties of minerals, we cannot make any one arrangement which
will enable us to treat all these properties in a single system of
classification. We must classify minerals in as many different ways
as there are different groups of unrelated properties of sufficient
importance. Even if, for the purpose of describing minerals
successively in a treatise, we select one chief system, that, for
instance, having regard to chemical composition, we ought mentally to
regard the minerals as classified in all other useful modes.

Exactly the same may be said of the classification of plants. An
immense number of different modes of classifying plants have been
proposed at one time or other, an exhaustive account of which will be
found in the article on classification in Rees’s “Cyclopædia,” or in
the introduction to Lindley’s “Vegetable Kingdom.” There have been the
Fructists, such as Cæsalpinus, Morison, Hermann, Boerhaave or Gaertner,
who arranged plants according to the form of the fruit. The Corollists,
Rivinus, Ludwig, and Tournefort, paid attention chiefly to the number
and arrangement of the parts of the corolla. Magnol selected the calyx
as the critical part, while Sauvage arranged plants according to their
leaves; nor are these instances more than a small selection from the
actual variety of modes of classification which have been tried. Of
such attempts it may be said that every system will probably yield some
information concerning the relations of plants, and it is only after
trying many modes that it is possible to approximate to the best.


*Natural and Artificial Systems of Classification.*

It has been usual to distinguish systems of classification as natural
and artificial, those being called natural which seemed to express the
order of existing things as determined by nature. Artificial methods of
classification, on the other hand, included those formed for the mere
convenience of men in remembering or treating natural objects.

The difference, as it is commonly regarded, has been well described
by Ampére,[563] as follows: “We can distinguish two kinds of
classifications, the natural and the artificial. In the latter kind,
some characters, arbitrarily chosen, serve to determine the place of
each object; we abstract all other characters, and the objects are thus
found to be brought near to or to be separated from each other, often
in the most bizarre manner. In natural systems of classification, on
the contrary, we employ concurrently all the characters essential to
the objects with which we are occupied, discussing the importance of
each of them; and the results of this labour are not adopted unless
the objects which present the closest analogy are brought most near
together, and the groups of the several orders which are formed from
them are also approximated in proportion as they offer more similar
characters. In this way it arises that there is always a kind of
connexion, more or less marked, between each group and the group which
follows it.”

  [563] *Essai sur la Philosophie des Sciences*, p. 9.

There is much, however, that is vague and logically false in this
and other definitions which have been proposed by naturalists to
express their notion of a natural system. We are not informed how the
*importance* of a resemblance is to be determined, nor what is the
measure of the *closeness* of analogy. Until all the words employed
in a definition are made clear in meaning, the definition itself is
worse than useless. Now if the views concerning classification here
upheld are true, there can be no sharp and precise distinction between
natural and artificial systems. All arrangements which serve any
purpose at all must be more or less natural, because, if closely enough
scrutinised, they will involve more resemblances than those whereby the
class was defined.

It is true that in the biological sciences there would be one
arrangement of plants or animals which would be conspicuously
instructive, and in a certain sense natural, if it could be attained,
and it is that after which naturalists have been in reality striving
for nearly two centuries, namely, that *arrangement which would display
the genealogical descent of every form from the original life germ*.
Those morphological resemblances upon which the classification of
living beings is almost always based are inherited resemblances, and
it is evident that descendants will usually resemble their parents and
each other in a great many points.

I have said that a natural is distinguished from an arbitrary or
artificial system only in degree. It will be found almost impossible
to arrange objects according to any circumstance without finding that
some correlation of other circumstances is thus made apparent. No
arrangement could seem more arbitrary than the common alphabetical
arrangement according to the initial letter of the name. But we cannot
scrutinise a list of names of persons without noticing a predominance
of Evans’s and Jones’s, under the letters E and J, and of names
beginning with Mac under the letter M. The predominance is so great
that we could not attribute it to chance, and inquiry would of course
show that it arose from important facts concerning the nationality
of the persons. It would appear that the Evans’s and Jones’s were of
Welsh descent, and those whose names bear the prefix Mac of Keltic
descent. With the nationality would be more or less strictly correlated
many peculiarities of physical constitution, language, habits, or
mental character. In other cases I have been interested in noticing
the empirical inferences which are displayed in the most arbitrary
arrangements. If a large register of the names of ships be examined
it will often be found that a number of ships bearing the same name
were built about the same time, a correlation due to the occurrence of
some striking incident shortly previous to the building of the ships.
The age of ships or other structures is usually correlated with their
general form, nature of materials, &c., so that ships of the same name
will often resemble each other in many points.

It is impossible to examine the details of some of the so-called
artificial systems of classification of plants, without finding that
many of the classes are natural in character. Thus in Tournefort’s
arrangement, depending almost entirely on the formation of the corolla,
we find the natural orders of the Labiatæ, Cruciferæ, Rosaceæ,
Umbelliferæ, Liliaceæ, and Papilionaceæ, recognised in his 4th, 5th,
6th, 7th, 9th, and 10th classes. Many of the classes in Linnæus’
celebrated sexual system also approximate to natural classes.


*Correlation of Properties.*

Habits and usages of language are apt to lead us into the error of
imagining that when we employ different words we always mean different
things. In introducing the subject of classification nominally I was
careful to draw the reader’s attention to the fact that all reasoning
and all operations of scientific method really involve classification,
though we are accustomed to use the name in some cases and not in
others. The name *correlation* requires to be used with the same
qualification. Things are correlated (*con*, *relata*) when they are
so related or bound to each other that *where one is the other is, and
where one is not the other is not*. Throughout this work we have then
been dealing with correlations. In geometry the occurrence of three
equal angles in a triangle is correlated with the existence of three
equal sides; in physics gravity is correlated with inertia; in botany
exogenous growth is correlated with the possession of two cotyledons,
or the production of flowers with that of spiral vessels. Wherever a
proposition of the form A = B is true there correlation exists. But it
is in the classificatory sciences especially that the word correlation
has been employed.

We find it stated that in the class Mammalia the possession of two
occipital condyles, with a well-ossified basi-occipital, is correlated
with the possession of mandibles, each ramus of which is composed of a
single piece of bone, articulated with the squamosal element of the
skull, and also with the possession of mammæ and non-nucleated red
blood-corpuscles. Professor Huxley remarks[564] that this statement of
the character of the class mammalia is something more than an arbitrary
definition; it is a statement of a law of correlation or co-existence
of animal structures, from which most important conclusions are
deducible. It involves a generalisation to the effect that in nature
the structures mentioned are always found associated together. This
amounts to saying that the formation of the class mammalia involves an
act of inductive discovery, and results in the establishment of certain
empirical laws of nature. Professor Huxley has excellently expressed
the mode in which discoveries of this kind enable naturalists to make
deductions or predictions with considerable confidence, but he has also
pointed out that such inferences are likely from time to time to prove
mistaken. I will quote his own words:

  [564] *Lectures on the Elements of Comparative Anatomy, and on the
  Classification of Animals*, 1864, p. 3.

“If a fragmentary fossil be discovered, consisting of no more than
a ramus of a mandible, and that part of the skull with which it
articulated, a knowledge of this law may enable the palæontologist to
affirm, with great confidence, that the animal of which it formed a
part suckled its young, and had non-nucleated red blood-corpuscles; and
to predict that should the back part of that skull be discovered, it
will exhibit two occipital condyles and a well-ossified basi-occipital
bone.

“Deductions of this kind, such as that made by Cuvier in the famous
case of the fossil opossum of Montmartre, have often been verified,
and are well calculated to impress the vulgar imagination; so that
they have taken rank as the triumphs of the anatomist. But it should
carefully be borne in mind, that, like all merely empirical laws, which
rest upon a comparatively narrow observational basis, the reasoning
from them may at any time break down. If Cuvier, for example, had had
to do with a fossil Thylacinus instead of a fossil Opossum, he would
not have found the marsupial bones, though the inflected angle of the
jaw would have been obvious enough. And so, though, practically,
any one who met with a characteristically mammalian jaw would be
justified in expecting to find the characteristically mammalian occiput
associated with it; yet, he would be a bold man indeed, who should
strictly assert the belief which is implied in this expectation, viz.,
that at no period of the world’s history did animals exist which
combined a mammalian occiput with a reptilian jaw, or *vice versâ*.”

One of the most distinct and remarkable instances of correlation in
the animal world is that which occurs in ruminating animals, and which
could not be better stated than in the following extract from the
classical work of Cuvier:[565]

  [565] *Ossemens Fossiles*, 4th edit. vol. i. p. 164. Quoted by
  Huxley, *Lectures*, &c., p. 5.

“I doubt if any one would have divined, if untaught by observation,
that all ruminants have the foot cleft, and that they alone have it. I
doubt if any one would have divined that there are frontal horns only
in this class: that those among them which have sharp canines for the
most part lack horns.

“However, since these relations are constant, they must have some
sufficient cause; but since we are ignorant of it, we must make good
the defect of the theory by means of observation: it enables us to
establish empirical laws which become almost as certain as rational
laws when they rest on sufficiently repeated observations; so that
now whoso sees merely the print of a cleft foot may conclude that the
animal which left this impression ruminated, and this conclusion is as
certain as any other in physics or morals. This footprint alone then,
yields, to him who observes it, the form of the teeth, the form of the
jaws, the form of the vertebræ, the form of all the bones of the legs,
of the thighs, of the shoulders, and of the pelvis of the animal which
has passed by: it is a surer mark than all those of Zadig.”

We meet with a good instance of the purely empirical correlation
of circumstances when we classify the planets according to their
densities and periods of axial rotation.[566] If we examine a table
specifying the usual astronomical elements of the solar system, we find
that four planets resemble each other very closely in the period of
axial rotation, and the same four planets are all found to have high
densities, thus:--

  [566] Chambers, *Descriptive Astronomy*, 1st edit. p. 23.

  Name of        Period of Axial
  Planet.          Rotation.         Density.

  Mercury      24 hours  5 minutes     7·94
  Venus        23  "    21  "          5·33
  Earth        23  "    56  "          5·67
  Mars         24  "    37  "          5·84

A similar table for the other larger planets, is as follows:--

  Jupiter       9 hours 55 minutes     1·36
  Saturn       10  "    29  "           ·74
  Uranus        9  "    30  "           ·97
  Neptune      --  "    --             1·02

It will be observed that in neither group is the equality of the
rotational period or the density more than rudely approximate;
nevertheless the difference of the numbers in the first and second
group is so very well marked, the periods of the first being at least
double and the densities four or five times those of the second, that
the coincidence cannot be attributed to accident. The reader will
also notice that the first group consists of the planets nearest to
the sun; that with the exception of the earth none of them possess
satellites; and that they are all comparatively small. The second group
are furthest from the sun, and all of them possess several satellites,
and are comparatively great. Therefore, with but slight exceptions, the
following correlations hold true:--

Interior planets. Long period. Small size. High Density. No satellites.
Exterior " Short " Great " Low " Many "

These coincidences point with much probability to a difference in the
origin of the two groups, but no further explanation of the matter is
yet possible.

The classification of comets according to their periods by Mr.
Hind and Mr. A. S. Davies, tends to establish the conclusion that
distinct groups of comets have been brought into the solar system
by the attractive powers of Jupiter, Uranus, or other planets.[567]
The classification of nebulæ as commenced by the two Herschels, and
continued by Lord Rosse, Mr. Huggins, and others, will probably lead
at some future time to the discovery of important empirical laws
concerning the constitution of the universe. The minute examination and
classification of meteorites, as carried on by Mr. Sorby and others,
seems likely to afford us an insight into the formation of the heavenly
bodies.

  [567] *Philosophical Magazine*, 4th Series, vol. xxxix. p. 396;
  vol. xl. p. 183; vol. xli. p. 44. See also Proctor, *Popular Science
  Review*, October 1874, p. 350.

We should never fail to remember the slightest and most inexplicable
correlations, for they may prove of importance in the future.
Discoveries begin when we are least expecting them. It is a significant
fact, for instance, that the greater number of variable stars are of
a reddish colour. Not all variable stars are red, nor all red stars
variable; but considering that only a small fraction of the observed
stars are known to be variable, and only a small fraction are red, the
number which fall into both classes is too great to be accidental.[568]
It is also remarkable that the greater number of stars possessing great
proper motion are double stars, the star 61 Cygni being especially
noticeable in this respect.[569] The correlation in these cases is
not without exception, but the preponderance is so great as to point
to some natural connexion, the exact nature of which must be a matter
for future investigation. Herschel remarked that the two double stars
61 Cygni and α Centauri of which the orbits were well ascertained,
evidently belonged to the same family or genus.[570]

  [568] Humboldt, *Cosmos* (Bohn), vol. iii. p. 224.

  [569] Baily, British *Association Catalogue*, p. 48.

  [570] *Outlines of Astronomy*, § 850, 4th edit. p. 578.


*Classification in Crystallography.*

Perhaps the most perfect and instructive instance of classification
which we can find is furnished by the science of crystallography
(p. 133). The system of arrangement now generally adopted is
conspicuously natural, and is even mathematically perfect. A crystal
consists in every part of similar molecules similarly related to the
adjoining molecules, and connected with them by forces the nature of
which we can only learn by their apparent effects. But these forces
are exerted in space of three dimensions, so that there is a limited
number of suppositions which can be entertained as to the relations of
these forces. In one case each molecule will be similarly related to
all those which are next to it; in a second case, it will be similarly
related to those in a certain plane, but differently related to those
not in that plane. In the simpler cases the arrangement of molecules is
rectangular; in the remaining cases oblique either in one or two planes.

In order to simplify the explanation and conception of the complicated
phenomena which crystals exhibit, an hypothesis has been invented which
is an excellent instance of the Descriptive Hypotheses before mentioned
(p. 522). Crystallographers imagine that there are within each crystal
certain axes, or lines of direction, by the comparative length and the
mutual inclination of which the nature of the crystal is determined.
In one class of crystals there are three such axes lying in one plane,
and a fourth perpendicular to that plane; but in all the other classes
there are imagined to be only three axes. Now these axes can be varied
in three ways as regards length: they may be (1) all equal, or (2) two
equal and one unequal, or (3) all unequal. They may also be varied in
four ways as regards direction: (1) they may be all at right angles
to each other; (2) two axes may be oblique to each other and at right
angles to the third; (3) two axes may be at right angles to each other
and the third oblique to both; (4) the three axes may be all oblique.
Now, if all the variations as regards length were combined with those
regarding direction, it would seem to be possible to have twelve
classes of crystals in all, the enumeration being then logically and
geometrically complete. But as a matter of empirical observation, many
of these classes are not found to occur, oblique axes being seldom or
never equal. There remain seven recognised classes of crystals, but
even of these one class is not positively known to be represented in
nature.

The first class of crystals is defined by possessing three equal
rectangular axes, and equal elasticity in all directions. The primary
or simple form of the crystals is the cube, but by the removal of the
corners of the cube by planes variously inclined to the axes, we have
the regular octohedron, the dodecahedron, and various combinations of
these forms. Now it is a law of this class of crystals that as each
axis is exactly like each other axis, every modification of any corner
of a crystal must be repeated symmetrically with regard to the other
axes; thus the forms produced are symmetrical or regular, and the
class is called the *Regular System* of crystals. It includes a great
variety of substances, some of them being elements, such as carbon in
the form of diamond, others more or less complex compounds, such as
rock-salt, potassium iodide and bromide, the several kinds of alum,
fluor-spar, iron bisulphide, garnet, spinelle, &c. No correlation
then is apparent between the form of crystallisation and the chemical
composition. But what we have to notice is that the physical properties
of the crystallised substances with regard to light, heat, electricity,
&c., are closely similar. Light and heat undulations, wherever they
enter a crystal of the regular system, spread with equal rapidity in
all directions, just as they would in a uniform fluid. Crystals of the
regular system accordingly do not in any case exhibit the phenomena
of double refraction, unless by mechanical compression we alter the
conditions of elasticity. These crystals, again, expand equally in all
directions when heated, and if we could cut a sufficiently large plate
from a cubical crystal, and examine the sound vibrations of which it
is capable, we should find that they indicated an equal elasticity
in every direction. Thus we see that a great number of important
properties are correlated with that of crystallisation in the regular
system, and as soon as we know that the primary form of a substance
is the cube, we are able to infer with approximate certainty that it
possesses all these properties. The class of regular crystals is then
an eminently natural class, one disclosing many general laws connecting
together the physical and mechanical properties of the substances
classified.

In the second class of crystals, called the dimetric, square prismatic,
or pyramidal system, there are also three axes at right angles to each
other; two of the axes are equal, but the third or principal axis is
unequal, being either greater or less than either of the other two. In
such crystals accordingly the elasticity and other properties are alike
in all directions perpendicular to the principal axis, but vary in all
other directions. If a point within a crystal of this system be heated,
the heat spreads with equal rapidity in planes perpendicular to the
principal axis, but more or less rapidly in the direction of this axis,
so that the isothermal surface is an ellipsoid of revolution round that
axis.

Nearly the same statement may be made concerning the third or hexagonal
or rhombohedral system of crystals, in which there are three axes lying
in one plane and meeting at angles of 60°, while the fourth axis is
perpendicular to the other three. The hexagonal prism and rhombohedron
are the commonest forms assumed by crystals of this system, and in
ice, quartz, and calc-spar, we have abundance of beautiful specimens
of the various shapes produced by the modification of the primitive
form. Calc-spar alone is said to crystallise in at least 700 varieties
of form. Now of all the crystals belonging both to this and the
dimetric class, we know that a ray of light passing in the direction
of the principal axis will be refracted singly as in a crystal of the
regular system; but in every other direction the light will suffer
double refraction being separated into two rays, one of which obeys
the ordinary law of refraction, but the other a much more complicated
law. The other physical properties vary in an analogous manner. Thus
calc-spar expands by heat in the direction of the principal axis, but
contracts a little in directions perpendicular to it. So closely are
the physical properties correlated that Mitscherlich, having observed
the law of expansion in calc-spar, was enabled to predict that the
double refracting power of the substance would be decreased by a rise
of temperature, as was proved by experiment to be the case.

In the fourth system, called the trimetric, rhombic, or right prismatic
system, there are three axes, at right angles, but all unequal in
length. It may be asserted in general terms that the mechanical
properties vary in such crystals in every direction, and heat spreads
so that the isothermal surface is an ellipsoid with three unequal axes.

In the remaining three classes, called the monoclinic, diclinic, and
triclinic, the axes are more or less oblique, and at the same time
unequal. The complication of phenomena is therefore greatly increased,
and it need only be stated that there are always two directions in
which a ray is singly refracted, but that in all other directions
double refraction takes place. The conduction of heat is unequal in
all directions, the isothermal surface being an ellipsoid of three
unequal axes. The relations of such crystals to other phenomena are
often very complicated, and hardly yet reduced to law. Some crystals,
called pyro-electric, manifest vitreous electricity at some points of
their surface, and resinous electricity at other points when rising in
temperature, the character of the electricity being changed when the
temperature sinks again. This production of electricity is believed to
be connected with the hemihedral character of the crystals exhibiting
it. The crystalline structure of a substance again influences its
magnetic behaviour, the general law being that the direction in which
the molecules of a crystal are most approximated tends to place itself
axially or equatorially between the poles of a magnet, respectively
as the body is magnetic or diamagnetic. Further questions arise if we
apply pressure to crystals. Thus doubly refracting crystals with one
principal axis acquire two axes when the pressure is perpendicular in
direction to the principal axis.

All the phenomena peculiar to crystalline bodies are thus closely
correlated with the formation of the crystal, or will almost
certainly be found to be so as investigation proceeds. It is upon
empirical observation indeed that the laws of connexion are in the
first place founded, but the simple hypothesis that the elasticity
and approximation of the particles vary in the directions of the
crystalline axes allows of the application of deductive reasoning. The
whole of the phenomena are gradually being proved to be consistent with
this hypothesis, so that we have in this subject of crystallography
a beautiful instance of successful classification, connected with
a nearly perfect physical hypothesis. Moreover this hypothesis was
verified experimentally as regards the mechanical vibrations of sound
by Savart, who found that the vibrations in a plate of biaxial crystal
indicated the existence of varying elasticity in varying directions.


*Classification an Inverse and Tentative Operation.*

If attempts at so-called natural classification are really attempts
at perfect induction, it follows that they are subject to the remarks
which were made upon the inverse character of the inductive process,
and upon the difficulty of every inverse operation (pp. 11, 12, 122,
&c.). There will be no royal road to the discovery of the best system,
and it will even be impossible to lay down rules of procedure to
assist those who are in search of a good arrangement. The only logical
rule would be as follows:--Having given certain objects, group them
in every way in which they can be grouped, and then observe in which
method of grouping the correlation of properties is most conspicuously
manifested. But this method of exhaustive classification will in almost
every case be impracticable, owing to the immensely great number of
modes in which a comparatively small number of objects may be grouped
together. About sixty-three elements have been classified by chemists
in six principal groups as monad, dyad, triad, &c., elements, the
numbers in the classes varying from three to twenty elements. Now if we
were to calculate the whole number of ways in which sixty-three objects
can be arranged in six groups, we should find the number to be so great
that the life of the longest lived man would be wholly inadequate
to enable him to go through these possible groupings. The rule of
exhaustive arrangement, then, is absolutely impracticable. It follows
that mere haphazard trial cannot as a general rule give any useful
result. If we were to write the names of the elements in succession
upon sixty-three cards, throw them into a ballot-box, and draw them
out haphazard in six handfuls time after time, the probability is
excessively small that we should take them out in a specified order,
that for instance at present adopted by chemists.

The usual mode in which an investigator proceeds to form a
classification of a new group of objects seems to consist in
tentatively arranging them according to their most obvious
similarities. Any two objects which present a close resemblance to
each other will be joined and formed into the rudiment of a class, the
definition of which will at first include all the apparent points of
resemblance. Other objects as they come to our notice will be gradually
assigned to those groups with which they present the greatest number
of points of resemblance, and the definition of a class will often
have to be altered in order to admit them. The early chemists could
hardly avoid classing together the common metals, gold, silver, copper,
lead, and iron, which present such conspicuous points of similarity as
regards density, metallic lustre, malleability, &c. With the progress
of discovery, however, difficulties began to present themselves in such
a grouping. Antimony, bismuth, and arsenic are distinctly metallic
as regards lustre, density, and some chemical properties, but are
wanting in malleability. The recently discovered tellurium presents
greater difficulties, for it has many of the physical properties of
metal, and yet all its chemical properties are analogous to those of
sulphur and selenium, which have never been regarded as metals. Great
chemical differences again are discovered by degrees between the
five metals mentioned; and the class, if it is to have any chemical
validity, must be made to include other elements, having none of the
original properties on which the class was founded. Hydrogen is a
transparent colourless gas, and the least dense of all substances; yet
in its chemical analogies it is a metal, as suggested by Faraday[571]
in 1838, and almost proved by Graham;[572] it must be placed in the
same class as silver. In this way it comes to pass that almost every
classification which is proposed in the early stages of a science will
be found to break down as the deeper similarities of the objects come
to be detected. The most obvious points of difference will have to be
neglected. Chlorine is a gas, bromine a liquid, and iodine a solid,
and at first sight these might have seemed formidable circumstances to
overlook; but in chemical analogy the substances are closely united.
The progress of organic chemistry, again, has yielded wholly new ideas
of the similarities of compounds. Who, for instance, would recognise
without extensive research a close similarity between glycerine and
alcohol, or between fatty substances and ether? The class of paraffins
contains three substances gaseous at ordinary temperatures, several
liquids, and some crystalline solids. It required much insight to
detect the analogy which exists between such apparently different
substances.

  [571] *Life of Faraday*, vol. ii. p. 87.

  [572] *Proceedings of the Royal Society*, vol. xvii. p. 212.
  *Chemical and Physical Researches*, reprint, by Young and Angus
  Smith, p. 290.

The science of chemistry now depends to a great extent on a correct
classification of the elements, as will be learnt by consulting
the able article on Classification by Professor G. C. Foster in
Watts’ *Dictionary of Chemistry*. But the present system of chemical
classification was not reached until at least three previous false
systems had been long entertained. And though there is much reason to
believe that the present mode of classification according to atomicity
is substantially correct, errors may yet be discovered in the details
of the grouping.


*Symbolic Statement of the Theory of Classification.*

The theory of classification can be explained in the most complete
and general manner, by reverting for a time to the use of the Logical
Alphabet, which was found to be of supreme importance in Formal Logic.
That form expresses the necessary classification of all objects and
ideas as depending on the laws of thought, and there is no point
concerning the purpose and methods of classification which may not
be stated precisely by the use of letter combinations, the only
inconvenience being the abstract form in which the subject is thus
represented.

If we pay regard only to three qualities in which things may resemble
each other, namely, the qualities A, B, C, there are according to
the laws of thought eight possible classes of objects, shown in the
fourth column of the Logical Alphabet (p. 94). If there exist objects
belonging to all these eight classes, it follows that the qualities A,
B, C, are subject to no conditions except the primary laws of thought
and things (p. 5). There is then no special law of nature to discover,
and, if we arrange the objects in any one order rather than another, it
must be for the purpose of showing that the combinations are logically
complete.

Suppose, however, that there are but four kinds of objects possessing
the qualities A, B, C, and that these kinds are represented by the
combinations ABC, A*b*C, *a*B*c*, *abc*. The order of arrangement will
now be of importance; for if we place them in the order

  {  ABC            {  A*b*C
  { *a*B*c*         { *abc*

placing the B’s first and those which are *b*’s last, we shall perhaps
overlook the law of correlation of properties involved. But if we
arrange the combinations as follows

  { ABC             { *a*B*c*
  { A*b*C           { *abc*

it becomes apparent at once that where A is, and only where A is, the
property C is to be found, B being indifferently present and absent.
The second arrangement then would be called a natural one, as rendering
manifest the conditions under which the combinations exist.

As a further instance, let us suppose that eight objects are presented
to us for classification, which exhibit combinations of the five
properties, A, B, C, D, E, in the following manner:--

  ABC*d*E          *a*BC*d*E
  AB*cde*          *a*B*cde*
  A*b*CDE          *ab*CDE
  A*bc*D*e*        *abc*D*e*

They are now classified, so that those containing A stand first, and
those devoid of A second, but no other property seems to be correlated
with A. Let us alter this arrangement and group the combinations thus:--

   ABC*d*E           A*b*CDE
   AB*cde*           A*bc*D*e*
  *a*BC*d*E         *ab*CDE
  *a*B*cde*         *abc*D*e*

It requires little examination to discover that in the first group B is
always present and D absent, whereas in the second group, B is always
absent and D present. This is the result which follows from a law of
the form B = d (p. 136), so that in this mode of arrangement we readily
discover correlation between two letters. Altering the groups again as
follows:--

   ABC*d*E           AB*cde*
  *a*BC*d*E         *a*B*cde*
   A*b*CDE           A*bc*D*e*
  *ab*CDE           *abc*D*e*,

we discover another evident correlation between C and E. Between A and
the other letters, or between the two pairs of letters B, D and C, E,
there is no logical connexion.

This example may seem tedious, but it will be found instructive in this
way. We are classifying only eight objects or combinations, in each
of which only five qualities are considered. There are only two laws
of correlation between four of those five qualities, and those laws
are of the simplest logical character. Yet the reader would hardly
discover what those laws are, and confidently assign them by rapid
contemplation of the combinations, as given in the first group. Several
tentative classifications must probably be made before we can resolve
the question. Let us now suppose that instead of eight objects and five
qualities, we have, say, five hundred objects and fifty qualities. If
we were to attempt the same method of exhaustive grouping which we
before employed, we should have to arrange the five hundred objects in
fifty different ways, before we could be sure that we had discovered
even the simpler laws of correlation. But even the successive
grouping of all those possessing each of the fifty properties would
not necessarily give us all the laws. There might exist complicated
relations between several properties simultaneously, for the detection
of which no rule of procedure whatever can be given.


