Nature and the Gods

By Arthur B. Moss

The Project Gutenberg EBook of Nature and the Gods, by Arthur B. Moss

This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever.  You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org


Title: Nature and the Gods
       From "The Atheistic Platform", Twelve Lectures

Author: Arthur B. Moss

Release Date: May 29, 2011 [EBook #36271]

Language: English


*** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK NATURE AND THE GODS ***




Produced by David Widger





NATURE AND THE GODS

From "The Atheistic Platform", Twelve Lectures

By Arthur B. Moss

London: Freethought Publishing Company

63, Fleet Street, E.C.

1884



NATURE AND THE GODS

Ladies and Gentlemen,--No word has played a more important part in
the discussion of scientific and philosophical questions than the word
Nature. Everyone thinks he knows the meaning of it. Yet how few have
used it to express the same idea; indeed it has been employed to convey
such a variety of impressions that John Stuart Mill asserts that it has
been the "fruitful source" of the propagation of "false taste, false
philosophy, false morality, and even bad law." Now, I propose in this
lecture that we start with some clear ideas concerning the meaning of
such words, upon the right understanding of which the whole force of my
arguments depends. What, then, is meant by the word Nature? When used
by a materialist it has two important meanings. In its large and
philosophical sense it means, as Mr. Mill says: "The sum of all
phenomena, together with the causes which produce them, including not
only all that happens, but all that is capable of happening--the unused
capabilities of matter being as much a part of the idea of Nature as
those which take effect." But the word Nature is often used, and rightly
used, to distinguish the "natural" from the "artificial" object--that
is, to indicate the difference between a thing produced spontaneously by
Nature, from a thing wrought by the skill and labor of man.

But it must not be supposed that the artificial object forms no part of
Nature. All art belongs to Nature. Art simply means the adaptation, the
moulding into certain forms of the things of Nature, and therefore the
artistic productions of man are included in the comprehensive sense of
the term Nature which I just now used.

Now in Nature there is a permanent and a changeable-element, but man
only takes cognisance of the changeable or phenomenal element; of the
substratum underlying phenomena he knows and can know nothing whatever;
that is, man does not know what matter and force are in themselves in
the abstract, he only knows them in the concrete, as they affect him
through the medium of his senses.

Now I allege that nearly all the mistakes of theology have arisen from
the ignorance of man in regard to Nature and her mode of operation. Let
us consider for a moment a few facts in reference to man. Of course I
don't want to take you back to his origin. But suppose we go back no
further than a few thousand years, we shall find that man lived in holes
in the earth; that he moved about in fear and trembling; that not only
did he fight against his fellow creatures, but that he went in constant
fear of animals who sought him as their prey. Under these circumstances
he looked to Nature for assistance. He felt how unspeakably helpless he
was, and he cried aloud for help. Sometimes he imagined that he received
what in his agony he had yearned for. Then it was that he thought that
Nature was most kind. Perhaps he wanted food to eat and had tried in
vain to procure it. But presently a poor beast comes across his path,
and he slays it and satisfies his hunger. Or perhaps he himself is in
danger. A ferocious animal is in pursuit of him and he sees no means of
escape, but presently comes in view a narrow stream of water which he
can swim across, but which his pursuer cannot. When he is again secure
he utters a deep sigh of relief. In time he makes rapid strides of
progress. He learns to keep himself warm while the animals about him are
perishing with cold; he learns to make weapons wherewith to destroy his
enemies; but his greatest triumph of all is when he has learned how to
communicate his thoughts to his fellows. Up to now it would be pretty
safe to say that man was destitute of all ideas concerning the existence
of god or gods. But he advances one stage further, and his thoughts
begin to take something like definite shape. He forms for himself a
theory as to the cause of the events happening about him. And now the
reign of the gods begins. Man is still a naked savage; as Voltaire truly
says: "Man had only his bare skin, which continually exposed to the
sun, rain and hail, became chapped, tanned, and spotted. The male in our
continent was disfigured by spare hairs on his body, which rendered him
frightful without covering him. His face was hidden by these hairs. His
skin became a rough soil which bore a forest of stalks, the roots of
which tended upwards and the branches of which grew downwards. It was
in this state that this animal ventured to paint god, when in course
of time he learnt the art of description." ("Philosophical Dictionary,"
vol. ii., page 182).