*Bifurcate Classification.*

Every system of classification ought to be formed on the principles of
the Logical Alphabet. Each superior class should be divided into two
inferior classes, distinguished by the possession and non-possession
of a single specified difference. Each of these minor classes, again,
is divisible by any other quality whatever which can be suggested,
and thus every classification logically consists of an infinitely
extended series of subaltern genera and species. The classifications
which we form are in reality very small fragments of those which would
correctly and fully represent the relations of existing things. But if
we take more than four or five qualities into account, the number of
subdivisions grows impracticably large. Our finite minds are unable to
treat any complex group exhaustively, and we are obliged to simplify
and generalise scientific problems, often at the risk of overlooking
particular conditions and exceptions.

Every system of classes displayed in the manner of the Logical Alphabet
may be called *bifurcate*, because every class branches out at each
step into two minor classes, existent or imaginary. It would be a
great mistake to regard this arrangement as in any way a peculiar or
special method; it is not only a natural and important one, but it is
the inevitable and only system which is logically perfect, according
to the fundamental laws of thought. All other arrangements of classes
correspond to the bifurcate arrangement, with the implication that
some of the minor classes are not represented among existing things.
If we take the genus A and divide it into the species AB and AC, we
imply two propositions, namely that in the class A, the properties of B
and C never occur together, and that they are never both absent; these
propositions are logically equivalent to one, namely AB = A*c*. Our
classification is then identical with the following bifurcate one:--

                       A
                       |
            +----------+----------+
            |                     |
           AB                    A*b*
            |                     |
     +------+------+       +------+------+
     |             |       |             |
  ABC = 0        AB*c*   A*b*C       A*bc* = 0

If, again, we divide the genus A into three species, AB, AC, AD, we
are either logically in error, or else we must be understood to imply
that, as regards the other letters, there exist only three combinations
containing A, namely AB*cd*, A*b*C*d*, and A*bc*D.

The logical necessity of bifurcate classification has been clearly and
correctly stated in the *Outline of a New System of Logic* by George
Bentham, the eminent botanist, a work of which the logical value has
been quite overlooked until lately. Mr. Bentham points out, in p. 113,
that every classification must be essentially bifurcate, and takes, as
an example, the division of vertebrate animals into four sub-classes,
as follows:--

  Mammifera--endowed with mammæ and lungs.
  Birds      without mammæ but with lungs and wings.
  Fish       deprived of lungs.
  Reptiles   deprived of mammæ and wings but with lungs.

We have, then, as Mr. Bentham says, three bifid divisions, thus
represented:--

                        Vertebrata
                            |
                +-----------+-----------+
                |                       |
       Endowed with lungs       deprived of lungs
                |                    = Fish.
       +--------+----------------+
       |                         |
  Endowed with              deprived of
     mammæ                     mammæ
  = Mammifera.                   |
                          +------+------+
                          |             |
                      with wings   without wings
                       = Birds.     = Reptiles.

It is quite evident that according to the laws of thought even this
arrangement is incomplete. The sub-class mammifera must either have
wings or be deprived of them; we must either subdivide this class, or
assume that none of the mammifera have wings, which is, as a matter of
fact, the case, the wings of bats not being true wings in the meaning
of the term as applied to birds. Fish, again, ought to be considered
with regard to the possession of mammæ and wings; and in leaving them
undivided we really imply that they never have mammæ nor wings, the
wings of the flying-fish, again, being no exception. If we resort to
the use of our letters and define them as follows--

  A = vertebrata,
  B = having lungs,
  C = having mammæ,
  D = having wings,

then there are four existent classes of vertebrata which appear to be
thus described--

  ABC     AB*c*D     AB*cd*     A*b*.

But in reality the combinations are implied to be

  ABC*d* = Mammifera,
  AB*c*D = Birds,
  AB*cd* = Reptiles,
  A*bcd* = Fish,

and we imply at the same time that the other four conceivable
combinations containing B, C, or D, namely ABCD, A*b*CD, A*b*C*d*, and
A*bc*D, do not exist in nature.

Mr. Bentham points out[573] that it is really this method of
classification which was employed by Lamarck and De Candolle in their
so-called analytical arrangement of the French Flora. He gives as an
example a table of the principal classes of De Candolle’s system, as
also a bifurcate arrangement of animals after the method proposed
by Duméril in his *Zoologie Analytique*, this naturalist being
distinguished by his clear perception of the logical importance of the
method. A bifurcate classification of the animal kingdom may also be
found in Professor Reay Greene’s *Manual of the Cœlenterata*, p. 18.

  [573] *Essai sur la Nomenclature et la Classification*, Paris, 1823,
  pp. 107, 108.

The bifurcate form of classification seems to be needless when the
quality according to which we classify any group of things admits
of numerical discrimination. It would seem absurd to arrange things
according as they have one degree of the quality or not one degree,
two degrees or not two degrees, and so on. The elements are classified
according as the atom of each saturates one, two, three, or more atoms
of a monad element, such as chlorine, and they are called accordingly
monad, dyad, triad, tetrad elements, and so on. It would be useless to
apply the bifid arrangement, thus:--

       Element
          |
    +-----+-------+
    |             |
  Monad       not-Monad
                  |
        +---------+---------+
        |                   |
      Dyad              not-Dyad
                            |
                  +---------+---------+
                  |                   |
                Triad             not-Triad
                                      |
                            +---------+--------+
                            |                  |
                         Tetrad            not-Tetrad.

The reason of this is that, by the nature of number (p. 157) every
number is logically discriminated from every other number. There can
thus be no logical confusion in a numerical arrangement, and the series
of numbers indefinitely extended is also exhaustive. Every thing
admitting of a quality expressible in numbers must find its place
somewhere in the series of numbers. The chords in music correspond to
the simpler numerical ratios and must admit of complete exhaustive
classification in respect to the complexity of the ratios forming
them. Plane rectilinear figures may be classified according to the
numbers of their sides, as triangles, quadrilateral figures, pentagons,
hexagons, heptagons, &c. The bifurcate arrangement is not false when
applied to such series of objects; it is even necessarily involved in
the arrangement which we do apply, so that its formal statement is
needless and tedious. The same may be said of the division of portions
of space. Reid and Kames endeavoured to cast ridicule on the bifurcate
arrangement[574] by proposing to classify the parts of England into
Middlesex and what is not Middlesex, dividing the latter again into
Kent and what is not Kent, Sussex and what is not Sussex; and so on.
This is so far, however, from being an absurd proceeding that it is
requisite to assure us that we have made an exhaustive enumeration of
the parts of England.

  [574] George Bentham, *Outline of a New System of Logic*, p. 115.


*The Five Predicables.*

As a rule it is highly desirable to consign to oblivion the ancient
logical names and expressions, which have infested the science for
many centuries past. If logic is ever to be a useful and progressive
science, logicians must distinguish between logic and the history of
logic. As in the case of any other science it may be desirable to
examine the course of thought by which logic has, before or since the
time of Aristotle, been brought to its present state; the history of a
science is always instructive as giving instances of the mode in which
discoveries take place. But at the same time we ought carefully to
disencumber the statement of the science itself of all names and other
vestiges of antiquity which are not actually useful at the present day.

Among the ancient expressions which may well be excepted from such
considerations and retained in use, are the “Five Words” or “Five
Predicables” which were described by Porphyry in his introduction to
Aristotle’s Organum. Two of them, *Genus* and *Species*, are the most
venerable names in philosophy, having probably been first employed
in their present logical meanings by Socrates. In the present day it
requires some mental effort, as remarked by Grote, to see anything
important in the invention of notions now so familiar as those of Genus
and Species. But in reality the introduction of such terms showed the
rise of the first germs of logic and scientific method; it showed that
men were beginning to analyse their processes of thought.

The Five Predicables are Genus, Species, Difference, Property, and
Accident, or in the original Greek, γένος, εἶδος, διαφορά, ἴδιον,
συμβεβηκός. Of these, Genus may be taken to mean any class of objects
which is regarded as broken up into two minor classes, which form
Species of it. The genus is defined by a certain number of qualities or
circumstances which belong to all objects included in the class, and
which are sufficient to mark out these objects from all others which
we do not intend to include. Interpreted as regards intension, then,
the genus is a group of qualities; interpreted as regards extension, it
is a group of objects possessing those qualities. If another quality
be taken into account which is possessed by some of the objects and
not by the others, this quality becomes a difference which divides
the genus into two species. We may interpret the species either in
intension or extension; in the former respect it is more than the genus
as containing one more quality, the difference: in the latter respect
it is less than the genus as containing only a portion of the group
constituting the genus. We may say, then, with Aristotle, that in one
sense the genus is in the species, namely in intension, and in another
sense the species is in the genus, namely in extension. The difference,
it is evident, can be interpreted in intension only.

A Property is a quality which belongs to the whole of a class, but does
not enter into the definition of that class. A generic property belongs
to every individual object contained in the genus. It is a property
of the genus parallelogram that the opposite angles are equal. If we
regard a rectangle as a species of parallelogram, the difference being
that *one* angle is a right angle, it follows as a specific property
that all the angles are right angles. Though a property in the strict
logical sense must belong to each of the objects included in the class
of which it is a property, it may or may not belong to other objects.
The property of having the opposite angles equal may belong to many
figures besides parallelograms, for instance, regular hexagons. It is a
property of the circle that all triangles constructed upon the diameter
with the apex upon the circumference are right-angled triangles, and
*vice versâ*, all curves of which this is true must be circles. A
property which thus belongs to the whole of a class and only to that
class, corresponds to the ἴδιον of Aristotle and Porphyry; we might
conveniently call it *a peculiar property*. Every such property enables
us to make a statement in the form of a simple identity (p. 37). Thus
we know it to be a peculiar property of the circle that for a given
length of perimeter it encloses a greater area than any other possible
curve; hence we may say--

  Curve of equal curvature = curve of greatest area.

It is a peculiar property of equilateral triangles that they are
equiangular, and *vice versâ*, it is a peculiar property of equiangular
triangles that they are equilateral. It is a property of crystals
of the regular system that they are devoid of the power of double
refraction, but this is not a property peculiar to them, because
liquids and gases are devoid of the same property.

An Accident, the fifth and last of the Predicables, is any quality
which may or may not belong to certain objects, and which has no
connexion with the classification adopted. The particular size of
a crystal does not in the slightest degree affect the form of the
crystal, nor does the manner in which it is grouped with other
crystals; these, then, are accidents as regards a crystallographic
classification. With respect to the chemical composition of a
substance, again, it is an accident whether the substance be
crystallised or not, or whether it be organised or not. As regards
botanical classification the absolute size of a plant is an accident.
Thus we see that a logical accident is any quality or circumstance
which is not known to be correlated with those qualities or
circumstances forming the definition of the species.

The meanings of the Predicables can be clearly explained by our
symbols. Let A be any definite group of qualities and B another quality
or group of qualities; then A will constitute a genus, and AB, A*b*
will be species of it, B being the difference. Let C, D and E be other
qualities or groups of qualities, and on examining the combinations in
which A, B, C, D, E occur let them be as follows:--

  ABCDE          A*b*C*d*E
  ABCD*e*        A*b*C*de*.

Here we see that wherever A is we also find C, so that C is a generic
property; D occurs always with B, so that it constitutes a specific
property, while E is indifferently present and absent, so as not to be
related to any other letter; it represents, therefore, an accident. It
will now be seen that the Logical Alphabet represents an interminable
series of subordinate genera and species; it is but a concise symbolic
statement of what was involved in the ancient doctrine of the
Predicables.


*Summum Genus and Infima Species.*

As a genus means any class whatever which is regarded as composed
of minor classes or species, it follows that the same class will be
a genus in one point of view and a species in another. Metal is a
genus as regards alkaline metal, a species as regards element, and
any extensive system of classes consists of a series of subordinate,
or as they are technically called, *subaltern* genera and species.
The question, however, arises, whether such a chain of classes
has a definite termination at either end. The doctrine of the old
logicians was to the effect that it terminated upwards in a *genus
generalissimum* or *summum genus*, which was not a species of any
wider class. Some very general notion, such as substance, object, or
thing, was supposed to be so comprehensive as to include all thinkable
objects, and for all practical purposes this might be so. But as I
have already explained (p. 74), we cannot really think of any object
or class without thereby separating it from what is not that object or
class. All thinking is relative, and implies discrimination, so that
every class and every logical notion must have its negative. If so,
there is no such thing as a *summum genus*; for we cannot frame the
requisite notion of a class forming it without implying the existence
of another class discriminated from it; add this new negative class to
the supposed *summum genus*, and we form a still higher genus, which is
absurd.

Although there is no absolute summum genus, nevertheless relatively to
any branch of knowledge or any particular argument, there is always
some class or notion which bounds our horizon as it were. The chemist
restricts his view to material substances and the forces manifested
in them; the mathematician extends his view so as to comprehend all
notions capable of numerical discrimination. The biologist, on the
other hand, has a narrower sphere containing only organised bodies, and
of these the botanist and the zoologist take parts. In other subjects
there may be a still narrower summum genus, as when the lawyer regards
only reasoning beings of his own country together with their property.

In the description of the Logical Alphabet it was pointed out (p. 93)
that every series of combinations is really the development of a
single class, denoted by X, which letter was accordingly placed in the
first column of the table on p. 94. This is the formal acknowledgment
of the principle clearly stated by De Morgan, that all reasoning
proceeds within an assumed summum genus. But at the same time the fact
that X as a logical term must have its negative *x*, shows that it
cannot be an absolute summum genus.

There arises, again, the question whether there be any such thing as
an *infima species*, which cannot be divided into minor species. The
ancient logicians were of opinion that there always was some assignable
class which could only be divided into individuals, but this doctrine
appears to be theoretically incorrect, as Mr. George Bentham long ago
stated.[575] We may put an arbitrary limit to the subdivision of our
classes at any point convenient to our purpose. The crystallographer
would not generally treat as different species crystalline forms which
differ only in the degree of development of the faces. The naturalist
overlooks innumerable slight differences between animals which he
refers to the same species. But in a strictly logical point of view
classification might be carried on as long as there is a difference,
however minute, between two objects, and we might thus go on until we
arrive at individual objects which are numerically distinct in the
logical sense attributed to that expression in the chapter upon Number.
Either, then, we must call the individual the *infima species* or allow
that there is no such thing at all.

  [575] *Outline of a New System of Logic*, 1827, p. 117.


*The Tree of Porphyry.*

Both Aristotle and Plato were acquainted with the value of bifurcate
classification, which they occasionally employed in an explicit manner.
It is impossible too that Aristotle should state the laws of thought,
and employ the predicables without implicitly recognising the logical
necessity of that method. It is, however, in Porphyry’s remarkable
and in many respects excellent *Introduction to the Categories of
Aristotle* that we find the most distinct account of it. Porphyry not
only fully and accurately describes the Predicables, but incidentally
introduces an example for illustrating those predicables, which
constitutes a good specimen of bifurcate classification. Translating
his words[576] freely we may say that he takes Substance as the genus
to be divided, under which are successively placed as Species--Body,
Animated Body, Animal, Rational Animal, and Man. Under Man, again,
come Socrates, Plato, and other particular men. Now of these notions
Substance is the genus generalissimum, and is a genus only, not a
species. Man, on the other hand, is the species specialissima (infima
species), and is a species only, not a genus. Body is a species of
substance, but a genus of animated body, which, again, is a species of
body but a genus of animal. Animal is a species of animated body, but
a genus of rational animal, which, again, is a species of animal, but
a genus of man. Finally, man is a species of rational animal, but is a
species merely and not a genus, being divisible only into particular
men.

  [576] *Porphyrii Isagoge*, Caput ii. 24.

Porphyry proceeds at some length to employ his example in further
illustration of the predicables. We do not find in Porphyry’s own
work any scheme or diagram exhibiting this curious specimen of
classification, but some of the earlier commentators and epitome
writers drew what has long been called the Tree of Porphyry. This
diagram, which may be found in most elementary works on Logic,[577] is
also called the Ramean Tree, because Ramus insisted much upon the value
of Dichotomy. With the exception of Jeremy Bentham[578] and George
Bentham, hardly any modern logicians have shown an appreciation of the
value of bifurcate classification. The latter author has treated the
subject, both in his *Outline of a New System of Logic* (pp. 105–118),
and in his earlier work entitled *Essai sur la Nomenclature et la
Classification des Principales Branches d’Art-et-Science* (Paris,
1823), which consists of a free translation or improved version of his
uncle’s Essay on Classification in the *Chrestomathia*. Some interest
attaches to the history of the Tree of Porphyry and Ramus, because
it is the prototype of the Logical Alphabet which lies at the basis
of logical method. Jeremy Bentham speaks truly of “the matchless
beauty of the Ramean Tree.” After fully showing its logical value as
an exhaustive method of classification, and refuting the objections
of Reid and Kames, on a wrong ground, as I think, he proceeds to
inquire to what length it may be carried. He correctly points out two
objections to the extensive use of bifid arrangements, (1) that they
soon become impracticably extensive and unwieldy, and (2) that they
are uneconomical. In his day the recorded number of different species
of plants was 40,000, and he leaves the reader to estimate the immense
number of branches and the enormous area of a bifurcate table which
should exhibit all these species in one scheme. He also points out the
apparent loss of labour in making any large bifurcate classification;
but this he considers to be fully recompensed by the logical value of
the result, and the logical training acquired in its execution. Jeremy
Bentham, then, fully recognises the value of the Logical Alphabet under
another name, though he apprehends also the limit to its use placed by
the finiteness of our mental and manual powers.

  [577] Jevons, *Elementary Lessons in Logic*, p. 104.

  [578] *Chrestomathia; being a Collection of Papers, &c.* London,
  1816, Appendix V.


*Does Abstraction imply Generalisation?*

Before we can acquire a sound comprehension of the subject of
classification we must answer the very difficult question whether
logical abstraction does or does not imply generalisation. It comes to
exactly the same thing if we ask whether a species may be coextensive
with its genus, or whether, on the other hand, the genus must contain
more than the species. To abstract logically is (p. 27), to overlook or
withdraw our notice from some point of difference. Whenever we form a
class we abstract, for the time being, the differences of the objects
so united in respect of some common quality. If we class together a
great number of objects as dwelling-houses, we overlook the fact that
some dwelling-houses are constructed of stone, others of brick, wood,
iron, &c. Often at least the abstraction of a circumstance increases
the number of objects included under a class according to the law of
the inverse relation of the quantities of extension and intension
(p. 26). Dwelling-house is a wider term than brick-dwelling-house.
House is more general than dwelling-house. But the question before
us is, whether abstraction *always* increases the number of objects
included in a class, which amounts to asking whether the law of
the inverse relation of logical quantities is *always* true. The
interest of the question partly arises from the fact, that so high
a philosophical authority as Mr. Herbert Spencer has denied that
generalisation is implied in abstraction,[579] making this doctrine
the ground for rejecting previous methods of classifying the sciences,
and for forming an ingenious but peculiar method of his own. The
question is also a fundamental one of the highest logical importance,
and involves subtle difficulties which have made me long hesitate in
forming a decisive opinion.

  [579] *The Classification of the Sciences*, &c., 3rd edit. p. 7.
  *Essays: Scientific, Political, and Speculative*, vol. iii. p. 13.

Let us attempt to answer the question by examination of a few examples.
Compare the two classes *gun* and *iron gun*. It is certain that there
are many guns which are not made of iron, so that abstraction of the
circumstance “made of iron” increases the extent of the notion. Next
compare *gun* and *metallic gun*. All guns made at the present day
consist of metal, so that the two notions seem to be coextensive;
but guns were at first made of pieces of wood bound together like
a tub, and as the logical term gun takes no account of time, it
must include all guns that have ever existed. Here again extension
increases as intension decreases. Compare once more “steam-locomotive
engine” and “locomotive engine.” In the present day, as far as I am
aware, all locomotives are worked by steam, so that the omission of
that qualification might seem not to widen the term; but it is quite
possible that in some future age a different motive power may be used
in locomotives; and as there is no limitation of time in the use of
logical terms, we must certainly assume that there is a class of
locomotives not worked by steam, as well as a class that is worked by
steam. When the natural class of Euphorbiaceæ was originally formed,
all the plants known to belong to it were devoid of corollas; it
would have seemed therefore that the two classes “Euphorbiaceæ,” and
“Euphorbiaceæ devoid of Corollas,” were of equal extent. Subsequently
a number of plants plainly belonging to the same class were found in
tropical countries, and they possessed bright coloured corollas.
Naturalists believe with the utmost confidence that “Ruminants” and
“Ruminants with cleft feet” are identical terms, because no ruminant
has yet been discovered without cleft feet. But we can see no
impossibility in the conjunction of rumination with uncleft feet, and
it would be too great an assumption to say that we are certain that an
example of it will never be met with. Instances can be quoted, without
end, of objects being ultimately discovered combining properties which
had never before been seen together. In the animal kingdom the Black
Swan, the Ornithorhynchus Paradoxus, and more recently the singular
fish called Ceratodus Forsteri, all discovered in Australia, have
united characters never previously known to coexist. At the present
time deep-sea dredging is bringing to light many animals of an
unprecedented nature. Singular exceptional discoveries may certainly
occur in other branches of science. When Davy first discovered metallic
potassium, it was a well established empirical law that all metallic
substances possessed a high specific gravity, the least dense of the
metals then known being zinc, of which the specific gravity is 7·1. Yet
to the surprise of chemists, potassium was found to be an undoubted
metal of less density than water, its specific gravity being 0·865.

It is hardly requisite to prove by further examples that our knowledge
of nature is incomplete, so that we cannot safely assume the
non-existence of new combinations. Logically speaking, we ought to
leave a place open for animals which ruminate but are without cleft
feet, and for every possible intermediate form of animal, plant, or
mineral. A purely logical classification must take account not only of
what certainly does exist, but of what may in after ages be found to
exist.

I will go a step further, and say that we must have places in our
scientific classifications for purely imaginary existences. A large
proportion of the mathematical functions which are conceivable have no
application to the circumstances of this world. Physicists certainly do
investigate the nature and consequences of forces which nowhere exist.
Newton’s *Principia* is full of such investigations. In one chapter of
his *Mécanique Céleste* Laplace indulges in a remarkable speculation
as to what the laws of motion would have been if momentum, instead of
varying simply as the velocity, had been a more complicated function
of it. I have already mentioned (p. 223) that Airy contemplated the
existence of a world in which the laws of force should be such that
a perpetual motion would be possible, and the Law of Conservation of
Energy would not hold true.

Thought is not bound down to the limits of what is materially existent,
but is circumscribed only by those Fundamental Laws of Identity,
Contradiction and Duality, which were laid down at the outset. This
is the point at which I should differ from Mr. Spencer. He appears
to suppose that a classification is complete if it has a place for
every existing object, and this may perhaps seem to be practically
sufficient; but it is subject to two profound objections. Firstly, we
do not know all that exists, and therefore in limiting our classes we
are erroneously omitting multitudes of objects of unknown form and
nature which may exist either on this earth or in other parts of space.
Secondly, as I have explained, the powers of thought are not limited by
material existences, and we may, or, for some purposes, must imagine
objects which probably do not exist, and if we imagine them we ought to
find places for them in the classifications of science.

The chief difficulty of this subject, however, consists in the fact
that mathematical or other certain laws may entirely forbid the
existence of some combinations. The circle may be defined as a plane
curve of equal curvature, and it is a property of the circle that it
contains the greatest area within the least possible perimeter. May we
then contemplate mentally a circle not a figure of greatest possible
area? Or, to take a still simpler example, a parallelogram possesses
the property of having the opposite angles equal. May we then mentally
divide parallelograms into two classes according as they do or do
not have their opposite angles equal? It might seem absurd to do so,
because we know that one of the two species of parallelogram would be
non-existent. But, then, unless the student had previously contemplated
the existence of both species as possible, what is the meaning of the
thirty-fourth proposition of Euclid’s first book? We cannot deny or
disprove the existence of a certain combination without thereby in a
certain way recognising that combination as an object of thought.

The conclusion at which I arrive is in opposition to that of Mr.
Spencer. I think that whenever we abstract a quality or circumstance we
do generalise or widen the notion from which we abstract. Whatever the
terms A, B, and C may be, I hold that in strict logic AB is mentally
a wider term than ABC, because AB includes the two species ABC and
AB*c*. The term A is wider still, for it includes the four species
ABC, AB*c*, A*b*C, A*bc*. The Logical Alphabet, in short, is the only
limit of the classes of objects which we must contemplate in a purely
logical point of view. Whatever notions be brought before us, we must
mentally combine them in all the ways sanctioned by the laws of thought
and exhibited in the Logical Alphabet, and it is a matter for after
consideration to determine how many of these combinations exist in
outward nature, or how many are actually forbidden by the conditions of
space. A classification is essentially a mental, not a material thing.


*Discovery of Marks or Characteristics.*

Although the chief purpose of classification is to disclose the
deepest and most general resemblances of the objects classified, yet
the practical value of a system will depend partly upon the ease with
which we can refer an object to its proper class, and thus infer
concerning it all that is known generally of that class. This operation
of discovering to which class of a system a certain specimen or case
belongs, is generally called *Diagnosis*, a technical term familiarly
used by physicians, who constantly require to diagnose or determine
the nature of the disease from which a patient is suffering. Now every
class is defined by certain specified qualities or circumstances, the
whole of which are present in every object contained in the class,
and *not all present* in any object excluded from it. These defining
circumstances ought to consist of the deepest and most important
circumstances, by which we vaguely mean those probably forming the
conditions with which the minor circumstances are correlated. But it
will often happen that the so-called important points of an object
are not those which can most readily be observed. Thus the two great
classes of phanerogamous plants are defined respectively by the
possession of two cotyledons or seed-leaves, and one cotyledon. But
when a plant comes to our notice and we want to refer it to the right
class, it will often happen that we have no seed at all to examine, in
order to discover whether there be one seed-leaf or two in the germ.
Even if we have a seed it will often be small, and a careful dissection
under the microscope will be requisite to ascertain the number of
cotyledons. Occasionally the examination of the germ would mislead us,
for the cotyledons may be obsolete, as in Cuscuta, or united together,
as in Clintonia. Botanists therefore seldom actually refer to the
seed for such information. Certain other characters of a plant are
correlated with the number of seed-leaves; thus monocotyledonous plants
almost always possess leaves with parallel veins like those of grass,
while dicotyledonous plants have leaves with reticulated veins like
those of an oak leaf. In monocotyledonous plants, too, the parts of the
flower are most often three or some multiple of three in number, while
in dicotyledonous plants the numbers four and five and their multiples
prevail. Botanists, therefore, by a glance at the leaves and flowers
can almost certainly refer a plant to its right class, and can infer
not only the number of cotyledons which would be found in the seed
or young plant, but also the structure of the stem and other general
characters.