Naturally enough man's first objects of worship were fetishes--gods of
wood, stone, trees, fire, water. By-and-bye, however, he came to worship
living beings; in fact, any animal that he thought was superior in any
way to himself was converted into an object of worship. But none of
these gods were of any assistance to him in promoting his advancement
in the world. And neither did he receive any assistance from the
spontaneous action of Nature. In fact he advanced in the road of
civilisation only in proportion as he offered ceaseless war against the
hurtful forces of nature, using one force to counteract the destructive
character of another. Think what the earth must have been without a
solitary house upon it, without a man who yet knew how to till the soil!
Must it not have been a howling wilderness fit only for savage beasts
and brutal barbarians? In course of time, however, man made great
strides. He began to live in communities, which afterwards grew, into
nations. He betook himself also to the art of agriculture, and supplied
himself and his fellows with good, nutritious food. And with this growth
of man the gods underwent a similar transition. Now instead of bowing
down before fetishes, man transferred his worship to gods and goddesses
who were supposed to dwell somewhere in the sky. And these gods were of
a very peculiar kind. Each of them had a separate department to himself
and performed only a certain class of actions. One made the sun to shine
and the trees to grow; one had a kind of dynamite factory to himself,
and manufactured lightning and thunder; another was a god of love;
another secretary for war; another perpetual president of the Celestial
Peace Society. Some had several heads; some had only one eye or one
arm; some had wings, while others appeared like giants, and hurled
thunderbolts at the heads of unoffending people. But these gods were of
no more service to man than those that preceded them. If man advanced it
was by his own effort, by virtue of using his intelligence, by strife,
warfare, and by suffering.

Neither Nature nor the gods taught man to be truthful, honest, just,
nor even to be clean. No god came to tell him that he must not lie,
nor steal, nor murder.. All virtues are acquired, all are the result of
education. And it was only after coming together and being criticised by
one another; men being criticised by women who no doubt taught them that
when they came a-wooing they would have a very slight chance if they
were not clean and respectable; living in societies and being governed
by the wisest among their fellows, who were able to judge as to what
kind of actions produced the most beneficial results, that laws against
theft, adultery, and murder, and other evil actions, were established.
From Polytheism, or belief in many gods, the next great step was to
Monotheism, or belief in one god. This was an important transition,
and meant the clearing from the heavens of many fictitious deities. But
though the monotheist believed only in one god, that did not prevent
others from believing in an entirely different deity. The ancient Jew
worshipped Jahveh, but that did not prevent the Baalites from having
a god of their own, to whom they could appeal in the hour of need. And
just let me here observe that the early monotheist always worshipped an
anthropomorphic or man-like deity. And he worshipped such a god because
man was the highest being of whom he had any conception. His god was
always the counterpart of himself and reflected all the characteristics
of his own nature. Was he brutal and licentious? So was his god. Was he
in favor of aggressive wars? So was his god. Was he a petty tyrant, in
favor of slavery? So was his god. Was he a polygamist? So was his god.
Was he ignorant of the facts of life? So was his god. Was he revengeful
and relentless? So was his god.

And in whatever book we find a deity described as a malevolent or
fiendish wretch depend upon it, by whatever name that book may be
known, and by whomsoever it may be reverenced, it was written by one who
possessed in his own person precisely the same characteristics as those
he depicted in the character of his deity.

The Jewish god, Jahveh, it must be understood, was not a spiritual
being, although it is sometimes pretended that he was. No. He was a
purely material being. True he lived somewhere up above, but he made
very frequent visits to the earth. Once he walked in the garden of Eden
"in the cool of day," or "his voice" did for him (Gen. iii., 8). Once he
stood upon a mountain, whither Moses, Aaron, Nadab and Abihu had gone to
hold a consultation with him (Ex. xxiv., 10). Once he talked with Moses
"face to face" (Ex. xxxiii., 11).