Any conspicuous and easily discriminated property which we thus
select for the purpose of deciding to which class an object belongs,
may be called a *characteristic*. The logical conditions of a good
characteristic mark are very simple, namely, that it should be
possessed by all objects entering into a certain class, and by none
others. Every characteristic should enable us to assert a simple
identity; if A is a characteristic, and B, viewed intensively, the
class of objects of which it is the mark, then A = B ought to be
true. The characteristic may consist either of a single quality or
circumstance, or of a group of such, provided that they all be constant
and easily detected. Thus in the classification of mammals the teeth
are of the greatest assistance, not because a slight variation in the
number and form of the teeth is of importance in the general economy
of the animal, but because such variations are proved by empirical
observation to coincide with most important differences in the general
affinities. It is found that the minor classes and genera of mammals
can be discriminated accurately by their teeth, especially by the
foremost molars and the hindmost pre-molars. Some teeth, indeed, are
occasionally missing, so that zoologists prefer to trust to those
characteristic teeth which are most constant,[580] and to infer from
them not only the arrangement of the other teeth, but the whole
conformation of the animal.

  [580] Owen, *Essay on the Classification and Geographical
  Distribution of the Mammalia*, p. 20.

It is a very difficult matter to mark out a boundary-line between the
animal and vegetable kingdoms, and it may even be doubted whether
a rigorous boundary can be established. The most fundamental and
important difference of a vegetable as compared with an animal
substance probably consists in the absence of nitrogen from the
constituent membranes. Supposing this to be the case, the difficulty
arises that in examining minute organisms we cannot ascertain directly
whether they contain nitrogen or not. Some minor but easily detected
circumstance is therefore needed to discriminate between animals and
vegetables, and this is furnished to some extent by the fact that the
production of starch granules is restricted to the vegetable kingdom.
Thus the Desmidiaceæ may be safely assigned to the vegetable kingdom,
because they contain starch. But we must not employ this characteristic
negatively; the Diatomaceæ are probably vegetables, though they do not
produce starch.


*Diagnostic Systems of Classification.*

We have seen that diagnosis is the process of discovering the place in
any system of classes, to which an object has been referred by some
previous investigation, the object being to avail ourselves of the
information relating to such an object which has been accumulated and
recorded. It is obvious that this is a matter of great importance,
for, unless we can recognise, from time to time, objects or substances
which have been investigated, recorded discoveries would lose their
value. Even a single investigator must have means of recording and
systematising his observations of any large groups of objects like the
vegetable and animal kingdoms.

Now whenever a class has been properly formed, a definition must have
been laid down, stating the qualities and circumstances possessed by
all the objects which are intended to be included in the class, and
not possessed *completely* by any other objects. Diagnosis, therefore,
consists in comparing the qualities of a certain object with the
definitions of a series of classes; the absence in the object of any
one quality stated in the definition excludes it from the class thus
defined; whereas, if we find every point of a definition exactly
fulfilled in the specimen, we may at once assign it to the class in
question. It is of course by no means certain that everything which has
been affirmed of a class is true of all objects afterwards referred
to the class; for this would be a case of imperfect inference, which
is never more than matter of probability. A definition can only make
known a finite number of the qualities of an object, and it always
remains possible that objects agreeing in those assigned qualities will
differ in others. *An individual cannot be defined*, and can only be
made known by the exhibition of the individual itself, or by a material
specimen exactly representing it. But this and other questions relating
to definition must be treated when I am able to take up the subject of
language in another work.

Diagnostic systems of classification should, as a general rule, be
arranged on the bifurcate method explicitly. Any quality may be chosen
which divides the whole group of objects into two distinct parts,
and each part may be sub-divided successively by any prominent and
well-marked circumstance which is present in a large part of the genus
and not in the other. To refer an object to its proper place in such an
arrangement we have only to note whether it does or does not possess
the successive critical differentiæ. Dana devised a classification of
this kind[581] by which to refer a crystal to its place in the series
of six or seven classes already described. If a crystal has all its
edges modified alike or the angles replaced by three or six similar
planes, it belongs to the monometric system; if not, we observe
whether the number of similar planes at the extremity of the crystal
is three or some multiple of three, in which case it is a crystal
of the hexagonal system; and so we proceed with further successive
discriminations. To ascertain the name of a mineral by examination with
the blow-pipe, an arrangement more or less evidently on the bifurcate
plan, has been laid down by Von Kobell.[582] Minerals are divided
according as they possess or do not possess metallic lustre; as they
are fusible or not fusible, according as they do or do not on charcoal
give a metallic bead, and so on.

  [581] Dana’s *Mineralogy*, vol. i. p. 123; quoted in Watts’
  *Dictionary of Chemistry*, vol. ii. p. 166.

  [582] *Instructions for the Discrimination of Minerals by Simple
  Chemical Experiments*, by Franz von Kobell, translated from the
  German by R. C. Campbell. Glasgow, 1841.

Perhaps the best example to be found of an arrangement devised simply
for the purpose of diagnosis, is Mr. George Bentham’s *Analytical Key
to the Natural Orders and Anomalous Genera of the British Flora*, given
in his *Handbook of the British Flora*.[583] In this scheme, the great
composite family of plants, together with the closely approximate
genus Jasione, are first separated from all other flowering plants
by the compound character of their flowers. The remaining plants are
sub-divided according as the perianth is double or single. Since no
plants are yet known in which the perianth can be said to have three
or more distinct rings, this division becomes practically the same as
one into double and not-double. Flowers with a double perianth are
next discriminated according as the corolla does or does not consist
of one piece; according as the ovary is free or not free; as it is
simple or not simple; as the corolla is regular or irregular; and so
on. On looking over this arrangement, it will be found that numerical
discriminations often occur, the numbers of petals, stamens, capsules,
or other parts being the criteria, in which cases, as already explained
(p. 697), the actual exhibition of the bifid division would be tedious.

  [583] Edition of 1866, p. lxiii.

Linnæus appears to have been perfectly acquainted with the nature and
uses of diagnostic classification, which he describes under the name
of Synopsis, saying:[584]--“Synopsis tradit Divisiones arbitrarias,
longiores aut breviores, plures aut pauciores: a Botanicis in genere
non agnoscenda. Synopsis est dichotomia arbitraria, quæ instar viæ ad
Botanicem ducit. Limites autem non determinat.”

  [584] *Philosophia Botanica* (1770), § 154, p. 98.

The rules and tables drawn out by chemists to facilitate the discovery
of the nature of a substance in qualitative analysis are usually
arranged on the bifurcate method, and form excellent examples of
diagnostic classification, the qualities of the substances produced
in testing being in most cases merely characteristic properties of
little importance in other respects. The chemist does not detect
potassium by reducing it to the state of metallic potassium, and
then observing whether it has all the principal qualities belonging
to potassium. He selects from among the whole number of compounds of
potassium that salt, namely the compound of platinum tetra-chloride,
and potassium chloride, which has the most distinctive appearance,
as it is comparatively insoluble and produces a peculiar yellow and
highly crystalline precipitate. Accordingly, potassium is present
whenever this precipitate can be produced by adding platinum chloride
to a solution. The fine purple or violet colour which potassium
salts communicate to the blowpipe flame, had long been used as a
characteristic mark. Some other elements were readily detected by the
colouring of the blowpipe flame, barium giving a pale yellowish green,
and salts of strontium a bright red. By the use of the spectroscope
the coloured light given off by an incandescent vapour is made to give
perfectly characteristic marks of the elements contained in the vapour.

Diagnosis seems to be identical with the process termed by the ancient
logicians *abscissio infiniti*, the cutting off of the infinite or
negative part of a genus when we discover by observation that an
object possesses a particular difference. At every step in a bifurcate
division, some objects possessing the difference will fall into
the affirmative part or species; all the remaining objects in the
world fall into the negative part, which will be infinite in extent.
Diagnosis consists in the successive rejection from further notice of
those infinite classes with which the specimen in question does not
agree.


*Index Classifications.*

Under classification we may include all arrangements of objects or
names, which we make for saving labour in the discovery of an object.
Even alphabetical indices are real classifications. No such arrangement
can be of use unless it involves some correlation of circumstances, so
that knowing one thing we learn another. If we merely arrange letters
in the pigeon-holes of a secretaire we establish a correlation, for all
letters in the first hole will be written by persons, for instance,
whose names begin with A, and so on. Knowing then the initial letter of
the writer’s name, we know also the place of the letter, and the labour
of search is thus reduced to one twenty-sixth part of what it would be
without arrangement.

Now the purpose of a catalogue is to discover the place in which an
object is to be found; but the art of cataloguing involves logical
considerations of some importance. We want to establish a correlation
between the place of an object and some circumstance about the object
which shall enable us readily to refer to it; this circumstance
therefore should be that which will most readily dwell in the memory
of the searcher. A piece of poetry will be best remembered by the
first line of the piece, and the name of the author will be the next
most definite circumstance; a catalogue of poetry should therefore be
arranged alphabetically according to the first word of the piece, or
the name of the author, or, still better, in both ways. It would be
impossible to arrange poems according to their subjects, so vague and
mixed are these found to be when the attempt is made.

It is a matter of considerable literary importance to decide upon the
best mode of cataloguing books, so that any required book in a library
shall be most readily found. Books may be classified in a great number
of ways, according to subject, language, date, or place of publication,
size, the initial words of the text or title-page, or colophon, the
author’s name, the publisher’s name, the printer’s name, the character
of the type, and so on. Every one of these modes of arrangement may be
useful, for we may happen to remember one circumstance about a book
when we have forgotten all others; but as we cannot usually go to the
expense of forming more than two or three indices, we must select
those circumstances which will lead to the discovery of a book most
frequently. Many of the criteria mentioned are evidently inapplicable.

The language in which a book is written is definite enough, provided
that the whole book is written in the same language; but it is obvious
that language gives no means for the subdivision and arrangement of
the literature of any one people. Classification by subjects would be
an exceedingly useful method if it were practicable, but experience
shows it to be a logical absurdity. It is a very difficult matter to
classify the sciences, so complicated are the relations between them.
But with books the complication is vastly greater, since the same book
may treat of different sciences, or it may discuss a problem involving
many branches of knowledge. A good account of the steam-engine will be
antiquarian, so far as it traces out the earliest efforts at discovery;
purely scientific, as regards the principles of thermodynamics
involved; technical, as regards the mechanical means of applying
those principles; economical, as regards the industrial results of
the invention; biographical, as regards the lives of the inventors.
A history of Westminster Abbey might belong either to the history of
architecture, the history of the Church, or the history of England.
If we abandon the attempt to carry out an arrangement according to
the natural classification of the sciences, and form comprehensive
practical groups, we shall be continually perplexed by the occurrence
of intermediate cases, and opinions will differ *ad infinitum* as to
the details. If, to avoid the difficulty about Westminster Abbey, we
form a class of books devoted to the History of Buildings, the question
will then arise whether Stonehenge is a building, and if so, whether
cromlechs, mounds, and monoliths are so. We shall be uncertain whether
to include lighthouses, monuments, bridges, &c. In regard to literary
works, rigorous classification is still less possible. The same work
may partake of the nature of poetry, biography, history, philosophy,
or if we form a comprehensive class of Belles-lettres, nobody can say
exactly what does or does not come under the term.

My own experience entirely bears out the opinion of De Morgan, that
classification according to the name of the author is the only one
practicable in a large library, and this method has been admirably
carried out in the great catalogue of the British Museum. The name
of the author is the most precise circumstance concerning a book,
which usually dwells in the memory. It is a better characteristic of
the book than anything else. In an alphabetical arrangement we have
an exhaustive classification, including a place for every name. The
following remarks[585] of De Morgan seem therefore to be entirely
correct. “From much, almost daily use, of catalogues for many years,
I am perfectly satisfied that a classed catalogue is more difficult
to use than to make. It is one man’s theory of the subdivision of
knowledge, and the chances are against its suiting any other man. Even
if all doubtful works were entered under several different heads, the
frontier of the dubious region would itself be a mere matter of doubt.
I never turn from a classed catalogue to an alphabetical one without
a feeling of relief and security. With the latter I can always, by
taking proper pains, make a library yield its utmost; with the former
I can never be satisfied that I have taken proper pains, until I have
made it, in fact, as many different catalogues as there are different
headings, with separate trouble for each. Those to whom bibliographical
research is familiar, know that they have much more frequently to
hunt an author than a subject: they know also that in searching for a
subject, it is never safe to take another person’s view, however good,
of the limits of that subject with reference to their own particular
purposes.”

  [585] *Philosophical Magazine*, 3rd Series (1845), vol. xxvi. p. 522.
  See also De Morgan’s evidence before the Royal Commission on the
  British Museum in 1849, Report (1850), Questions, 5704*-5815*,
  6481–6513. This evidence should be studied by every person who wishes
  to understand the elements of Bibliography.

It is often desirable, however, that a name catalogue should be
accompanied by a subordinate subject catalogue, but in this case
no attempt should be made to devise a theoretically complete
classification. Every principal subject treated in a book should
be entered separately in an alphabetical list, under the name most
likely to occur to the searcher, or under several names. This method
was partially carried out in Watts’ *Bibliotheca Britannica*, but
it was excellently applied in the admirable subject index to the
*British Catalogue of Books*, and equally well in the *Catalogue
of the Manchester Free Library* at Campfield, drawn up under the
direction of Mr. Crestadoro, this latter being the most perfect model
of a printed catalogue with which I am acquainted. The Catalogue of
the London Library is also in the right form, and has a useful index
of subjects, though it is too much condensed and abbreviated. The
public catalogue of the British Museum is arranged as far as possible
according to the alphabetical order of the authors’ names, but in
writing the titles for this catalogue several copies are simultaneously
produced by a manifold writer, so that a catalogue according to the
order of the books on the shelves, and another according to the first
words of the title-page, are created by a mere rearrangement of the
spare copies. In the *English Cyclopædia* it is suggested that twenty
copies of the book titles might readily have been utilised in forming
additional catalogues, arranged according to the place of publication,
the language of the book, the general nature of the subject, and so
forth.[586] An excellent suggestion has also been made to the effect
that each book when published should have a fly-leaf containing half
a dozen printed copies of the title, drawn up in a form suitable for
insertion in catalogues. Every owner of a library could then easily
make accurate printed catalogues to suit his own purposes, by merely
cutting out these titles and pasting them in books in any desirable
order.

  [586] *English Cyclopædia, Arts and Sciences*, vol. v. p. 233.

It will hardly be a digression to point out the enormous saving of
labour, or, what comes to the same thing, the enormous increase in our
available knowledge, both literary and scientific, which arises from
the formation of extensive indices. The “State Papers,” containing
the whole history of the nation, were practically sealed to literary
inquirers until the Government undertook the task of calendaring and
indexing them. The British Museum Catalogue is another national work,
of which the importance in advancing knowledge cannot be overrated.
The Royal Society is doing great service in publishing a complete
catalogue of memoirs upon physical science. The time will perhaps
come when our views upon this subject will be extended, and either
Government or some public society will undertake the systematic
cataloguing and indexing of masses of historical and scientific
information which are now almost closed against inquiry.


*Classification in the Biological Sciences.*

The great generalisations established in the works of Herbert Spencer
and Charles Darwin have thrown much light upon other sciences, and
have removed several difficulties out of the way of the logician. The
subject of classification has long been studied in almost exclusive
reference to the arrangement of animals and plants. Systematic botany
and zoology have been commonly known as the Classificatory Sciences,
and scientific men seemed to suppose that the methods of arrangement,
which were suitable for living creatures, must be the best for all
other classes of objects. Several mineralogists, especially Mohs, have
attempted to arrange minerals in genera and species, just as if they
had been animals capable of reproducing their kind with variations.
This confusion of ideas between the relationship of living forms and
the logical relationship of things in general prevailed from the
earliest times, as manifested in the etymology of words. We familiarly
speak of a *kind* of things meaning a class of things, and the kind
consists of those things which are *akin*, or come of the same race.
When Socrates and his followers wanted a name for a class regarded in a
philosophical light, they adopted the analogy in question, and called
it a γένος, or race, the root γεν- being connected with the notion of
generation.

So long as species of plants and animals were believed to proceed from
distinct acts of Creation, there was no apparent reason why methods of
classification suitable to them should not be treated as a guide to
the classification of other objects generally. But when once we regard
these resemblances as hereditary in their origin, we see that the
sciences of systematic botany and zoology have a special character of
their own. There is no reason to suppose that the same kind of natural
classification which is best in biology will apply also in mineralogy,
in chemistry, or in astronomy. The logical principles which underlie
all classification are of course the same in natural history as in the
sciences of lifeless matter, but the special resemblances which arise
from the relation of parent and offspring will not be found to prevail
between different kinds of crystals or mineral bodies.

The genealogical view of the relations of animals and plants leads us
to discard all notions of a regular progression of living forms, or
any theory as to their symmetrical relations. It was at one time a
question whether the ultimate scheme of natural classification would
lead to arrangement in a simple line, or a circle, or a combination
of circles. Macleay’s once celebrated system was a circular one, and
each class-circle was composed of five order-circles, each of which was
composed again of five tribe-circles, and so on, the subdivision being
at each step into five minor circles. Macleay held that in the animal
kingdom there are five sub-kingdoms--the Vertebrata, Annulosa, Radiata,
Acrita, and Mollusca. Each of these was again divided into five--the
Vertebrata, consisting of Mammalia, Reptilia, Pisces, Amphibia, and
Aves.[587] It is evident that in such a symmetrical system the animals
were made to suit themselves to the classes instead of the classes
being suited to the animals.

  [587] Swainson, “Treatise on the Geography and Classification of
  Animals,” *Cabinet Cyclopædia*, p. 201.

We now perceive that the ultimate system will have the form of an
immensely extended genealogical tree, which will be capable of
representation by lines on a plane surface of sufficient extent.
Strictly speaking, this genealogical tree ought to represent the
descent of each individual living form now existing or which has
existed. It should be as personal and minute in its detail of
relations, as the Stemma of the Kings of England. We must not assume
that any two forms are exactly alike, and in any case they are
numerically distinct. Every parent then must be represented at the apex
of a series of divergent lines, representing the generation of so many
children. Any complete system of classification must regard individuals
as the infimæ species. But as in the lower races of animals and
plants the differences between individuals are slight and apparently
unimportant, while the numbers of such individuals are immensely
great, beyond all possibility of separate treatment, scientific men
have always stopped at some convenient but arbitrary point, and have
assumed that forms so closely resembling each other as to present no
constant difference were all of one kind. They have, in short, fixed
their attention entirely upon the main features of family difference.
In the genealogical tree which they have been unconsciously aiming to
construct, diverging lines meant races diverging in character, and the
purpose of all efforts at so-called natural classification was to trace
out the descents between existing groups of plants or animals.

Now it is evident that hereditary descent may have in different
cases produced very different results as regards the problem of
classification. In some cases the differentiation of characters may
have been very frequent, and specimens of all the characters produced
may have been transmitted to the present time. A living form will then
have, as it were, an almost infinite number of cousins of various
degrees, and there will be an immense number of forms finely graduated
in their resemblances. Exact and distinct classification will then
be almost impossible, and the wisest course will be not to attempt
arbitrarily to distinguish forms closely related in nature, but to
allow that there exist transitional forms of every degree, to mark
out if possible the extreme limits of the family relationship, and
perhaps to select the most generalised form, or that which presents the
greatest number of close resemblances to others of the family, as the
*type* of the whole.

Mr. Darwin, in his most interesting work upon Orchids, points out
that the tribe of Malaxeæ are distinguished from Epidendreæ by the
absence of a caudicle to the pollinia; but as some of the Malaxeæ
have a minute caudicle, the division really breaks down in the most
essential point. “This is a misfortune,” he remarks,[588] “which every
naturalist encounters in attempting to classify a largely developed
or so-called natural group, in which, relatively to other groups,
there has been little extinction. In order that the naturalist may be
enabled to give precise and clear definitions of his divisions, whole
ranks of intermediate or gradational forms must have been utterly swept
away: if here and there a member of the intermediate ranks has escaped
annihilation, it puts an effectual bar to any absolutely distinct
definition.”

  [588] Darwin, *Fertilisation of Orchids*, p. 159.

In other cases a particular plant or animal may perhaps have
transmitted its form from generation to generation almost unchanged,
or, what comes to the same result, those forms which diverged in
character from the parent stock may have proved unsuitable to their
circumstances, and perished. We shall then find a particular form
standing apart from all others, and marked by many distinct characters.
Occasionally we may meet with specimens of a race which was formerly
far more common but is now undergoing extinction, and is nearly the
last of its kind. Thus we explain the occurrence of exceptional forms
such as are found in the Amphioxus. The Equisetaceæ perplex botanists
by their want of affinity to other orders of Acrogenous plants. This
doubtless indicates that their genealogical connection with other
plants must be sought for in the most distant ages of geological
development.

Constancy of character, as Mr. Darwin has said,[589] is what is chiefly
valued and sought after by naturalists; that is to say, naturalists
wish to find some distinct family mark, or group of characters, by
which they may clearly recognise the relationship of descent between a
large group of living forms. It is accordingly a great relief to the
mind of the naturalist when he comes upon a definitely marked group,
such as the Diatomaceæ, which are clearly separated from their nearest
neighbours the Desmidiaceæ by their siliceous framework and the absence
of chlorophyll. But we must no longer think that because we fail in
detecting constancy of character the fault is in our classificatory
sciences. Where gradation of character really exists, we must devote
ourselves to defining and registering the degrees and limits of that
gradation. The ultimate natural arrangement will often be devoid of
strong lines of demarcation.

  [589] *Descent of Man*, vol. i. p. 214.

Let naturalists, too, form their systems of natural classification
with all care they can, yet it will certainly happen from time to
time that new and exceptional forms of animals or vegetables will be
discovered and will require the modification of the system. A natural
system is directed, as we have seen, to the discovery of empirical laws
of correlation, but these laws being purely empirical will frequently
be falsified by more extensive investigation. From time to time the
notions of naturalists have been greatly widened, especially in the
case of Australian animals and plants, by the discovery of unexpected
combinations of organs, and such events must often happen in the
future. If indeed the time shall come when all the forms of plants are
discovered and accurately described, the science of Systematic Botany
will then be placed in a new and more favourable position, as remarked
by Alphonse Decandolle.[590]

  [590] *Laws of Botanical Nomenclature*, p. 16.

It ought to be remembered that though the genealogical classification
of plants or animals is doubtless the most instructive of all, it is
not necessarily the best for all purposes. There may be correlations
of properties important for medicinal, or other practical purposes,
which do not correspond to the correlations of descent. We must regard
the bamboo as a tree rather than a grass, although it is botanically
a grass. For legal purposes we may continue with advantage to treat
the whale, seal, and other cetaceæ, as fish. We must also class plants
according as they belong to arctic, alpine, temperate, sub-tropical or
tropical regions. There are causes of likeness apart from hereditary
relationship, and *we must not attribute exclusive excellence to any
one method of classification*.


*Classification by Types.*

Perplexed by the difficulties arising in natural history from the
discovery of intermediate forms, naturalists have resorted to what they
call classification by types. Instead of forming one distinct class
defined by the invariable possession of certain assigned properties,
and rigidly including or excluding objects according as they do or
do not possess all these properties, naturalists select a typical
specimen, and they group around it all other specimens which resemble
this type more than any other selected type. “The type of each genus,”
we are told,[591] “should be that species in which the characters
of its group are best exhibited and most evenly balanced.” It would
usually consist of those descendants of a form which had undergone
little alteration, while other descendants had suffered slight
differentiation in various directions.

  [591] Waterhouse, quoted by Woodward in his *Rudimentary Treatise of
  Recent and Fossil Shells*, p. 61.

It would be a great mistake to suppose that this classification by
types is a logically distinct method. It is either not a real method
of classification at all, or it is merely an abbreviated mode of
representing a complicated system of arrangement. A class must be
defined by the invariable presence of certain common properties. If,
then, we include an individual in which one of these properties does
not appear, we either fall into logical contradiction, or else we form
a new class with a new definition. Even a single exception constitutes
a new class by itself, and by calling it an exception we merely imply
that this new class closely resembles that from which it diverges in
one or two points only. Thus in the definition of the natural order
of Rosaceæ, we find that the seeds are one or two in each carpel, but
that in the genus Spiræa there are three or four; this must mean either
that the number of seeds is not a part of the fixed definition of the
class, or else that Spiræa does not belong to that class, though it
may closely approximate to it. Naturalists continually find themselves
between two horns of a dilemma; if they restrict the number of marks
specified in a definition so that every form intended to come within
the class shall possess all those marks, it will then be usually found
to include too many forms; if the definition be made more particular,
the result is to produce so-called anomalous genera, which, while they
are held to belong to the class, do not in all respects conform to its
definition. The practice has hence arisen of allowing considerable
latitude in the definition of natural orders. The family of Cruciferæ,
for instance, forms an exceedingly well-marked natural order, and among
its characters we find it specified that the fruit is a pod, divided
into two cells by a thin partition, from which the valves generally
separate at maturity; but we are also informed that, in a few genera,
the pod is one-celled, or indehiscent, or separates transversely into
several joints.[592] Now this must either mean that the formation of
the pod is not an essential point in the definition of the family, or
that there are several closely associated families.

  [592] Bentham’s *Handbook of the British Flora* (1866), p. 25.

The same holds true of typical classification. The type itself is
an individual, not a class, and no other object can be exactly like
the type. But as soon as we abstract the individual peculiarities
of the type and thus specify a finite number of qualities in which
other objects may resemble the type, we immediately constitute
a class. If some objects resemble the type in some points, and
others in other points, then each definite collection of points of
resemblance constitutes intensively a separate class. The very notion
of classification by types is in fact erroneous in a logical point of
view. The naturalist is constantly occupied in endeavouring to mark
out definite groups of living forms, where the forms themselves do not
in many cases admit of such rigorous lines of demarcation. A certain
laxity of logical method is thus apt to creep in, the only remedy for
which will be the frank recognition of the fact, that, according to the
theory of hereditary descent, gradation of characters is probably the
rule, and precise demarcation between groups the exception.


*Natural Genera and Species.*

One important result of the establishment of the theory of evolution
is to explode all notions about natural groups constituting separate
creations. Naturalists long held that every plant belongs to some
species, marked out by invariable characters, which do not change by
difference of soil, climate, cross-breeding, or other circumstances.
They were unable to deny the existence of such things as sub-species,
varieties, and hybrids, so that a species of plants was often
subdivided and classified within itself. But then the differences upon
which this sub-classification depended were supposed to be variable,
and thus distinguished from the invariable characters imposed upon the
whole species at its creation. Similarly a natural genus was a group of
species, and was marked out from other genera by eternal differences of
still greater importance.

We now, however, perceive that the existence of any such groups as
genera and species is an arbitrary creation of the naturalist’s
mind. All resemblances of plants are natural so far as they express
hereditary affinities; but this applies as well to the variations
within the species as to the species itself, or to the larger groups.
All is a matter of degree. The deeper differences between plants have
been produced by the differentiating action of circumstances during
millions of years, so that it would naturally require millions of
years to undo this result, and prove experimentally that the forms can
be approximated again. Sub-species may sometimes have arisen within
historical times, and varieties approaching to sub-species may often
be produced by the horticulturist in a few years. Such varieties can
easily be brought back to their original forms, or, if placed in the
original circumstances, will themselves revert to those forms; but
according to Darwin’s views all forms are capable of unlimited change,
and it might possibly be, unlimited reversion if suitable circumstances
and sufficient time be granted.