And not only was Jahveh a material being, but on the whole he was not
a very formidable deity. In point of truth he was a very little fellow.
And by way of diversion he was sometimes drawn about in a small box,
or ark, two feet long and three feet wide (Sam. vi., 6, 7). As evidence
that even among professional Christians to-day Jahveh is not looked upon
as a very stalwart fellow, Mr. Edward Gibson, in the House of Commons,
a short time ago said that if Mr. Bradlaugh were admitted into that
assembly the effect of it would be that god would be "thrown out of the
window."

And if you want to find a man with "small ideas" on general matters
it is only necessary to know the kind of god he worships to be able to
determine the intellectual width and depth of such a man's mind.

Why is this? Because all ideas of god were born in the fertile
imaginations of men, and a man's idea of god is invariably the exact
measurement of himself, morally and intellectually. It may be urged by
some Theists that man is indebted to Jahveh for his existence, and that
he owes his moral and intellectual advancement to the fact that this
deity, through the medium of Moses and the other inspired writers,
laid down certain commandments for his guidance in life. When it is
remembered, however, that if man is indebted in any way to Jahveh for
his existence, he owes him only the exact equivalent of the benefits
he has received, I think it will be seen that on the whole man's
indebtedness to this deity is very small indeed.

Was Adam indebted to Jahveh for the imperfect nature which compelled him
to commit the so-called sin which imperilled the future destiny of human
race? Were all the "miserable sinners"--the descendants of the first
pair--indebted to Jahveh for their "corrupt" natures?

If yes, what kind of god was man indebted to? To a god who once drowned
the whole of mankind except one family? To a god who said that he was a
jealous being who "visited the sins of the father upon the children
unto a third and fourth generation." (Ex. xx., 5)? To a god who sanctioned
slavery (Lev. xxv., 44, 45) and injustice of all kinds? To a god who
said "thou shalt not suffer a witch to live" (Ex. xxii., 18), and gave
instructions for men to kill the blasphemers among their fellows (Lev.
xxiv., 16)? To a god who told Moses to go against the Midianites and
slay every man among them, preserving only the virgins among the women
to satisfy the lustful natures of a brutal horde of soldiers (Numbers
xxxi., 7--18)? To a god to whom, as Shelley says, the only acceptable
offerings were "the steam of slaughter, the dissonance of groans,
and the flames of a desolate land" (Dialogue between "Eusebes and
Theosophus," prose writings, page 300)? I deny that man has ever been
in any way indebted to such a god, and I say moreover that such a
deity never had any real existence, except in the base imaginations of
ignorant and brutal men. But the next stage was from the material to the
spiritual god. Many ages must have elapsed before this more elevating
though equally absurd belief became to be accepted, even by a small
minority of mankind. But the time eventually did come--a time which
happily is now rapidly passing away--when intellectual men believed that
the proposition of the existence of god could be demonstrated to all
rational minds. Some said that god's existence was self-evident to every
intelligent mind; others that Nature and men could not have come by
"chance"; that they must have had a cause; some said that the harmony
existing in the universe proved god's existence; others that everybody
except fools "felt in their hearts" that there was a god. But these
imaginary proofs did not always convince. At last there came forth
philosophers who said that there was a mode of reasoning, the adoption
of which "leads irresistibly up to the belief in god," and that that
mode was called the mode _à priori_. Another school said that the _à
priori_, or reasoning from cause to effect, was an altogether fallacious
method, and that the only satisfactory mode of establishing god's
existence was the _à posteriori_, or reasoning from effect to cause.

Another school said that taken singly neither of these modes of
reasoning established the existence of deity, but that both taken
together "formed a perfect chain" of reasoning that was quite conclusive
on the point. Neither of these schools, however, showed how two bad
arguments could possibly make one good one. But let me just briefly
examine these arguments put forward so confidently by leading Theists.
The first method--_à priori_--invariably takes the form of an attempt to
establish what is called a "Great First Cause."

When it is said that there must be a "first cause" to account for the
existence of Nature, such language, to say the least, shows a total
misapprehension of the meaning of the word "cause," as used by
scientific men. "First cause," as applied to Nature as a whole,
remembering the definition I have given, is an absurdity. Cause
and effect apply only to phenomena. Each effect is a cause of some
subsequent effect, and each cause is an effect of some antecedent
cause. The phenomena of the universe form a complete chain of causes and
effects, and in an infinite regression there can be no first cause.
Let me explain what I mean more fully. For instance, here is a chain;
suppose it is to form a perfect circle, every link in which is perfect;
now if you were to go round and round this chain from now to doomsday
you would never come to the first link. It is the same in Nature. You
can go back, and back, and back through successive causes and effects,
but you will never come to a "first cause"; you will not be able to say
"here is the end of Nature, and here the beginning of something else."
There is no brick wall to mark the boundary line of Nature. You
cannot "look through Nature up to Nature's God,"--the poet Pope
notwithstanding--for Nature seems endless, and you can neither penetrate
her heights nor fathom her depths. And I have one other word to say in
reference to this _à priori_ method, before finally disposing of it. It
is this, that it is an altogether unscientific method. Man knows nothing
whatever of cause except in the sense' that in the immediate antecedent
of an effect. Man's experience is of effects; these he takes cognisance
of; of these he has some knowledge, but of cause, except as a means to
an end, he has none. But this brings me to the second mode of reasoning
in proof of God's existence, the _à posteriori_ and this has one
advantage in its favor, and that is, that it is a scientific method. It
reasons from known effects up to the supposed causes of them. Now this
generally assumes the form, no matter under what guise, of the famous
"design argument." Dr. Paley stated it many years ago, and it has not
been much improved since his day. It is generally stated in this
way: "The world exhibits marks of design; that design must have had a
designer; that designer must be a person; that person is God." A number
of illustrations are then brought forward to support this contention.
For instance, it is argued that when a man observes a watch or a
telescope, or any article that has been made to answer a certain
purpose, and the mechanism of which is so adjusted as to effect the
desired object, it is said that from the marks of design or contrivance
observed in the mechanism, he infers that these articles are the
products of some human designer. And so it is said that when we look
around the world and see how beautifully things are designed, the eye
to see, the ear to hear; how admirably things are adapted the one to
the other, are we not justified by similar reasoning in concluding that
these are the productions of an almighty and infinite designer? Briefly
stated that is the argument. Now let me examine it. And in the first
place it will be observed that it is assumed that there is a great
resemblance between the works of Nature and the artistic works of
man. But is this really a fact? Man simply moulds natural objects into
certain forms; they are then called artificial objects. We know that man
designs watches and telescopes; it is a fact within our experience. But
there is not the slightest similarity between the process of manufacture
and the natural process of growth; so that when we see various objects
of Nature, we do hot conclude, however harmoniously the parts may work
together, that they were designed. We know a manufactured article from
a natural object, we could not mistake the one for the other. But let us
suppose that we did not know that men made watches; it is very probable
that we should then think that a watch was not made at all, but that it
was a natural object. Take an illustration. Suppose that I were to lay a
watch upon the earth somewhere in South Africa; suppose that in a short
time a savage wandering near the spot where the watch was deposited
should observe it, should take it into his hand and handle it--I am
assuming that the savage had never seen a watch before, and was not
aware that men designed and constructed watches--think you that he would
for a moment notice that it exhibited marks of design? No, I think
he would be more likely to come to the opinion that it was alive. The
design argument therefore is purely an argument drawn from experience.
But what experience has man of god? Speaking for myself I can say that
I have absolutely no experience of him at all, and I am not acquainted
with anybody who has. Man does not know god as a designer or
constructor; he neither knows of his capabilities, nor his existence;
and he therefore cannot reasonably say that god is the designer of
anything.

The human eye is very often adduced by the Theist as an illustration of
design. Now nobody can deny that the eye is a delicate, complicated,
and beautiful structure; nobody could fail to see and acknowledge with
feelings of admiration the wonderful adjustment and harmonious working
of its various parts; and all would readily acknowledge how admirably it
is fitted to perform its functions. But yet to acknowledge all this is
not to admit that the eye is designed. To point to the combinations
and conditions which produce this result, without showing that these
conditions were designed, is to beg the whole question. And it must be
distinctly understood that the _onus probandi_ as the lawyers say, lies
with the affirmer of the design argument and not with him who does not
see evidence in it sufficient to command belief. To show that a thing
is capable of effecting a certain result does not prove that it was
designed for that purpose.