Many fruitless attempts have been made to establish a rigorous
criterion of specific and generic difference, so that these classes
might have a definite value and rank in all branches of biology.
Linnæus adopted the view that the species was to be defined as a
distinct creation, saying,[593] “Species tot numeramus, quot diversæ
formæ in principio sunt creatæ;” or again, “Species tot sunt, quot
diversas formas ab initio produxit Infinitum Ens; quæ formæ, secundum
generationis inditas leges, produxere plures, at sibi semper similes.”
Of genera he also says,[594] “Genus omne est naturale, in primordio
tale creatum.” It was a common doctrine added to and essential to that
of distinct creation that these species could not produce intermediate
and variable forms, so that we find Linnæus obliged by the ascertained
existence of hybrids to take a different view in another work; he
says,[595] “Novas species immo et genera ex copula diversarum specierum
in regno vegetabilium oriri primo intuitu paradoxum videtur; interim
observationes sic fieri non ita dissuadent.” Even supposing in the
present day that we could assent to the notion of a certain number of
distinct creational acts, this notion would not help us in the theory
of classification. Naturalists have never pointed out any method of
deciding what are the results of distinct creations, and what are
not. As Darwin says,[596] “the definition must not include an element
which cannot possibly be ascertained, such as an act of creation.”
It is, in fact, by investigation of forms and classification that we
should ascertain what were distinct creations and what were not; this
information would be a result and not a means of classification.

  [593] *Philosophia Botanica* (1770), § 157, p. 99.

  [594] *Ibid.* § 159, p. 100.

  [595] *Amœnitates Academicæ* (1744), vol. i. p. 70. Quoted in
  *Edinburgh Review*, October 1868, vol. cxxviii. pp. 416, 417.

  [596] *Descent of Man*, vol. i. p. 228.

Agassiz seemed to consider that he had discovered an important
principle, to the effect that general plan or structure is the true
ground for the discrimination of the great classes of animals, which
may be called branches of the animal kingdom.[597] He also thought that
genera are definite and natural groups. “Genera,” he says,[598] “are
most closely allied groups of animals, differing neither in form, nor
in complication of structure, but simply in the ultimate structural
peculiarities of some of their parts; and this is, I believe, the best
definition which can be given of genera.” But it is surely apparent
that there are endless degrees both of structural peculiarity and of
complication of structure. It is impossible to define the amount of
structural peculiarity which constitutes the genus as distinguished
from the species.

  [597] Agassiz, *Essay on Classification*, p. 219.

  [598] *Ibid.* p. 249.

The form which any classification of plants or animals tends to take is
that of an unlimited series of subaltern classes. Originally botanists
confined themselves for the most part to a small number of such
classes. Linnæus adopted Class, Order, Genus, Species, and Variety, and
even seemed to think that there was something essentially natural in a
five-fold arrangement of groups.[599]

  [599] *Philosophia Botanica*, § 155, p. 98.

With the progress of botany intermediate and additional groups
have gradually been introduced. According to the Laws of Botanical
Nomenclature adopted by the International Botanical Congress, held at
Paris[600] in August 1867, no less than twenty-one names of classes
are recognised--namely, Kingdom, Division, Sub-division, Class,
Sub-class, Cohort, Sub-cohort, Order, Sub-order, Tribe, Sub-tribe,
Genus, Sub-genus, Section, Sub-section, Species, Sub-species, Variety,
Sub-variety, Variation, Sub-variation. It is allowed by the authors of
this scheme, that the rank or degree of importance to be attributed
to any of these divisions may vary in a certain degree according to
individual opinion. The only point on which botanists are not allowed
discretion is as to the order of the successive sub-divisions; any
inversion of the arrangement, such as division of a genus into tribes,
or of a tribe into orders, is quite inadmissible. There is no reason
to suppose that even the above list is complete and inextensible. The
Botanical Congress itself recognised the distinction between variations
according as they are Seedlings, Half-breeds, or *Lusus Naturæ*.
The complication of the inferior classes is increased again by the
existence of *hybrids*, arising from the fertilisation of one species
by another deemed a distinct species, nor can we place any limit to the
minuteness of discrimination of degrees of breeding short of an actual
pedigree of individuals.

  [600] *Laws of Botanical Nomenclature*, by Alphonse Decandolle,
  translated from the French, 1868, p. 19.

It will be evident to the reader that in the remarks upon
classification as applied to the Natural Sciences, given in this
and the preceding sections, I have not in the least attempted to
treat the subject in a manner adequate to its extent and importance.
A volume would be insufficient for tracing out the principles of
scientific method specially applicable to these branches of science.
What more I may be able to say upon the subject will be better said,
if ever, when I am able to take up the closely-connected subjects of
Scientific Nomenclature, Terminology, and Descriptive Representation.
In the meantime, I have wished to show, in a negative point of
view, that natural classification in the animal and vegetable
kingdoms is a special problem, and that the particular methods and
difficulties to which it gives rise are not those common to all cases
of classification, as so many physicists have supposed. Genealogical
resemblances are only a special case of resemblances in general.


*Unique or Exceptional Objects.*

In framing a system of classification in almost any branch of science,
we must expect to meet with unique or peculiar objects, which stand
alone, having comparatively few analogies with other objects. They may
also be said to be *sui generis*, each unique object forming, as it
were, a genus by itself; or they are called *nondescript*, because from
thus standing apart it is difficult to find terms in which to describe
their properties. The rings of Saturn, for instance, form a unique
object among the celestial bodies. We have indeed considered this and
many other instances of unique objects in the preceding chapter on
Exceptional Phenomena. Apparent, Singular, and Divergent Exceptions
especially, are analogous to unique objects.

In the classification of the elements, Carbon stands apart as a
substance entirely unique in its powers of producing compounds. It is
considered to be a quadrivalent element, and it obeys all the ordinary
laws of chemical combination. Yet it manifests powers of affinity in
such an exalted degree that the substances in which it appears are
more numerous than all the other compounds known to chemists. Almost
the whole of the substances which have been called organic contain
carbon, and are probably held together by the carbon atoms, so that
many chemists are now inclined to abandon the name Organic Chemistry,
and substitute the name Chemistry of the Carbon Compounds. It used to
be believed that the production of organic compounds could be effected
only by the action of vital force, or of some inexplicable cause
involved in the phenomena of life; but it is now found that chemists
are able to commence with the elementary materials, pure carbon,
hydrogen, and oxygen, and by strictly chemical operations to combine
these so as to form complicated organic compounds. So many substances
have already been formed that we might be inclined to generalise and
infer that all organic compounds might ultimately be produced without
the agency of living beings. Thus the distinction between the organic
and the inorganic kingdoms seems to be breaking down, but our wonder at
the peculiar powers of carbon must increase at the same time.

In considering generalisation, the law of continuity was applied
chiefly to physical properties capable of mathematical treatment. But
in the classificatory sciences, also, the same important principle
is often beautifully exemplified. Many objects or events seem to be
entirely exceptional and abnormal, and in regard to degree or magnitude
they may be so termed; but it is often easy to show that they are
connected by intermediate links with ordinary cases. In the organic
kingdoms there is a common groundwork of similarity running through
all classes, but particular actions and processes present themselves
conspicuously in particular families and classes. Tenacity of life
is most marked in the Rotifera, and some other kinds of microscopic
organisms, which can be dried and boiled without loss of life. Reptiles
are distinguished by torpidity, and the length of time they can live
without food. Birds, on the contrary, exhibit ceaseless activity and
high muscular power. The ant is as conspicuous for intelligence and
size of brain among insects as the quadrumana and man among vertebrata.
Among plants the Leguminosæ are distinguished by a tendency to sleep,
folding their leaves at the approach of night. In the genus Mimosa,
especially the Mimosa pudica, commonly called the sensitive plant,
the same tendency is magnified into an extreme irritability, almost
resembling voluntary motion. More or less of the same irritability
probably belongs to vegetable forms of every kind, but it is of course
to be investigated with special ease in such an extreme case. In the
Gymnotus and Torpedo, we find that organic structures can act like
galvanic batteries. Are we to suppose that such animals are entirely
anomalous exceptions; or may we not justly expect to find less intense
manifestations of electric action in all animals?

Some extraordinary differences between the modes of reproduction
of animals have been shown to be far less than was at first sight
apparent. The lower animals seem to differ entirely from the higher
ones in the power of reproducing lost limbs. A kind of crab has the
habit of casting portions of its claws when much frightened, but
they soon grow again. There are multitudes of smaller animals which,
like the Hydra, may be cut in two and yet live and develop into new
complete individuals. No mammalian animal can reproduce a limb, and
in appearance there is no analogy. But it was suggested by Blumenbach
that the healing of a wound in the higher animals really represents in
a lower degree the power of reproducing a limb. That this is true may
be shown by adducing a multitude of intermediate cases, each adjoining
pair of which are clearly analogous, so that we pass gradually from one
extreme to the other. Darwin holds, moreover, that any such restoration
of parts is closely connected with that perpetual replacement of
the particles which causes every organised body to be after a time
entirely new as regards its constituent substance. In short, we
approach to a great generalisation under which all the phenomena of
growth, restoration, and maintenance of organs are effects of one and
the same power.[601] It is perhaps still more surprising to find that
the complicated process of reproduction in the higher animals may be
gradually traced down to a simpler and simpler form, which at last
becomes undistinguishable from the budding out of one plant from the
stem of another. By a great generalisation we may regard all the modes
of reproduction of organic life as alike in their nature, and varying
only in complexity of development.[602]

  [601] Darwin, *The Variation of Animals and Plants*, vol. ii.
  pp. 293, 359, &c.; quoting Paget, *Lectures on Pathology*, 1853,
  pp. 152, 164.

  [602] *Ibid.* vol. ii. p. 372.


*Limits of Classification.*

Science can extend only so far as the power of accurate classification
extends. If we cannot detect resemblances, and assign their exact
character and amount, we cannot have that generalised knowledge which
constitutes science; we cannot infer from case to case. Classification
is the opposite process to discrimination. If we feel that two tastes
differ, the tastes of two kinds of wine for instance, the mere fact of
difference existing prevents inference. The detection of the difference
saves us, indeed, from false inference, because so far as difference
exists, inference is impossible. But classification consists in
detecting resemblances of all degrees of generality, and ascertaining
exactly how far such resemblances extend, while assigning precisely the
points at which difference begins. It enables us, then, to generalise,
and make inferences where it is possible, and it saves us at the same
time from going too far. A full classification constitutes a complete
record of all our knowledge of the objects or events classified,
and the limits of exact knowledge are identical with the limits of
classification.

It must by no means be supposed that every group of natural objects
will be found capable of rigorous classification. There may be
substances which vary by insensible degrees, consisting, for instance,
in varying mixtures of simpler substances. Granite is a mixture of
quartz, felspar, and mica, but there are hardly two specimens in which
the proportions of these three constituents are alike, and it would
be impossible to lay down definitions of distinct species of granite
without finding an infinite variety of intermediate species. The
only true classification of granites, then, would be founded on the
proportions of the constituents present, and a chemical or microscopic
analysis would be requisite, in order that we might assign a specimen
to its true position in the series. Granites vary, again, by insensible
degrees, as regards the magnitude of the crystals of felspar and mica.
Precisely similar remarks might be made concerning the classification
of other plutonic rocks, such as syenite, basalt, pumice-stone, lava.

The nature of a ray of homogeneous light is strictly defined, either
by its place in the spectrum or by the corresponding wave-length, but
a ray of mixed light admits of no simple classification; any of the
infinitely numerous rays of the continuous spectrum may be present or
absent, or present in various intensities, so that we can only class
and define a mixed colour by defining the intensity and wave-length
of each ray of homogeneous light which is present in it. Complete
spectroscopic analysis and the determination of the intensity of
every part of the spectrum yielded by a mixed ray is requisite for
its accurate classification. Nearly the same may be said of complex
sounds. A simple sound undulation, if we could meet with such a sound,
would admit of precise and exhaustive classification as regards pitch,
the length of wave, or the number of waves reaching the ear per
second being a sufficient criterion. But almost all ordinary sounds,
even those of musical instruments, consist of complex aggregates of
undulations of different pitches, and in order to classify the sound
we should have to measure the intensities of each of the constituent
sounds, a work which has been partially accomplished by Helmholtz, as
regards the vowel sounds. The different tones of voice distinctive
of different individuals must also be due to the intermixture of
minute waves of various pitch, which are yet quite beyond the range
of experimental investigation. We cannot, then, at present attempt to
classify the different kinds or *timbres* of sound.

The difficulties of classification are still greater when a varying
phenomenon cannot be shown to be a mixture of simpler phenomena. If
we attempt to classify tastes, we may rudely group them according as
they are sweet, bitter, saline, alkaline, acid, astringent or fiery;
but it is evident that these groups are bounded by no sharp lines
of definition. Tastes of mixed or intermediate character may exist
almost *ad infinitum*, and what is still more troublesome, the tastes
clearly united within one class may differ more or less from each
other, without our being able to arrange them in subordinate genera and
species. The same remarks may be made concerning the classification of
odours, which may be roughly grouped according to the arrangement of
Linnæus as, aromatic, fragrant, ambrosiac, alliaceous, fetid, virulent,
nauseous. Within each of these vague classes, however, there would be
infinite shades of variety, and each class would graduate into other
classes. The odours which can be discriminated by an acute nose are
infinite; every rock, stone, plant, or animal has some slight smell,
and it is well known that dogs, or even blind men, can discriminate
persons by a slight distinctive odour which usually passes unnoticed.

Similar remarks may be made concerning the feelings of the human mind,
called emotions. We know what is anger, grief, fear, hatred, love;
and many systems for classifying these feelings have been proposed.
They may be roughly distinguished according as they are pleasurable
or painful, prospective or retrospective, selfish or sympathetic,
active or passive, and possibly in many other ways; but each mode of
arrangement will be indefinite and unsatisfactory when followed into
details. As a general rule, the emotional state of the mind at any
moment will be neither pure anger nor pure fear, nor any one pure
feeling, but an indefinite and complex aggregate of feelings. It may
be that the state of mind is really a sum of several distinct modes
of agitation, just as a mixed colour is the sum of the several rays
of the spectrum. In this case there may be more hope of some method
of analysis being successfully applied at a future time. But it may
be found that states of mind really graduate into each other so that
rigorous classification would be hopeless.

A little reflection will show that there are whole worlds of
existences which in like manner are incapable of logical analysis and
classification. One friend may be able to single out and identify
another friend by his countenance among a million other countenances.
Faces are capable of infinite discrimination, but who shall classify
and define them, or say by what particular shades of feature he does
judge? There are of course certain distinct types of face, but each
type is connected with each other type by infinite intermediate
specimens. We may classify melodies according to the major or minor
key, the character of the time, and some other distinct points;
but every melody has, independently of such circumstances, its
own distinctive character and effect upon the mind. We can detect
differences between the styles of literary, musical, or artistic
compositions. We can even in some cases assign a picture to its
painter, or a symphony to its composer, by a subtle feeling of
resemblances or differences which may be felt, but cannot be described.

Finally, it is apparent that in human character there is unfathomable
and inexhaustible diversity. Every mind is more or less like every
other mind; there is always a basis of similarity, but there is a
superstructure of feelings, impulses, and motives which is distinctive
for each person. We can sometimes predict the general character of the
feelings and actions which will be produced by a given external event
in an individual well known to us; but we also know that we are often
inexplicably at fault in our inferences. No one can safely generalise
upon the subtle variations of temper and emotion which may arise even
in a person of ordinary character. As human knowledge and civilisation
progress, these characteristic differences tend to develop and multiply
themselves, rather than decrease. Character grows more many-sided. Two
well educated Englishmen are far better distinguished from each other
than two common labourers, and these are better distinguished than two
Australian aborigines. The complexities of existing phenomena probably
develop themselves more rapidly than scientific method can overtake
them. In spite of all the boasted powers of science, we cannot really
apply scientific method to our own minds and characters, which are more
important to us than all the stars and nebulæ.




BOOK VI.




CHAPTER XXXI.

REFLECTIONS ON THE RESULTS AND LIMITS OF SCIENTIFIC METHOD.


Before concluding a work on the Principles of Science, it will not be
inappropriate to add some remarks upon the limits and ultimate bearings
of the knowledge which we may acquire by the employment of scientific
method. All science consists, it has several times been stated, in the
detection of identities in the action of natural agents. The purpose of
inductive inquiry is to ascertain the apparent existence of necessary
connection between causes and effects, expressed in the form of natural
laws. Now so far as we thus learn the invariable course of nature, the
future becomes the necessary sequel of the present, and we are brought
beneath the sway of powers with which nothing can interfere.

By degrees it is found, too, that the chemistry of organised substances
is not entirely separated from, but is continuous with, that of earth
and stones. Life seems to be nothing but a special form of energy
which is manifested in heat and electricity and mechanical force. The
time may come, it almost seems, when the tender mechanism of the brain
will be traced out, and every thought reduced to the expenditure of
a determinate weight of nitrogen and phosphorus. No apparent limit
exists to the success of scientific method in weighing and measuring,
and reducing beneath the sway of law, the phenomena both of matter
and of mind. And if mental phenomena be thus capable of treatment by
the balance and the micrometer, can we any longer hold that mind is
distinct from matter? Must not the same inexorable reign of law which
is apparent in the motions of brute matter be extended to the subtle
feelings of the human heart? Are not plants and animals, and ultimately
man himself, merely crystals, as it were, of a complicated form? If
so, our boasted free will becomes a delusion, moral responsibility a
fiction, spirit a mere name for the more curious manifestations of
material energy. All that happens, whether right or wrong, pleasurable
or painful, is but the outcome of the necessary relations of time and
space and force.

Materialism seems, then, to be the coming religion, and resignation
to the nonentity of human will the only duty. Such may not generally
be the reflections of men of science, but I believe that we may thus
describe the secret feelings of fear which the constant advance of
scientific investigation excites in the minds of many. Is science,
then, essentially atheistic and materialistic in its tendency?
Does the uniform action of material causes, which we learn with an
ever-increasing approximation to certainty, preclude the hypothesis of
a benevolent Creator, who has not only designed the existing universe,
but who still retains the power to alter its course from time to time?

To enter upon actual theological discussions would be evidently beyond
the scope of this work. It is with the scientific method common to all
the sciences, and not with any of the separate sciences, that we are
concerned. Theology therefore would be at least as much beyond my scope
as chemistry or geology. But I believe that grave misapprehensions
exist as regards the very nature of scientific method. There are
scientific men who assert that the interposition of Providence is
impossible, and prayer an absurdity, because the laws of nature are
inductively proved to be invariable. Inferences are drawn not so
much from particular sciences as from the logical nature of science
itself, to negative the impulses and hopes of men. Now I may state
that my own studies in logic lead me to call in question such negative
inferences. Laws of nature are uniformities observed to exist in the
action of certain material agents, but it is logically impossible to
show that all other agents must behave as these do. The too exclusive
study of particular branches of physical science seems to generate an
over-confident and dogmatic spirit. Rejoicing in the success with which
a few groups of facts are brought beneath the apparent sway of laws,
the investigator hastily assumes that he is close upon the ultimate
springs of being. A particle of gelatinous matter is found to obey
the ordinary laws of chemistry; yet it moves and lives. The world is
therefore asked to believe that chemistry can resolve the mysteries of
existence.


*The Meaning of Natural Law.*

Pindar speaks of Law as the Ruler of the Mortals and the Immortals, and
it seems to be commonly supposed that the so-called Laws of Nature, in
like manner, rule man and his Creator. The course of nature is regarded
as being determined by invariable principles of mechanics which have
acted since the world began, and will act for evermore. Even if the
origin of all things is attributed to an intelligent creative mind,
that Being is regarded as having yielded up arbitrary power, and as
being subject like a human legislator to the laws which he has himself
enacted. Such notions I should describe as superficial and erroneous,
being derived, as I think, from false views of the nature of scientific
inference, and the degree of certainty of the knowledge which we
acquire by inductive investigation.

A law of nature, as I regard the meaning of the expression, is not a
uniformity which must be obeyed by all objects, but merely a uniformity
which is as a matter of fact obeyed by those objects which have come
beneath our observation. There is nothing whatever incompatible with
logic in the discovery of objects which should prove exceptions to any
law of nature. Perhaps the best established law is that which asserts
an invariable correlation to exist between gravity and inertia, so that
all gravitating bodies are found to possess inertia, and all bodies
possessing inertia are found to gravitate. But it would be no reproach
to our scientific method, if something were ultimately discovered
to possess gravity without inertia. Strictly defined and correctly
interpreted, the law itself would acknowledge the possibility; for with
the statement of every law we ought properly to join an estimate of the
number of instances in which it has been observed to hold true, and the
probability thence calculated, that it will hold true in the next case.
Now, as we found (p. 259), no finite number of instances can warrant
us in expecting with certainty that the next instance will be of like
nature; in the formulas yielded by the inverse method of probabilities
a unit always appears to represent the probability that our inference
will be mistaken. I demur to the assumption that there is any necessary
truth even in such fundamental laws of nature as the Indestructibility
of Matter, the Conservation of Energy, or the Laws of Motion. Certain
it is that men of science have recognised the conceivability of
other laws, and even investigated their mathematical consequences.
Airy investigated the mathematical conditions of a perpetual motion
(p. 223), and Laplace and Newton discussed imaginary laws of forces
inconsistent with those observed to operate in the universe (pp. 642,
706).

The laws of nature, as I venture to regard them, are simply general
propositions concerning the correlation of properties which have been
observed to hold true of bodies hitherto observed. On the assumption
that our experience is of adequate extent, and that no arbitrary
interference takes place, we are then able to assign the probability,
always less than certainty, that the next object of the same apparent
nature will conform to the same laws.


*Infiniteness of the Universe.*

We may safely accept as a satisfactory scientific hypothesis the
doctrine so grandly put forth by Laplace, who asserted that a perfect
knowledge of the universe, as it existed at any given moment, would
give a perfect knowledge of what was to happen thenceforth and for
ever after. Scientific inference is impossible, unless we may regard
the present as the outcome of what is past, and the cause of what is
to come. To the view of perfect intelligence nothing is uncertain. The
astronomer can calculate the positions of the heavenly bodies when
thousands of generations of men shall have passed away, and in this
fact we have some illustration, as Laplace remarks, of the power which
scientific prescience may attain. Doubtless, too, all efforts in the
investigation of nature tend to bring us nearer to the possession of
that ideally perfect power of intelligence. Nevertheless, as Laplace
with profound wisdom adds,[603] we must ever remain at an infinite
distance from the goal of our aspirations.

  [603] *Théorie Analytique des Probabilités*, quoted by Babbage,
  *Ninth Bridgewater Treatise*, p. 173.

Let us assume, for a time at least, as a highly probable hypothesis,
that whatever is to happen must be the outcome of what is; there then
arises the question, What is? Now our knowledge of what exists must
ever remain imperfect and fallible in two respects. Firstly, we do
not know all the matter that has been created, nor the exact manner
in which it has been distributed through space. Secondly, assuming
that we had that knowledge, we should still be wanting in a perfect
knowledge of the way in which the particles of matter will act upon
each other. The power of scientific prediction extends at the most
to the limits of the data employed. Every conclusion is purely
hypothetical and conditional upon the non-interference of agencies
previously undetected. The law of gravity asserts that every body tends
to approach towards every other body, with a certain determinate force;
but, even supposing the law to hold true, it does not assert that the
body *will* approach. No single law of nature can warrant us in making
an absolute prediction. We must know all the laws of nature and all
the existing agents acting according to those laws before we can say
what will happen. To assume, then, that scientific method can take
everything within its cold embrace of uniformity, is to imply that the
Creator cannot outstrip the intelligence of his creatures, and that
the existing Universe is not infinite in extent and complexity, an
assumption for which I see no logical basis whatever.


*The Indeterminate Problem of Creation.*

A second and very serious misapprehension concerning the import of a
law of nature may now be pointed out. It is not uncommonly supposed
that a law determines the character of the results which shall take
place, as, for instance, that the law of gravity determines what force
of gravity shall act upon a given particle. Surely a little reflection
must render it plain that a law by itself determines nothing. It is
*law plus agents obeying law which has results*, and it is no function
of law to govern or define the number and place of its own agents.
Whether a particle of matter shall gravitate, depends not only upon the
law of Newton, but also upon the distribution of surrounding particles.
The theory of gravitation may perhaps be true throughout all time
and in all parts of space, and the Creator may never find occasion
to create those possible exceptions to it which I have asserted to
be conceivable. Let this be as it may; our science cannot certainly
determine the question. Certain it is, that the law of gravity does not
alone determine the forces which may be brought to bear at any point of
space. The force of gravitation acting upon any particle depends upon
the mass, distance, and relative position of all the other particles
of matter within the bounds of space at the instant in question.
Even assuming that all matter when once distributed through space at
the Creation was thenceforth to act in an invariable manner without
subsequent interference, yet the actual configuration of matter at any
moment, and the consequent results of the law of gravitation, must have
been entirely a matter of free choice.

Chalmers has most distinctly pointed out that the existing
*collocations* of the material world are as important as the laws
which the objects obey. He remarks that a certain class of writers
entirely overlook the distinction, and forget that mere laws without
collocations would have afforded no security against a turbid and
disorderly chaos.[604] Mill has recognised[605] the truth of Chalmers’
statement, without drawing the proper inferences from it. He says[606]
of the distribution of matter through space, “We can discover nothing
regular in the distribution itself; we can reduce it to no uniformity,
to no law.” More lately the Duke of Argyll in his well-known work on
the *Reign of Law* has drawn attention to the profound distinction
between laws and collocations of causes.

  [604] *First Bridgewater Treatise* (1834), pp. 16–24.

  [605] *System of Logic*, 5th edit. bk. III. chap. V. § 7; chap. XVI.
  § 3.

  [606] *System of Logic*, vol. i. p. 384.

The original conformation of the material universe, as far as we can
tell, was free from all restriction. There was unlimited space in
which to frame it, and an unlimited number of material particles,
each of which could be placed in any one of an infinite number of
different positions. It should be added, that each particle might be
endowed with any one of an infinite number of quantities of *vis viva*
acting in any one of an infinite number of different directions. The
problem of Creation was, then, what a mathematician would call *an
indeterminate problem*, and it was indeterminate in a great number of
ways. Infinitely numerous and various universes might then have been
fashioned by the various distribution of the original nebulous matter,
although all the particles of matter should obey the law of gravity.

Lucretius tells us how in the original rain of atoms some of these
little bodies diverged from the rectilinear direction, and coming into
contact with other atoms gave rise to the various combinations of
substances which exist. He omitted to tell us whence the atoms came,
or by what force some of them were caused to diverge; but surely these
omissions involve the whole question. I accept the Lucretian conception
of creation when properly supplemented. Every atom which existed in
any point of space must have existed there previously, or must have
been created there by a previously existing Power. When placed there
it must have had a definite mass and a definite energy. Now, as before
remarked, an unlimited number of atoms can be placed in unlimited space
in an unlimited number of modes of distribution. Out of infinitely
infinite choices which were open to the Creator, that one choice must
have been made which has yielded the Universe as it now exists.

It would be a mistake, indeed, to suppose that the law of gravity,
when it holds true, is no restriction on the distribution of
force. That law is a geometrical law, and it would in many cases
be mathematically impossible, as far as we can see, that the force
of gravity acting on one particle should be small while that on a
neighbouring particle is great. We cannot conceive that even Omnipotent
Power should make the angles of a triangle greater than two right
angles. The primary laws of thought and the fundamental notions of the
mathematical sciences do not seem to admit of error or alteration. Into
the metaphysical origin and meaning of the apparent necessity attaching
to such laws I have not attempted to inquire in this work, and it is
not requisite for my present purpose. If the law of gravity were the
only law of nature and the Creator had chosen to render all matter
obedient to that law, there would doubtless be restrictions upon the
effects derivable from any one distribution of matter.