For example. I hold this glass in my hand; I now release my hold from it
and it instantly falls to the ground; that does not surely prove
either that I was designed to hold up that glass, or that the glass was
designed to fall on withdrawing my grasp from it. At most it only proves
that I am capable of holding it, and that when I release it, it is
impelled by the law of gravitation to fall towards the earth.

But there is another view of this question I wish to present to you.
From this argument it is not quite clear that there is only one
supreme god of the universe. Admittedly this is an argument based upon
experience. What does experience teach us in respect to a person? Simply
this. That a person must have an organisation, and a person with an
organisation must be a limited being. Has god an organisation? If he has
not, he cannot be intelligent, cannot perceive, recollect, judge; and
if he has, then an organisation implies contrivance, and contrivance
implies a contriver, and this again instead of leading up to one
god, leads to an innumerable tribe of deities each mightier and more
complicated than the other.

If the Theist retorts that a person need not have an organisation, the
Atheist at once replies that neither need the designer of Nature be a
person.

But these are not the only objections to be used against the design
argument. The _à priori_ theologians have some very potent arguments to
advance. Mr. William Gillespie has discovered twenty-four defects of _à
posteriori_ arguments, and I think he has conclusively shown that all
the attributes claimed for deity are impeached by this method.

In my humble opinion the design argument has grown out of the arrogance
and conceit of man, who imagines that the earth and all the things
existing upon it were treated especially for his benefit.

Suppose that I admit that there is design in Nature, the Theist has then
to account for some awkward and many horrible designs. How will he get
over the fact that Nature is one vast battle-field on which all life is
engaged in warfare? What goodness will he see in the design that gives
the strong and cunning the advantage over the weak and simple? What
beneficence will he detect in the fact that all animals "prey" upon one
another? and that man is not exempt from the struggle? Famine destroys
thousands; earthquakes desolate a land; and what tongue can tell the
anguish and pain endured by the very poor in all great countries of the
earth? Think of the "ills to which flesh is heir." Think of the diseases
from which so many thousands suffer. Think how many endure agony from
cancer or tumor, how many have within their bodies parasites which
locate themselves in the liver, the muscles, and the intestines, causing
great agony and sometimes death. Think how many are born blind and how
many become sightless on account of disease. Think of the deaf and the
dumb, and of the poor idiots who pass a dreary and useless existence in
asylums. Then think of the accidents to which all men are liable. Think
of the many who are killed or injured on railways every year. Think of
men and boys who injure or destroy their limbs in machinery during
the performance of their daily work. Think of the thousands who find
a premature and watery grave. In one of our London workhouses I saw
recently a young man who had met with a dreadful accident; who had had
his hand frightfully lacerated by a circular saw, which will prevent him
from ever working again. Think of his suffering. Think of the misery his
wife and children will have to bear on account of it. It almost makes
one shed bitter tears to think of it; and yet we are to be told, we who
are striving to alleviate suffering and mitigate the evils which afflict
our fellow creatures, we are to be told that an infinitely wise and good
god designs these things.

Oh the blasphemy of it! Surely an infinite fiend could not do worse;
and if I thought that Nature were intelligent, that Nature knew of the
suffering she inflicted on all kinds of living beings and had the power
to prevent it, but would not, I would curse Nature even though the curse
involved for me a sudden and painful death. But Nature heareth not man's
protests or appeals--she is blind to his sufferings and deaf to his
prayers.

Oh, but it's said: "See what harmony there is in the Universe:" _per se_
there is neither harmony nor chaos in Nature; we call that harmony
which pleasantly affects us, and that chaos which does the reverse.
Some Theist may say: "Suppose that I grant that I cannot prove that
god exists, what then? You cannot prove your own existence, and yet
you believe that you exist." I am well aware that I cannot prove my
own existence; I don't want to prove it; it's a fact, and it stands for
itself--to me it is not a matter of belief, it is a matter of certainty.
I know that I exist. Cannot god make the evidence of his existence as
clear as my own is to me? If he cannot, what becomes of his power? and
if he will not, what of his goodness?