*Hierarchy of Natural Laws.*

A further consideration presents itself. A natural law like that
of gravity expresses a certain uniformity in the action of agents
submitted to it, and this produces, as we have seen, certain
geometrical restrictions upon the effects which those agents may
produce. But there are other forces and laws besides gravity. One
force may override another, and two laws may each be obeyed and may
each disguise the action of the other. In the intimate constitution of
matter there may be hidden springs which, while acting in accordance
with their own fixed laws, may lead to sudden and unexpected changes.
So at least it has been found from time to time in the past, and so
there is every reason to believe it will be found in the future. To
the ancients it seemed incredible that one lifeless stone could make
another leap towards it. A piece of iron while it obeys the magnetic
force of the loadstone does not the less obey the law of gravity.
A plant gravitates downwards as regards every constituent cell or
fibre, and yet it persists in growing upwards. Life is altogether an
exception to the simpler phenomena of mineral substances, not in the
sense of disproving those laws, but in superadding forces of new and
inexplicable character. Doubtless no law of chemistry is broken by the
action of the nervous cells, and no law of physics by the pulses of the
nervous fibres, but something requires to be added to our sciences in
order that we may explain these subtle phenomena.

Now there is absolutely nothing in science or in scientific method to
warrant us in assigning a limit to this hierarchy of laws. When in
many undoubted cases we find law overriding law, and at certain points
in our experience producing unexpected results, we cannot venture to
affirm that we have exhausted the strange phenomena which may have been
provided for in the original constitution of matter. The Universe might
have been so designed that it should go for long intervals through the
same round of unvaried existence, and yet that events of exceptional
character should be produced from time to time. Babbage showed in that
most profound and eloquent work, *The Ninth Bridgewater Treatise*, that
it was theoretically possible for human artists to design a machine,
consisting of metallic wheels and levers, which should work invariably
according to a simple law of action during any finite number of steps,
and yet at a fixed moment, however distant, should manifest a single
breach of law. Such an engine might go on counting, for instance, the
natural numbers until they would reach a number requiring for its
expression a hundred million digits. “If every letter in the volume
now before the reader’s eyes,” says Babbage,[607] “were changed into
a figure, and if all the figures contained in a thousand such volumes
were arranged in order, the whole together would yet fall far short
of the vast induction the observer would have had in favour of the
truth of the law of natural numbers.... Yet shall the engine, true to
the prediction of its director, after the lapse of myriads of ages,
fulfil its task, and give that one, the first and only exception to
that time-sanctioned law. What would have been the chances against the
appearance of the excepted case, immediately prior to its occurrence?”

  [607] *Ninth Bridgewater Treatise*, p. 140.

As Babbage further showed,[608] a calculating engine, after proceeding
through any required number of motions according to a first law, may
be made suddenly to suffer a change, so that it shall then commence
to calculate according to a wholly new law. After giving the natural
numbers for a finite time, it might suddenly begin to give triangular,
or square, or cube numbers, and these changes might be conceived
theoretically as occurring time after time. Now if such occurrences can
be designed and foreseen by a human artist, it is surely within the
capacity of the Divine Artist to provide for analogous changes of law
in the mechanism of the atom, or the construction of the heavens.

  [608] *Ibid.* pp. 34–43.

Physical science, so far as its highest speculations can be trusted,
gives some indication of a change of law in the past history of the
Universe. According to Sir W. Thomson’s deductions from Fourier’s
*Theory of Heat*, we can trace down the dissipation of heat by
conduction and radiation to an infinitely distant time when all
things will be uniformly cold. But we cannot similarly trace the
heat-history of the Universe to an infinite distance in the past.
For a certain negative value of the time the formulæ give impossible
values, indicating that there was some initial distribution of heat
which could not have resulted, according to known laws of nature,[609]
from any previous distribution.[610] There are other cases in which a
consideration of the dissipation of energy leads to the conception of
a limit to the antiquity of the present order of things.[611] Human
science, of course, is fallible, and some oversight or erroneous
simplification in these theoretical calculations may afterwards be
discovered; but as the present state of scientific knowledge is the
only ground on which erroneous inferences from the uniformity of nature
and the supposed reign of law are founded, I am right in appealing to
the present state of science in opposition to these inferences. Now
the theory of heat places us in the dilemma either of believing in
Creation at an assignable date in the past, or else of supposing that
some inexplicable change in the working of natural laws then took
place. Physical science gives no countenance to the notion of infinite
duration of matter in one continuous course of existence. And if in
time past there has been a discontinuity of law, why may there not be
a similar event awaiting the world in the future? Infinite ingenuity
could have implanted some agency in matter so that it might never yet
have made its tremendous powers manifest. We have a very good theory
of the conservation of energy, but the foremost physicists do not
deny that there may possibly be forms of energy, neither kinetic nor
potential, and therefore of unknown nature.[612]

  [609] Professor Clifford, in his most interesting lecture on “The
  First and Last Catastrophe” (*Fortnightly Review*, April 1875,
  p. 480, reprint by the Sunday Lecture Society, p. 24), objects that I
  have erroneously substituted “known laws of nature” for “known laws
  of conduction of heat.” I quite admit the error, without admitting
  all the conclusions which Professor Clifford proceeds to draw; but I
  maintain the paragraph unchanged, in order that it may be discussed
  in the Preface.

  [610] Tait’s *Thermodynamics*, p. 38. *Cambridge Mathematical
  Journal*, vol. iii. p. 174.

  [611] Clerk Maxwell’s *Theory of Heat*, p. 245.

  [612] Maxwell’s *Theory of Heat*, p. 92.

We can imagine reasoning creatures dwelling in a world where the
atmosphere was a mixture of oxygen and inflammable gas like the
fire-damp of coal-mines. If devoid of fire, they might have lived
through long ages unconscious of the tremendous forces which a single
spark would call into play. In the twinkling of an eye new laws might
come into action, and the poor reasoning creatures, so confident about
their knowledge of the reign of law in their world, would have no time
to speculate upon the overthrow of all their theories. Can we with our
finite knowledge be sure that such an overthrow of our theories is
impossible?


*The Ambiguous Expression, “Uniformity of Nature.”*

I have asserted that serious misconception arises from an erroneous
interpretation of the expression Uniformity of Nature. Every law of
nature is the statement of a certain uniformity observed to exist among
phenomena, and since the laws of nature are invariably obeyed, it seems
to follow that the course of nature itself is uniform, so that we can
safely judge of the future by the present. This inference is supported
by some of the results of physical astronomy. Laplace proved that
the planetary system is stable, so that no perturbation which planet
produces upon planet can become so great as to cause disruption and
permanent alteration of the planetary orbits. A full comprehension of
the law of gravity shows that all such disturbances are essentially
periodic, so that after the lapse of millions of years the planets will
return to the same relative positions, and a new cycle of disturbances
will then commence.

As other branches of science progress, we seem to gain assurance
that no great alteration of the world’s condition is to be expected.
Conflict with a comet has long been the cause of fear, but now it is
credibly asserted that we have passed through a comet’s tail without
the fact being known at the time, or manifested by any more serious a
phenomenon than a slight luminosity of the sky. More recently still
the earth is said to have touched the comet Biela, and the only result
was a beautiful and perfectly harmless display of meteors. A decrease
in the heating power of the sun seems to be the next most probable
circumstance from which we might fear the extinction of life on the
earth. But calculations founded on reasonable physical data show
that no appreciable change can be going on, and experimental data to
indicate a change are wholly wanting. Geological investigations show
indeed that there have been extensive variations of climate in past
times; vast glaciers and icebergs have swept over the temperate regions
at one time, and tropical vegetation has flourished near the poles
at another time. But here again the vicissitudes of climate assume a
periodic character, so that the stability of the earth’s condition does
not seem to be threatened.

All these statements may be reasonable, but they do not establish the
Uniformity of Nature in the sense that extensive alterations or sudden
catastrophes are impossible. In the first place, Laplace’s theory of
the stability of the planetary system is of an abstract character, as
paying regard to nothing but the mutual gravitation of the planetary
bodies and the sun. It overlooks several physical causes of change
and decay in the system which were not so well known in his day as at
present, and it also presupposes the absence of any interruption of the
course of things by conflict with foreign astronomical bodies.

It is now acknowledged by astronomers that there are at least two ways
in which the *vis viva* of the planets and satellites may suffer loss.
The friction of the tides upon the earth produces a small quantity
of heat which is radiated into space, and this loss of energy must
result in a decrease of the rotational velocity, so that ultimately
the terrestrial day will become identical with the year, just as the
periods of revolution of the moon upon its axis and around the earth
have already become equal. Secondly, there can be little doubt that
certain manifestations of electricity upon the earth’s surface depend
upon the relative motions of the planets and the sun, which give
rise to periods of increased intensity. Such electrical phenomena
must result in the production and dissipation of heat, the energy
of which must be drawn, partially at least, from the moving bodies.
This effect is probably identical (p. 570) with the loss of energy of
comets attributed to the so-called resisting medium. But whatever be
the theoretical explanation of these phenomena, it is almost certain
that there exists a tendency to the dissipation of the energy of the
planetary system, which will, in the indefinite course of time, result
in the fall of the planets into the sun.

It is hardly probable, however, that the planetary system will be left
undisturbed throughout the enormous interval of time required for the
dissipation of its energy in this way. Conflict with other bodies is
so far from being improbable, that it becomes approximately certain
when we take very long intervals of time into account. As regards
cometary conflicts, I am by no means satisfied with the negative
conclusions drawn from the remarkable display on the evening of the
27th of November, 1872. We may often have passed through the tail of a
comet, the light of which is probably an electrical manifestation no
more substantial than the aurora borealis. Every remarkable shower of
shooting stars may also be considered as proceeding from a cometary
body, so that we may be said to have passed through the thinner parts
of innumerable comets. But the earth has probably never passed, in
times of which we have any record, through the nucleus of a comet,
which consists perhaps of a dense swarm of small meteorites. We can
only speculate upon the effects which might be produced by such a
conflict, but it would probably be a much more serious event than any
yet registered in history. The probability of its occurrence, too,
cannot be assigned; for though the probability of conflict with any one
cometary nucleus is almost infinitesimal, yet the number of comets is
immensely great (p. 408).

It is far from impossible, again, that the planetary system may be
invaded by bodies of greater mass than comets. The sun seems to be
placed in so extensive a portion of empty space that its own proper
motion would not bring it to the nearest known star (α Centauri) in
less than 139,200 years. But in order to be sure that this interval of
undisturbed life is granted to our globe, we must prove that there are
no stars moving so as to meet us, and no dark bodies of considerable
size flying through intervening space unknown to us. The intrusion
of comets into our system, and the fact that many of them have
hyperbolic paths, is sufficient to show that the surrounding parts of
space are occupied by multitudes of dark bodies of some size. It is
quite probable that small suns may have cooled sufficiently to become
non-luminous; for even if we discredit the theory that the variation of
brightness of periodic stars is due to the revolution of dark companion
stars, yet there is in our own globe an unquestionable example of a
smaller body which has cooled below the luminous point.

Altogether, then, it is a mere assumption that the uniformity of nature
involves the unaltered existence of our own globe. There is no kind
of catastrophe which is too great or too sudden to be theoretically
consistent with the reign of law. For all that our science can tell,
human history may be closed in the next instant of time. The world may
be dashed to pieces against a wandering star; it may be involved in a
nebulous atmosphere of hydrogen to be exploded a second afterwards; it
may be scorched up or dissipated into vapour by some great explosion in
the sun; there might even be within the globe itself some secret cause
of disruption, which only needs time for its manifestation.

There are some indications, as already noticed (p. 660), that violent
disturbances have actually occurred in the history of the solar system.
Olbers sought for the minor planets on the supposition that they were
fragments of an exploded planet, and he was rewarded with the discovery
of some of them. The retrograde motion of the satellites of the more
distant planets, the abnormal position of the poles of Uranus and the
excessive distance of Neptune, are other indications of some violent
event, of which we have no other evidence. I adduce all these facts
and arguments, not to show that there is any considerable probability,
as far as we can judge, of interruption within the scope of human
history, but to prove that the Uniformity of Nature is theoretically
consistent with the most unexpected events of which we can form a
conception.


*Possible States of the Universe.*

When we give the rein to scientific imagination, it becomes apparent
that conflict of body with body must not be regarded as the rare
exception, but as the general rule and the inevitable fate of each
star system. So far as we can trace out the results of the law of
gravitation, and of the dissipation of energy, the universe must be
regarded as undergoing gradual condensation into a single cold solid
body of gigantic dimensions. Those who so frequently use the expression
Uniformity of Nature seem to forget that the Universe might exist
consistently with the laws of nature in the most diverse conditions. It
might consist, on the one hand, of a glowing nebulous mass of gaseous
substances. The heat might be so intense that all elements, even carbon
and silicon, would be in the state of gas, and all atoms, of whatever
nature, would be flying about in chemical independence, diffusing
themselves almost uniformly in the neighbouring parts of space. There
would then be no life, unless we can apply that name to the passage
through each part of space of similar average trains of atoms, the
particular succession of atoms being governed only by the theory of
probability, and the law of divergence from a mean exhibited in the
Arithmetical Triangle. Such a universe would correspond partially to
the Lucretian rain of atoms, and to that nebular hypothesis out of
which Laplace proposed philosophically to explain the evolution of the
planetary system.

According to another extreme supposition, the intense heat-energy of
this nebulous mass might be radiated away into the unknown regions
of outer space. The attraction of gravity would exert itself between
each two particles, and the energy of motion thence arising would,
by incessant conflicts, be resolved into heat and dissipated.
Inconceivable ages might be required for the completion of this
process, but the dissipation of energy thus proceeding could end only
in the production of a cold and motionless universe. The relation of
cause and effect, as we see it manifested in life and growth, would
degenerate into the constant existence of every particle in a fixed
position relative to every other particle. Logical and geometrical
resemblances would still exist between atoms, and between groups of
atoms crystallised in their appropriate forms for evermore. But time,
the great variable, would bring no variation, and as to human hopes and
troubles, they would have gone to eternal rest.

Science is not really adequate to proving that such is the inevitable
fate of the universe, for we can seldom trust our best-established
theories far from their data. Nevertheless, the most probable
speculations which we can form as to the history, especially of our own
planetary system, is that it originated in a heated revolving nebulous
mass of gas, and is in a state of excessively slow progress towards
the cold and stony condition. Other speculative hypotheses might
doubtless be entertained. Every hypothesis is pressed by difficulties.
If the whole universe be cooling, whither does the heat go? If we are
to get rid of it entirely, outer space must be infinite in extent, so
that it shall never be stopped and reflected back. But not to speak
of metaphysical difficulties, if the medium of heat undulations be
infinite in extent, why should not the material bodies placed in
it be infinite also in number and aggregate mass? It is apparent
that we are venturing into speculations which surpass our powers of
scientific inference. But then I am arguing negatively; I wish to show
that those who speak of the uniformity of nature, and the reign of
law, misinterpret the meaning involved in those expressions. Law is
not inconsistent with extreme diversity, and, so far as we can read
the history of this planetary system, it did probably originate in
heated nebulous matter, and man’s history forms but a brief span in
its progress towards the cold and stony condition. It is by doubtful
and speculative hypotheses alone that we can avoid such a conclusion,
and I depart least from undoubted facts and well-established laws
when I assert that, whatever uniformities may underlie the phenomena
of nature, constant variety and ever-progressing change is the real
outcome.


*Speculations on the Reconcentration of Energy.*

There are unequivocal indications, as I have said, that the material
universe, as we at present see it, is progressing from some act of
creation, or some discontinuity of existence of which the date may be
approximately fixed by scientific inference. It is progressing towards
a state in which the available energy of matter will be dissipated
through infinite surrounding space, and all matter will become cold
and lifeless. This constitutes, as it were, the historical period of
physical science, that over which our scientific foresight may more
or less extend. But in this, as in other cases, we have no right to
interpret our experience negatively, so as to infer that because the
present state of things began at a particular time, there was no
previous existence. It may be that the present period of material
existence is but one of an indefinite series of like periods. All that
we can see, and feel, and infer, and reason about may be, as it were,
but a part of one single pulsation in the existence of the universe.

After Sir W. Thomson had pointed out the preponderating tendency
which now seems to exist towards the conversion of all energy into
heat-energy, and its equal diffusion by radiation throughout space,
the late Professor Rankine put forth a remarkable speculation.[613] He
suggested that the ethereal, or, as I have called it, the *adamantine*
medium in which all the stars exist, and all radiation takes place, may
have bounds, beyond which only empty space exists. All heat undulations
reaching this boundary will be totally reflected, according to the
theory of undulations, and will be reconcentrated into foci situated in
various parts of the medium. Whenever a cold and extinct star happens
to pass through one of these foci, it will be instantly ignited and
resolved by intense heat into its constituent elements. Discontinuity
will occur in the history of that portion of matter, and the star will
begin its history afresh with a renewed store of energy.

  [613] *Report of the British Association* (1852), Report of Sections,
  p. 12.

This is doubtless a mere speculation, practically incapable of
verification by observation, and almost free from restrictions afforded
by present knowledge. We might attribute various shapes to the
adamantine medium, and the consequences would be various. But there
is this value in such speculations, that they draw attention to the
finiteness of our knowledge. We cannot deny the possible truth of such
an hypothesis, nor can we place a limit to the scientific imagination
in the framing of other like hypotheses. It is impossible, indeed, to
follow out our scientific inferences without falling into speculation.
If heat be radiated into outward space, it must either proceed *ad
infinitum*, or it must be stopped somewhere. In the latter case we fall
upon Rankine’s hypothesis. But if the material universe consist of a
finite collection of heated matter situated in a finite portion of an
infinite adamantine medium, then either this universe must have existed
for a finite time, or else it must have cooled down during the infinity
of past time indefinitely near to the absolute zero of temperature. I
objected to Lucretius’ argument against the destructibility of matter,
that we have no knowledge whatever of the laws according to which
it would undergo destruction. But we do know the laws according to
which the dissipation of heat appears to proceed, and the conclusion
inevitably is that a finite heated material body placed in a perfectly
cold infinitely extended medium would in an infinite time sink to
zero of temperature. Now our own world is not yet cooled down near to
zero, so that physical science seems to place us in the dilemma of
admitting either the finiteness of past duration of the world, or else
the finiteness of the portion of medium in which we exist. In either
case we become involved in metaphysical and mechanical difficulties
surpassing our mental powers.


*The Divergent Scope for New Discovery.*

In the writings of some recent philosophers, especially of Auguste
Comte, and in some degree John Stuart Mill, there is an erroneous
and hurtful tendency to represent our knowledge as assuming an
approximately complete character. At least these and many other
writers fail to impress upon their readers a truth which cannot be
too constantly borne in mind, namely, that the utmost successes which
our scientific method can accomplish will not enable us to comprehend
more than an infinitesimal fraction of what there doubtless is to
comprehend.[614] Professor Tyndall seems to me open to the same charge
in a less degree. He remarks[615] that we can probably never bring
natural phenomena completely under mathematical laws, because the
approach of our sciences towards completeness may be asymptotic, so
that however far we may go, there may still remain some facts not
subject to scientific explanation. He thus likens the supply of novel
phenomena to a convergent series, the earlier and larger terms of which
have been successfully disposed of, so that comparatively minor groups
of phenomena alone remain for future investigators to occupy themselves
upon.

  [614] Mr. C. J. Monroe objects that in this statement I do injustice
  to Comte, who, he thinks, did impress upon his readers the inadequacy
  of our mental powers compared with the vastness of the subject matter
  of science. The error of Comte, he holds, was in maintaining that
  science had been carried about as far as it is worth while to carry
  it, which is a different matter. In either case, Comte’s position is
  so untenable that I am content to leave the question undecided.

  [615] *Fragments of Science*, p. 362.

On the contrary, as it appears to me, the supply of new and unexplained
facts is divergent in extent, so that the more we have explained, the
more there is to explain. The further we advance in any generalisation,
the more numerous and intricate are the exceptional cases still
demanding further treatment. The experiments of Boyle, Mariotte,
Dalton, Gay-Lussac, and others, upon the physical properties of gases,
might seem to have exhausted that subject by showing that all gases
obey the same laws as regards temperature, pressure, and volume. But
in reality these laws are only approximately true, and the divergences
afford a wide and quite unexhausted field for further generalisation.
The recent discoveries of Professor Andrews have summed up some of
these exceptional facts under a wider generalisation, but in reality
they have opened to us vast new regions of interesting inquiry,
and they leave wholly untouched the question why one gas behaves
differently from another.

The science of crystallography is that perhaps in which the most
precise and general laws have been detected, but it would be untrue
to assert that it has lessened the area of future discovery. We can
show that each one of the seven or eight hundred forms of calcite is
derivable by geometrical modifications from an hexagonal prism; but
who has attempted to explain the molecular forces producing these
modifications, or the chemical conditions in which they arise? The law
of isomorphism is an important generalisation, for it establishes a
general resemblance between the forms of crystallisation of natural
classes of elements. But if we examine a little more closely we find
that these forms are only approximately alike, and the divergence
peculiar to each substance is an unexplained exception.

By many similar illustrations it might readily be shown that in
whatever direction we extend our investigations and successfully
harmonise a few facts, the result is only to raise up a host of other
unexplained facts. Can any scientific man venture to state that there
is less opening now for new discoveries than there was three centuries
ago? Is it not rather true that we have but to open a scientific book
and read a page or two, and we shall come to some recorded phenomenon
of which no explanation can yet be given? In every such fact there is a
possible opening for new discoveries, and it can only be the fault of
the investigator’s mind if he can look around him and find no scope for
the exercise of his faculties.


*Infinite Incompleteness of the Mathematical Sciences.*

There is one privilege which a certain amount of knowledge should
confer; it is that of becoming aware of the weakness of our powers
compared with the tasks which they might undertake if stronger. To the
poor savage who cannot count twenty the arithmetical accomplishments of
the schoolboy are miraculously great. The schoolboy cannot comprehend
the vastly greater powers of the student, who has acquired facility in
algebraic processes. The student can but look with feelings of surprise
and reverence at the powers of a Newton or a Laplace. But the question
at once suggests itself, Do the powers of the highest human intellect
bear a finite ratio to the things which are to be understood and
calculated? How many further steps must we take in the rise of mental
ability and the extension of mathematical methods before we begin to
exhaust the knowable?

I am inclined to find fault with mathematical writers because they
often exult in what they can accomplish, and omit to point out that
what they do is but an infinitely small part of what might be done.
They exhibit a general inclination, with few exceptions, not to do
so much as mention the existence of problems of an impracticable
character. This may be excusable as far as the immediate practical
result of their researches is in question, but the custom has the
effect of misleading the general public into the fallacious notion
that mathematics is a *perfect* science, which accomplishes what it
undertakes in a complete manner. On the contrary, it may be said that
if a mathematical problem were selected by chance out of the whole
number which might be proposed, the probability is infinitely slight
that a human mathematician could solve it. Just as the numbers we can
count are nothing compared with the numbers which might exist, so the
accomplishments of a Laplace or a Lagrange are, as it were, the little
corner of the multiplication-table, which has really an infinite extent.

I have pointed out that the rude character of our observations prevents
us from being aware of the greater number of effects and actions
in nature. It must be added that, if we perceive them, we should
usually be incapable of including them in our theories from want of
mathematical power. Some persons may be surprised that though nearly
two centuries have elapsed since the time of Newton’s discoveries, we
have yet no general theory of molecular action. Some approximations
have been made towards such a theory. Joule and Clausius have measured
the velocity of gaseous atoms, or even determined the average distance
between the collisions of atom and atom. Thomson has approximated to
the number of atoms in a given bulk of substance. Rankine has formed
some reasonable hypotheses as to the actual constitution of atoms. It
would be a mistake to suppose that these ingenious results of theory
and experiment form any appreciable approach to a complete solution
of molecular motions. There is every reason to believe, judging from
the spectra of the elements, their atomic weights and other data, that
chemical atoms are very complicated structures. An atom of pure iron
is probably a far more complicated system than that of the planets
and their satellites. A compound atom may perhaps be compared with
a stellar system, each star a minor system in itself. The smallest
particle of solid substance will consist of a great number of such
stellar systems united in regular order, each bounded by the other,
communicating with it in some manner yet wholly incomprehensible. What
are our mathematical powers in comparison with this problem?

After two centuries of continuous labour, the most gifted men have
succeeded in calculating the mutual effects of three bodies each
upon the other, under the simple hypothesis of the law of gravity.
Concerning these calculations we must further remember that they are
purely approximate, and that the methods would not apply where four or
more bodies are acting, and all produce considerable effects upon each
other. There is reason to believe that each constituent of a chemical
atom goes through an orbit in the millionth part of the twinkling of
an eye. In each revolution it is successively or simultaneously under
the influence of many other constituents, or possibly comes into
collision with them. It is no exaggeration to say that mathematicians
have the least notion of the way in which they could successfully
attack so difficult a problem of forces and motions. As Herschel has
remarked,[616] each of these particles is for ever solving differential
equations, which, if written out in full, might belt the earth.

  [616] *Familiar Lectures on Scientific Subjects*, p. 458.

Some of the most extensive calculations ever made were those required
for the reduction of the measurements executed in the course of the
Trigonometrical Survey of Great Britain. The calculations arising out
of the principal triangulation occupied twenty calculators during
three or four years, in the course of which the computers had to solve
simultaneous equations involving seventy-seven unknown quantities.
The reduction of the levellings required the solution of a system of
ninety-one equations. But these vast calculations present no approach
whatever to what would be requisite for the complete treatment of
any one physical problem. The motion of glaciers is supposed to
be moderately well understood in the present day. A glacier is a
viscid, slowly yielding mass, neither absolutely solid nor absolutely
rigid, but it is expressly remarked by Forbes,[617] that not even an
approximate solution of the mathematical conditions of such a moving
mass can yet be possible. “Every one knows,” he says, “that such
problems are beyond the compass of exact mathematics;” but though
mathematicians may know this, they do not often enough impress that
knowledge on other people.

  [617] *Philosophical Magazine*, 3rd Series, vol. xxvi. p. 406.

The problems which are solved in our mathematical books consist of
a small selection of those which happen from peculiar conditions to
be solvable. But the very simplest problem in appearance will often
give rise to impracticable calculations. Mr. Todhunter[618] seems to
blame Condorcet, because in one of his memoirs he mentions a problem
to solve which would require a great and impracticable number of
successive integrations. Now, if our mathematical sciences are to cope
with the problems which await solution, we must be prepared to effect
an unlimited number of successive integrations; yet at present, and
almost beyond doubt for ever, the probability that an integration taken
haphazard will come within our powers is exceedingly small.

  [618] *History of the Theory of Probability*, p. 398.

In some passages of that remarkable work, the *Ninth Bridgewater
Treatise* (pp. 113–115), Babbage has pointed out that if we had power
to follow and detect the minutest effects of any disturbance, each
particle of existing matter would furnish a register of all that has
happened. “The track of every canoe--of every vessel that has yet
disturbed the surface of the ocean, whether impelled by manual force or
elemental power, remains for ever registered in the future movement of
all succeeding particles which may occupy its place. The furrow which
it left is, indeed, instantly filled up by the closing waters; but they
draw after them other and larger portions of the surrounding element,
and these again, once moved, communicate motion to others in endless
succession.” We may even say that “The air itself is one vast library,
on whose pages are for ever written all that man has ever said or
even whispered. There, in their mutable but unerring characters, mixed
with the earliest as well as the latest sighs of mortality, stand for
ever recorded, vows unredeemed, promises unfulfilled, perpetuating in
the united movements of each particle the testimony of man’s changeful
will.”

When we read reflections such as these, we may congratulate ourselves
that we have been endowed with minds which, rightly employed, can
form some estimate of their incapacity to trace out and account for
all that proceeds in the simpler actions of material nature. It ought
to be added that, wonderful as is the extent of physical phenomena
open to our investigation, intellectual phenomena are yet vastly more
extensive. Of this I might present one satisfactory proof were space
available by pointing out that the mathematical functions employed
in the calculations of physical science form an infinitely small
fraction of the functions which might be invented. Common trigonometry
consists of a great series of useful formulæ, all of which arise out
of the relation of the sine and cosine expressed in one equation,
sin ^{2}*x* + cos ^{2}*x* = 1. But this is not the only trigonometry
which may exist; mathematicians also recognise hyperbolic trigonometry,
of which the fundamental equation is cos ^{2}*x* - sin ^{2}*x* = 1. De
Morgan has pointed out that the symbols of ordinary algebra form but
three of an interminable series of conceivable systems.[619] As the
logarithmic operation is to addition or addition to multiplication, so
is the latter to a higher operation, and so on without limit.

  [619] *Trigonometry and Double Algebra*, chap. ix.

We may rely upon it that immense, and to us inconceivable, advances
will be made by the human intellect, in the absence of any catastrophe
to the species or the globe. Within historical periods we can trace
the rise of mathematical science from its simplest germs. We can
prove our descent from ancestors who counted only on their fingers.
How infinitely is a Newton or a Laplace above those simple savages.
Pythagoras is said to have sacrificed a hecatomb when he discovered the
forty-seventh proposition of Euclid, and the occasion was worthy of
the sacrifice. Archimedes was beside himself when he first perceived
his beautiful mode of determining specific gravities. Yet these great
discoveries are the commonplaces of our school books. Step by step we
can trace upwards the acquirement of new mental powers. What could be
more wonderful than Napier’s discovery of logarithms, a new mode of
calculation which has multiplied perhaps a hundredfold the working
powers of every computer, and has rendered easy calculations which were
before impracticable? Since the time of Newton and Leibnitz worlds of
problems have been solved which before were hardly conceived as matters
of inquiry. In our own day extended methods of mathematical reasoning,
such as the system of quaternions, have been brought into existence.
What intelligent man will doubt that the recondite speculations of a
Cayley, a Sylvester, or a Clifford may lead to some new development of
new mathematical power, at the simplicity of which a future age will
wonder, and yet wonder more that to us they were so dark and difficult.
May we not repeat the words of Seneca: “Veniet tempus, quo ista quæ
nunc latent, in lucem dies extrahat, et longioris ævi diligentia:
ad inquisitionem tantorum ætas una non sufficit. Veniet tempus, quo
posteri nostri tam aperta nos nescisse mirentur.”


*The Reign of Law in Mental and Social Phenomena.*

After we pass from the so-called physical sciences to those which
attempt to investigate mental and social phenomena, the same general
conclusions will hold true. No one will be found to deny that there
are certain uniformities of thinking and acting which can be detected
in reasoning beings, and so far as we detect such laws we successfully
apply scientific method. But those who attempt to establish social or
moral sciences soon become aware that they are dealing with subjects
of enormous perplexity. Take as an instance the science of political
economy. If a science at all, it must be a mathematical science,
because it deals with quantities of commodities. But as soon as we
attempt to draw out the equations expressing the laws of demand and
supply, we discover that they have a complexity entirely surpassing
our powers of mathematical treatment. We may lay down the general form
of the equations, expressing the demand and supply for two or three
commodities among two or three trading bodies, but all the functions
involved are so complicated in character that there is not much fear
of scientific method making rapid progress in this direction. If such
be the prospects of a comparatively formal science, like political
economy, what shall we say of moral science? Any complete theory of
morals must deal with quantities of pleasure and pain, as Bentham
pointed out, and must sum up the general tendency of each kind of
action upon the good of the community. If we are to apply scientific
method to morals, we must have a calculus of moral effects, a kind
of physical astronomy investigating the mutual perturbations of
individuals. But as astronomers have not yet fully solved the problem
of three gravitating bodies, when shall we have a solution of the
problem of three moral bodies?

The sciences of political economy and morality are comparatively
abstract and general, treating mankind from simple points of view,
and attempting to detect general principles of action. They are to
social phenomena what the abstract sciences of chemistry, heat, and
electricity are to the concrete science of meteorology. Before we
can investigate the actions of any aggregate of men, we must have
fairly mastered all the more abstract sciences applying to them,
somewhat in the way that we have acquired a fair comprehension of
the simpler truths of chemistry and physics. But all our physical
sciences do not enable us to predict the weather two days hence with
any great probability, and the general problem of meteorology is almost
unattempted as yet. What shall we say then of the general problem of
social science, which shall enable us to predict the course of events
in a nation?

Several writers have proposed to lay the foundations of the science
of history. Buckle undertook to write the *History of Civilisation
in England*, and to show how the character of a nation could be
explained by the nature of the climate and the fertility of the soil.
He omitted to explain the contrast between the ancient Greek nation
and the present one; there must have been an extraordinary revolution
in the climate or the soil. Auguste Comte detected the simple laws
of the course of development through which nations pass. There are
always three phases of intellectual condition,--the theological, the
metaphysical, and the positive; applying this general law of progress
to concrete cases, Comte was enabled to predict that in the hierarchy
of European nations, Spain would necessarily hold the highest place.
Such are the parodies of science offered to us by the *positive*
philosophers.

A science of history in the true sense of the term is an absurd notion.
A nation is not a mere sum of individuals whom we can treat by the
method of averages; it is an organic whole, held together by ties of
infinite complexity. Each individual acts and re-acts upon his smaller
or greater circle of friends, and those who acquire a public position
exert an influence on much larger sections of the nation. There will
always be a few great leaders of exceptional genius or opportunities,
the unaccountable phases of whose opinions and inclinations sway the
whole body. From time to time arise critical situations, battles,
delicate negotiations, internal disturbances, in which the slightest
incidents may change the course of history. A rainy day may hinder a
forced march, and change the course of a campaign; a few injudicious
words in a despatch may irritate the national pride; the accidental
discharge of a gun may precipitate a collision the effects of which
will last for centuries. It is said that the history of Europe depended
at one moment upon the question whether the look-out man upon Nelson’s
vessel would or would not descry a ship of Napoleon’s expedition
to Egypt which was passing not far off. In human affairs, then,
the smallest causes may produce the greatest effects, and the real
application of scientific method is out of the question.


*The Theory of Evolution.*

Profound philosophers have lately generalised concerning the production
of living forms and the mental and moral phenomena regarded as their
highest development. Herbert Spencer’s theory of evolution purports
to explain the origin of all specific differences, so that not even
the rise of a Homer or a Beethoven would escape from his broad
theories. The homogeneous is unstable and must differentiate itself,
says Spencer, and hence comes the variety of human institutions
and characters. In order that a living form shall continue to exist
and propagate its kind, says Darwin, it must be suitable to its
circumstances, and the most suitable forms will prevail over and
extirpate those which are less suitable. From these fruitful ideas
are developed theories of evolution and natural selection which go
far towards accounting for the existence of immense numbers of living
creatures--plants, and animals. Apparent adaptations of organs to
useful purposes, which Paley regarded as distinct products of creative
intelligence, are now seen to follow as natural effects of a constantly
acting tendency. Even man, according to these theories, is no distinct
creation, but rather an extreme case of brain development. His nearest
cousins are the apes, and his pedigree extends backwards until it joins
that of the lowliest zoophytes.

The theories of Darwin and Spencer are doubtless not demonstrated; they
are to some extent hypothetical, just as all the theories of physical
science are to some extent hypothetical, and open to doubt. Judging
from the immense numbers of diverse facts which they harmonise and
explain, I venture to look upon the theories of evolution and natural
selection in their main features as two of the most probable hypotheses
ever proposed. I question whether any scientific works which have
appeared since the *Principia* of Newton are comparable in importance
with those of Darwin and Spencer, revolutionising as they do all our
views of the origin of bodily, mental, moral, and social phenomena.

Granting all this, I cannot for a moment admit that the theory of
evolution will destroy theology. That theory embraces several laws
or uniformities which are observed to be true in the production of
living forms; but these laws do not determine the size and figure of
living creatures, any more than the law of gravitation determines the
magnitudes and distances of the planets. Suppose that Darwin is correct
in saying that man is descended from the Ascidians: yet the precise
form of the human body must have been influenced by an infinite train
of circumstances affecting the reproduction, growth, and health of the
whole chain of intermediate beings. No doubt, the circumstances being
what they were, man could not be otherwise than he is, and if in any
other part of the universe an exactly similar earth, furnished with
exactly similar germs of life, existed, a race must have grown up there
exactly similar to the human race.

By a different distribution of atoms in the primeval world a different
series of living forms on this earth would have been produced. From the
same causes acting according to the same laws, the same results will
follow; but from different causes acting according to the same laws,
different results will follow. So far as we can see, then, infinitely
diverse living creatures might have been created consistently with the
theory of evolution, and the precise reason why we have a backbone,
two hands with opposable thumbs, an erect stature, a complex brain,
about 223 bones, and many other peculiarities, is only to be found in
the original act of creation. I do not, any less than Paley, believe
that the eye of man manifests design. I believe that the eye was
gradually developed, and we can in fact trace its gradual development
from the first germ of a nerve affected by light-rays in some simple
zoophyte. In proportion as the eye became a more accurate instrument
of vision, it enabled its possessor the better to escape destruction,
but the ultimate result must have been contained in the aggregate of
the causes, and these causes, as far as we can see, were subject to the
arbitrary choice of the Creator.

Although Agassiz was clearly wrong in holding that every species of
living creature appeared on earth by the immediate intervention of
the Creator, which would amount to saying that no laws of connection
between forms are discoverable, yet he seems to be right in asserting
that living forms are distinct from those produced by purely physical
causes. “The products of what are commonly called physical agents,”
he says,[620] “are everywhere the same (*i.e.* upon the whole surface
of the earth), and have always been the same (*i.e.* during all
geological periods); while organised beings are everywhere different
and have differed in all ages. Between two such series of phenomena
there can be no causal or genetic connection.” Living forms as we now
regard them are essentially variable, but from constant mechanical
causes constant effects would ensue. If vegetable cells are formed
on geometrical principles being first spherical, and then by mutual
compression dodecahedral, then all cells should have similar forms. In
the Foraminifera and some other lowly organisms, we seem to observe the
production of complex forms on geometrical principles. But from similar
causes acting according to similar laws only similar results could
be produced. If the original life germ of each creature is a simple
particle of protoplasm, unendowed with any distinctive forces, then the
whole of the complex phenomena of animal and vegetable life are effects
without causes. Protoplasm may be chemically the same substance, and
the germ-cell of a man and of a fish may be apparently the same, so far
as the microscope can decide; but if certain cells produce men, and
others as uniformly produce a species of fish, there must be a hidden
constitution determining the extremely different results. If this were
not so, the generation of every living creature from the uniform germ
would have to be regarded as a distinct act of creation.

  [620] Agassiz, *Essay on Classification*, p. 75.

Theologians have dreaded the establishment of the theories of Darwin
and Huxley and Spencer, as if they thought that those theories could
explain everything upon the purest mechanical and material principles,
and exclude all notions of design. They do not see that those theories
have opened up more questions than they have closed. The doctrine of
evolution gives a complete explanation of no single living form. While
showing the general principles which prevail in the variation of living
creatures, it only points out the infinite complexity of the causes
and circumstances which have led to the present state of things. Any
one of Mr. Darwin’s books, admirable though they all are, consists
but in the setting forth of a multitude of indeterminate problems. He
proves in the most beautiful manner that each flower of an orchid is
adapted to some insect which frequents and fertilises it, and these
adaptations are but a few cases of those immensely numerous ones which
have occurred in the lives of plants and animals. But why orchids
should have been formed so differently from other plants, why anything,
indeed, should be as it is, rather than in some of the other infinitely
numerous possible modes of existence, he can never show. The origin
of everything that exists is wrapped up in the past history of the
universe. At some one or more points in past time there must have been
arbitrary determinations which led to the production of things as they
are.


*Possibility of Divine Interference.*

I will now draw the reader’s attention to pages 149 to 152. I there
pointed out that all inductive inference involves the assumption that
our knowledge of what exists is complete, and that the conditions of
things remain unaltered between the time of our experience and the
time to which our inferences refer. Recurring to the illustration
of a ballot-box, employed in the chapter on the inverse method of
probabilities, we assume when predicting the probable nature of
the next drawing, firstly, that our previous drawings have been
sufficiently numerous to give us knowledge of the contents of the
box; and, secondly, that no interference with the ballot-box takes
place between the previous and the next drawings. The results yielded
by the theory of probability are quite plain. No finite number of
casual drawings can give us sure knowledge of the contents of the
box, so that, even in the absence of all disturbance, our inferences
are merely the best which can be made, and do not approach to
infallibility. If, however, interference be possible, even the theory
of probability ceases to be applicable, for, the amount and nature
of that interference being arbitrary and unknown, there ceases to
be any connection between premises and conclusion. Many years of
reflection have not enabled me to see the way of avoiding this hiatus
in scientific certainty. The conclusions of scientific inference appear
to be always of a hypothetical and provisional nature. Given certain
experience, the theory of probability yields us the true interpretation
of that experience and is the surest guide open to us. But the best
calculated results which it can give are never absolute probabilities;
they are purely relative to the extent of our information. It seems to
be impossible for us to judge how far our experience gives us adequate
information of the universe as a whole, and of all the forces and
phenomena which can have place therein.

I feel that I cannot in the space remaining at my command in the
present volume, sufficiently follow out the lines of thought suggested,
or define with precision my own conclusions. This chapter contains
merely *Reflections* upon subjects of so weighty a character that I
should myself wish for many years--nay for more than a lifetime of
further reflection. My purpose, as I have repeatedly said, is the
purely negative one of showing that atheism and materialism are no
necessary results of scientific method. From the preceding reviews of
the value of our scientific knowledge, I draw one distinct conclusion,
that we cannot disprove the possibility of Divine interference in
the course of nature. Such interference might arise, so far as our
knowledge extends, in two ways. It might consist in the disclosure
of the existence of some agent or spring of energy previously
unknown, but which effects a given purpose at a given moment. Like
the pre-arranged change of law in Babbage’s imaginary calculating
machine, there may exist pre-arranged surprises in the order of
nature, as it presents itself to us. Secondly, the same Power, which
created material nature, might, so far as I can see, create additions
to it, or annihilate portions which do exist. Such events are in a
certain sense inconceivable to us; yet they are no more inconceivable
than the existence of the world as it is. The indestructibility of
matter, and the conservation of energy, are very probable scientific
hypotheses, which accord satisfactorily with experiments of scientific
men during a few years past, but it would be gross misconception of
scientific inference to suppose that they are certain in the sense
that a proposition in geometry is certain. Philosophers no doubt hold
that *de nihilo nihil fit*, that is to say, their senses give them no
means of imagining to the mind how creation can take place. But we are
on the horns of a trilemma; we must either deny that anything exists,
or we must allow that it was created out of nothing at some moment of
past time, or that it existed from eternity. The first alternative is
absurd; the other two seem to me equally conceivable.


*Conclusion.*

It may seem that there is one point where our speculations must end,
namely where contradiction begins. The laws of Identity and Difference
and Duality were the foundations from which we started, and they are,
so far as I can see, the foundations which we can never quit without
tottering. Scientific Method must begin and end with the laws of
thought, but it does not follow that it will save us from encountering
inexplicable, and at least apparently contradictory results. The nature
of continuous quantity leads us into extreme difficulties. Any finite
space is composed of an infinite number of infinitely small spaces,
each of which, again, is composed of an infinite number of spaces of
a second order of smallness; these spaces of the second order are
composed, again, of infinitely small spaces of the third order. Even
these spaces of the third order are not absolute geometrical points
answering to Euclid’s definition of a point, as position without
magnitude. Go on as far as we will, in the subdivision of continuous
quantity, yet we never get down to the absolute point. Thus scientific
method leads us to the inevitable conception of an infinite series
of successive orders of infinitely small quantities. If so, there is
nothing impossible in the existence of a myriad universes within the
compass of a needle’s point, each with its stellar systems, and its
suns and planets, in number and variety unlimited. Science does nothing
to reduce the number of strange things that we may believe. When fairly
pursued it makes absurd drafts upon our powers of comprehension and
belief.

Some of the most precise and beautiful theorems in mathematical science
seem to me to involve apparent contradiction. Can we imagine that a
point moving along a perfectly straight line towards the west would
ever get round to the east and come back again, having performed, as
it were, a circuit through infinite space, yet without ever diverging
from a perfectly straight direction? Yet this is what happens to the
intersecting point of two straight lines in the same plane, when one
line revolves. The same paradox is exhibited in the hyperbola regarded
as an infinite ellipse, one extremity of which has passed to an
infinite distance and come back in the opposite direction. A varying
quantity may change its sign by passing either through zero or through
infinity. In the latter case there must be one intermediate value of
the variable for which the variant is indifferently negative infinity
and positive infinity. Professor Clifford tells me that he has found
a mathematical function which approaches infinity as the variable
approaches a certain limit; yet at the limit the function is finite!
Mathematicians may shirk difficulties, but they cannot make such
results of mathematical principles appear otherwise than contradictory
to our common notions of space.

The hypothesis that there is a Creator at once all-powerful
and all-benevolent is pressed, as it must seem to every candid
investigator, with difficulties verging closely upon logical
contradiction. The existence of the smallest amount of pain and evil
would seem to show that He is either not perfectly benevolent, or
not all-powerful. No one can have lived long without experiencing
sorrowful events of which the significance is inexplicable. But if we
cannot succeed in avoiding contradiction in our notions of elementary
geometry, can we expect that the ultimate purposes of existence shall
present themselves to us with perfect clearness? I can see nothing to
forbid the notion that in a higher state of intelligence much that is
now obscure may become clear. We perpetually find ourselves in the
position of finite minds attempting infinite problems, and can we be
sure that where we see contradiction, an infinite intelligence might
not discover perfect logical harmony?

From science, modestly pursued, with a due consciousness of the extreme
finitude of our intellectual powers, there can arise only nobler and
wider notions of the purpose of Creation. Our philosophy will be an
affirmative one, not the false and negative dogmas of Auguste Comte,
which have usurped the name, and misrepresented the tendencies of a
true *positive philosophy*. True science will not deny the existence of
things because they cannot be weighed and measured. It will rather lead
us to believe that the wonders and subtleties of possible existence
surpass all that our mental powers allow us clearly to perceive. The
study of logical and mathematical forms has convinced me that even
space itself is no requisite condition of conceivable existence.
Everything, we are told by materialists, must be here or there,
nearer or further, before or after. I deny this, and point to logical
relations as my proof.

There formerly seemed to me to be something mysterious in the
denominators of the binomial expansion (p. 190), which are reproduced
in the natural constant ε, or

  1 + 1/1 + 1/(1 . 2) + 1/(1 . 2 . 3) + ...

and in many results of mathematical analysis. I now perceive, as
already explained (pp. 33, 160, 383), that they arise out of the fact
that the relations of space do not apply to the logical conditions
governing the numbers of combinations as contrasted to those of
permutations. So far am I from accepting Kant’s doctrine that space is
a necessary form of thought, that I regard it as an accident, and an
impediment to pure logical reasoning. Material existences must exist in
space, no doubt, but intellectual existences may be neither in space
nor out of space; they may have no relation to space at all, just as
space itself has no relation to time. For all that I can see, then,
there may be intellectual existences to which both time and space are
nullities.

Now among the most unquestionable rules of scientific method is
that first law that *whatever phenomenon is, is*. We must ignore no
existence whatever; we may variously interpret or explain its meaning
and origin, but, if a phenomenon does exist, it demands some kind
of explanation. If then there is to be competition for scientific
recognition, the world without us must yield to the undoubted existence
of the spirit within. Our own hopes and wishes and determinations are
the most undoubted phenomena within the sphere of consciousness. If men
do act, feel, and live as if they were not merely the brief products of
a casual conjunction of atoms, but the instruments of a far-reaching
purpose, are we to record all other phenomena and pass over these? We
investigate the instincts of the ant and the bee and the beaver, and
discover that they are led by an inscrutable agency to work towards
a distant purpose. Let us be faithful to our scientific method, and
investigate also those instincts of the human mind by which man is led
to work as if the approval of a Higher Being were the aim of life.




INDEX.


  Abacus, logical, 104;
    arithmetical, 107;
    Panchrestus, 182.

  Aberration of light, 561;
    systematic, 547.

  Abscissio infiniti, 79, 713.

  Abstract terms, 27;
    number, 159.

  Abstraction, 704;
    logical, 25;
    numerical, 158;
    of indifferent circumstances, 97.

  Accademia del Cimento, 427, 432, 436, 527.

  Accident, logical, 700.

  Accidental discovery, 529.

  Achromatic lenses, 432.

  Actinometer, 337.

  Adamantine medium, 605, 751.

  Adjectives, 14, 30, 31, 35;
    indeterminate, 41.

  Adrain, of New Brunswick, 375.

  Affirmation, 44.

  Agassiz, on genera, 726;
    on creation of species, 763.

  Agreement, 44.

  Airy, Sir George Biddell, on perpetual motion, 223;
    new property of sphere, 232;
    pendulum experiments, 291, 304, 348, 567;
    standard clock, 353;
    book on *Errors of Observation*, 395;
    tides, 488;
    extra-polation, 495;
    Thales’ eclipse, 537;
    interference of light, 539;
    density of earth, 291.

  Alchemists, 505;
    how misled, 428.

  Algebra, 123, 155, 164;
    Diophantine, 631.

  Algebraic, equations, 123;
    geometry, 633.

  Allotropic state, 663, 670.

  Alloys, possible number, 191;
    properties, 528.

  Alphabet, the Logical, 93, 104, 125;
    Morse, 193.

  Alphabet, permutations of letters of the, 174, 179.

  Alphabetic indexes, 714.

  Alternative relations, 67;
    exclusive and unexclusive, 205.

  Ampère, electricity, 547;
    classification, 679.

  Anagrams, 128.

  Analogy, 627;
    of logical and numerical terms, 160;
    and generalisation, 596;
    in mathematical sciences, 631;
    in theory of undulations, 635;
    in astronomy, 638;
    failure of, 641.

  Analysis, logical, 122.

  Andrews, Prof. Thomas, experiments on gaseous state, 71, 613, 665, 753.

  Angström, on spectrum, 424.

  Angular magnitude, 305, 306, 326.

  Antecedent defined, 225.

  Anticipation of Nature, 509.

  Anticipations, of Principle of Substitution, 21;
    of electric telegraph, 671.

  Apparent, equality, 275;
    sequence of events, 409.

  Approximation, theory of, 456;
    to exact laws, 462;
    mathematical principles of, 471;
    arithmetic of, 481.

  Aqueous vapour, 500.

  Aquinas, on disjunctive propositions, 69.

  Arago, photometer, 288;
    rotating disc, 535;
    his philosophic character, 592.

  Archimedes, *De Arenæ Numero*, 195;
    centre of gravity, 363.

  Arcual unit, 306, 330.

  Argyll, Duke of, 741.

  Aristarchus on sun’s and moon’s distances, 294.

  Aristotelian doctrines, 666.

  Aristotle, dictum, 21;
    singular terms, 39;
    overlooked simple identities, 40;
    order of premises, 114;
    logical error, 117;
    definition of time, 307;
    on science, 595;
    on white swans, 666.

  Arithmetic, reasoning in, 167;
    of approximate quantities, 481.

  Arithmetical triangle, 93, 143, 182, 202, 378, 383;
    diagram of, 184;
    connection with Logical Alphabet, 189;
    in probability, 208.

  Asteroids, discovery of, 412, 748.

  Astronomy, physical, 459.

  Atmospheric tides, 553.

  Atomic theory, 662.

  Atomic weights, 563.

  Atoms, size of, 195;
    impossibility of observing, 406.

  Augustin on time, 307.

  Average, 359, 360;
    divergence from, 188;
    etymology of, 363.

  Axes of crystals, 686.

  Axioms of algebra, 164.


  Babbage, Charles, calculating machine, 107, 231, 743;
    lighthouse signals, 194;
    natural constants, 329;
    Mosaic history, 412;
    universal and general truths, 646;
    change of law, 230;
    persistence of effects, 757.

  Bacon, Francis Lord, *Novum Organum*, 107;
    on induction, 121;
    biliteral cipher, 193;
    First Aphorism, 219;
    on causes, 221;
    Copernican system, 249, 638;
    deficient powers of senses, 278;
    observation, 402;
    Natural History, 403;
    use of hypothesis, 506;
    his method, 507;
    *experimentum crucis*, 519;
    error of his method, 576;
    ostensive, clandestine instances, &c., 608, 610;
    *latens precessus*, 619.

  Bacon, Roger, on the rainbow, 526, 598.

  Baily, Francis, 272;
    density of earth, 342, 566;
    experiments with torsion balance, 370, 397, 432, 567–8;
    motions of stars, 572.

  Bain,  Alexander, on powers of mind, 4;
    Mill’s reform of logic, 227.

  Baker’s poem, *The Universe*, 621.

  Balance, use of the chemical, 292, 351, 354, 369;
    delicacy of, 304;
    vibrations of, 369.

  Ballot, Buys, experiment on sound, 541.

  Ballot-box, simile of, 150, 251–6, 765.

  Barbara, 55, 57, 88, 105, 141.

  Baroko, 85.

  Barometer, 659;
    Gay Lussac’s standard, 346;
    variations, 337, 346, 349.

  Bartholinus on double refraction, 585.

  Base-line, measurement of, 304.

  Bauhusius, verses of, 175.

  Baxendell, Joseph, 552.

  Beneke, on substitution, 21.

  Bennet, momentum of light, 435.

  Bentham, George, 15;
    bifurcate classification, 695;
    infima species, 702;
    works on classification, 703;
    analytical key to flora, 712.

  Bentham, Jeremy, on analogy, 629;
    bifurcate classification, 703.

  Benzenberg’s experiment, 388.

  Bernoulli, Daniel, planetary orbits, 250;
    resisting media and projectiles, 467;
    vibrations, 476.

  Bernoulli, James, 154;
    numbers of, 124;
    Protean verses, 175;
    *De Arte Conjectandi* quoted, 176, 183;
    on figurate numbers, 183;
    theorem of, 209;
    false solution in probability, 213;
    solution of inverse problem, 261.

  Bessel, F. W., 375;
    law of error, 384;
    formula for periodic variations, 488;
    use of hypothesis, 506;
    solar parallax, 560–2;
    ellipticity of earth, 565;
    pendulum experiments, 604.

  Bias, 393, 402.

  Biela’s comet, 746.

  Bifurcate classification, 694.

  Binomial theorem, 190;
    discovery of, 231.

  Biot, on tension of vapour, 500.

  Blind experiments, 433.

  Bode’s law, 147, 257, 660.

  Boethius, quoted, 33;
    on kinds of mean, 360.

  Boiling point, 442, 659.

  Bonnet’s theory of reproduction, 621.

  Boole, George, on sign of equality, 15;
    his calculus of logic, 23, 113, 634;
    on logical terms, 33;
    law of commutativeness, 35;
    use of *some*, 41–2;
    disjunctive propositions, 70;
    Venn on his method, 90;
    *Laws of Thought*, 155;
    statistical conditions, 168;
    propositions numerically definite, 172;
    on probability, 199;
    general method in probabilities, 206;
    Laplace’s solution of inverse problem, 256;
    law of error, 377.

  Borda, his repeating circle, 290.

  Boscovich’s hypothesis, 512.

  Botany, 666, 678, 681;
    modes of classification, 678;
    systematic, 722;
    nomenclature of, 727.