And it must be remembered that there are thousands of intelligent
Atheists in the world to-day. Now, either god does not wish man to
believe in him, or if he does he lacks the power to produce conviction.
O Theist--you who profess to be conversant with the ways of the
almighty--explain to me, now, how it is that in proportion as men
cultivate their minds and reason on theological questions that the
tendency is for them to disbelieve even in the ethereal deity of modern
Theism. And it will not do in the nineteenth century to put Jesus
forward as a god. He was no god. He possessed many good qualities, no
doubt, as a man--but not one attribute which is claimed for god. He
was neither all-wise, nor all-good, nor all-powerful, and he was only
a finite being. And how can it be pretended by sensible persons that
a finite man living on the earth, born of a woman, and dying like
any other ordinary being, could possibly be the infinite god of the
Universe? Is it not absurd? I cannot believe it, and anybody with brains
that devotes a moment's thought to the matter, must acknowledge either
that it is incomprehensible, or that it is monstrously absurd.

In this country we are not asked to believe in any of the "foreign
gods"--the gods of ancient Greece or Rome--the gods of China, India,
or Egypt, etc.--and we need not now discuss as to how far these deities
have influenced human conduct for good or for ill. England, as a
civilised country, is not very old. And civilisation has always meant
a banishment of the gods. While men considered how to please the gods,
they neglected in a great measure the work of the world. As Plato said:
"The gods only help those who help themselves." Well they are just the
persons who do not want help; and I shall never worship any god who
leaves the helpless and the unfortunate to perish.

If god only "helps those who help themselves," he might as well leave
the helping alone, because even as we find the world to-day, the whole
of life seems to be based on the principle that, "unto him that hath
shall be given, and he shall have in abundance, and from him that hath
not shall be taken away even that which he seemeth to have." The man who
has a strong constitution may struggle successfully in the world; the
man with great affluence may win an easy victory over his fellows; the
man who has plenty of "influential friends" has good prospects; but the
poor, the weakly, the ignorant, what hope have they--they have to suffer
and toil, and toil and suffer from the cradle to the tomb.

How is it, then, you may ask, if man has received no assistance from
without, either from Nature or the gods, that he has achieved such
splendid results in the world? The answer is simple enough. The great
struggle for life--the desire to get food, clothing, habitation,
comfort--these have been the motives which have urged men on. The desire
to get food caused men to till the soil, and, as the demand increased,
the methods of cultivation improved; with improved taste came improved
raiment and dwellings for the rich; plain dress and decent habitation
for the poor. Men having given up the worship of Nature, began to study
her; they found that by diligent investigation, and the application of
their augmented knowledge, they were able to beautify the world,
and render their lives happy. Then we began to have great scientific
discoveries. Navigation, steam-power, telegraphy, electricity; by a
knowledge of the use of these powers man has been able to conquer the
destructive character of many natural forces, and to transfer a world of
misery into a home of comparative comfort. And I say that the world is
indebted far more to those who built houses, made clothes, navigated
ships, made machinery, wrote books, than to all the gods and their
clerical representatives the world has ever known. Belief in god never
helped a man to supersede the sailing vessel by the steamship, the
old coach by the railroad, the scythe by the reaping machine, nor the
fastest locomotion by the telegraph wires. Man's necessities allured
him on to all these achievements. One Stephenson is worth a thousand
priests--one Edison of more value to the world than all the gods ever
pictured by the imagination. And we must not forget the men who freed
the human intellect from the fetters of a degrading superstition. We
must not forget what the world owes to our Brunos, our Spinozas, our
Voltaires, our Paines, our Priestleys; for these, by teaching men to
rely on their reason, have opened out channels of thought that were
previously closed, and mines of intellectual and material wealth that
have since yielded great results. And so it must now be said that man is
master of Nature, and he finds that she is just as good as a servant as
she was bad as a master.

But the earth is not yet a Paradise. Theology is not yet entirely
banished; the debris of the decayed beliefs still cumber our path and
impede our progress. There is even now much that remains to be done.
Plenty of labor to be performed. Ignorance, poverty, and crime and
misery still exist and exert their evil influence in the world. The
philanthropist and the reformer have still their work to do. The
ignorant have yet to be instructed, the hungry have yet to be fed, the
homeless have yet to be provided for. And I have come to the opinion
after years of experience, that ignorance is the real cause of all the
misery and suffering in the world; that that man is truly wise who sees
that it is against his own interest to do a paltry act, to perform an
evil deed. All actions carry with them their consequences, and you can
no more escape the effects of your evil deeds than you can evade the
law of gravitation, or elude the grim monster Death when the dread hour
arrives.