  Bowen, Prof. Francis, on inference, 118;
    classification, 674.

  Boyle’s, Robert, law of gaseous pressure, 468, 470, 619;
    on hypothesis, 510;
    barometer, 659.

  Bradley, his observations, 384;
    accuracy of, 271;
    aberration of light, 535.

  Bravais, on law of error, 375.

  Brewer, W. H., 142.

  Brewster, Sir David, iridescent colours, 419;
    spectrum, 429;
    Newton’s theory of colours, 518;
    refractive indices, 10, 527;
    optic axes, 446.

  British Museum, catalogue of, 717.

  Brodie, Sir B. C., on errors of experiment, 388, 464;
    ozone, 663.

  Brown, Thomas, on cause, 224.

  Buckle, Thomas, on constancy of average, 656;
    science of history, 760.

  Buffon, on probability, 215;
    definition of genius, 576.

  Bunsen, Robert, spectrum, 244;
    photometrical researches, 273, 324, 441;
    calorimeter, 343.

  Butler, Bishop, on probability, 197.


  Calorescence, 664.

  Camestres, 84.

  Canton, on compressibility of water, 338.

  Carbon, 640, 728;
    conductibility of, 442.

  Cardan, on inclined plane, 501.

  Cards, combinations of, 190.

  Carlini, pendulum experiments, 567.

  Carnot’s law, 606.

  Carpenter, Dr. W. B., 412.

  Catalogues, art of making, 714.

  Cauchy, undulatory theory, 468.

  Cause, 220;
    definition of, 224.

  Cavendish’s experiment, 272, 566.

  Cayley, Professor, 145;
    on mathematical tables, 331;
    numbers of chemical compounds, 544.

  Celarent, 55.

  Centre of gravity, 363, 524;
    of oscillation, gyration, &c., 364.

  Centrobaric bodies, 364.

  Certainty, 235, 266.

  Cesare, 85.

  Chalmers, on collocations, 740.

  Chance, 198.

  Character, human, 733.

  Characteristics, 708.

  Chauvenet, Professor W., on treatment of observations, 391.

  Chemical affinity, 614;
    analysis, 713.

  Chladni, 446.

  Chloroform, discovery of, 531.

  Chronoscope, 616.

  Cipher, 32;
    Bacon’s, 193.

  Circle, circumference of, 389.

  Circumstances, indifferent, 419.

  Circumstantial evidence, 264.

  Clairaut, 650, 651;
    on gravity, 463.

  Classes, 25;
    problem of common part of three, 170.

  Classification, 673;
    involving induction, 675;
    multiplicity of modes, 677;
    natural and artificial systems, 679;
    in crystallography, 685;
    symbolic statement of, 692;
    bifurcate, 694;
    an inverse and tentative operation, 689;
    diagnostic, 710;
    by indexes, 714;
    of books, 715;
    in biological sciences, 718;
    genealogical, 719;
    by types, 722;
    limits of, 730.

  Clifford, Professor, on types of compound statements, 143, 529;
    first and last catastrophe, 744;
    mathematical function, 768.

  Clocks, astronomical, 340, 353.

  Clouds, 447;
    cirrous, 411.

  Coincidences, 128;
    fortuitous, 261;
    measurement by, 292;
    method of, 291.

  Collective terms, 29, 39.

  Collocations of matter, 740.

  Colours, iridescent, 419;
    natural, 518;
    perception of, 437;
    of spectrum, 584.

  Combinations, 135, 142;
    doctrine of, 173;
    of letters of alphabet, 174;
    calculations of, 180;
    higher orders of, 194.

  Combinatorial analysis, 176.

  Comets, 449;
    number of, 408;
    hyperbolic, 407;
    classification of, 684;
    conflict with, 746–7;
    Halley’s comet, 537;
    Lexell’s comet, 651.

  Commutativeness, law of, 35, 72, 177.

  Comparative use of instruments, 299.

  Compass, variations of, 281.

  Complementary statements, 144.

  Compossible alternatives, 69.

  Compound statements, 144;
    events, 204.

  Compounds, chemical, 192.

  Comte, Auguste, on probability, 200, 214;
    on prevision, 536;
    his positive philosophy, 752, 760, 768.

  Concrete number, 159.

  Conditions, of logical symbols, 32;
    removal of usual, 426;
    interference of unsuspected, 428;
    maintenance of similar, 443;
    approximation to natural, 465.

  Condorcet, 2;
    his problem, 253.

  Confusion of elements, 237.

  Conical refraction, 653.

  Conjunction  of  planets,  293, 657.

  Consequent, definition of, 225.

  Conservation of energy, 738.

  Constant numbers of nature, 328;
    mathematical, 330;
    physical, 331;
    astronomical, 332;
    terrestrial, 333;
    organic, 333;
    social, 334.

  Continuity, law of, 615, 729;
    sense of, 493;
    detection of, 610;
    failure of, 619.

  Continuous quantity, 274, 485.

  Contradiction, law of, 31, 74.

  Contrapositive,  proposition,  84, 136;
    conversion, 83.

  Conversion of propositions, 46, 118.

  Copernican theory, 522, 625, 638, 647.

  Copula, 16.

  Cornu, velocity of light, 561.

  Corpuscular theory, 520, 538, 667.

  Correction, method of, 346.

  Correlation, 678, 681.

  Cotes, Roger, use of mean, 359;
    method of least squares, 377.

  Coulomb, 272.

  Couple, mechanical, 653.

  Creation, problem of, 740.

  Crookes’ radiometer, 435.

  Cross divisions, 144.

  Crystallography, 648, 654, 658, 678, 754;
    systems of, 133;
    classification in, 685.

  Crystals, 602;
    Dana’s classification of, 711;
    pseudomorphic, 658.

  Curves, use of, 392, 491, 496;
    of various degrees, 473.

  Cuvier, on experiment, 423;
    on inferences, 682.

  Cyanite, 609.

  Cycloid, 633.

  Cycloidal pendulum, 461.

  Cypher, 124.


  D’Alembert, blunders in probability, 213, 214;
    on gravity, 463.

  Dalton, laws of, 464, 471;
    atomic theory, 662.

  Darapti, 59.

  Darii, 56.

  Darwin, Charles, his works, 131;
    negative results of observation, 413;
    arguments against his theory, 437;
    cultivated plants, 531;
    his influence, 575;
    classification, 718;
    constancy of character in classification, 720–1;
    on definition, 726;
    restoration of limbs, 730;
    tendency of his theory, 762, 764.

  Davy, Sir H., on new instruments, 270;
    nature of heat, 343, 417;
    detection of salt in electrolysis, 428.

  Day, sidereal, 310;
    length of, 289.

  Decandolle, on classification, 696.

  Decyphering, 124.

  Deduction, 11, 49.

  Deductive reasoning, 534;
    miscellaneous forms of, 60;
    probable, 209.

  Definition, 39, 62, 711, 723;
    purpose of, 54;
    of cause and power, 224.

  De Morgan, Augustus, negative terms, 14;
    Aristotle’s logic, 18;
    relatives, 23;
    logical universe, 43;
    complex propositions, 75;
    contraposition, 83;
    formal logic quoted, 101;
    error of his system, 117;
    anagram of his name, 128;
    numerically definite reasoning, 168–172;
    probability, 198;
    belief, 199;
    experiments in probability, 207;
    probable deductive arguments, 209–210;
    trisection of angle, 233;
    probability of inference, 259;
    arcual unit, 306;
    mathematical tables, 331;
    personal error, 348;
    average, 363;
    his works on probability, 394–395;
    apparent sequence, 409;
    sub-equality, 480;
    rule of approximation, 481;
    negative areas, 529;
    generalisation, 600;
    double algebra, 634;
    bibliography, 716;
    catalogues, 716;
    extensions of algebra, 758.

  Density, unit of, 316;
    of earth, 387;
    negative, 642.

  Descartes, vortices, 517;
    geometry, 632.

  Description, 62.

  Design, 762–763.

  Determinants, inference by, 50.

  Development, logical, 89, 97.

  Diagnosis, 708.

  Dichotomy, 703.

  Difference, 44;
    law of, 5;
    sign of, 17;
    representation of, 45;
    inference with, 52, 166;
    form of, 158.

  Differences of numbers, 185.

  Differential calculus, 477.

  Differential thermometer, 345.

  Diffraction of light, 420.

  Dimensions, theory of, 325.

  Dip-needle, observation of, 355.

  Direct deduction, 49.

  Direction of motion, 47.

  Discontinuity, 620.

  Discordance, of theory and experiment, 558;
    of theories, 587.

  Discoveries, accidental, 529;
    predicted, 536;
    scope for, 752.

  Discrimination, 24;
    power of, 4.

  Disjunctive, terms, 66;
    conjunction, 67;
    propositions, 66;
    syllogism, 77;
    argument, 106.

  Dissipation of energy, 310.

  Distance of statements, 144.

  Divergence from average, 188.

  Diversity, 156.

  Divine interference, 765.

  Dollond, achromatic lenses, 608.

  Donkin, Professor, 375;
    on probability, 199, 216;
    principle of inverse method, 244.

  Double refraction, 426.

  Dove’s law of winds, 534.

  Draper’s law, 606.

  Drobitsch, 15.

  Duality, 73, 81;
    law of, 5, 45, 92, 97.

  Dulong and Petit, 341, 471.

  Duration, 308.


  ε, 330, 769.

  Earth, density of, 387;
    ellipticity, 565.

  Eclipses, 656;
    Egyptian records of, 246;
    of Jupiter’s satellites, 294, 372;
    solar, 486.

  Electric, sense, 405;
    acid, 428;
    fluid, 523.

  Electric telegraph, anticipations of, 671.

  Electricity, theories of, 522;
    duality of, 590.

  Electrolysis, 428, 530.

  Electro-magnet, use of, 423.

  Elements, confusion of, 237;
    definition, 427;
    classification, 676, 677, 690.

  Elimination, 58.

  Ellicott, observation on clocks, 455.

  Ellipsis, 41;
    of terms, 57.

  Elliptic variation, 474.

  Ellipticity of earth, 565.

  Ellis, A. J., contributions to formal logic, 172.

  Ellie, Leslie, 23, 375.

  Ellis, W., on moon’s influence, 410.

  Emanation, law of, 463.

  Emotions, 732.

  Empirical, knowledge, 505, 525–526;
    measurement, 552.

  Encke, on mean, 386, 389;
    his comet, 570, 605;
    on resisting medium, 523;
    solar parallax, 562.

  Energy, unit of, 322;
    conservation of, 465;
    reconcentration of, 751.

  English language, words in, 175.

  Eözoon canadense, 412, 668.

  Equality, sign of, 14;
    axiom, 163;
    four meanings of, 479.

  Equations, 46, 53, 160;
    solution of, 123.

  Equilibrium, unstable, 276, 654.

  Equisetaceæ, 721.

  Equivalence of propositions, 115, 120, 132;
    remarkable case of, 529, 657.

  Eratosthenes, sieve of, 82, 123, 139;
    measurement of degree, 293.

  Error, function, 330, 376, 381;
    elimination of, 339, 353;
    personal, 347;
    law of, 374;
    origin of law, 383;
    verification of law, 383;
    probable, 386;
    mean, 387;
    constant, 396;
    variation of small errors, 479.

  Ether, luminiferous, 512, 514, 605.

  Euclid, axioms, 51, 163;
    indirect proof, 84;
    10th book, 117th proposition, 275;
    on analogy, 631.

  Euler, on certainty of inference, 238;
    corpuscular theory, 435;
    gravity, 463;
    on ether, 514.

  Everett, Professor, unit of angle, 306;
    metric system, 328.

  Evolution, theory of, 761.

  Exact science, 456.

  Exceptions, 132, 644, 728;
    classification of, 645;
    imaginary, 647;
    apparent, 649;
    singular, 652;
    divergent, 655;
    accidental, 658;
    novel, 661;
    limiting, 663;
    real, 666;
    unclassed, 668.

  Excluded middle, law of, 6.

  Exclusive alternatives, 68.

  Exhaustive investigation, 418.

  Expansion, of bodies, 478;
    of liquids, 488.

  Experiment, 400, 416;
    in probability, 208;
    test or blind, 433;
    negative results of, 434;
    limits of, 437;
    collective, 445;
    simplification of, 422;
    failure in simplification, 424.

  Experimentalist, character of, 574, 592.

  Experimentum crucis, 518, 667.

  Explanation, 532.

  Extent of meaning, 26;
    of terms, 48.

  Extrapolation, 495.


  Factorials, 179.

  Facts, importance of false, 414;
    conformity with, 516.

  Fallacies, 62;
    analysed by indirect method, 102;
    of observation, 408.

  Faraday, Michael, measurement of gold-leaf, 296;
    on gravity, 342, 589;
    magnetism of gases, 352;
    vibrating plate, 419;
    electric poles, 421;
    circularly polarised light, 424, 588, 630;
    freezing mixtures, 427;
    magnetic experiments, 431, 434;
    lines of magnetic force, 446, 580;
    errors of experiment, 465;
    electrolysis, 502;
    velocity of light, 520;
    prediction, 543;
    relations of physical forces, 547;
    character of, 578, 587;
    ray vibrations, 579;
    mathematical power, 580;
    philosophic reservation of opinion, 592;
    use of heavy glass, 609;
    electricity, 612;
    radiant matter, 642;
    hydrogen, 691.

  Fatality, belief in, 264.

  Ferio, 56.

  Figurate numbers, 183, 186.

  Figure of earth, 459, 565.

  Fizeau, use of Newton’s rings, 297, 582;
    fixity of properties, 313;
    velocity of light, 441, 561.

  Flamsteed, use of wells, 294;
    standard stars, 301;
    parallax of pole-star, 338;
    selection of observations, 358;
    astronomical instruments, 391;
    solar eclipses, 486.

  Fluorescence, 664.

  Fontenelle on the senses, 405.

  Forbes, J. D., 248.

  Force, unit of, 322, 326;
    emanating, 464;
    representation of, 633.

  Formulæ, empirical, 487;
    rational, 489.

  Fortia, *Traité des Progressions*, 183.

  Fortuitous coincidences, 261.

  Fossils, 661.

  Foster, G. C., on classification, 691.

  Foucault, rotating mirror, 299;
    pendulum, 342, 431, 522;
    on velocity of light, 441, 521, 561.

  Fourier, Joseph, theory of dimensions, 325;
    theory of heat, 469, 744.

  Fowler, Thomas, on method of difference, 439;
    reasoning from case to case, 227.

  Frankland, Professor Edward, on spectrum of gases, 606.

  Franklin’s experiments on heat, 424.

  Fraunhofer, dark lines of spectrum, 429.

  Freezing-point, 546.

  Freezing mixtures, 546.

  Fresnel, inflexion of light, 420;
    corpuscular theory, 521;
    on use of hypothesis, 538;
    double refraction, 539.

  Friction, 417;
    determination of, 347.

  Function, definitions of, 489.

  Functions, discovery of, 496.


  Galileo, 626;
    on cycloid, 232, 235;
    differential method of observation, 344;
    projectiles, 447, 466;
    use of telescope, 522;
    gravity, 604;
    principle of continuity, 617.

  Gallon, definition of, 318.

  Galton, Francis, divergence from mean, 188;
    works by, 188, 655;
    on hereditary genius, 385, 655.

  Galvanometer, 351.

  Ganières, de, 182.

  Gases, 613;
    properties of, 601, 602;
    perfect, 470;
    liquefiable, 665.

  Gauss, pendulum experiments, 316;
    law of error, 375–6;
    detection of error, 396;
    on gravity, 463.

  Gay Lussac, on boiling point, 659;
    law of, 669.

  Genealogical classification, 680, 719.

  General, terms, 29;
    truths, 647;
    notions, 673.

  Generalisation, 2, 594, 704;
    mathematical, 168;
    two meanings of, 597;
    value of, 599;
    hasty, 623.

  Genius, nature of, 575.

  Genus, 433, 698;
    generalissimum, 701;
    natural, 724.

  Geology, 667;
    records in, 408;
    slowness of changes, 438;
    exceptions in, 660.

  Geometric mean, 361.

  Geometric reasoning, 458;
    certainty of, 267.

  Giffard’s injector, 536.

  Gilbert, on rotation of earth, 249;
    magnetism of silver, 431;
    experimentation, 443.

  Gladstone, J. H., 445.

  Glaisher, J. W. L., on mathematical tables, 331;
    law of error, 375, 395.

  Gold, discovery of, 413.

  Gold-assay process, 434.

  Gold-leaf, thickness of, 296.

  Graham, Professor Thomas, on chemical affinity, 614;
    continuity, 616;
    nature of hydrogen, 691.

  Grammar, 39;
    rules of, 31.

  Grammatical, change, 119;
    equivalence, 120.

  Gramme, 317.

  Graphical method, 492.

  Gravesande, on inflection of light, 420.

  Gravity, 422, 512, 514, 604, 740;
    determination of, 302;
    elimination of, 427;
    law of, 458, 462, 474;
    inconceivability of, 510;
    Newton’s theory, 555;
    variation of, 565;
    discovery of law, 581;
    Faraday on, 589;
    discontinuity in, 620;
    Aristotle on, 649;
    Hooke’s experiment, 436.

  Grimaldi on the spectrum, 584.

  Grove, Mr. Justice, on ether, 514;
    electricity, 615.

  Guericke, Otto von, 432.


  Habit, formation of, 618.

  Halley, trade-winds, 534.

  Halley’s comet, 537, 570.

  Hamilton, Sir William, disjunctive propositions, 69;
    inference, 118;
    free-will, 223.

  Hamilton, Sir W. Rowan, on conical refraction, 540;
    quaternions, 634.

  Harley, Rev. Robert, on Boole’s logic, 23, 155.

  Harris, standards of length, 312.

  Hartley, on logic, 7.

  Hatchett, on alloys, 191.

  Haughton, Professor, on tides, 450;
    muscular exertion, 490.

  Haüy, on crystallography, 529.

  Hayward, R. B., 142.

  Heat, unit of, 324;
    measurement of, 349;
    experiments on, 444;
    mechanical equivalent of, 568.

  Heavy glass, 588, 609.

  Helmholtz, on microscopy, 406;
    undulations, 414;
    sound, 476.

  Hemihedral crystals, 649.

  Herschel, Sir John, on rotation of plane of polarisation of light, 129, 630;
    quartz crystals, 246;
    numerical precision, 273;
    photometry, 273;
    light of stars, 302;
    actinometer, 337;
    mean and average, 363;
    eclipses of Jupiter’s satellites, 372;
    law of error, 377;
    error in observations, 392;
    on observation, 400;
    moon’s influence on clouds, 410;
    comets, 411;
    spectrum analysis, 429;
    collective instances, 447;
    principle of forced vibrations, 451, 663;
    meteorological variations, 489;
    double stars, 499, 685;
    direct action, 502;
    use of theory, 508;
    ether, 515;
    *experimentum crucis*, 519;
    interference of light, 539;
    interference of sound, 540;
    density of earth, 567;
    residual phenomena, 569;
    helicoidal dissymmetry, 630;
    fluorescence, 664.

  Hindenburg, on combinatorial analysis, 176.

  Hipparchus, used method of repetition, 289;
    longitudes of stars, 294.

  Hippocrates, area of lunule, 480.

  History, science of, 760.

  Hobbes, Thomas, definition of cause, 224;
    definition of time, 307;
    on hypothesis, 510.

  Hofmann, unit called crith, 321;
    on prediction, 544;
    on anomalies, 670.

  Homogeneity, law of, 159, 327.

  Hooke, on gravitation, 436, 581;
    philosophical method, 507;
    on strange things, 671.

  Hopkinson, John, 194;
    method of interpolation, 497.

  Horrocks, use of mean, 358;
    use of hypothesis, 507.

  Hume on perception, 34.

  Hutton, density of earth, 566.

  Huxley, Professor Thomas, 764;
    on hypothesis, 509;
    classification, 676;
    mammalia, 682;
    palæontology, 682.

  Huyghens, theory of pendulum, 302;
    pendulum standard, 315;
    cycloidal pendulum, 341;
    differential method, 344;
    distant stars, 405;
    use of hypothesis, 508;
    philosophical method of, 585;
    on analogy, 639.

  Hybrids, 727.

  Hydrogen, expansion of, 471;
    refractive power, 527;
    metallic nature of, 691.

  Hygrometry, 563.

  Hypotheses, use of, 265, 504;
    substitution of simple hypotheses, 458;
    working hypotheses, 509;
    requisites of, 510;
    descriptive, 522, 686;
    representative, 524;
    probability of, 559.


  Identical propositions, 119.

  Identities, simple, 37;
    partial, 40;
    limited, 42;
    simple and partial, 111;
    inference from, 51, 55.

  Identity, law of, 5, 6, 74;
    expression of, 14;
    propagating power, 20;
    reciprocal, 46.

  Illicit process, of major term, 65, 103;
    of minor term, 65.

  Immediate inference, 50, 61.

  Imperfect induction, 146, 149.

  Inclusion, relation of, 40.

  Incommensurable quantities, 275.

  Incompossible events, 205.

  Independence of small effects, 475.

  Independent events, 204.

  Indestructibility of matter, 465.

  Indexes, classification by, 714;
    formation of, 717.

  India-rubber, properties of, 545.

  Indirect method of deduction, 49, 81;
    illustrations of, 98;
    fallacies analysed by, 102;
    the test of equivalence, 115.

  Induction, 11, 121;
    symbolic statement of, 131;
    perfect, 146;
    imperfect, 149;
    philosophy of, 218;
    grounds of, 228;
    illustrations of, 229;
    quantitative, 483;
    problem of two classes, 134;
    problem of three classes, 137.

  Inductive truths, classes of, 219.

  Inequalities, reasoning by, 47, 163, 165–166.

  Inference, 9;
    general formula of, 17;
    immediate, 50;
    with two simple identities, 51;
    from simple and partial identity, 53;
    with partial identities, 55;
    by sum of predicates, 61;
    by disjunctive propositions, 76;
    indirect method of, 81;
    nature of, 118;
    principle of mathematical, 162;
    certainty of, 236.

  Infima species, 701, 702.

  Infiniteness of universe, 738.

  Inflection of light, 420.

  Instantiæ, citantes, evocantes, radii, curriculi, 270;
    monodicæ, irregulares, heteroclitæ, 608;
    clandestinæ, 610.

  Instruments of measurement, 284.

  Insufficient enumeration, 176.

  Integration, 123.

  Intellect, etymology of, 5.

  Intension of logical terms, 26, 48;
    of propositions, 47.

  Interchangeable system, 20.

  Interpolation, 495;
    in meteorology, 497.

  Inverse, process, 12;
    operation, 122, 689;
    problem of two classes, 134;
    problem of three classes, 137;
    problem of probability, 240, 251;
    rules of inverse method, 257;
    simple illustrations, 253;
    general solution, 255.

  Iodine, the substance X, 523.

  Iron, properties of, 528, 670.

  *Is*, ambiguity of verb, 16, 41.

  Isomorphism, 662.

  Ivory, 375.


  James, Sir H., on density of earth, 567.

  Jenkin, Professor Fleming, 328.

  Jevons, W. S., on use of mean, 361;
    on pedesis or molecular movement of microscopic particles, 406, 549;
    cirrous clouds, 411;
    spectrum analysis, 429;
    elevated rain-gauges, 430;
    experiments on clouds, 447;
    on muscular exertion, 490;
    resisting medium, 570;
    anticipations of the electric telegraph, 671.

  Jones, Dr. Bence, Life of Faraday, 578.

  Jordanus, on the mean, 360.

  Joule, 545;
    on thermopile, 299, 300;
    mechanical equivalent of heat, 325, 347, 568;
    temperature of air, 343;
    rarefaction, 444;
    on Thomson’s prediction, 543;
    molecular theory of gases, 548;
    friction, 549;
    thermal phenomena of fluids, 557.

  Jupiter, satellites of, 372, 458, 638, 656;
    long inequality of, 455;
    figure of, 556.


  Kames, Lord, on bifurcate classification, 697.

  Kant, disjunctive propositions, 69;
    analogy, 597;
    doctrine of space, 769.

  Kater’s pendulum, 316.

  Keill, law of emanating forces, 464;
    axiom of simplicity, 625.

  Kepler, on star-discs, 390;
    comets, 408;
    laws of, 456;
    refraction, 501;
    character of, 578.

  Kinds of things, 718.

  King Charles and the Royal Society, 647.

  Kirchhoff, on lines of spectrum, 245.

  Kohlrausch, rules of approximate calculation, 479.


  Lagrange, formula for interpolation, 497;
    accidental discovery, 531;
    union of algebra and geometry, 633.

  Lambert, 15.

  Lamont, 452.

  Language, 8, 628, 643.

  Laplace, on probability, 200, 216;
    principles of inverse method, 242;
    solution of inverse problem, 256;
    planetary motions, 249, 250;
    conjunctions of planets, 293;
    observation of tides, 372;
    atmospheric tides, 367;
    law of errors, 378;
    dark stars, 404;
    hyperbolic comets, 407;
    his works on probability, 395;
    velocity of gravity, 435;
    stability of planetary system, 448, 746;
    form of Jupiter, 556;
    corpuscular theory, 521;
    ellipticity of earth, 565;
    velocity of sound, 571;
    analogy, 597;
    law of gravity, 615;
    inhabitants of planets, 640;
    laws of motion, 706;
    power of science, 739.

  Lavoisier, mistaken inference of, 238;
    pyrometer, 287;
    on experiments, 423;
    prediction of, 544;
    theory, 611;
    on acids, 667

  Law, 3;
    of simplicity, 33, 72, 161;
    commutativeness, 35, 160;
    disjunctive relation, 71;
    unity, 72, 157, 162;
    identity, 74;
    contradiction, 74, 82;
    duality, 73, 74, 81, 97, 169;
    homogeneity, 159;
    error, 374;
    continuity, 615;
    of Boyle, 619;
    natural, 737.

  Laws, of thought, 6;
    empirical mathematical, 487;
    of motion, 617;
    of botanical nomenclature, 727;
    natural hierarchy of, 742.

  Least squares, method of, 386, 393.

  Legendre, on geometry, 275;
    rejection of observations, 391;
    method of least squares, 377.

  Leibnitz, 154, 163;
    on substitution, 21;
    propositions, 42;
    blunder in probability, 213;
    on Newton, 515;
    continuity, 618.

  Leslie, differential thermometer, 345;
    radiating power, 425;
    on affectation of accuracy, 482.

  Letters, combinations of, 193.

  Leverrier, on solar parallax, 562.

  Lewis, Sir G. C., on time, 307.

  Life is change, 173.

  Light, intensity of, 296;
    unit, 324;
    velocity, 535, 560, 561;
    science of, 538;
    total reflection, 650;
    waves of, 637;
    classification of, 731.

  Lighthouses, Babbage on, 194.

  Limited identities, 42;
    inference of 59.

  Lindsay, Prof. T. M., 6, 21.

  Linear variation, 474.

  Linnæus on synopsis, 712;
    genera and species, 725.

  Liquid state, 601, 614.

  Locke, John, on induction, 121;
    origin of number, 157;
    on probability, 215;
    the word power, 221.

  Lockyer, J. Norman, classification of elements, 676.

  Logarithms, 148;
    errors in tables, 242.

  Logic, etymology of name, 5.

  Logical abacus, 104.

  Logical alphabet, 93, 116, 173, 417, 701;
    table of, 94;
    connection with arithmetical triangle, 189;
    in probability, 205.

  Logical conditions, numerical meaning of, 171.

  Logical machine, 107.

  Logical relations, number of, 142.