No. If you would be happy you must act virtuously--act as you would
desire all others to do to promote your happiness. Say to yourselves:
"if every one were to act as I am doing, would the world be benefited?"
and if you come to the opinion that the world would not be improved by
such conduct, depend upon it your actions are not good. Remember that
once you perform a deed in Nature it is irrevocable; and if it is bad
repentance is worse than useless. All actions either have an evil or
a good result. Every deed leaves its indelible impress on the book of
Nature, from which no leaves can be torn and nothing can be expunged.
And remember, too, that the man who makes his fellow-creatures happy
cannot displease a god who is good; and a god who is not good is neither
deserving of admiration nor service.

An infinite and all-powerful god cannot need the assistance of man;
but man needs the assistance of his brothers and sisters to diffuse
the glorious light of knowledge through the world; needs assistance to
alleviate suffering, to remove injustice, and secure the possibility of
freedom and happiness for all. Therefore I urge you to abate not your
enthusiasm, but work bravely on; and when the evening of your life
approaches, with wife by your side and your children playing joyously
about you, with many friends to cheer and thank you--then will you know
that your life's labor has not been in vain.






End of the Project Gutenberg EBook of Nature and the Gods, by Arthur B. Moss

*** END OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK NATURE AND THE GODS ***

***** This file should be named 36271-8.txt or 36271-8.zip *****
This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
        http://www.gutenberg.org/3/6/2/7/36271/

Produced by David Widger

Updated editions will replace the previous one--the old editions
will be renamed.

Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no
one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation
(and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without
permission and without paying copyright royalties.  Special rules,
set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to
copying and distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works to
protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm concept and trademark.  Project
Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you
charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission.  If you
do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the
rules is very easy.  You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose
such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and
research.  They may be modified and printed and given away--you may do
practically ANYTHING with public domain eBooks.  Redistribution is
subject to the trademark license, especially commercial
redistribution.



*** START: FULL LICENSE ***

THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting the free
distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work
(or any other work associated in any way with the phrase "Project
Gutenberg"), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project
Gutenberg-tm License (available with this file or online at
http://gutenberg.org/license).


Section 1.  General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic works

1.A.  By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to
and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement.  If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy
all copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in your possession.
If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the
terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or
entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B.  "Project Gutenberg" is a registered trademark.  It may only be
used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who
agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement.  There are a few
things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works
even without complying with the full terms of this agreement.  See
paragraph 1.C below.  There are a lot of things you can do with Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement
and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works.  See paragraph 1.E below.

1.C.  The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation ("the Foundation"
or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic works.  Nearly all the individual works in the
collection are in the public domain in the United States.  If an
individual work is in the public domain in the United States and you are
located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from
copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative
works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg
are removed.  Of course, we hope that you will support the Project
Gutenberg-tm mission of promoting free access to electronic works by
freely sharing Project Gutenberg-tm works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg-tm name associated with
the work.  You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by
keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project
Gutenberg-tm License when you share it without charge with others.

1.D.  The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern
what you can do with this work.  Copyright laws in most countries are in
a constant state of change.  If you are outside the United States, check
the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement
before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or
creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project
Gutenberg-tm work.  The Foundation makes no representations concerning
the copyright status of any work in any country outside the United
States.

1.E.  Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1.  The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate
access to, the full Project Gutenberg-tm License must appear prominently
whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg-tm work (any work on which the
phrase "Project Gutenberg" appears, or with which the phrase "Project
Gutenberg" is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed,
copied or distributed:

This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever.  You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org

1.E.2.  If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is derived
from the public domain (does not contain a notice indicating that it is
posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied
and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees
or charges.  If you are redistributing or providing access to a work
with the phrase "Project Gutenberg" associated with or appearing on the
work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1
through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the
Project Gutenberg-tm trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or
1.E.9.

1.E.3.  If an individual Project Gutenberg-tm electronic work is posted
with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional
terms imposed by the copyright holder.  Additional terms will be linked
to the Project Gutenberg-tm License for all works posted with the
permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work.

1.E.4.  Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this
work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg-tm.

1.E.5.  Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg-tm License.

1.E.6.  You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any
word processing or hypertext form.  However, if you provide access to or
distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg-tm work in a format other than
"Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other format used in the official version
posted on the official Project Gutenberg-tm web site (www.gutenberg.org),
you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a
copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon
request, of the work in its original "Plain Vanilla ASCII" or other
form.  Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg-tm
License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7.  Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg-tm works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8.  You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
access to or distributing Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works provided
that

- You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
     the use of Project Gutenberg-tm works calculated using the method
     you already use to calculate your applicable taxes.  The fee is
     owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark, but he
     has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the
     Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation.  Royalty payments
     must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you
     prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax
     returns.  Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and
     sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the
     address specified in Section 4, "Information about donations to
     the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation."

- You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies
     you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he
     does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg-tm
     License.  You must require such a user to return or
     destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium
     and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of
     Project Gutenberg-tm works.

- You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any
     money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
     electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days
     of receipt of the work.

- You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
     distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm works.

1.E.9.  If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg-tm
electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
both the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and Michael
Hart, the owner of the Project Gutenberg-tm trademark.  Contact the
Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1.  Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable
effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread
public domain works in creating the Project Gutenberg-tm
collection.  Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain
"Defects," such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or
corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other medium, a
computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by
your equipment.

1.F.2.  LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the "Right
of Replacement or Refund" described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project
Gutenberg-tm trademark, and any other party distributing a Project
Gutenberg-tm electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all
liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
fees.  YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT
LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3.  YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE
LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR
INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH
DAMAGE.

1.F.3.  LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a
defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a
written explanation to the person you received the work from.  If you
received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with
your written explanation.  The person or entity that provided you with
the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a
refund.  If you received the work electronically, the person or entity
providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to
receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund.  If the second copy
is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further
opportunities to fix the problem.

1.F.4.  Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS' WITH NO OTHER
WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5.  Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by
the applicable state law.  The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.

1.F.6.  INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
providing copies of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works in accordance
with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production,
promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm electronic works,
harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees,
that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg-tm
work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any
Project Gutenberg-tm work, and (c) any Defect you cause.


Section  2.  Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg-tm

Project Gutenberg-tm is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers
including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.  It exists
because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from
people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
assistance they need, are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg-tm's
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg-tm collection will
remain freely available for generations to come.  In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure
and permanent future for Project Gutenberg-tm and future generations.
To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4
and the Foundation web page at http://www.pglaf.org.


Section 3.  Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation

The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service.  The Foundation's EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541.  Its 501(c)(3) letter is posted at
http://pglaf.org/fundraising.  Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state's laws.

The Foundation's principal office is located at 4557 Melan Dr. S.
Fairbanks, AK, 99712., but its volunteers and employees are scattered
throughout numerous locations.  Its business office is located at
809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887, email
business@pglaf.org.  Email contact links and up to date contact
information can be found at the Foundation's web site and official
page at http://pglaf.org

For additional contact information:
     Dr. Gregory B. Newby
     Chief Executive and Director
     gbnewby@pglaf.org


Section 4.  Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation

Project Gutenberg-tm depends upon and cannot survive without wide
spread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be
freely distributed in machine readable form accessible by the widest
array of equipment including outdated equipment.  Many small donations
($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt
status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States.  Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up
with these requirements.  We do not solicit donations in locations
where we have not received written confirmation of compliance.  To
SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any
particular state visit http://pglaf.org

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we
have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition
against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who
approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States.  U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
methods and addresses.  Donations are accepted in a number of other
ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations.
To donate, please visit: http://pglaf.org/donate


Section 5.  General Information About Project Gutenberg-tm electronic
works.

Professor Michael S. Hart is the originator of the Project Gutenberg-tm
concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared
with anyone.  For thirty years, he produced and distributed Project
Gutenberg-tm eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support.


Project Gutenberg-tm eBooks are often created from several printed
editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S.
unless a copyright notice is included.  Thus, we do not necessarily
keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition.


Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:

     http://www.gutenberg.org

This Web site includes information about Project Gutenberg-tm,
including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to
subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.