  Logical slate, 95.

  Logical truths, certainty of, 153.

  Lottery, the infinite, 2.

  Lovering, Prof., on ether, 606.

  Lubbock and Drinkwater-Bethune, 386, 395.

  Lucretius, rain of atoms, 223, 741;
    indestructibility of matter, 622.


  Machine, logical, 107.

  Macleay, system of classification, 719.

  Magnetism of gases, 352.

  Mallet, on earthquakes, 314.

  Malus, polarised light, 530.

  Mammalia, characters of, 681.

  Manchester Literary and Philosophical Society, papers quoted, 137, 143, 168.

  Mansel, on disjunctive propositions, 69.

  Mars, white spots of, 596.

  Maskelyne, on personal error, 347;
    deviation of plumbline, 369;
    density of earth, 566.

  Mass, unit of, 317, 325.

  Mathematical science, 767;
    incompleteness of, 754.

  Matter, uniform properties of, 603;
    variable properties, 606.

  Matthiessen, 528.

  Maximum points, 371.

  Maxwell, Professor Clerk, on the balance, 304;
    natural system of standards, 311, 319;
    velocity of electricity, 442;
    on Faraday, 580;
    his book on *Matter and Motion*, 634.

  Mayer, proposed repeating circle, 290;
    on mechanical equivalent of heat, 568, 572.

  Mean, etymology of, 359–360;
    geometric, 362;
    fictitious, 363;
    precise, 365;
    probable, 385;
    rejection of, 389;
    method of, 357, 554.

  Mean error, 387.

  Meaning, of names, 25;
    of propositions, 47.

  Measurement, of phenomena, 270;
    methods of, 282;
    instruments, 284;
    indirect, 296;
    accuracy of, 303;
    units and standards of, 305;
    explained results of, 554;
    agreement of modes of, 564.

  Mediate statements, 144.

  Melodies, possible number of, 191.

  Melvill, Thomas, on the spectrum, 429.

  *Membra dividentia*, 68.

  Metals, probable character of new, 258;
    transparency, 548;
    classification, 675;
    density, 706.

  Method, indirect, 98;
    of avoidance of error, 340;
    differential, 344;
    correction, 346;
    compensation, 350;
    reversal, 354;
    means, 357;
    least squares, 377, 386, 393;
    variations, 439;
    graphical, 492;
    Baconian, 507.

  Meteoric streams, 372.

  Meteoric cycle, 537.

  Metre, 349;
    error of, 314.

  Metric system, 318, 323.

  Michell, speculations, 212;
    on double stars, 247;
    Pleiades, 248;
    torsion balance, 566.

  Middle term undistributed, 64.

  Mill, John Stuart, disjunctive propositions, 69;
    induction, 121, 594;
    music, 191;
    probability, 200–201, 222;
    supposed reform of logic, 227;
    deductive method, 265, 508;
    elimination of chance, 385;
    joint method of agreement and difference, 425;
    method of variations, 484;
    on collocations, 740;
    erroneous tendency of his philosophy, 752.

  Miller, Prof. W. H., kilogram, 318.

  Mind, powers of, 4;
    phenomena of, 672.

  Minerals, classification of, 678.

  Minor term, illicit process of, 65.

  Mistakes, 7.

  *Modus, tolendo ponens*, 77;
    *ponendo tollens*, 78.

  Molecular movement, or pedesis, 406.

  Molecules, number of, 195.

  Momentum, 322, 326.

  Monro, C. J., correction by, 172;
    on Comte, 753.

  Monstrous productions, 657.

  Moon, supposed influence on clouds, 410;
    atmosphere of, 434;
    motions, 485;
    fall towards earth, 555.

  Morse alphabet, 193.

  Mother of pearl, 419.

  Müller, Max, on etymology of intellect, 5.

  Multiplication in logic, 161.

  Murphy, J. J., on disjunctive relation, 71.

  Murray, introduced use of ice, 343.

  Muscular susurrus, 298.

  Music, possible combinations of, 191.


  Names, 25;
    of persons, ships, &c., 680.

  Nature, 1;
    laws of, 737;
    uniformity of, 745.

  Nebular theory, 427.

  Negation, 44.

  Negative arguments, 621.

  Negative density, 642.

  Negative premises, 63, 103.

  Negative propositions, 43.

  Negative results of experiment, 434.

  Negative terms, 14, 45, 54, 74.

  Neil on use of hypothesis, 509.

  Neptune, discovery of, 537, 660.

  Newton, Sir Isaac, binomial theorem, 231;
    spectrum, 262, 418, 420, 424, 583;
    rings of, 288, 470;
    velocity of sound, 295;
    wave-lengths, 297;
    use of pendulum, 303;
    on time, 308;
    definition of matter, 316;
    pendulum experiment, 348, 443, 604;
    centrobaric bodies, 365;
    on weight, 422;
    achromatic lenses, 432;
    resistance of space, 435;
    absorption of light, 445;
    planetary motions, 249, 457, 463, 466, 467;
    infinitesimal calculus, 477;
    as an alchemist, 505;
    his knowledge of Bacon’s works, 507;
    *hypotheses non fingo*, 515;
    on vortices, 517;
    theory of colours, 518;
    corpuscular theory of light, 520;
    fits of easy reflection, &c., 523;
    combustible substances, 527;
    gravity, 555, 650;
    density of earth, 566;
    velocity of sound, 571;
    third law of motion, 622;
    his rules of philosophising, 625;
    fluxions, 633;
    theory of sound, 636;
    negative density, 642;
    rays of light having sides, 662.

  Newtonian Method, 581.

  Nicholson, discovery of electrolysis, 530.

  *Ninth Bridgewater Treatise* quoted, 743, 757.

  Nipher, Professor, on muscular exertion, 490.

  Noble, Captain, chronoscope, 308, 616.

  Nomenclature, laws of botanical, 727.

  Non-observation, arguments from, 411.

  Norwood’s measurement of a degree, 272.

  Nothing, 32.

  Number, nature of, 153, 156;
    concrete and abstract, 159, 305.

  Numbers, prime, 123;
    of Bernoulli, 124;
    figurate, 183;
    triangular, &c., 185.

  Numerical abstraction, 158.


  Observation, 399;
    mental conditions, 402;
    instrumental and sensual conditions, 404;
    external conditions, 407.

  Obverse statements, 144.

  Ocean, depth of, 297.

  Odours, 732.

  Oersted, on electro-magnetism, 530, 535.

  *Or*, meaning of, 70.

  Order, of premises, 114;
    of terms, 33.

  Orders of combinations, 194.

  Original research, 574.

  Oscillation, centre of, 364.

  Ostensive instances, 608.

  Ozone, 663.


  π, value of, 234, 529.

  Pack of cards, arrangement of, 241.

  Paley on design, 762, 763.

  Parallax, of stars, 344;
    of sun, 560.

  Parallel forces, 652.

  Paralogism, 62.

  Parity of reasoning, 268.

  Partial identities, 40, 55, 57, 111;
    induction of, 130.

  Particular quantity, 56.

  Particulars, reasoning from, 227.

  Partition, 29.

  Pascal, 176;
    arithmetical machine, 107;
    arithmetical triangle, 182;
    binomial formula, 182;
    error in probabilities, 213;
    barometer, 519.

  Passive state of steel, 659.

  Pedesis, or molecular movement of microscopic particles, 406, 612.

  Peirce, Professor, 23;
    on rejection of observations, 391.

  Pendulum, 290, 302, 315;
    faults of, 311;
    vibrations, 453, 454;
    cycloidal, 461.

  Perfect induction, 146, 149.

  Perigon, 306.

  Permutations, 173, 178;
    distinction from combinations, 177.

  Personal error, 347.

  Photometry, 288.

  Physiology, exceptions in, 666.

  Planets, conjunctions of, 181, 187, 657;
    discovery of, 412;
    motions, 457;
    perturbations of, 657;
    classification, 683;
    system of, 748.

  Plants, classification of, 678.

  Plateau’s experiments, 427.

  Plato on science, 595.

  Plattes, Gabriel, 434, 438.

  Pliny on tides, 451.

  Plumb-line, divergence of, 461.

  Plurality, 29, 156.

  Poinsot, on probability, 214.

  Poisson, on principle of the inverse method, 244;
    work on Probability, 395;
    Newton’s rings, 470;
    simile of ballot box, 524.

  Polarisation, 653;
    discovery of, 530.

  Pole-star, 652;
    observations of, 366.

  Poles, of magnets, 365;
    of battery, 421.

  Political economy, 760.

  Porphyry, on the Predicables, 698;
    tree of, 702.

  Port Royal logic, 22.

  Positive philosophy, 760, 768.

  Pouillet’s pyrheliometer, 337.

  Powell, Baden, 623;
    on planetary motions, 660.

  Power, definition of, 224.

  Predicables, 698.

  Prediction, 536, 739;
    in science of light, 538;
    theory of undulations, 540;
    other sciences, 542;
    by inversion of cause and effect, 545.

  Premises, order of, 114.

  Prime numbers, 123, 139;
    formula for, 230.

  *Principia*, Newton’s, 581, 583.

  Principle, of probability, 200;
    inverse method, 242;
    forced vibrations, 451;
    approximation, 471;
    co-existence of small vibrations, 476;
    superposition of small effects, 476.

  Probable error, 555.

  Probability, etymology of, 197;
    theory of, 197;
    principles, 200;
    calculations, 203;
    difficulties of theory, 213;
    application of theory, 215;
    in induction, 219;
    in judicial proceedings, 216;
    works on, 394;
    results of law, 656.

  Problems, to be worked by reader, 126;
    inverse problem of two classes, 135;
    of three classes, 137.

  Proclus, commentaries of, 232.

  Proctor, R. A., star-drifts, 248.

  Projectiles, theory of, 466.

  Proper names, 27.

  Properties, generality of, 600;
    uniform, 603;
    extreme instances, 607;
    correlation, 681.

  Property, logical, 699;
    peculiar, 699.

  Proportion, simple, 501.

  Propositions, 36;
    negative, 43;
    conversion of, 46;
    twofold meaning, 47;
    disjunctive, 66;
    equivalence of, 115;
    identical, 119;
    tautologous, 119.

  Protean verses, 175.

  Protoplasm, 524, 764.

  Prout’s law, 263, 464.

  Provisional units, 323.

  Proximate statements, 144.

  Pyramidal numbers, 185.

  Pythagoras, on duality, 95;
    on the number seven, 262, 624.


  Quadric variation, 474.

  Qualitative, reasoning, 48;
    propositions, 119.

  Quantification of predicate, 41.

  Quantitative, reasoning, 48;
    propositions, 119;
    questions, 278;
    induction, 483.

  Quantities, continuous, 274;
    incommensurable, 275.

  Quaternions, 160, 634.

  Quetelet, 188;
    experiment on probability, 208;
    on mean and average, 363;
    law of error, 378, 380;
    verification of law of error, 385.


  Radian, 306.

  Radiant matter, 642.

  Radiation of heat, 430.

  Radiometer, 435.

  Rainbow, theory of, 526, 533.

  Rainfall, variation of, 430.

  Ramean tree, 703, 704.

  Ramsden’s balance, 304.

  Rankine, on specific heat of air, 557;
    reconcentration of energy, 751.

  Rational formulæ, 489.

  Rayleigh, Lord, on graphical method, 495.

  Reasoning, arithmetical, 167;
    numerically definite, 168;
    geometrical, 458.

  Recorde, Robert, 15.

  Reduction, of syllogisms, 85;
    *ad absurdum*, 415;
    of observations, 552, 572.

  Reflection, total, 650.

  Refraction, atmospheric, 340, 356, 500;
    law of, 501;
    conical, 540;
    double, 585.

  Regnault, dilatation of mercury, 342;
    measurement of heat, 350;
    exact experiment, 397;
    on Boyle’s law, 468, 471;
    latent heat of steam, 487;
    graphical method, 494;
    specific heat of air, 557.

  Reid, on bifurcate classification, 697.

  Reign of law, 741, 759.

  Rejection of observations, 390.

  Relation, sign of, 17;
    logic of, 22;
    logical, 35;
    axiom of, 164.

  Repetition, method of, 287, 288.

  Representative hypotheses, 524.

  Reproduction, modes of, 730.

  Reservation of judgment, 592.

  Residual effects, 558;
    phenomena, 560, 569.

  Resisting medium, 310, 523, 570.

  Resonance, 453.

  Reusch, on substitution, 21.

  Reversal, method of, 354.

  Revolution, quantity of, 306.

  Robertson, Prof. Croom, 27, 101.

  Robison, electric curves, 446.

  Rock-salt, 609.

  Rœmer, divided circle, 355;
    velocity of light, 535.

  Roscoe, Prof., photometrical researches, 273;
    solubility of salts, 280;
    constant flame, 441;
    absorption of gases, 499;
    vanadium, 528;
    atomic weight of vanadium, 392, 649.

  Rousseau on geometry, 233.

  Rules, of inference, 9, 17;
    indirect method of inference, 89;
    for calculation of combinations, 180;
    of probabilities, 203;
    of inverse method, 257;
    for elimination of error, 353.

  Rumford, Count, experiments on heat, 343, 350, 467.

  Ruminants, Cuvier on, 683.

  Russell, Scott, on sound, 541.


  Sample, use of, 9.

  Sandeman, on perigon, 306;
    approximate arithmetic, 481.

  Saturn, motions of satellites, 293;
    rings, 293.

  Schehallien, attraction of, 369, 566.

  Schottus, on combinations, 179.

  Schwabe, on sun-spots, 452.

  Science, nature of, 1, 673.

  Selenium, 663, 670.

  Self-contradiction, 32.

  Senior’s definition of wealth, 75.

  Senses, fallacious indications of, 276.

  Seven, coincidences of number, 262;
    fallacies of, 624.

  Sextus, fatality of name, 264.

  Sieve of Eratosthenes, 82, 123, 139.

  Similars, substitution of, 17.

  Simple identity, 37, 111;
    inference of, 58;
    contrapositive, 86;
    induction of, 127.

  Simple statement, 143.

  Simplicity, law of, 33, 58, 72.

  Simpson, discovery of property of chloroform, 531.

  Simultaneity of knowledge, 34.

  Singular names, 27;
    terms, 129.

  Siren, 10, 298, 421.

  Slate, the logical, 95.

  Smeaton’s experiments, on water-wheels, 347;
    windmills, 401, 441.

  Smee, Alfred, logical machines, 107.

  Smell, delicacy of, 437.

  Smithsonian Institution, 329.

  Smyth, Prof. Piazzi, 452.

  Socrates, on the sun, 611.

  Solids, 602.

  Solubility of salts, 279.

  *Some*, the adjective, 41, 56.

  Sorites, 60.

  Sound, observations on, 356;
    undulations, 405, 421;
    velocity of, 571;
    classification of sounds, 732.

  Space, relations of, 220.

  Species, 698;
    infima, 701;
    natural, 724.

  Specific gravities, 301;
    heat of air, 557.

  Spence, on boiling point, 546.

  Spencer, Herbert, nature of logic, 4, 7;
    sign of equality, 15;
    rhythmical motion, 448;
    abstraction, 705;
    philosophy of, 718, 761, 762.

  Spectroscope, 437.

  Spectrum, 583.

  Spiritualism, 671.

  Spontaneous generation, 432.

  Standards of measurement, 305;
    the bar, 312;
    terrestrial, 314;
    pendulum, 315;
    provisional, 318;
    natural system, 319.

  Stars, discs of, 277;
    motions of, 280, 474;
    variations of, 281;
    approach or recess, 298;
    standard stars, 301;
    apparent diameter, 390;
    variable, 450;
    proper motions, 572;
    Bruno on, 639;
    new, 644;
    pole-star, 652;
    conflict with wandering stars, 748.

  Stas, M., his balance, 304;
    on atomic weights, 464.

  Statements, kinds of, 144.

  Statistical conditions, 168.

  Stevinus, on inclined plane, 622.

  Stewart, Professor Balfour, on resisting medium, 570;
    theory of exchanges, 571.

  Stifels, arithmetical triangle, 182.

  Stokes, Professor, on resistance, 475;
    fluorescence, 664.

  Stone, E. J., heat of the stars, 370;
    temperature of earth’s surface, 452;
    transit of Venus, 562.

  Struve on double stars, 247.

  Substantial terms, 28.

  Substantives, 14.

  Substitution of similars, 17, 45, 49, 104, 106;
    anticipations of, 21.

  Substitutive weighing, 345.

  *Sui generis*, 629, 728.

  Sulphur, 670.

  Summum genus, 93, 701.

  Sun, distance, 560;
    variations of spots, 452.

  Superposition, of small effects, 450;
    small motions, 476.

  Swan, W., on sodium light, 430.

  Syllogism, 140;
    moods of, 55, 84, 85, 88, 105, 141;
    numerically definite, 168.

  Symbols, use of, 13, 31, 32;
    of quantity, 33.

  Synthesis, 122;
    of terms, 30.


  Table-turning, 671.

  Tacit knowledge, 43.

  Tacquet on combinations, 179.

  Tait, P. G., 375;
    theory of comets, 571.

  Talbot on the spectrum, 429.

  Tartaglia on projectiles, 466.

  Tastes, classification of, 732.

  Tautologous propositions, 119.

  Teeth, use in classification, 710.

  Temperature, variations of, 453.

  Tension of aqueous vapour, 500.

  Terms, 24;
    abstract, 27;
    substantial, 28;
    collective, 29;
    synthesis of, 30;
    negative, 45.

  Terrot, Bishop, on probability, 212.

  Test experiments, 347, 433.

  Tetractys, 95.

  Thales, predicted eclipse, 537.

  Theory, results of, 534;
    facts known by, 547;
    quantitative, 551;
    of exchanges, 571;
    freedom of forming, 577;
    of evolution, 761.

  Thermometer, differential, 345;
    reading of, 390;
    change of zero, 390.

  Thermopile, 300.

  Thomas, arithmetical machine, 107.

  Thomson, Archbishop, 50, 61.

  Thomson, James, prediction by, 542;
    on gaseous state, 654.

  Thomson, Sir W., lighthouse signals, 194;
    size of atoms, 195;
    tides, 450;
    capillary attraction, 614;
    magnetism, 665;
    dissipation of energy, 744.

  Thomson and Tait, chronometry, 311;
    standards of length, 315;
    the crowbar, 460;
    polarised light, 653.

  Thomson, Sir Wyville, 412.

  Thunder-cloud, 612.

  Tides, 366, 450, 476, 541;
    velocity of, 298;
    gauge, 368;
    atmospheric, 367, 553.

  Time, 220;
    definition of, 307.

  Todhunter, Isaac, *History of the Theory of Probability*, 256, 375, 395;
    on insoluble problems, 757.

  Tooke, Horne, on cause, 226.

  Torricelli, cycloid, 235;
    his theorem, 605;
    on barometer, 666.

  Torsion balance, 272, 287.

  Transit of Venus, 294, 348, 562.

  Transit-circle, 355.

  Tree of Porphyry, 702;
    of Ramus, 703.

  Triangle, arithmetical, 93, 182.

  Triangular numbers, 185.

  Trigonometrical survey, 301;
    calculations of, 756.

  Trisection of angles, 414.

  Tuning-fork, 541.

  Tycho Brahe, 271;
    on star discs, 277;
    obliquity of earth’s axis, 289;
    circumpolar stars, 366;
    Sirius, 390.

  Tyndall, Professor, on natural constants, 328;
    magnetism of gases, 352;
    precaution in experiments, 431;
    use of imagination, 509;
    on Faraday, 547;
    magnetism, 549, 607;
    scope for discovery, 753.

  Types, of logical conditions, 140, 144;
    of statements, 145;
    classification by, 722.


  Ueberweg’s logic, 6.

  Ultimate statements, 144.

  Undistributed, attribute, 40;
    middle term, 64, 103.

  Undulations, of light, 558;
    analogy in theory of, 635.

  Undulatory theory, 468, 520, 538, 540;
    inconceivability of, 510.

  Unique objects, 728.

  Unit, definition of, 157;
    groups, 167;
    of measurement, 305;
    arcual, 306;
    of time, 307;
    space, 312;
    density, 316;
    mass, 317;
    subsidiary, 320;
    derived, 321;
    provisional, 323;
    of heat, 325;
    magnetical and electrical units, 326, 327.

  Unity, law of, 72.

  Universe, logical, 43;
    infiniteness of, 738;
    heat-history of, 744, 749;
    possible states of, 749.

  Uranus, anomalies of, 660.


  Vacuum, Nature’s abhorrence of, 513.

  Vapour densities, 548.

  Variable, variant, 440, 441, 483.

  Variation, linear, elliptic, &c., 474;
    method of, 439.

  Variations, logical, 140;
    periodic, 447;
    combined, 450;
    integrated, 452;
    simple proportional, 501.

  Variety, of nature, 173;
    of nature and art, 190;
    higher orders of, 192.

  Velocity, unit of, 321.

  Venn, Rev. John, logical problem by, 90;
    on Boole, 155;
    his work on *Logic of Chance*, 394.

  Venus, 449;
    transits of, 294.

  Verses, Protean, 175.

  Vibrations, law of, 295;
    principle of forced, 451;
    co-existence of small, 476.

  Vital force, 523.

  Voltaire on fossils, 661.

  Vortices, theory of, 513, 517.

  Vulcan, supposed planet, 414.


  Wallis, 124, 175.

  Water, compressibility of, 338;
    properties of, 610.

  Watt’s parallel motion, 462.

  Waves, 599, 635;
    nature of, 468;
    in canals, 535;
    earthquake, 297.

  Weak arguments, effect of, 211.

  Wells, on dew, 425.

  Wenzel, on neutral salts, 295.

  Whately, disjunctive propositions, 69;
    probable arguments, 210.

  Wheatstone, cipher, 124;
    galvanometer, 286;
    revolving mirror, 299, 308;
    kaleidophone, 445;
    velocity of electricity, 543.

  Whewell, on tides, 371, 542;
    method of least squares, 386.

  Whitworth, Sir Joseph, 304, 436.

  Whitworth, Rev. W. A., on *Choice and Chance*, 395.

  Wilbraham, on Boole, 206.

  Williamson, Professor A. W., chemical unit, 321;
    prediction by, 544.

  Wollaston, the goniometer, 287;
    light of moon, 302;
    spectrum, 429.

  Wren, Sir C., on gravity, 581.


  X, the substance, 523.


  Yard, standard, 397.

  Young, Dr. Thomas, tension of aqueous vapour, 500;
    use of hypotheses, 508;
    ethereal medium, 515.


  Zero point, 368.

  Zodiacal light, 276.

  Zoology, 666.


LONDON: R. CLAY, SONS, AND TAYLOR, PRINTERS,




BY THE SAME AUTHOR.


  ELEMENTARY LESSONS IN LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE. With Copious
  Questions and Examples, and a Vocabulary of Logical Terms. Ninth
  Edition. Fcap. 8vo. 3*s.* 6*d.*

  PRIMER OF LOGIC. With Illustrations and Questions. New Edition. 18mo.
  1*s.*

  STUDIES IN DEDUCTIVE LOGIC. A Manual for Students. Crown 8vo. 6*s.*

  THE SUBSTITUTION OF SIMILARS THE TRUE PRINCIPLE OF REASONING. Derived
  from a Modification of Aristotle’s Dictum. Fcap. 8vo. 2*s.* 6*d.*

  THE COAL QUESTION: an Inquiry Concerning the Progress of the Nation,
  and the probable exhaustion of our Coal Mines. Second Edition,
  revised. 8vo. 10*s.* 6*d.*

  THE THEORY OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. Second Edition, Revised and
  Enlarged, with New Preface. 8vo. 10*s.* 6*d.*

  PRIMER OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. New Edition. 18mo. 1*s.*

  INVESTIGATIONS IN CURRENCY AND FINANCE. With Diagrams, &c. 8vo.
  [*Just ready.*]

  THE STATE IN RELATION TO LABOUR (English Citizen Series). Crown 8vo.
  3*s.* 6*d.*


MACMILLAN AND CO., LONDON.


ELEMENTARY MANUAL OF THE PRINCIPLES OF CURRENCY.

  MONEY AND THE MECHANISM OF EXCHANGE. Fourth Edition. Crown 8vo. 5*s.*
  (International Scientific Series.)


HENRY S. KING AND CO.




SPELLING CORRECTIONS

  acording → according
  aklaline → alkaline
  an an → an
  aws → laws
  beween → between
  BOOK III → BOOK IV
  errror → error
  incapadle → incapable
  interpretion → interpretation
  justifed → justified
  longtitude → longitude
  Marriotte → Mariotte
  melecules → molecules
  Meropolitana → Metropolitana
  necesssarily → necessarily
  nnmber → number
  or → of
  probabilty → probability
  quantites → quantities
  secresy → secrecy
  sucession → succession
  suficiently → sufficiently
  telecope → telescope
  verifiy → verify





*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE PRINCIPLES OF SCIENCE ***


    

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S. copyright
law means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works,
so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United
States without permission and without paying copyright
royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part
of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™
concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark,
and may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following
the terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use
of the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for
copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very
easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as creation
of derivative works, reports, performances and research. Project
Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given away—you may
do practically ANYTHING in the United States with eBooks not protected
by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject to the trademark
license, especially commercial redistribution.


START: FULL LICENSE

THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE

PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free
distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
(or any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at
www.gutenberg.org/license.

Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works

1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your
possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be bound
by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person
or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be
used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few
things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See
paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this
agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg™
electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.

1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection
of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the individual
works in the collection are in the public domain in the United
States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in the
United States and you are located in the United States, we do not
claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing,
displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as
all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope
that you will support the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting
free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg™
works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the
Project Gutenberg™ name associated with the work. You can easily
comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the
same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when
you share it without charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are
in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States,
check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this
agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing,
distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any
other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes no
representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any
country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other
immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must appear
prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™ work (any work
on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or with which the
phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is accessed, displayed,
performed, viewed, copied or distributed:

    This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and most
    other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions
    whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms
    of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online
    at www.gutenberg.org. If you
    are not located in the United States, you will have to check the laws
    of the country where you are located before using this eBook.
  
1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is
derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not
contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the
copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in
the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply
either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or
obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg™
trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted
with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works
posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the
beginning of this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg™
License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg™.

1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.

1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including
any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access
to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work in a format
other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in the official
version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain
Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the
full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:

    • You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
        the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the method
        you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed
        to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, but he has
        agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project
        Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid
        within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are
        legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty
        payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project
        Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in
        Section 4, “Information about donations to the Project Gutenberg
        Literary Archive Foundation.”
    
    • You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
        you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
        does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
        License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
        copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue
        all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg™
        works.
    
    • You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of
        any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
        electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of
        receipt of the work.
    
    • You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
        distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.
    

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project
Gutenberg™ electronic work or group of works on different terms than
are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing
from the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating the Project
Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg™
electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may
contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate
or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other
intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or
other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or
cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the “Right
of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
Gutenberg™ electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you
received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium
with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you
with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in
lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person
or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second
opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If
the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing
without further opportunities to fix the problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT
LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of
damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement
violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the
agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or
limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or
unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the
remaining provisions.

1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
providing copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in
accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the
production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses,
including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of
the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this
or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b) alteration, modification, or
additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any
Defect you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg™

Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It
exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations
from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see
Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation

The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by
U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,
Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation

Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without widespread
public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the widest
array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small donations
($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations
where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND
DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular state
visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other
ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To
donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg™ electronic works

Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed
editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,
including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.